International Journal of Civil Engineering and Technology (IJCIET) Volume 10, Issue 04, April 2019, pp. 228-247, Article ID: IJCIET_10_04_025 Available online at http://www.iaeme.com/ijciet/issues.asp?JType=IJCIET&VType=10&IType=04 ISSN Print: 0976-6308 and ISSN Online: 0976-6316 © IAEME Publication Scopus Indexed ARCHITECTURAL PHILOSOPHICAL TERM FROM PRE-SOCRATIC TO ENLIGHTENMENT Kadhim Fathel Khalil Department of Architectural Engineering, University of Duhok, Kurdistan, Iraq ABSTRACT The philosophical term is considers as a basic intellectual background of architecture throughout history, but the architectural theories that touched on this subject haven’t been diagnosed this term clearly, so I bring this paper to diagnose this term in philosophical architectural knowledge through the epochs of time, what gives this paper an importance in the study of architectural theories is disintegrate the knowledge confusion about this term and thus will be the beginning for more accurately topics that related to what the philosophical-architecture term is. The problem of the current research has been represented by the lack of studies with regard to essence of the philosophical-architectural term and it’s employ in architecture. The objective of the study was defined in an attempt to discover the philosophical-architecture term and its mechanism employed in architecture. To achieve this goal the structural approach in building knowledge about the philosophical-architecture term has been adopted according to the epochs of time starting from the Pre-Socratic era down to Present era, that gives a high holistic to this study in the diagnosis of the philosophical- architecture term. This study is dividing into two main stages, first is covering the Pre-Socratic to the Enlightenment era, the subsequent study is covering modernism to the present era. Keywords: Philosophy, Architecture, Term, Geometry, Form, Aesthetic. Cite this Article: Kadhim Fathel Khalil, Architectural Philosophical Term from PreSocratic to Enlightenment. International Journal of Civil Engineering and Technology, 10(04), 2019, pp. 228-247 http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/issues.asp?JType=IJCIET&VType=10&IType=04 1. INTRODUCTION One looks at philosophers and philosophical ideas in the way that they were interpreted and utilized by architects, independent from whether their reading should be seen as a correct or even plausible interpretation. Architectural theory is nurtured by philosophical ideas, the concern and questions that move people at a certain time as much as their visions and worldviews are mirrored in their architectural design: Architecture provides functional and technical solution but is also a practical answer to philosophical questions. Yet to account for philosophy’s role for architecture, one faces a profound difficulty: Architects have often read \http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 228 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil philosophers in ways that scholars find very problematic. Because architectural debates are embedded in wider reflection of a culture, they are shaped as such by clichés as by ideas that are current at any time. This attempt illustrates the relationship between western philosophy and architecture. It discusses philosophy’s contribution to architecture and the way in which one can reflect philosophically about architecture, the recognition of philosophical architectural term, through which philosopher’s interpreted architecture, will enable theorists and architects to be closer to state of philosophical expression of architecture. It has been said that there is a relationship between philosophy and architecture, but it is not clear the essence of this link, however, the existentialism of the philosophy based on conventional linguistic construction, drives towards the realization that this association exists through -term- so the question came about what the most influential philosophical-architectural terms overtimes are, or what are the common terms between philosophy and architecture, which can be called the philosophical-architectural term. In an attempt to find an answer to this research question, it was necessary to analyze the studies that dealt with philosophy and architecture, where we found that the study of Śuvaković focused on the notions of “philosophy of architecture” and “aesthetics of architecture” and the differences between traditional and contemporary philosophy and aesthetics of architecture [1].While Ahmed took the major motivating tributary to descend a relation between the modalities of classical philosophy and theory of aesthetics associated with ancient Greek architecture [2]. Branko topics in his study include Aristotle's theories of "visual imagination" and their relevance to digital design, the problem of optical correction as explored by Plato, Hegel's theory of zeitgeist, and Kant's examinations of space and aesthetics, among others. Focusing primarily on nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy, it provides students with a wider perspective relating to philosophical problems that come up in contemporary architectural debts [3]. Mitias study is a critical exploration of the main questions concerning the intersection of philosophy and architecture. Is architecture art? How does a building mean? What is our experience of the architectural work? Philosophical reflection focuses here on the aesthetic status, cultural value, and human significance of architecture [4]. Hendrix examines philosophical structures of Plato in their structural, spatial, and architectonic implications. It examines elements of Plato's philosophical systems in relation to other philosophical systems, including those of Anaximander, Plotinus, Proclus, Nicolas Cusanus, Marsilio Ficino, Georges Bataille, Jacques Lacan, and Jacques Derrida [5]. Also, Hendrix examines architectural and architectonic forms as products of philosophical and epistemological structures in selected cultures and time periods of Western civilization, beginning in Egypt and Greece and culminating in twentiethcentury Europe and America, and analyzes architecture as a text of its culture. Relations between architectural forms and philosophical structures are explored in Architecture, like all forms of artistic expression, is interwoven with the beliefs and the structures of knowledge of its culture [6]. Previous studies that have been analyzed, despite their accuracy and comprehensiveness, have left gaps in knowledge in terms of how they deal with the relationship of philosophy to architecture. Where we find that most of them confirm the obvious relationship, without addressing the problem of what this relationship, which is a whole descriptive style. So, we can say Knowledge is ambiguous about essence which stand behind the relationship between philosophy and architecture, and therefore, regard to essence of the philosophical-architectural term. The problem of the current research has been represented by the lack of studies with regard to essence of the philosophical-architectural term and it’s employ in architecture. In light of problem statement, the objective of the study was defined in an attempt to discover the philosophical-architecture term in architecture. http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 229 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. 2 PHILOSOPHY First of all, it is necessary to identify philosophy, where according to Oxford English Dictionary Philosophy: Philosophy is the study of general and fundamental problems concerning matters such as existence, knowledge, values, reason, mind, and language [7].[8].The term was probably coined by Pythagoras. Philosophical methods include questioning, critical discussion, rational argument, and systematic presentation [9].Classic philosophical questions include: Is it possible to know anything and to prove it? [10].The term is the agreement of some people to name the thing in the name of what is transmitted from the first subject, and to remove the word from the linguistic meaning to another, for the occasion between them [11]. While the terminology of a subject according to Collins English Dictionary is the set of special words and expressions used in connection with it. And according to vocabulary dictionary Terminology is vocabulary associated with a certain field of study, profession, or activity. Know the terminology is an important part of being able to work in a given profession. The body of terms used with a particular technical application in a subject of study, profession, etc. Scientific terminology is a special words or expressions used in relation to a particular subject or activity [12][13]. 3 PHILOSOPHY AND ARCHITECTURE Philosophy lies at the heart of the relationship between architecture and theory. The philosopher is someone who is always on the road, and yet who can never reach to an ultimate destination. A person engaged in philosophy always goes after various illusions and finds material for questioning in her environment, leading to continuous reproduction. The architect, on the other hand, engages in intellectual production, by coming up with ideas and concepts through the design process. She works on the problems in the environment, and feels an excitement with the development of different routes to thought. Philosophy is also a part of the act of design. Architecture, in contrast, can evolve into a space for the philosopher to develop thought. The intellectual initiatives, which a thinker brings to architects, clarify the concepts by helping locate the architect within the wider framework of architectural thought. That is why architects and philosophers, who had hitherto contributed immensely to world literature, are members of disciplines, which have now virtually amalgamated in each other [14][15]. In Architectural Forms and Philosophical Structures examines architectural and architectonic forms as products of philosophical and epistemological structures in selected cultures and time periods, and analyzes architecture as a text of its culture. Relations between architectural forms and philosophical structures are explored in civilization, beginning in Egypt and Greece and culminating in twentieth-century Europe and America. Architecture, like all forms of artistic expression, is interwoven with the beliefs and the structures of knowledge of its culture.While philosophical approaches might be seen as part and parcel of architecture practice from its most clearly defined beginnings in Vitruvius’s well-known Ten Books on Architecture (ca 27 BCE), it is particularly in the last decades of the twentieth century that philosophy took centre stage. In the late 1980s, architecture positioned itself as meaningful cultural intervention with reference to many philosophical perspectives on the social and the aesthetic. In essence, one could argue that philosophy and architecture make natural bedfellows, as they seek to understand some of the most fundamental concerns of human existence [16]. Philosophy, just as it does with other phenomena, conceptualises architectonic work each time selecting definite architectonic object symbolising a supersensory principle of the world. On the other hand, philosophy takes over from architecture the interrelationships and through them it articulates its own domain of problems. Moreover, on the basis of architectonic metaphor, it constructs a notional framework enabling presenting the world as an entity. Presence of architectonic value http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 230 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil is apparent in metaphysics, the knowledge presenting principal understanding of existence as an entity. Let us have a look at the architecture and metaphysics interrelatedness with its transformations in the context of three key concepts for philosophical tradition and European culture. Firstly, the moment metaphysics was born, i.e. when Plato discovered the order of ideas superseding sensory world, secondly, identification by I. Kant a crisis of metaphysics – reformulation of traditional metaphysics, thirdly, M. Heidegger’s transgression beyond metaphysics [17]. Architecture does not mean only constructing buildings. It is also a symbol for human activity and culture. Understand the idea of architectural structure and introducing the universal architectural knowledge can be attained by probing the concepts related to architecture with the disciplines attached to these concepts and how these relationships have been established. Analyzing the relationship between architecture and philosophy assuming the constructions of renaissance, 17th and 18th century and contribute to universal architectural knowledge by this way [18]. 4 METHODOLOGY The methodology of research is based on the chronological observation of Western philosophy throughout history, which has been classified into eight eras: Pre-Socratic era, Socratic era, Hellenistic era, Roman era, Medieval era, Renaissance era, Reason era, and Enlightenment era, In preparation for the survey and careful research on the term for each of these periods, as shown in the research annexes. So, Method of analysis is based on a series of steps to achieve the goal of defining the architectural term in philosophy for each era and includes: I. the Temporal survey of all philosophers from the pre-Socratic era to the pre-Modern era. II. Identify philosophers who mentioned terms related to architecture in each era. III. Identify the philosophy-architecture terms for each era. 5 PRE-SOCRATIC ERA The Pre-Socratics introduced a new way of inquiring into the world and the place of human beings in it. They sought natural explanations for phenomena. These philosophers asked questions about "the essence of things". Pre-Socratic philosophy actually refers more to a brand of philosophy, dominated by an interest in the Natural world, mathematics, form, etc. [19]. Thales of Miletus used geometry to calculate the heights of pyramids and the distance of ships from the shore. He is the first known individual to use deductive reasoning applied to geometry. Thales understood similar triangles and right triangles, while Anaximander of Miletus imagined a world both "natural", in the sense of a thing changing and growing organically, and "artificial", in the sense of having been created. His model for this thought be specifically architectural. One in which architectural structure and natural structure had not yet become distinct [20][21]. In the Pythagorean tradition, astronomy is interpreted as magnitudes in motion, geometry as magnitudes at rest, arithmetic as numbers absolute, and music as numbers applied. Linking between architecture and music and linking magnitudes at rest, with numbers applied, and Heraclitus of Ephesus deposited his book as a dedication in the great temple of Artemis. The implication of Heraclitus writings, with particular importance for architecture, is that fire gives the appearance of stability. Afire, just as a building, may appear to have a continuous and singular existence. This existence, however, is marked by continual change, while Protagoras of Abdera best describes the basis for his civilization art and architecture when he stated. Of all thing the measure is man. Greek culture emphasized the beauty of the human body. And created idealized male and female [22][32][24]. http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 231 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. 6 SOCRATIC ERA Socrates developed a system of critical reasoning in order to work out how to live properly and to tell the difference between right and wrong. In the Socratic era, philosophers distinguished architecture from building, attributing the former to mental traits, and the latter to the divine or natural. It was only with Socratic irony that the name craftsman could become representative of a religious deity. The presence of some degree of formalism ale Platonism continues to be an important trait in distinguishing one architectural style from another, and thus in distinguishing the philosophy of a style [25].Socrates of Athens thinks If building were a natural thing, it would be executed by nature no differently than it would be by architecture, and nature would be constrained to use the same rules to give it perfection: just as the very abodes of the gods were devised by poets with the skill of architects, arrayed with arches and columns, which is how they described the royal palace of sun of Love, transporting architecture to heaven, as well as Criteria of Athens criticized for analogizing self-knowledge with forms of productive knowledge auch as architecture. Critias claims that some forms of specialized knowledge lack products. Critias says that its use is considerable, since its product is an excellent one, namely. Similarly with architecture, which produces building, and with the other crafts [26][27]. The objects of our perception are not, according to Democritus of Abdera, the things themselves, but "images" given off by surrounding bodies in the form of atoms, and projected onto the sense organs. The image seen by eye is not an exact likeness of the thing itself, but distorted by the intervening air, and Speusippus thinks Figure and One together manifest the point from which is derived all other geometrical shapes. The geometrical entities can interact with Multiplicity to form Soul, which is defined as the form of dimensionality, the very essence of existing in space. From the Soul come the forms of the souls and bodies that form our world [28][29]. Eudoxus of Cnidus introduced the idea of non-quantified mathematical magnitude to describe and work with continuous geometrical entities such as lines, angles, areas and volumes, while Aristotle presents the four causes drawing on the example of causal roles in the architecture of a temple. For example, the architect’s idea of the temple, as realized through craftsmanship of the workers whom the architect commands, represents the efficient cause of the temple-whereas the architect’s vision of or plan for the temple provides the formal cause [30][31]. 7. HELLENISTIC ERA Hellenistic philosophers, focused upon the life of the individual, independently of the society as a whole, describing in detail the kinds of character and action that might enable a person to live well despite the prevailing political realities. In Hellenistic art "to represent nature as it really is. In architecture, however, naturalism is not a term usually encountered; there is no stylistic equivalent to its use in art, and its philosophical meaning is only implied in relation to terms like 'natural' or 'naturalistic'. An architecture is only termed 'natural', and therefore is seen as subscribing to a kind of naturalism, it is this synergy of the self and the un self to produce naturalistic architecture that intrigues [32]. Chrysippus regarded bodies, surfaces, lines, places, the void and time as all being infinitely divisible. Chrysippus was negating the law of excluded middle with respect to the equal and unequal, and thus he may have anticipated an important principle of modern infinitesimal calculus, namely, the limit and the process of convergence towards a limit [33]. 8. ROMAN ERA http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 232 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil Roman philosophy focused on objective inquiry, asking unbiased questions that favor no particular outcome. It is often seen as humanity's first attempt to provide rational explanations for the workings of the world. Their use of logical analysis led to the rise of the scientific method. The scientific method is an approach to conducting research in which a problem is stated, data or pieces of information are gathered, a hypothesis or intelligent guess is made from these data, and this hypothesis is then tested through experiments [34]. Cicero says now carry your mind to the form and figure of human being or even of the other living creatures: you will discover that the body has no part added to its structure that is superfluous, and that its whole shape has the perfection of a work of art and not of accident. Cicero believes that the body-building connection finally is not one of analogy or metaphor but rather of identity: both the build building and living body are equally part of nature and must abide by nature's general rules of morphogenesis, while Seneca the Younger believes that architecture, like philosophy, showed the intellect at its highest. He thus used and criticized a classical authority and an authoritative classicist at one [35]. In architecture all of a buildings architectural elements, no matter their individual beauty, are used to draw the eye to appreciate a building in its entirety. Architecture is a leading idea in Plotinus's account of beauty for Plotinus the beauty of the sensuous realm is hardly the most important kind of beauty. Yet he has something valuable to say about it, and for Proclus mathematics and geometry are the means by which the motion of bodies can be applied toward the dialectical movement of understanding toward nous [36]. 9. MEDIVAL ERA The principles that underlie the medieval thinkers work are: The use of logic, dialectic, and analysis to discover the truth, known as ratio. Respect for the insights of ancient philosophers. The obligation to co-ordinate the insights of philosophy with theological teaching and revelation. Medieval philosophers provided significant contributions to aesthetic theory during the middle ages. Certain topics, such as proportion, light, and symbolism, played important roles in medieval aesthetics, and they will be given prominence in this article. Proportion was particularly important for architecture [37]. Boethius said that the idea of numbers seen as the origin and point of return of all things, that is to say, fundamentally, a certain idea of the universe based on the power of number. The form of the markers, square or circular, could vary with the time-period, as could their color. The majority of the numbers concerned are the plane numbers according to the theory of Boethius, but there is also, in each field, a number that is solid a pyramid to be precise, as well as Al-Kindi authored works on a number of important mathematical subjects, including arithmetic, geometry, the harmony of numbers, lines and multiplication with numbers, relative quantities, measuring proportion. In geometry he wrote on the theory of parallels [38][39]. Architecture in classification of sciencesnof al-Farabi is a language and style of philosophical works, and Peter Abelard saw what the analogy between the Music and architecture obviated any obligation to be faithful to surfaces, which in the case of the Temple would have been impossible, or to a specific plan, rather, it was essential to follow the ideal consonances of the Temple in shaping the interior spaces of the cathedral [40][41]. The writings of Robert Grossteste provide a basis for a model by which architectural geometries can be catechism for them in their intelligible geometrical structures. Robert Grosseteste, was interested in discovering the nature of light. The effects of light in architecture, and he frequently associated light with their theories of color, Albert the Great chose rather to use the Aristotelian concepts of matter and form to explain how all things combine color or, more generally, the resplendence of light, with proportion and so are http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 233 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. beautiful. The beautiful is the resplendence of a substantial that or accidental form over proportioned and bounded parts of matter. A well-proportioned, colored body provides an obvious example of beauty [42][43]. Roger Bacon attempts to explain the operation of the eye and combined an extra mission theory of vision with an intromission theory, that is, vision was the product of both an act of perception on the part of the perceiver, and the light emanating from the object to the eye, and Thomas Aquinas focused his comments mostly on the notion of beauty. Thomas’ definition of beauty is as follows: beauty is that which gives pleasure when seen [44][45]. For Gersonides the world was created by an architecture God. God produces the forms eternally through hid eternal act of self-intellection, these constitute the intelligible order of the universe. God is like an architect who design in his mind the ideal house for its inhabitants and then actually brings the house into being. The plan is eternal, its instantiation occurs at an instant while Nicholas of Cusa recognize the creative dimension of mental, mathematical, geometrical and conceptual structures of the human intellect. Cusa explicitly refers to the art of building. The concept of lineaments, independent power of the mind, which, is very different from the surmises of reason that are attached to perceptible material objects. Cusa argues that the original constructive principle of the human mind makes assimilations of forms as they are in and of themselves. For example, a geometrical circle conceived within the human mind is immutable and perfect, acting as a measure of truth for a materialized circle in a patterned floor, and Marsilio Ficino compare the architecture of the building to the design of forms in nature. Ficino proposed. (If anyone asked in what way the form of the body can be like the form and Reason of the Soul and Mind, let him consider, I ask, the building of the architect), expressing the core idea of Renaissance Humanism, that the human mind corresponds to the workings of nature [46][47][48]. 10. RENAISSANE ERA The renaissance represents a movement away from Christianity and medieval Scholasticism and towards Humanism, with an increasing focus on the temporal and personal over merely seeing this world as a gateway to the Christian afterlife. Renaissance art was driven by the new notion of "Humanism," a philosophy which had been the foundation for many of the achievements. Renaissance comment on architectures makes explicit the relationship between fiction and taste in architecture, which they believed was highly undesirable. Building was too important a matter in the lives and economies of people [49]. Petrus Ramus shows the splendour of geometry in its application because the architects, painters and sculptors of the 16th century emphasized that their art was based on drawing that is also on measurement. Ramus concern on proportionality and symmetry as with Vitruvius, and John Calvin is arguably the most significant architects of the Reformation. "If Luther sounded the trumpet for reform, Calvin orchestrated the score by which the Reformation became a part of Western civilization, while Giordano Bruno call the attribution of a new morality to the heavens, the universal architecture. Which will be completely achieved by means of his comprehensive philosophy [50][51][52]. 11. REASON ERA The Age of Reason saw a continuation of the move away from theology and faith-based arguments, and marks the shaking off of medieval approaches to philosophy. The advances in science, the growth of religious tolerance and the rise of philosophical liberalism also led to a revival in Political Philosophy in general.The most fundamental concept of theis era were faith in nature and belief in human progress. Nature was seen as a complex of interacting laws http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 234 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil governing the universe. The individual human being, as part of that system, was designed to act rationally [53]. Galileo believed that nature was inherently mathematical, that mathematics was the key to understanding the reality behind the appearance of natural phenomena. Galileo disproved harmonious proportion that derive from the perfect Forms of the divine Idea are universally applicable, he shows that, proportions necessary vary according to the size and material of natural bodies. There can be no doubt that this theory and this type of reasoning revolutionized architectural thinking and practice, while rational architects, following the philosophy of René Descartes emphasized geometric forms and ideal proportions. Descartes used an architectural metaphor for knowledge – To build a great tower needs very firm foundations, when Blaise Pascal’s Treatise on the Arithmetical Triangle described a convenient tabular presentation for binomial coefficients, now called Pascal's triangle. Pascal wrote a significant treatise on the subject of projective geometry, known as-Pascal's Theorem [54][55]. According to Pierre Nicole, reason, and pleasure, should be taken as the criterion of beauty. Nicole wrote, ( there is nothing so bad as to be to no one’s taste, and nothing so perfect as to be to everyone’s taste). Unlike in music there were no natural beauties in architecture dependent on mathematical harmony and that it was therefore up to man to establish rules. The beauty of architecture was this seen as independent of transcendental givens in a far more radical way that in literature or music, and Baruch Spinoza’s philosophy consists of generative concepts persistently expressing architectural and spatial connotations. Its social actors, and its associated ecology. God is not a craftsman or an architect. Baruch Spinoza refuses any form of negativity in the construction of an ethics of joy for which the body attempts to continuously compose harmonious relationships with its environment [56][57]. Samuel von Pufendorf drew an analogy to a building designed in disregard of the (Rules of Architecture) or which had suffered from (some great Fault) that had (been curd and made up after a strange and unseemly manner). The architecture was an important and essential part of the rituals. Issac Newton claimed that geometry is founded upon mechanic, whereas one would expect mechanics to be defined as an application of geometry to the science of motion [58][59]. 12. ENLIGHTENMENT ERA The Enlightenment advocated freedom, democracy and reason as the primary values of society. It started from the standpoint that men's minds should be freed from ignorance, from superstition and from the arbitrary powers of the State, in order to allow mankind to achieve progress and perfection. The period was marked by a further decline in the influence of the church, governmental consolidation and greater rights for the common people. Aesthetics flourishes in the period because of its strong affinities with the tendencies of the age. “Aesthetics” is derived from the Greek word for “senses”, because for Baumgarten a science of the beautiful would be a science of the sensible, a science of sensible cognition. Given the intimate connection between beauty and human sensibility [60]. Gottfried Leibniz is the geometrician who knows the best way to construct a problem, the architect who makes the best use of use means and his location. The criterion is so to speak an aesthetic one note in the sense of a radically different criteria from the moral, while Giambattista Vico proposed that the human imagination, not the circumstances of environment or innovations of technology, shaped culture, thought, and human institutions. Vico has lain dormant in architecture thinking. This was ironic, for Vico in his own day was “an architect’s philosophy [61]. Shaftesbury argues that beauty is a matter of harmonious proportion or “numbers.” The “beauties of the human soul,” then, are “the harmony and numbers of an inward kind”. Yet terms like “design” and “form” can be either nouns or verbs. That is, we can speak either of the form of an object or the act of forming the object. Anthony Ashley Cooper, Architecture is http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 235 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. seen as contributing substantially to taste, with the virtuoso judging and educating the artist and his work, and According to Samuel Clarke, the ideas of space and time are the two “first and most obvious simple Ideas that every man has in his mind”. Clarke believed that space is necessarily infinite because “to set bounds to space, is to suppose it bounded by something which itself takes up space” or else that “it is bounded by nothing, and then the idea of that nothing will still be space,” and both suppositions are contradictory [62]. The absolute beauty of architecture provides, for Hutcheson, further evidence that the basis of beauty is in unify amidst mrieoc And Francia Hutcheson makes it clear that architecture serves here merely to exemplify what is universal to all of the fine arts, when David Hume drew a sharp distinction between `relations of ideas' and 'matters of fact'. The first—exemplified by mathematics, and presumably also by its offspring, systems of proportion—were certain, and discoverable by pure thought. But they had no necessary relation to the external world: 'Though there never were a circle or a triangle in nature [63][64]. Alexander Baumgarten aesthetics came to mean the study of good and bad taste, and was related to the judgment of what was beautiful. Good taste was the ability to judge what was beautiful by intuition and not through analysis by the intellect. Baumgarten hoped to develop nevertheless a science of aesthetics, the deduction of principles of both natural and artistic beauty based on a sense of good taste, and Immanuel Kant believes he can show that aesthetic judgment is not fundamentally different from ordinary theoretical cognition of nature, and he believes he can show that aesthetic judgment has a deep similarity to moral judgment. For these two reasons, Kant claims he can demonstrate that the physical and moral universes – and the philosophies and forms of thought that present them – are not only compatible, but unified [65][66]. Moses Mendelssohn sets out from the assumption that the human spirit has learned to imitate beauty, “the self-empowered mistress of all our sentiments,” in works of art, while, as well Edmund Burke investigated some aspects of human perception that would become relevant to the discourse of art and architecture. Burke tries to isolate the psychological causes of emotions that produce the effects of the sublime and the beautiful. His new epistemology would draw a correspondence between the notion of taste and absolute judgment. Burke determine the sources of the sublime and the beautiful. For Burke, taste is a refined form of judgment that is initiated in sensory perception, while Thomas Jefferson wrote that “architecture is my delight, and putting up and pulling down, one of my favorite amusements”. As an architect Jefferson created structures of beauty and functionality [67][68][69]. 13. TEMPORAL LIMITS The fact in this subject lies in the difficulty of identifying the relevant case horizontally, i.e. identifying the case within a certain period of time. So, the study, in this approach, will depend on temporal survey, whereas, Spatial-temporal reasoning is the ability to visualize spatial patterns and mentally manipulate them over a time-ordered sequence of spatial transformations. This ability is important for generating and conceptualizing solutions to multistep problems that arise in areas such as architecture, engineering, science, mathematics and art. Table1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7 & 8. http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 236 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil Table 1: Illustrates the chronological survey of philosophers in the pre-Socratic era. 1-1 1-2 1-3 1-4 1-5 1-6 1-7 1-8 1-9 1-10 1-11 1-12 1-13 1-14 1-15 1-16 Total 1. Pre-Socratic Thales of Miletus. c. 624 – 546 BCE Pherecydes of Syros c. 620 - c. 550 BCE Anaximander of Miletus c. 610 – 546 BCE Anaximander of Miletus c. 610 – 546 BCE Pythagoras of Samos c.580 – c. 500 BCE Xenophanes of Colophon c. 570 – 480 BCE Epicharmus of Kos c. 530 – 450 BCE Heraclitus of Ephesus c. 535 – c. 475 BCE Parmenides of Elea c. 515 – 450 BCE Anaxagoras of Clazomenae c. 500 – 428 BCE Empedocles 492 - 432 BCE Zeno of Elea c. 490 – 430 BCE Protagoras of Abdera c. 481 – 420 BCE Antiphon 480 - 411 BCE Middle of the 5th century Hippias BCE Gorgias. c. 483 – 375 BCE 1- Pre-Socratic 5/16 31% It can be seen from (table 1) that the number of philosophers who talk about terms related in some way to the architecture in the pre-Socratic era is five philosophers out of 16, which means the percentage is 31%.The most words used by philosophers in Pre-Socratic era are Geometry, Number, Human body and Form. Table 2: Illustrates the chronological survey of philosophers in the Socratic era. 2-1 2-2 2-3 2-4 2-5 2-6 2-7 2-8 2-9 2-10 2-11 2-12 2-13 2-14 2-15 2-16 2. Socratic Socrates of Athens c. 470 – 399 BCE Critias of Athens c. 460 - 413 Prodicus of Ceos c. 465 BC – c. 395 BCE First half of the 5th century Leucippus of Miletus BCE Thrasymachus of Miletus c. 459 - c. 400 BCE Democritus of Abdera c. 450 – 370 BCE Diagoras of Melos c. 450 – 415 BCE Archelaus Melissus of Samos. Cratylus. Ion of Chios. Echecrates. Timaeus of Locri. Antisthenes c. 444 – 365 BCE Aristippus of Cyrene c. 440 – 366 BCE Alcidamas c. 435 – c. 350 BCE http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 237 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. 2-17 2-18 2-19 2-20 2-21 2-22 2-23 2-24 2-25 2-26 Total Lycophron c. 430 – c. 350 BCE Diogenes of Apollonia c. 425 BCE – c 350 BCE Hippo c. 425 – c 350 BCE Xenophon c. 427 – 355 BCE Plato c. 427 – 347 BCE Speusippus c. 408 – 339 BCE Eudoxus of Cnidus c. 408 – 355 BCE Diogenes of Sinope c. 399 – 323 BCE Xenocrates c. 396 – 314 BCE Aristotle c. 384 – 322 BCE 2- Socratic (classic) 10/26 38% It can be seen from (table 2) that the number of philosophers who talk about terms related in some way to the architecture in the Socratic (Classic) era is ten philosophers out of 26, which means the percentage is 38%. The most words used by philosophers in Socratic (Classic) era are Nature, Form, Geometry, Proportion, Beauty and Number. Table 3: Illustrates the chronological survey of philosophers in the Hellenistic era. 3-1 3-2 3-3 3-4 3-5 3-6 3-7 3-8 Total 3. Hellenistic Theophrastus c. 371 BCE–c. 287 BCE Pyrrho of Elis c. 360 – 270 BCE Strato of Lampsacus c. 340 BCE–c. 268 BCE Epicurus c. 341 – 270 BCE Zeno of Citium c. 333 – 264 BCE Timon c. 320 – 230 BCE Chrysippus of Soli c. 280 – 207 BCE Carneades c. 214 – 129 BCE 3- Hellenistic 1/8 13% It can be seen from (table 3) that the number of philosophers who talk about terms related in some way to the architecture in the Hellenistic era is one philosopher out of 8, which means the percentage is 13%. The most words used by philosophers in Hellenistic era are Line, Surface, Body, and Number. Table 4: Illustrates the chronological survey of philosophers in the Romanic era. 4-1 4-2 4-3 4-4 4-5 4-6 4-7 4-8 4. Romanic Lucretius c. 99 – 55 BCE Cicero c. 106 BCE – 43 BCE Philo c. 20 BCE – 40 CE Seneca the Younger c. 4 BCE – 65 CE Epictetus c. 55 – 135 Marcus Aurelius 121–180 during the 2nd and possibly Sextus Empiricus the 3rd centuries CE Plotinus c. 205 – 270 http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 238 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil 4-9 4-10 4-11 4-12 Total Porphyry Iamblichus of Syria Augustine of Hippo Proclus 4- Romanic 5/12 c. 232 – 304 c. 245 – 325 c. 354 – 430 c. 412 – 485 42% It can be seen from (table 4) that the number of philosophers who talk about terms related in some way to the architecture in the Romanic era is five philosopher out of 12, which means the percentage is 42%. The most words used by philosophers in Hellenistic era are Form of human being, Art, Beauty, Geometry and Mathematic. Table 5: Illustrates the chronological survey of philosophers in the Medievalism era. 5-1 5-2 5-3 5-4 5-5 5-6 5-7 5-8 5-9 5-10 5-11 5-12 5-13 5-14 5-15 5-16 5-17 5-18 5-19 5-20 5-21 5-22 5-23 5-24 5-25 5-26 5-27 5-28 5-29 5-30 5-31 5-32 5-33 5. Medievalism Boethius c. 480–524 John Philoponus c. 490–570 Al-Kindi c. 801 – 873 John the Scot c. 815 – 877 al-Faràbi c. 870 – 950 Saadia Gaon c. 882 – 942 al-Razi c. 865 – 925 Ibn Sina c. 980 – 1037 Ibn Gabirol c. 1021–1058 Anselm c. 1034–1109 al-Ghazali c. 1058–1111 Peter Abelard c. 1079–1142 Abraham ibn Daud c. 1110–1180 Peter Lombard c. 1100–1160 Averroes (Ibn Rushd) c. 1126- 1198 Maimonides c. 1135–1204 St Francis of Assisi c. 1182–1226 Robert Grosseteste c. 1175–1253 Albert the Great c. 1193–1280 Roger Bacon c. 1214–1294 Thomas Aquinas c. 1221–1274 Bonaventure c. 1225–1274 Siger c. 1240 – c. 1280 Boetius of Dacia. Ramon Llull c. 1232–1315 Meister Eckhart c. 1260–1328 Duns Scotus c. 1266–1308 Marsilius of Padua c. 1270–1342 William of Ockham c. 1288–1348 Gersonides c. 1288–1344 Jean Buridan c. 1300–1358 John Wycliffe c. 1320–1384 Nicole Oresme c. 1320-5 – 1382 http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 239 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. 5-34 5-35 5-36 5-37 5-38 Total c. 1340 – c. 1411 1401–1464 1407–1457 1433-1499 1463–1494 13/38 34% Hasdai Crescas Nicholas of Cusa Lorenzo Valla Marsilio Ficino Pico della Mirandola 5- Medievalism It can be seen from (table 5) that the number of philosophers who talk about terms related in some way to the architecture in the Medievalism era is thirteen philosopher out of 38, which means the percentage is 34%. The most words used by philosophers in Medievalism era are Number, Geometry, Music, Color, Nature, Perception, Beauty (Pleasure), Mathematic, Architect, Order and Design. Table 6: Illustrates the chronological survey of philosophers in the Renaissance era. 6-1 6-2 6-3 6-4 6-5 6-6 6-7 6-8 6-9 6-10 Total 6. Renaissance Desiderius Erasmus Niccolò Machiavelli Sir Thomas More Martin Luther Petrus Ramus John Calvin Michel de Montaigne Pierre Charron Giordano Bruno Francisco Suarez 6- Renaissance 4/10 1466–1536 1469–1527 1478–1535 1483–1546 1515–1572 1509–1564 1533–1592 1541–1603 1548–1600 1548–1617 40% It can be seen from (table 6) that the number of philosophers who talk about terms related in some way to the architecture in the Renaissance era is four philosopher out of 10, which means the percentage is 40%. The most words used by philosophers in Medievalism era are Building, Architecture, Geometry, Measure, and Proportion. Table 7: Illustrates the chronological survey of philosophers in the Reason era. 7-1 7-2 7-3 7-4 7-5 7-6 7-7 7-8 7-9 7-10 7-11 7-12 7. Reason Herbert of Cherbury. Francis Bacon Galileo Galilei Hugo Grotius Marin Mersenne Robert Filmer Pierre Gassendi René Descartes Baltasar Gracián Thomas Hobbes Antoine Arnauld Henry More http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 240 1561–1626 1564–1642 1583–1645 1588–1648 1588–1653 1592–1655 1596–1650 1601–1658 1588–1679 1612–1694 1614–1687 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil 7-13 7-14 7-15 7-16 7-17 7-18 7-19 7-20 7-21 7-22 7-23 7-24 7-25 7-26 7-27 7-28 7-29 7-30 7-31 7-32 Total Jacques Rohault. Ralph Cudworth Blaise Pascal Margaret Cavendish Arnold Geulincx Pierre Nicole Geraud Cordemoy Robert Boyle Anne Conway, Richard Cumberland Baruch Spinoza Samuel von Pufendorf John Locke Joseph Glanvill Nicolas Malebranche Isaac Newton Simon Foucher Pierre Bayle Damaris Masham John Toland 7- Reason 1617–1672 1617–1688 1623–1662 1623–1673 1624–1669 (1625–1695) 1626-1684 1627–1691 1631–1679 1631–1718 1632–1677 1632–1694 1632–1704 1636–1680 1638–1715 1643–1727 1644–1696 1647–1706 1659–1708 1670–1722 10/32 31% It can be seen from (table 7) that the number of philosophers who talk about terms related in some way to the architecture in the Reason era is ten philosopher out of 32, which means the percentage is 31%. The most words used by philosophers in Reason era are Fashion, Architecture, Mathematic, Beauty, Aesthetic, Craftsman, and Architect. Table 8: Illustrates the chronological survey of philosophers in the Enlightenment era. 8-1 8-2 8-3 8-4 8-5 8-6 8-7 8-8 8-9 8-10 8-11 8-12 8-13 8-14 8-15 8-16 8-17 8. Enlightenment Gottfried Leibniz John Norris Jean Meslier Giambattista Vico Bernard Mandeville Anthony Ashley-Cooper Samuel Clarke Catherine Cockburn Christian Wolff George Berkeley Charles de Secondat Joseph Butler Francis Hutcheson John Gay David Hartley Julien La Mettrie Voltaire http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 241 1646–1716 1657–1711 1664-1729 1668–1744 1670–1733 1671–1713 1675–1729 1679–1749 1679–1754 1685–1753 1689–1755 1692–1752 1694–1746 1699–1745 1705–1757 1709–1751 1694–1778 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. 8-18 8-19 8-20 8-21 8-22 8-23 8-24 8-25 8-26 8-27 8-28 8-29 8-30 8-31 8-32 8-33 8-34 8-35 8-36 8-37 8-38 8-39 8-40 8-41 Total Thomas Reid David Hume Jean-Jacques Rousseau Denis Diderot Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten Claude Adrien Helvétius Etienne de Condillac Jean d'Alembert Baron d'Holbach Adam Smith Richard Price Immanuel Kant Moses Mendelssohn Gotthold Ephraim Lessing Edmund Burke William Paley Thomas Jefferson Jeremy Bentham Sylvain Maréchal Dugald Stewart William Godwin Mary Wollstonecraft Friedrich Schiller Johann Gottlieb Fichte 8- Enlightenment 15/41 1710–1796 1711–1776 1712–1778 1713–1784 1714-1762 1715–1771 1715-1780 1717–1783 1723–1789 1723–1790 1723–1791 1724–1804 1729–1786 1729–1781 1729–1797 1743–1805 1743–1826 1748–1832 1750–1803 1753–1828 1756–1836 1759–1797 1759–1805 1762–1814 37% It can be seen from (table 8) that the number of philosophers who talk about terms related in some way to the architecture in the Enlightenment era is fifteen philosopher out of 41, which means the percentage is 37%. The most words used by philosophers in Enlightenment era are Geometry, Aesthetic, Harmony, Proportion, Number, Form, Mathematic and art. 14 RESULTS The number of philosophers is different in each era and they are between 8 philosophers in the Hellenistic era to the 41 philosophers in the Enlightenment era, and the number of philosophers who talk about term related to architecture is also different and they are from 1 philosopher in the Hellenistic era to the 15 philosophers in the Enlightenment era. Following are the number and percentage of philosophers talked about terms related to architecture in each era separately out of the number of philosophers in each era. Pre-Socratic 5/16 31% Socratic (classic) 10/26 38% Hellenistic 1/8 13% Romanic 5/12 42% Medievalism 13/38 34% Renaissance 4/10 40% Reason 10/32 31% http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 242 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil Enlightenment 15/41 37% 45% 40% 35% 30% 25% 20% 15% 10% 5% 0% Figure 9: Percentage of philosophers who talk about term related to architecture in each era. Number of philosophers who talked about terms related to Architecture in all eras is 63 philosophers, they are divided in all era. The following are the numbers and percentage of philosophers who talk about terms related to architecture in each era out of total number of the philosopher only who talked about architecture. Pre-Socratic 5/63 7.9 % Socratic (classic) 10/63 15.9% Hellenistic 1/63 1.6% Romanic 5/63 7.9 % Medievalism 13/63 20.6% Renaissance 4/63 6.4% Reason 10/63 15.9% Enlightenment 15/63 23.8% Pre-Socratic 8% 24% Socratic 16% 2% 8% 16% Hellenistic Romanic Medievalism Renaissance 6% 20% Reason Figure 10: The percentage of philosophers who talk about term related to architecture in all era together. 15. CONCLUSIONS The research concludes that whenever the philosophers interested in architectural terms is increase the quality of architecture is also increased in that era, where it is noted that it reached the highest level in the Roman era, which represents the base of classical architecture. The percentage of philosophers interested in architecture begins in the Pre-Socratic era which is 8% http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 243 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. and increased to reach to the peak in the Enlightenment era which is 23%, concluded from this that philosophers interest in architecture is increasing with time.There is a lot of terms related to architecture repeated by philosophers such as proportion, aesthetic and geometry in all eras but the most repeated term is geometry. Geometry is the term which related philosophy to architecture. Eras 1- Pre-Socratic: 2- Socratic (classic): 3- Hellenistic: 4- Romanic: 5- Medievalism: 6- Renaissance: 7- Reason: 8- Enlightenment: Terms used by philosophers Geometry Human body Aesthetic Geometry Line Surface Aesthetic Geometry Geometry Aesthetic Architecture Geometry Aesthetic Architecture Geometry Aesthetic Form Proportion Number Form Architect Proportion Mathematic Proportion So, the process of proving the philosophical term of architecture is not merely a technical process, but a dialectical answer to it. Where philosophy leads to knowledge and knowledge of the higher arts, including architecture, because philosophy is the entrance to knowledge about what. It is the basis of all knowledge and science. Therefore, architecture as a Semitic shroud is not something autonomous, whatever the architect tried to do. The existence of the philosophical term consciously or unconsciously ensures the presence of the philosopher in architectural work. 16 REFERENCES [1] [2] [3] [4] [5] [6] [7] [8] [9] [10] [11] [12] Suvakovic, M., Architecture and philosophy. Relations, potentialities and critical points, Serbian Architectural Journal 2012. Ahmed, S., Philosophy of Architecture and Architecture as Philosophy: The Potentialities in Accordance to Critical Sermon, Architecture, Engineering and Construction, 83, 2016. Branko, Mitrovic, Philosophy for Architect, Princeton Architectural Press, 2011. Mitias, Michael H., Philosophy and Architecture, Brill/Rodop, 1994. Hendrix, John Shannon, Platonic Architectonics: Platonic Philosophies & the Visual Arts, Peter Lang Gmbh, Internationaler Verlag Der Wissenschaften, 2004. Hendrix, John Shannon, Architectural Forms and Philosophical Structures, Peter Lang Gmbh, Internationaler Verlag Der Wissenschaften, 2003. Teichmann, Jenny & Evans, Katherine C., Philosophy: A Beginner's Guide. Blackwell Publishing, Teichmann& Evans, p.1, 1999. Grayling, A.C., Philosophy 1: A Guide through the Subject, Oxford University Press, p.2, 1998. Adler, Mortimer J., How to think about the Great Ideas: From the Great Books of Western Civilization, Chicago, Ill.: Open Court, p.44, 2000. Greco, John., The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism (1st ed.), Oxford University Press, p.44, 2011. Al-Jarjani, Book of Definitions, Author: Ali bin Mohammed bin Ali Al-Zain Al-Sharif AlJarjani (deceased: 816 e).Investigator: A group of scientists controlled and corrected by the publisher. Publisher: Dar Al Kuttab Al-Salloumiya Beirut - Lebanon.Edition: First 1403 AH-1983AD. Oxford English Dictionary. http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 244 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil [13] [14] [15] [16] [17] [18] [19] [20] [21] [22] [23] [24] [25] [26] [27] [28] [29] [30] [31] [32] [33] [34] [35] [36] [37] [38] Oxford University Press. Oxford University Press, 2018. ]Durmus,S., Considering the Relationship between Architecture and Philosophy: Toyo Ito’s Conceptual Architecture. World Academy of Science, Engineering and Technology, International Journal of Civil, Environmental, Structural, Construction and Architectural Engineering, 10, p. 925-932, 2016. Hendrix, J., Architectural forms and philosophical structures, 2003. August, K. & Schrijver, L. Architecture Thinking in a ‘Post-truth Era’: Recalibrations through analytic philosophy. Footprint, 1-10. 2017. rewniak, T. Philosophy of Architecture and Architecttonics of Philosophy. Perker, Z. The Analysis of the Relationship between Architecture and Philosophy Assuming the Constructions of Renaissance 17th and 18th Century. Engineering Sciences, 4, 589-600. 2009. Freely, J. Before Galileo: The Birth of Modern Science in Medieval Europe. 2012. Boyer. Ionia and the Pythagoreans. 1991. Hahn, R. Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Philosophy. State university of New York. 2001. Freeman, K. Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic philosophers, A Complete Translation of the Fragments in Diels, Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, HUP. 1948. Kahn, C. The Art and Thought of Heraclitus: Fragments with Translation and Commentary. London: Cambridge University Press. 1979. Guthrie, W. The Sophists. New York: Cambridge University Press. 1977. Harries, K. Philosophy and the Task of Architecture. Journal of Architectural Education 40 (2). 1987. Bellori, G. & Wohl, H. The Lives of the Modern Painters, Sculptors and Architects. Cambridge University Press. p61. 2005. Tuckey, T. Plato's "Charmides": Text and Commentary. Cambridge University Press. p31. 1951. Padovan, R. Proportion: Science, Philosophy, Architecture. Taylor & Francis. p72. 1999. Dillon, John. the Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy (347-274 BC). Oxford Scholarship Online. p74. 2003. Kline, M. Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times. Oxford University Press. p48-50. 1972. Ogle, W. On the Parts of Animals, Aristotle 350 BC,Book I. Translated by William Ogle, Prepared by Robert Robbins, HTML Edition: Electronic Scholarly Publishing. p4. 2001. Mastin, L. The basics of philosophy, a huge subject broken down into manageable chunks. Luke Mastin personal Website. 2008. Plutarch, M. & Gregorius N. De Communibus Notitiis, 1079F. Tufts University, De Communibus Notitiis. 2007. Gale, T. Greco-Roman Religion and Philosophy. World Religions Reference Library. p33. 2007. Pellizzi, F. Anthropology and Aesthetics. Permanent/Impermanent, Edited, Harvard University Press, 48: Autumn. p130. 2005. Gracia, J. & Noone, T. A Companion to Philosophy in the middle Ages. Oxford: WilyBlackwell. p112. 2003. Kaylor, N. & Phillips, P. A Companion to Boethius in the Middle Ages. BRILL.VN, Leiden, the Netherlands. p158. 2012. Al-Kindi, A. Retrieved -01-12. p57. 2007 http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 245 editor@iaeme.com Architectural Philosophical Term from Pre-Socratic to Enlightenment. [39] [40] [41] [42] [43] [44] [45] [46] [47] [48] [49] [50] [51] [52] [53] [54] [55] [56] [57] [58] [59] [60] [61] [62] Daiber, H. Bibliography of Islamic Philosophy: Alphabetical list of publications. Volume 1edited, Brill. Leiden. Boston. Koln. p57. 1999. McClung,W. The Architecture of Paradise: Survivals of Eden and Jerusalem. University of California Press. p69. 1983. Glick, T. Medieval Science, Technology, and Medicine: An Encyclopedia. Routledge, Tylor & Francis Group, New York. p375. 2005. Davies, S, Higgins, K. Hopkins, R. Stecker, R. & Cooper, D. Companion to Aesthetics. Second edition, Blackwell Publishing Ltd. p23. 2009. Hendrix, J. Architecture as Cosmology: Lincoln Cathedral and English Gothic Architecture. Peter Lng Publishing, Inc., New York. p121. 2011. Aquinas, T. The Summa Theologica. Translated by Westminster: Christian Classics. p34. 1981. Glasner, R. Gersonides: A Portrait of a Fourteenth-century Philosopher-scientist. Oxford Scholarship Online. p106. 2015. Bandyopadhyay, S. Lomholt, J. Temple, N. & Tobe, R. The Humanities in Architectural Design: A Contemporary and Historical perspective. Taylor & Francis. p141. 2010 Hendrix, J. Architecture as Cosmology: Lincoln Cathedral and English Gothic Architecture. Peter Lng Publishing, Inc., New York. p41. 2011. Mastin, L. The basics of philosophy, a huge subject broken down into manageable chunks. Luke Mastin personal Website. 2008. Hooykaas, R. Humanities, Mechanics and Painting (Petrus Ramus; Francisco de Holanda). UC Biblioteca Geral 1. p23. 1991. Perry, D. God’s Offer of Eternal Salvation and why Arminianism or Calvinism do not conform to Gods word. First edition design publishing, Inc. p5. 2016. Hill, C. The new light of Europe: Giordano Bruno and the modern age. Geoffrey Neal Cassady McTighe. p124. 2007. Mastin, Luke. The basics of philosophy, a huge subject broken down into manageable chunks. Luke Mastin personal Website. p87. 2008. Lefaivre, L. & Tzonis, A. The Emergence of Modern Architecture: A Documentary History, from 1000 to 1810. Routledge. Taylor & Francis Group, New York. p341. 2003. Morello, E. & Piga, B. Envisioning Architecture: Design, Evaluation, Communication. p290. 2013. Perrault, C. Ordonnance for the Five Kinds of Columns after the Method of the Ancients. The History of Art and the Humanities. p32. 1993. Lambert, L. Arakawa + Madeline Gins. The Funambulist Pamphlets: Vol. 08. Punctum Books, New York. p7. 2014. Claus, L. Law's Evolution and Human Understanding. Oxford Scholarship Online. p230. 2012. Morrison, T. Isaac Newton's Temple of Solomon and his Reconstruction of Sacred Architecture. Springer, Basel. p103. 2011. Mastin, Luke: The basics of philosophy, a huge subject broken down into manageable chunks. Luke Mastin personal Website. p99. 2008. Kunze, D. The Big Architectural Adventure of Giambattista Vico. Alexandrine PressKunze, p59. 2005. Schmidt, F. Passion and Control: Dutch Architectural Culture of the Eighteenth Century. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd. p212. 2015. Kivy, P. The Seventh Sense: Francis Hutcheson and Eighteenth-Century British Aesthetics. Oxford Scholarship Online. p104. 2003. http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 246 editor@iaeme.com Kadhim Fathel Khalil [63] [64] [65] [66] [67] [68] Padovan, R. Proportion: Science, Philosophy, and Architecture. Taylor & Francis. p7. 1999. Frascari, M. Eleven Exercises in the Art of Architectural Drawing: Slow Food for the Architect's Imagination. Taylor & Francis. p178. 2011. Budd, M. The Pure Judgement of Taste as an Aesthetic Reflective Judgement. British Journal of Aesthetics, 41. p247-260. 2001. Bamberger, F. Philosophical Writings. Berlin: Voß, 1761. p172. 1938. Pelletier, L. Architecture in Words: Theatre, Language and the Sensuous Space of Architecture. Routledge. Taylor & Francis Group, New York. p138. 2006. Smith, M. A Winter in Washington; Or, Memoirs of the Seymour Family. E.Bliss and E.White, New York. p261.1824. http://www.iaeme.com/IJCIET/index.asp 247 editor@iaeme.com