“The equilibrium between advancing technologies and the enthusiasm of unpredictable human thoughts.” SID: 470371455 Tutor: Charlotte Tutorial: 12pm-1pm Introduction: This essay attempts to investigate the idea of whether there could be a perfect equilibrium between advancing technologies and the enthusiasm of unpredictable human thoughts, indeed, the tolerance of each other. Under the influence of industrial revolution starting from the nineteenth century, later the scientific revolution, today the artificial intelligence, the society is almost overthrown by the concept of enlightenment thinking. It pumps us to think of whether there is any place left for the traditional method of good old-fashion empiricism. On the appearance, technology and human empathy run counter to each other; indeed, the relationship between the two has never been simple. The essay aims to clarify on several grounds and raise awareness of things that technicality has left behind with the analysis of several buildings. The first argument is related to the origin and the start point of enlightenment concerning Plato’s Republic. Then discuss the relationship between exact science and empiricism. Also, the necessity of technological rules and its effect on the sublime. Finally, the interaction between actual and virtual, clearness and obscurity. Section 1: Gloom-Enlightenment and metaphysics The idea of enlightenment and metaphysics instead of confronting each other are both coming from the same root with distinct status. Plato has illustrated the process of turning away from stereotypes to archetypes in his allegory of the cave.1 He has 1 Francis Macdonald Cornford, The Republic of Plato, (Oxford University Press, New York, 1970), 233 demonstrated that there is a great difficulty to undertake that transformation. When suddenly come out of the cave, the eyes are first blind, and then slowly adjust to the light. Plato suggests that if a person could be free from worldly concerns, the soul would turn around towards true reality. In Plato’s last writings he expressed the longing of all demythologizing, and that number became enlightenment’s canon.2 However, it does not necessarily suggest that the program of coming out of the cave is due to enlightenment thinking at all. The knowledge gained by the process of withdrawing the soul from the weight charged with affinity to the moral world3 is not necessarily the knowledge of technologies and science. It is also culture based and human based. Thinking opposite to Plato, could the reality and truth be a form that engendered from that shadow cased on the well. It could be that human first has a thought which generated from himself, then trying to organize mediums to build the physical object from that thought. Later the product of thought turns into reality. This thought that science could not prove has probably become metaphysics. This argument is supported by ‘The concept of Enlightenment’.4 In the book mythology has regarded as an endless process of enlightenment, and that every definite 2 Max Horkheimer, and Adorno Theodor W. "The concept of Enlightenment," in Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 10 3 Francis Macdonald Cornford, The Republic of Plato, (Oxford University Press, New York, 1970), 233 4 Max Horkheimer, and Adorno Theodor W. "The concept of Enlightenment," in Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 7 theoretical view is subjected to the annihilating criticism that it is only a belief until enlightenment itself have been reduced to animistic magic.5 They criticized that in progress towards modern science human beings have discarded meaning, the concept of things is replaced by a formula that could be explained by simple causation, by rules and probability. Section 2: Gleam-Exact science, human science and Empiricism-as a counter to Enlightenment rationality, in which confusion, tumult and general unrest dominate: Notre Dame du Haut As Foucault suggests that modern episteme should be represented by three dimensions which include deductive science which is mathematical and physical science, empirical science which is the science of language, life and production and distribution of wealth, lastly, philosophical reflection.6 Human science which relates to psychology and sociology7, is an exception or even an internal threat to the modern episteme. However, it is a simple fact that man should have become the object of science which is in the order of knowledge. In reality, what amounts to an empiricist or cognitive architecture is vague.8 One piece of architecture that could best express that idea of mentality is the Notre Dame du Haut 5 Ibid. Michel Foucault, “Chapter 10 The Human Sciences” in The Order of Things (New York: Pantheon Books, 1970), 347 7 Ibid., 348 8 Javier Simonpietri, Aspects of an Empiricist Cognitive Architecture: An Initial Approximation to the Functional Organization of Minds and the Development of Mental Representations. July 2007 6 in Ronchamp by Le Corbusier.9 Due to the inability to categorize the building, it is covered with mysteriousness. It functions as a Catholic church within a religious site of pilgrimage. The space created is pure without any old-tedious ornamentations and visual noise. The purpose set by the designer is to make it reflective and meditative. Therefore, it is all about the sensations. The white wall and various light openings excite the highest potential of inner thought. It gets rid of the outside world, with the purpose to gain knowledge and self-cognitions. The roof although block the sky, the curved shape extends up towards heaven. The majority of chapels and churches seem to drag us back into a cave in order to clarify the soul and gain knowledge, compare to Plato’s allegory of the cave. Another example is the Bruder Klaus Chapel.10 It is proof that the process of obtaining knowledge as Plato described could be reversible. The building’s complexity in style and form is not the same as the complexity that the technological formulation could produce, because if rationalized, it is only a composition of simple shapes. The roof no doubt has said to be a mimicry of an airplane wing and used aerodynamic science as the only elements in the building that has influenced by the mechanism. Undeniably, science and technology are the indispensable part 9 Andrew Kroll, AD Classics: Ronchamp/Le Corbusier. Arch Daily, 3 November 2010. Accessed from: https://www.archdaily.com/84988/ad-classics-ronchamp-lecorbusier# 10 Megan Sveiven, Bruder Klaus Field Chapel/Peter Zumthor, Archi Daily, 26 January 2011. Accessed from: https://www.archdaily.com/106352/bruder-klaus-field-chapelpeter-zumthor of the architecture. However, as a tool, it is unlikely that mathematics could constitute human sciences in its particular positivity, as Foucault argues, even if it did, it would create a superficial counter-effect.11 Michel Foucault, “Chapter 10 The Human Sciences” in The Order of Things (New York: Pantheon Books, 1970), 351 11 (Notre Dame du Haut in Ronchamp by Le Corbusier) Section 3: Sublime- Clearness and obscurity, technical rules and sublime: Bruder Klaus Chapel It is a mere delusion in attempting to reduce sublime to technical rules. “The Sublime is born in a man, and not to be acquired by instruction.” On the contrary, a man only learns from ruled directions while giving up on his waywardness. Section 4: Fragment-Actual and virtual-ambiguityunfinished-reticence-real-potentiality-mind as decentralized functional web: Teshima Art Museum,21st Century Museum ‘law is outside itself, and that sovereignty has the legitimate power to suspend the law.’12 It somehow can be interpreted as technical rules can be suspended by humanity in the same way. 12 Giorgio Agamben, “The Messiah and the Sovereign”, 161 Man’s intangible thoughts do not need to actualize itself either, based on its indivisible nature with rules already exists. Similar to the relationship between actual and virtual. Conclusion Although there are tensions between the innovation of technology and human empathy, they are inseparable to each other and always have been and will be existing simultaneously. Annotated Bibliography 1. Cornford, Francis. “The Republic of Plato” (Oxford University Press, New York, 1970): 227-235 In the allegory of the cave, Plato argues that every man has the potential to possess the power of learning the truth. We each have the organ to see but what various is that some of us have been dragged and turned away by the changing world. Thus, the soul has been bent downwards by weight charged with affinity to this moral world.13 He suggests that if a person could be free from worldly concerns, the soul would turn around towards true reality. He also raised the argument that a state can never be properly governed either by the uneducated who know nothing of truth or by men who with all his mind pursuing culture. 14 The same rule could be 13 Francis Macdonald Cornford, The Republic of Plato, (Oxford University Press, New York, 1970), 233 14 Ibid. interpreted in light of architecture. The designers need to be educated to climb the ascent to the vision of truth, while must not become insist on its heights and refuse to come down again to the ‘prisoners’. Plato’s theory provides a ground towards the need for the balance between illusion and reality, with a particular emphasis on the importance of knowledge. Word Count: 194 2. Foucault, Michel. “Chapter 10 The Human Sciences” in The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. New York: Pantheon Books, 1970: 344-366 Foucault in his book has shown his concern that human sciences are facing a difficulty, as to their precariousness, uncertainty, approximation and imperfection as sciences, their dangerous familiarity with philosophy, their reliance upon other domains of knowledge.15 He emphasised here the importance of knowing mathematics as a tool to practise formalizations of human science. Stating it as the clearest, the most untroubled and transparent way that human sciences may maintain.16 He has provided evidence including Fechner and Condorcet who are able to find the probability of emotion.17 It leads to the question that if this idea could be taken to the extreme, whether all things derived from empirical practices could have its potential to be formalized by mathematics. However, he then discussed on the counter side given that it is unlikely that mathematics could constitute human sciences in its Michel Foucault, “Chapter 10 The Human Sciences” in The Order of Things (New York: Pantheon Books, 1970), 348 16 Ibid., 351 17 Ibid., 349 15 particular positivity.18 His demonstration of human science and exact science combine with the phrase ‘art without science is noting’ shows perplexing complementation between regulation and the things that cannot possibly be regulated. Unlike Plato, Foucault’s overall arguments seem to lean toward the unique nature of human knowledge. Word Count: 192 3. Horkheimer, Max and Theodor W. Adorno. "The concept of Enlightenment," in Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Translated by Edmund Jephcott. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002: 1-34. The authors regard the Enlightenment’s program as a disenchantment of the world and aim to dispel myths with knowledge. Confusingly enough a paradox has been raised that all myth were themselves the products of enlightenment.19 They expressed their concern that even the denial of God itself, falls under the same judgment as metaphysics.20 They seem to take the view that mythology is an endless process of enlightenment, and that every definite theoretical view is subjected to the annihilating criticism that it is only a belief until enlightenment itself have been reduced to animistic magic.21 18 Ibid., 351 Max Horkheimer, and Adorno Theodor W. "The concept of Enlightenment," in Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 5 20 Ibid., 19 21 Ibid., 7 19 They have taken a criticized view and argued that Enlightenment pushed aside the classical demand to think thinking,22 instead, thought could be reified as an autonomous process under enlightenment, so that the machine can finally replace it. The mathematical procedure became a kind of ritual of thought, it made thought into a thing, a tool. It leads itself into a similar position as totalitarian, and bourgeois where everything is ruled by equivalence.23 Overall, they tend to support the view that scientific knowledge has not always driven us forward by itself but interdependent with myth. Word Count: 199 4. Kant, Immanuel. “what is Enlightenment”, 1784 Kant has interpreted enlightenment as a man’s release from his self-incurred tutelage, thus, it is a process of developing one’s own reasoning instead of using what has been told by others. The hesitation to discover truth has been timid and frightened by the high possibility of failure. He states that some of us have been limited by everlasting tutelages such as statutes, formulas also misemployment.24 However, without those regulations and limits, one could fail over the narrowest ditch as he is not accustomed to that kind of free motion. He argues that there is a public tendency of incitement by guardians who are capable of some enlightenment, and the effect is harmful as it could result in implanting 22 Ibid., 19 Max Horkheimer, and Adorno Theodor W. "The concept of Enlightenment," in Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 4 24 Immanuel Kant, “what is Enlightenment”, 1784, 1 23 prejudices.25 In his theory, the public can only attain enlightenment slowly by themselves. Unlike the totalitarian nature of enlightenment mentioned by Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor, Kant has seen the process of enlightenment more as anti-despotism and encourages the masses to argue about things, figuring out things to get rid of their restrictions on freedom. Word Count: 182 5. Longinus, On the Sublime. Translated by G. M. A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company Inc., 1991: Sections II Longinus holds a dissenting position on the question of whether any art can teach sublimity in writing. The general view suggests that there is mere delusion in attempting to reduce sublime to technical rules. It says: “The Sublime is born in a man, and not to be acquired by instruction.”26 It is the vigorous product of nature which will be weakened when robbed their flesh and blood by frigid technicalities. Longinus gives counter arguments that nature although detesting all restraint is reluctant to show its utterly wayward and reckless. Virtually all principles are derived from nature and have been practiced and experienced in the province of the scientific method.27 Longinus went further concerns about the danger of having great passion without control of reason. Finally, he has come into a conclusion that could be applied to architecture: that a creator can only learn from art when he is to abandon himself to the 25 Ibid., 2 Longinus, On the Sublime (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company Inc., 1991), Section II 27 Ibid. 26 direction of his genius. He seems to suggest that we will only learn from ruled directions while giving up on our waywardness. Word Count: 187 6. Burke, Edmund. A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful. London: R & J Dodsley, 1757. Part I Section VII, Of the Sublime; Section III, Obscurity; Section IV, Of the Difference between Clearness and Obscurity with Regard to the Passions. Burke has suggested that sublime is delightful due to our passion for self-preservation.28 On the difference between clearness and obscurity concerning the passions, Burke points out that one is to make an idea clear, and another affecting the imagination. He suggests that the most lively and spirited description would give rise a very obscure and imperfect idea of an object. It is in the creator’s discretion to raise the degree of emotion. He argues that in fact, a great clearness helps but do little on the passions as it is the enemy to all enthusiasms.29 He tends to support that obscurity has a more general and powerful dominion over passions, and that obscure 28 Edmund Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful (London: R & J Dodsley, 1757). Part I Section VII, “Of the Sublime”, 14 29 Burke, Part 2 Section IV, “the Difference between Clearness and Obscurity with Regard to the Passions”, 46 should be more affecting than the clear.30 Applying his theory that the obscure of what is unpredictable perhaps could create the most affecting passion. Word Count: 196 7. Agamben, Giorgio. “The Messiah and the Sovereign” in Potentialities: Collective Essay in Philosophy, edited by Daniel Heller-Roazen. California: Stanford University Press, 1999: 160 As to the relation between imagination and rule, Agamben cited Warburg’s teaching stating that a theory of knowledge is in truth simply disguised metaphysics. It once again supports the view given by Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor, that enlightenment is deception.31 On potentiality, Agamben thinks that the concept of potentiality has never ceased to function in life and humanity. He cites the second book of Aristotle’s De anima, suggesting that in the absence of external objects, the senses do not give any sensation, because that sensibility is not actual but only potential.32 Having a potential could mean, however, the existence of a privation. Aristotle’s understanding of potential is the potential for someone to not bring his/her knowledge Burke, Part 2 Section V, “the Same Subject Continued”, 47 Giorgio Agamben, “Warburg and the Nameless Science”, 102 32 Giorgio Agamben, “On Potentiality”, 178 30 31 into actuality through not making a work, instead of in a genetic sense the potential to learn. The counterargument of Aristotle’s theory carried out by Megarians is that all potentiality exists only in actuality.33 Agamben gives the conclusion that potentiality conserves itself and saves itself in actuality.34 These discussions prompt the thinking, whether individual potential can be represented and carried out by technologies. Word Count: 197 8. Deleuze, Gilles. “The Actual and the Virtual” in Dialogues II. Translated by Eliot Ross Albert. London: Continuum, 2002: 148-152. Deleuze introduces that all theories are composed of actual and virtual elements, and purely actual object never exists. In his theory, every actual is associated with virtual images.35 He has described actual and virtual into an atom like relationship, the ‘nucleus’ is the actual object, and the ‘electrons’ are the circles of virtual images. Virtuals is subject to uncertainty or indetermination, and it can react upon actual objects, thus, the actual object itself becomes virtual. The continuum of virtual images is fragmented, and the spatium cut up according to whether the temporal decompositions are regular or irregular. Deleuze gives the conclusion that there are two ways of the two interact, one is the actual refers to the virtuals where the virtual is actualized; another is that the actual refers to the virtual as its own virtual, where virtual crystallizes with the 33 Ibid., 180 Ibid., 184 35 Gilles Deleuze, “The Actual and the Virtual” in Dialogues II, trans. Eliot Ross Albert (London: Continuum, 2002), 148 34 actual.36 Pure virtual no longer needs to actualize itself, because they are indistinguishable.37 Seemingly, man’s intangible thoughts do not need to actualize itself either, based on its indivisible nature with rules already exists. Word Count: 198 36 37 Ibid., 152. Ibid., 151