Institutions,• Industries, Technologies Defining Phonography: An Experiment in Theory ...none Gives motion to perfection more serene Than yours, out of our imperfections wrought. . . —Wallace Stevens, "To the One of Fictive Music" Phonography can be taken to define a period in our relation to music, a period marked by a distinct set of attitudes, practices, and institutions made possible by a particular technology, the phonograph.1 The age of phonography came into being with the popularization of the phonograph as in-home entertainment, cultural medium, and educational tool. With the popularization of digital recording and playback techniques (CD, DAT, DCC, etc.), the end of the age of phonography is at hand. In one of those luminous phrases more often quoted than understood, Hegel said that "the owl of Minerva begins its flight only with the onset of dusk."2 By this he meant that an era or civilization can be understood only as it begins to disappear from the scene of history. Death, for Hegel, is the price of intelligibility. Hence there is always something both mournful and belated about historical understanding. We believe that small differences in the media of recorded music are not mere trifles for the fetishist but have large cultural consequences. The death of the vinyl LP is an event of potential civilizational significance and deserves to be mourned properly. This essay is in part a meditation on those graveyards of recorded sound that fill shelf space in our living rooms. Precisely how the coming and going of phonography matters is yet to be seen, perhaps partly because the LP's death is yet incomplete. The recent "analog renaissance" may mean the return of vinyl in full force;3 it may also be a passing retro phase of the fashion cycle that only shows how dead vinyl is. But before speculating on the nature of the age, we must define the nature of the technique. This essay discusses phonography as a technology and social practice in contrast to the pre-phonographic era and the post- 242 Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 Eric W. Rothenbuhler and John Durham Peters Defining Phonography 243 1. Pre-phonography Like most things social, it is not clear that the phonograph caused anything at all. But it does appear in retrospect that it allowed a number of interesting developments. The phonograph helped change our relationship with music: music no longer required a live performer. Music took on a life of its own, independent of composers, musicians, or audiences. Music, in short, became an object. The record, as Adorno put it, "is the first means of musical presentation that can be possessed as a thing."5 This is not to say that music became a text, which is something far older, thanks to various notational systems. The phonograph inscribes not the spirit of music but its body, its acoustic being in time. Phonography captures not the code but the act, not the script but the voice, not the score but the performance. Phonography and film attack the monopoly once held by printing: "the storage of serial data."6 After Scott, Cros, Edison, Bell and Tainter, and Berliner, sound no longer vanished into thin air.? It could be caught on tiny concentric grooves on cylinders or disks. As Edison supposedly said, "Speech has become immortal." Many of the implications of the phonographic transformation are insightfully discussed in Eisenberg's The Recording Angel, and we will only mention some here.8 The phonograph meant we could own music—not sheet music, but music itself. Rather than going to hear music often, we could go to buy it often—and play it at home often. The phonograph allowed repeated listening for more people than the privileged scholar or aesthete. Anyone who wanted to, within reasonable means, could study music in performance and thus alter his or her own perceptions of it. Or, one could forget about the music as music and rather pursue pride of ownership via extensive collections or elaborate equipment. There is something about phonography, as we shall see, that invites collecting—something missing in digitally recorded music. It is no accident, Adorno noted, that stamps, photographs, and records are all kept in those "herbaria of artificial life" called albums.9 Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 phonographic era of digital recording, storage, and playback. Throughout we explore some ideas from the audiophile culture of high fidelity.4 One does not normally speak of originality and authenticity in the postmodern academy without an ironic tone, but some issues cannot be avoided. What makes a sign stick? What compels credence? The audiophile's passion for analog and distrust of digital discloses, we will argue, less a fetishist's obsession with fine differences than an implicit answer to these fundamental questions. What is at stake in the interpretive attitude of the audiophile is not a rhetoric of inquiry but a hermeneutics of testimony. 244 The Musical Quarterly Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 Further, many copies of a musical performance could be made, such that the phonograph contributed to the development of audiences distributed in time and space and essentially unaware of each other. Indeed, compared to the newspaper, the audience for music was radically distributed and anonymous; but no more so than the audience for books. The heterogeneity of musical tastes proved, for example, a painful obstacle to the BBC's dream of a national broadcasting service to include newsventertainment, and music.10 The phonograph, like the radio, surely played a key role in reinforcing the nonlocalized segmentation of musical taste cultures. The phonograph allowed the auditor, not just the performer, to control music as an individual. The phonograph belongs to a family of techniques for both telecommunication and preserving time in the late nineteenth century: telegraphy, telephony, standardized time zones, time and motion studies, and split-second photography. As Perriault notes, the phonograph sits at the confluence of the world of engineers and of poets.11 The phonograph gave us, in our capacities as consumers, a new kind of control over time. We could choose time's rhythms and when we entered and left its control—and in what space we did so. As the phonograph made more kinds of recorded music more portable, it began to move music into the control of space as well as of time.12 The convenience of the phonograph allowed music to become a casual thing. Pre-phonographic performance was usually bound to a public venue (concert hall, church, dance hall, street, wedding) or a private one (the bourgeois parlor). (Taking a longer and wider view, musical performance was not always set apart from daily labors and rhythms, as work songs, lullabies, and sports chants remind us.) For most people under the sway of the phonograph, music could become both entertainment and part of the background noise of everyday life. The culmination of "background listening" (as the BBC planners disparagingly called it) is Muzak, designed not to be listened to.13 As Williams argues, we should understand the rise of new forms of portable entertainment media in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries as part of a larger historical process he calls "mobile privatization."14 With the increasing mobility of material and symbolic commodities, the walls of the home become permeable, and private reception of drama and music (along with private ownership of media) becomes the norm. Creation is sundered from recreation; making and enjoying music become increasingly remote tasks. The phonograph, in other words, descends from a long line of pieces of "bourgeois furniture," as Weber called the piano.15 Like the radio, it is a musical practice designed for interior domestic spaces, unlike, say, the organ or the orchestra. And yet it brings a world of musical choices to the bourgeois interior. Defining Phonography 245 2. The Contrast with Digital Recording The crucial difference between phonographic techniques and digital recording and playback is that the digital storage medium holds no analog of either the original recorded signal or the resulting playback. The digital storage medium holds numbers—data. These numbers are related to waveforms by a convention arrived at in intercorporate negotiations and established as an industry standard; but they could be anything.19 Since the numbers, like all such data, are arbitrary—related to their referent only by social convention—it is in principle possible for the consumer to treat them as anything. The CDs we buy in record stores are data storage devices and could be treated as storing data. We could read our CDs into computers other than the CD player, manipulate the data with programs other than those encoded in the chips of our CD player, to produce other results: other music, graphics, mathematical equations, puzzles, artwork, or Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 Finally, the phonograph made the very idea of "live" music thinkable, thitherto largely a redundancy. Though wind chimes and echoes are ancient and the romantics loved the Aeolian harp for its apparently spontaneous music, the phonograph marks the decisive separation between musical performance and human labor. Music became disembodied.16 The phonograph is indifferent to the physical presence of composer, performer, or audience. Edison boasted of its ability to reproduce sound waves "with all their original characteristics at will, without the presence or consent of the original source, and after the lapse of any period of time."17 It would be hard to find a clearer statement of the founding dreams of phonography: fidelity, manipulability, distantiation, and the overcoming of death. There was something unsettling about the phonograph to early audiences, especially its ability to capture voices and sounds no longer tied to the human body or to the organic cycle of birth and death. Once recorded, music belongs to a spirit world of sorts. It is fixed in a state of suspended animation. The voices and music of the dead or distant can be revived at will and without their presence or permission. More work needs to be done on the strong link between spiritualism, psychical research, the Victorian cult of mourning, and the reception of late-nineteenth-century media technologies. Nipper, obedient to "his master's voice," was often painted as if standing atop a coffin, clearly fitting the Victorian iconography of the loyal dog mourning his master's death. The phonograph speaks from "the other side," as if in a seance. Its uncanniness consists in its ability to suppress absence, to span the chasm between source and addressee that death and distance once seemed to make impossible.18 246 The Musical Quarterly Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 maps of imaginary worlds. Indeed, the idea that we buy music when we buy a CD is a holdover from phonography; actually, there is no music there. By contrast, the phonograph record and the analog magnetic tape do contain physical traces of the music. At a crude level this is visible with the naked eye in the grooves of the record and can be seen with a microscope on a magnetic tape if it is treated with a special fluid. The hills and valleys of those grooves are physical analogs of the vibrations of the music. They were cut into the master disc and then pressed into the vinyl under the rule of cause and effect in a physical world—not, as is the case with digital recording and CD playback, the rule of Sony and Phillips in an institutional world.20 When we buy a record we buy music, and when we buy a CD we buy data. If that key claim is true, then the end of the age of phonography will be marked by the spread of attitudes and practices that take advantage of that difference. If the age of phonography began with the realization of an unprecedented convenience of music—within economic limits, anyone could have it at their command—it was also marked by a continued attitude toward music as an object of the environment, something external to the self and its doings (for most of us, who have learned to act as consumers and not producers). We buy music, bring it home, and play it. It is made available to us, but as a preserved object; it has a given nature, independent of our experience of it. These ideas are encoded as value standards in the culture of high fidelity so that the goal is to reproduce the music as it really was, unchanged by recording and playback. Today we can spot in these value standards the historicist dream of accurate reproduction of lost moments, the positivist (or modernist) project of fidelity to the real, a hierarchical separation between production and enjoyment, and the metaphysics of presence.21 In contrast to the highfidelity vision of phonography, thinking of digital recording media as storing data rather than music makes it possible to enter into the musical process, to intervene in its playback, to participate in the creation of what it is one has gotten when one buys a CD. So digital technology would seem to invite a participatory stance that analog inhibits. There are some hints that these attitudes are present and growing; some of them began to appear prior to the ready availability of digital recording and editing systems. The attitude that recorded music is something available to be manipulated, to be used in the creation of a new text, was present in the age of phonography in the mixing and scratching of the hip-hop DJ.22 These techniques have been pushed to a new level, though, with digital sampling technologies. Digital samplers allow one musician to control the recorded sounds of many, or to create whole songs out of bits and pieces Defining Phonography 247 Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 sampled from other songs and the sounds of everyday life. But even the most dedicated samplers treat their samples most of the time as samples of sounds, not as numeric data per se. In other words, the interpretation scheme applied to the encoded numbers is the decoding half of the same industry convention applied to the sounds in the encoding process. They treat their sampling machines more or less the same way they would treat an analog magnetic tape recorder. The sampling machine is wonderfully more convenient and flexible, but still its basic purpose is to capture sounds that can be played back later. (The old maxim of media history recurs: the content of a new medium is a previous medium.) The real breakthrough will come when the data that represent the "recorded" sound are manipulated as data, in the numerical domain, to later produce something else other than an analog of the original sound. Computer-based audio editing software invites thinking that is closer to this possibility of distinctly "digital" attitudes toward recorded sound. These programs are designed for the micromanipulation of sound, and in addition to being miraculously quick and convenient analogs of traditional tape recording, mixing, and editing systems, they invite fiddling with pitch, duration, amplitude, filtering, synthesis, mixing, and so on. The software works by manipulating the digital code as data, while the user works with visual displays of waveforms, a musical score, or conventional analog recording studio equipment (such as a visual display of a mixer). Much cheaper and more widely advertised and distributed than only a few years ago, this type of software is no longer unfamiliar among people working, or playing, in audio fields. Indeed, it has become a regular tool, and toy, for radio, audio, and film students in our own university. But this is still professional equipment, not yet a device for living-room entertainment analogous to the phonograph.23 A move in the direction of listener co-creation of music is present in stereo components that adjust amplitude, frequency balance, and phase relations in the digital domain. The first ones did not do much more than could be done with the ordinary electromechanical controls common to many other stereo components. A few more sophisticated components allow tailoring of the frequency balance of particular speakers to particular rooms. Designed to produce further fidelity, there were many more ways to get these components set up wrong than right. They did not sell particularly well, and few new ones are coming to market. Industrial noise control—where fidelity is an enemy rather than an aesthetic—appears to be the profitable area of application for this type of digital audio processing. Whether the current generation is successful or not, audio playback equipment with digital controls provides an important example for our argument. No matter how similar appearing, they do what they do in a 248 The Musical Quarterly Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 fundamentally different way than the electrical circuitry of the last seventy or so years. Electromechanical controls, such as the volume, balance, and tone controls on ordinary stereo receivers, work by manipulating an electrical signal that is an analog of the waveform vibrations of the music itself. The electricity passing through an ordinary amplifier has a shape in time that is physically similar to the movements in time of vibrating musical instruments and stereo speakers. The electromechanical controls of analog equipment alter that wave shape. But manipulation of volume, balance, tone, and so on in the digital domain works on data as data. From this point we could imagine a far more radical manipulation of the "original" data, making it more upbeat or less, transposing the song into a minor key, pulling the pitch down so we could more comfortably sing along, perhaps even adding some strings in the background. Certainly it would be possible to use the data to generate accompanying graphics for television or even to create a synesthetic surround-experience. The Wagnerian dream of a Gesamtkunstwerk seems not far off; imagine what poem of ecstasy a latter-day Scriabin could write with digital technologies.24 Another early development of digital thinking is the production of CD-ROMs by musicians and audio artists. This depends on the same recording and storage technology as the audio CD but uses the software manipulability of the desktop computer rather than the dedicated functioning of the living-room CD player. Though the use of CD-ROM as an artistic medium may be increasingly common, it has not yet attracted a large popular audience in any form other than video games. The newest consumer digital format, DVD, just entering the market as this article goes to press, confirms the hold of phonographic thinking into the digital era. Using new laser technology to read data at finer levels of resolution, the DVD features enormous storage capacity. This capacity could be used in a variety of ways, including the encoding of software that would allow a living-room device to operate an audio equivalent of a hypertext CD-ROM, allow users to manipulate the sound at whim, or produce multimedia experiences from audio data. Perhaps in the future the technology will be used in these ways and more. But for now the DVD will be used to fit movies onto a CD-sized disk, and the closest we come to living-room interaction with the data of digitally recorded music is the occasional inclusion of a hidden track on CDs by alternative-rock bands. As yet, most people do not think of CDs as data storage devices and are not interested in manipulating the data to produce anything other than an analog of the original recorded sound. The social and economic value of CDs is based on their working as if they were analogs of recorded music. We buy them because we want to play back music, not because we want to play with data. Audiophiles criticize CDs and CD players for Defining Phonography 249 falling short of the perfect-analog goal of high fidelity. These phonographic attitudes are likely to stick with us well into the future, perhaps forever. The values of high fidelity would condemn anything else. 3. Symbol Theory Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 In some ways the vision of "recorded" music as data is a realization of postmodern hopes and fears. The encoding scheme is an arbitrary convention institutionally arrived at; it is widely seen as such and so denied the power of a natural or taken for granted truth. Hence the freedom to decode in arbitrary ways is realized, but now the choices may be individual and idiosyncratic. They will certainly represent the greater diversity of everyday life rather than the more narrow imaginings of the institutional powers. Compared with the democratizing potential of digital technology, the hopes of high fidelity—like all forms of aura-bearing art—appear frighteningly conservative, a form of orthodoxy, even of fundamentalism. Whether the shift to digital spells the ushering in of an electronic millennium, a new toy for the old powers, or the final dissolution of the humanist subject remains a problem we cannot solve here.25 But the contrast of analog and digital clearly has older sources. In terms of the logic of the sign-referent relation, the difference between analog recording and digital recording is the difference between indexes and symbols in Peirce's scheme. The analog recording is an index of music because it is physically caused by it. The digital recording is a symbol of music because the relation is one of convention. Of course the world of phonography is not wholly constructed of nature, physics, and cause-effect. A wide range of choices had to be settled by convention or intercorporate negotiations: cylinders or disks; vertical or lateral grooves; the early incompatibility of stereo and mono recordings and equipment; record speed; the angle of the cutting head and the phonograph pick-up; and others. Still, phonography is at its heart a physical process. The angle of the cutting head and the proper setup of the phonograph to repeat that angle and tracking is important not because of conventional encoding and decoding rules, but because if the angles are not all correct the cause-effect rules of nature will vibrate the stylus in different ways than the cutting head first vibrated. That will produce different electrical patterns that will push and pull the speakers into different vibrational patterns than were present at the microphones of the original recording session. Pursuit of the goal offidelityrequires conformity with the laws of nature; pursuit of the goals of business requires that companies agree on a convention. This convention narrows the range of physical constraint that must be conformed to: of all the possible angles for a cutting head, for example, we 250 The Musical Quarterly Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 will use this one or close approximations and no others. Business demands social convention because it is a social practice. But setting aside the complications of mass production for profit, phonography is a natural phenomenon. Within the range of social convention, nature rules. On the other hand, of course, digital recording is not all arbitrary convention. The ones and zeroes are caused to be recorded by ordinary physical means. The complex waveforms of music are first broken down into and then rebuilt up from simpler combinations of sine waves, not because Sony and Phillips decided it would be so but because mathematicians imagined the possibility and proved within the conventions of mathematics that it could work, because Fourier analysis and the Nyquist sampling theorem demonstrate conformity with prevalent patterns of nature and culture, and because engineers were able to devise circuits that did it. But at its heart, digital recording is as fundamentally arbitrary as analog recording is fundamentally natural. The representation of a given complex waveform by a given set of sine waves may result because Fourier analysis shows it to be the one and only set of sine waves that will adequately do so. But the representation of those sine waves by a certain digital code is because Sony and Phillips agreed to do it that way. In this case, within the range of natural possibility, social convention rules. It is not nature's stylus that writes the music. The phonograph's script may be squiggly, but it is difficult to forge. The ones and zeroes of the PhillipsSony convention, in contrast, are only copies without originals. When Sony and Phillips decided to cooperate in the development of the CD, with the plan of setting an industry standard, they had to coordinate what had previously been two different sets of corporate goals. Sony had had much success with miniaturization and enjoyed a high-tech public image. Phillips was heavily invested in the music business as well as hardware, and that was important for their corporate image as well as their pocketbook. Sony wanted the CD to be small enough to fit in the standard-sized cutout for in-dash car stereos. Phillips wanted the CD to hold the full length of any available recording of Beethoven's Ninth—the longest among standard-repertoire symphonies. While twenty-bit systems were the standard for professional digital recording, the consumer CD format was set at sixteen bits. Why? So that a ninety-minute recording could fit on a twelve-centimeter disc using then available laser technology. This oft-repeated story may not be true in every detail, but it makes the important point that decisions had to be made at some point about the size of the CD, the bit rate of the format, and the music capacity of the CD. Any two of the decisions will determine the third and any of the three could be made by any criterion. Yet the new CD technology was promoted ac offering "perfect sound forever"—even though the people Defining Phonography 251 Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 promoting it knew that the format was not as good as that of the other equipment they manufactured for professional audio. More insidiously, these same companies offered a line of consumer CD players, some of which they said sounded better than others. Better than perfect? Of course, they were right; some of them did sound better than others because the perfect-sdund-forever line was a lie. But some magazines picked up on the promotion and advised consumers not to buy more expensive CD players because, they assured us without having listened to them all, they all sound more or less alike anyway. Over the years CD players have improved tremendously, as has engineering knowledge for recording and mastering sound for CDs. This history of performance improvements represents the same kind of experiential learning that has produced improvements in phonograph technology over the last century. But the improvements in CD technology remain limited to the original decisions about the format. The upper limit on improvement is not perfection, but maximum efficiency within the possibilities of the sixteen-bit system. As further evidence of the arbitrariness of digital recording and playback technology, consider MD and DCC, the more recent bit-reduced formats. The MD, or mini-disc, is a Sony system that allows digital recording and playback on a disc the size of small computer disks. It is a further step in miniaturization and allows home recording, both features that Sony's experience shows are valuable to consumers. The DCC, or digital compact cassette, is a Phillips system that allows digital recording and playback on a cassette tape of the familiar size. This allows DCC home recording machines to be backwards compatible, working with analog cassettes as well. Backwards compatibility is always a good thing when selling new technology, and Phillips, as the inventor of the compact cassette—its formal name—was sensitive to just how ubiquitous that medium is. But how do they fit digital recordings on the smaller media of MD and DCC? By throwing away some of the data.26 Using psychoacoustic studies of auditory masking, computers are programmed to decide which of the data points are not necessary because, in the presence of the others occurring at the same time, they represent musical frequencies that would not be audible to average listeners. Crudely put, it is sort of like deciding that since few can hear the oboe anyway, the oboist should be left out of the orchestra. But rather than dealing with whole instruments, these data reduction systems deal with specific data points representing specific frequency-amplitudes that are part of the complex synthesis that is the sound of the musical performance. Of course engineering and manufacturing decisions had to be made in the history of phonography that are in important ways similar to these 252 The Musical Quarterly 4. Measurement and Fidelity Analog recording has a physical relation to the sound recorded and digital does not. Analog playback—that is, the music from the speakers driven by a record player—thus has a continuous physical relation to the original music recorded, while digital does not. There is an unbroken chain from the sound in the living room to the original sound as recorded. Analog recording is, in essence, a trace of the phenomenon such that analog playback can, in principle, be a reproduction. Digital recording is a measurement of the phenomenon and so digital playback must be a reconstruction. This simple distinction is rich with implications. Because analog recording is an indexical trace of a phenomenon, the analog storage medium will contain whatever information is allowed by the physics of the situation. Because digital recording is a measurement of a phenomenon, the digital storage medium will only contain the information for which the measurement conventions are designed. At the replay end, analog reproduction can be as close to what is stored in the vinyl Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 stories about the history of the CD. The size and speed of the record and size and shape of the stylus determine the bandwidth of response and length of recording for records just as size, bit rate, and laser technology do for digital. The now standard RIAA equalization curve is an arbitrary method for increasing the bandwidth capacity of the grooves—it decreases the amplitude of bass frequencies and increases that of high frequencies during record mastering to decrease the range of wiggle size in the groove. This frequency-amplitude adjustment is then reversed in record playback. Prior to that standardization, different companies used different equalizations. Different companies and mastering engineers still work for different sounds. Different media and playback systems have different ranges of frequency response. But all of these issues in analog recording are matters of determining the margins of bandwidth or of overall frequency balance within the bandwidth. In no case in analog recording can we go into the signal, the way we can with digital data, and decide that some of it is not necessary or that some of it should be recoded to represent something it did not before. We can filter the signal and we can shape it and it will sound like it has been filtered and shaped. But we cannot divide it up and rearrange the bits. The manipulability characteristic of digital recording and playback spells both the dream of democratic co-creation and the nightmare of lost nature. As in Benjamin's analysis of technical reproducibility, we here encounter both new possibilities for audience engagement and the loss of an aura.27 Defining Phonography 253 Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 grooves as the physics of the situation allow. Digital sound is, of course, best created by good equipment in a good room, but the first step is recon' structing an analog signal from the digital data. This is done with hardware and software circuits following the Sony-Phillips conventions and can only do that for which the convention was designed. The upper limit of fidelity in an analog system is perfection, while the upper limit of fidelity in a digital system is the Sony-Phillips convention. Whether consciously grasped or not, it is the possibility of perfection that motivates the values of the audiophile. Since in real life it is so improbable, and our own stereo systems are so obviously far from it, fidelity operates as a transcendent value. In a nutshell, this is the structure of religion: a set of practices on earth, associated with ideas about the cosmos, that bring us into contact with the transcendent. For the audiophile the endless hours of listening and tweaking and comparing and talking and worrying both prepare for and occasionally bring him or her into contact with the transcendent; it is a moment of fidelity when the equipment disappears and the pure music flows through. NX/Tien everything is right, the hair stands on end. For those who believe, it is a religious experience. The point is not that the religious experience of music depends on expensive audio equipment, but that the audiophile's attention to equipment has the structure of a religious attitude.28 The equipment and the audiophile's fussing over it is to the religious experience of music as Catholic ritual is to Christianity: not necessary, but one of the routes. Whether religion or not, the ideas on which the culture of fidelity is based can only be founded logically on an indexical medium. The index that is the record groove holds forth the possibility of oneness between the transcription and the playback devices. What further sustains the religious attitude is the faith that on the other side of the transcription device is something natural, mysterious, cosmic, and beyond the control of human devices. (Schopenhauer nominates music as our only bridge between the worlds of noumena and phenomena.) The religious circle is closed when the psyche of the listener and the stereo are tuned just right. The medium disappears; so does the ego. In that moment, there is the possibility of a communion that reaches all the way back to the music's source of inspiration. We break through to the other side. It is also possible, of course, for a good CD player to make listeners' hair stand on end. Yet some of the most experienced audio critics, with access to the finest equipment, say it has never happened for them.29 Of course, it is possible to ignore, or transcend if you like, the limits of equipment. Those who love music must do so if they are to think of the stereo as worthy of music at all. But the logic of the medium is such that the CD is not nearly so well suited to religious attitudes as the phonograph. The 254 The Musical Quarterly Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 CD player depends on symbols whose relation to their referent is due to conventions that are dressed up as neither cosmic nor natural, neither charismatic nor traditional. They make no claims to a legitimacy that transcends the practical affairs of humans at all. The symbol system of the CD is defined by for-profit decisions by Sony and Phillips and the rest of the electronics manufacturers. Even for those with no consciousness of these facts, the difference between CDs and records is built into each one's symbol system and media form. In the culture of high fidelity, analog recording has an automatic advantage; digital recording has an automatic disadvantage. If we were to pursue oneness with the original sound through the CD, the chain would halt with a bunch of businesspeople and their engineers—a good distance short of the angel with the stylus, Deutsche Grammophon's logo for decades. There are some perhaps for whom the CD can motivate a religious attitude. For them the CD and the CD player are themselves the significant symbols of science and progress. They are not media of music; the key sign relations are not between the listener and the original recording event but between a new technology and an outdated one. The holy is revealed in the rush of time's passage, the suggestion of progress. Their apprehension of time travels constantly in one direction, whereas the audiophile constantly seeks to meet recorded past time. In the terms of Benjamin, the CD technocrats live in "homogeneous and empty time," in which one event relentlessly succeeds the next, while the audiophiles live in "revolutionary time," in which it is possible to make immediate links between the now and the then, in which a historical moment can surge into the present.30 In other words, analog recording retains the otherness of past time; digital recording fixes it in code. Experience has taught that analog and digital media respond very differently to new developments in equipment quality. The history of phonography is one of repeatedly discovering that old records can sound better than anyone had realized at the time. Put an old record on a new and better player and we discover more and bettersounding music in those grooves that had been heard before. By significant contrast, the short history of digital is one of discovering that earlier digital recordings, like earlier digital playback equipment, still sound dreadful. With analog we keep discovering buried treasures; with digital we keep improving on a flawed but convenient medium. There is both something simple and something profound here. Those old records were encoded, as we now say, not by convention but by nature. There is more information, as we now say, in those old grooves than record players of the time could retrieve, even players that were recognized as the very best of their day. But modern record players, with their smaller stylus tips, more finely adjusted tracking angles, more stable speed, Defining Phonography 255 Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 and greater mechanical isolation and resonance control, reproduce a more realistic, more lively listening experience with apparently greater fidelity to the original event. As new equipment makes audible new musical details from the same old grooves, the experiential result is one of being brought closer to the old original, even across the greater distance of time. Records, then, are objects that support the activity of discovery. There is historical experience in their grooves; with the right equipment we can recover and reexperience it. Such experiences invite the idea that there are yet more musical details, more audible experience waiting there to be recovered, waiting to bring us closer to that old, preserved event of the original musical performance. This conjures a vision of the possibility of perfect fidelity that the sixteen-bit CD does not. What is the upper limit of possible resolution of the record? Nobody knows. What is the upper limit of the possible resolution of the CD? Sixteen bits. Perfection or convention, nature or society, the gods or the humans. If this is not mythic, we do not know what is. While these experiences and the thinking they produce may be common among audiophiles, they are not among the general public. To the extent that records are different from CDs for most people—aside from their conveniences—it is because the record has a body on which its own history is inscribed along with the music. Because both the music and the wear and tear of its own life are recorded on the body of the record and the playback technology is sensitive to both, playback audibilizes two histories: one of recording and one of the record. The record has a body with a voice. The data encoded on the CD do not mix with the history of the disk; they can be obscured by dirt and scratches, but dirt and scratches cannot sound from a CD player. As the history of records speaks while they are being played, they thus invite us to think about the passage of time; by contrast, CDs obscure it. The record, then, we expect is a better medium for both collective and personal memory. Not only does listening to "my records" conjure personal memory more completely than listening to a recent CD rerelease of the same music does, but listening to music of an era on the playback medium of the time should serve better as a medium of time travel. For the theorist the phonograph disc works as an indexical sign of a recorded musical performance, serving as one link in a chain of direct connections across history and space. For the audiophile it is an object of discovery, yielding ever more treasures to ever more careful exploration. For most ordinary users, it is a repository of history, sentiment, and memory. In sum, we have argued that the experience of audio equipment and hence its meaning and social significance will be structured by the practical 256 The Musical Quarterly 5. Indiscernibility and Incarnation We have heard the critics roaring in our ears. Vinyl fanaticism, they say. Totalizing longing for a natural original. Is not the degree of fidelity digital provides to most listeners effectively indexical? Can one really distinguish the continuity of analog from the infinitesimal discreteness of digital? Ought we to expect implicit logics to exert much force on standards, practices, and listening habits? Do we not know that "originality" is an effect and that sound events are always already heterogeneous, dependent both on the material space-time setting and on the position of the auditor?31 And should not the fact that a sign is a sign stop us from thinking of one sign as more natural than another? Is not naturalness itself an effect or function? Do we not edge dangerously close to the precipice of ontology in saying there is no music in a CD while there is in an LP? Are not tropes like "nature's pencil" not only descriptively dubious, but politically dangerous, since they induce a longing for order only one step away from the exclusion of otherness? Is there really a difference that makes a difference between the sound and experience of the very best digital and analog technology? We conceive much of this paper as a thought experiment that tries to unfold implications of a dying practice of musical production. Like Adorno's essay on the radio symphony, ours is "an experiment in theory."32 Adorno fights the commonsense view that radio reproduction has nothing to do with the essence of a symphony, which for him lies in the thematic apperception of the total relation of the parts and the wholes, a totality that has the potential to transcend time itself. The radio sym- Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 possibilities of the medium and by the logic of the embedded sign systems. To a large extent, the CD player continues the practical possibilities of the phonograph. It also adds a whole family of possibilities yet to be taken advantage of, due to the nature of the CD as a data storage device. Yet the CD player and the phonograph diverge sharply at the level of the logics of their sign systems. The phonograph is an indexical tracing system, holding out the hope of perfection and union with something not-here, notnow. It has a logical correspondence with the values of high fidelity, which aim to replicate the original musical event. The CD is a symbolic measurement system, holding out technique, convention, and convenience as its highest goals. It is logically at odds with the values of high fidelity. The logic of engineering aside, the phonograph is as if designed for the pursuit of transcendence; the CD is as if designed for what it was, the pursuit of convenience and profit. Defining Phonography 257 Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 phony, in contrast, becomes chamber music, as dynamic range is shrunk to fit the bourgeois interior; the "thematic interwovenness" of development becomes a series of quotations to be sampled like hors-d'oeuvres; and the balance of timbres and colors, once integrated into the whole, becomes a frivolous embellishment. Radio turns the transcendent achievement of Beethoven into kitsch. The key to his case is the proposition that technical minutiae have ontological consequences, that the means or media of artworks are an essential part of their form. Adorno remains consistently attuned to the massive alterations of aesthetic objects wrought by seemingly fine distinctions in reproduction. We claim him, with Walter Benjamin, a predecessor in our effort to take processes of mediation as of profound importance to the quality and experience of art, not just as indifferent delivery systems. Though we would not defend all of our thought experiment's propositions with equal intensity, we do insist that there is a difference that makes a difference between digital and analog. Even given a musically identical output of the two kinds of systems, the social uses and experiences of each will be necessarily different. We are thus taking a strong position on the role that symbolic logics and the media forms in which they are encoded play in shaping experience and practice. The argument that experience depends radically upon its form of mediation is clear in the case of the work of art, as Benjamin has so famously shown. Imagine that some novel technical process could replicate the Mona Lisa molecule for molecule, including the effects of aging and exposure to pollution, heat, and humidity. It would be impossible to tell copy and original apart if they were switched. And yet the two works would not at all mean the same thing. One would invite inquiries about the fetching smile, the other about the amazing process. One would invite us to travel a chain of contagious magic back to Leonardo's time, the other would leave us puzzling about the technological prowess of our own. One would be fit for the Louvre, the other for Disneyland. Their distinct institutional destinies suggest there is more to meaning than matter in motion. A sense for history makes us all metaphysicians. Signs do not signify by themselves^ their meaning resides in historical networks. The embodiment of signs is crucial to our experience. There is no such thing as what Leibniz called the "identity of indiscernibles" in cultural matters. Some may propose that we subject the two Mona Lisas to the Turing test: whether an uninformed party could tell the original from the copy.33 Clearly, no one could discern the difference. And yet the problem with the Turing test is that the body is hidden, as it is in all good murder mysteries (Turing's victim, as Kittler argues, is the humanist subject).34 The problem with digital technology is that the embodied means, the mortal 258 The Musical Quarterly 6. The Hermeneutics of Testimony What we love about the phonograph is its power to witness to historicity. To give testimony is not to state the essence of a situation but to comment on its particular embodiment. A witness's forensic value—and credibility—depends on knowledge of the accidents of an event: Did the defendant have one or two gloves on? Was he wearing a short- or longsleeved shirt? Was the traffic light yellow or red? Everything turns on those all but inconspicuous differences. In the same way, the things we collect and put into albums—canceled postage stamps, family photos obscure to anyone else, and records—are all singular traces, clues of lost time. The phonograph can serve as an archive of memory in ways impossible for a CD player. Phonography preserves the trace of events: or, rather, its testimony is given in an indexical voice. It reveals the importance of contiguity as well as resemblance as an axis of cognition.36 A model of such a hermeneutic is supplied by Carlo Ginzburg. He argues that a mode of interpretation arises in late-nineteenth-century criminology (Sherlock Holmes/Conan Doyle), psychology (Freud), and art history (Morelli) based on the notion that the scrutiny of "infinitesimal traces permit the comprehension of a deeper, otherwise unattainable reality" such as the perpetrator of a crime, a patient's mental illness, or the authenticity of a painting.37 Such a style of detection might be dismissed Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 mechanism, of musical production is obscured. Records bear the trace of a body and have an erotics impossible to CDs.35 Eros is the relation of one body to another, and this is what both the Turing test and digital technology eliminate. The analog of the Turing test in audio equipment reviewing is the A-B-X test. It is a system designed in imitation of double-blind experiments, in which the identities of the equipment under review, two amplifiers, for example, are hidden from the reviewer. The reviewer listens to brand A and brand B until familiar with their sound qualities; then an automated switching system presents either A or B, selected randomly, as X for a series of identification tests. The advocates of A-B-X testing insist that any audible difference between A and B that cannot reliably be identified in X is not real. Interestingly for our argument, whatever the merits or flaws of A-B-X testing, it obviously cannot be used to compare things that differ in such interesting ways as records and CDs. For it hides the embodiment of each medium, the source of their differential pull on the imagination. What matters in phonography is, to speak theologically, its incarnation. Defining Phonography 259 Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 as a fetish for accidents and details—shapes of ears, slips of the tongue, the painting of fingers—were it not so potent a forensic method. He contrasts this mode to the style of interpretation in literature, which generally assumes an indifference to the embodiment of the text: we have grown used to thinking of Hamlet as Hamlet whether it is found in twelve- or ten-point type, handwritten or calligraphed. And yet we insist—with a fussiness due only to sacred objects—on the integrity of a painting's or sculpture's form in every detail. The embodiment of a text, we suppose, is insignificant, while that of the image is all important. In analyzing the unique status of phonography as a vehicle of musical experience, we wish to take the notion of graphy seriously. Phonography offers something like handwriting, with its tracing of the quirks of the author's body, rather than typewriting, which effaces such crucial contingencies. Phonography traces events not only in its method of recording, but in the life of the record as well. As phonograph records age they pick up dirt, scratches, and wear from use and handling. When an old phonograph record is played, the sound of its age, the tale of its physical history, is reproduced. When an old CD is played, its life history is irrelevant. The scratches on a vinyl disk modulate the phonograph stylus in a manner that produces a sound at the speakers that can reasonably be understood as the sound of scratches. A scratched CD—appropriately enough for an on-off medium—either plays or does not play; either works in spite of the conditions of the mechanism or malfunctions.38 CD technology, being immune to personalized inscription, cannot sustain the collector's attitude, which requires the ability to discover the singularity in multiplied objects. As Benjamin argues, the art of collection is the creation of an ordered realm of memories.39 The aging of the body also explains the existence of a collector's market for records and the complete lack of one for CDs. As bodies age they become feeble and less able to do what they did before. The old phonograph record that is as good as new is a rare item; both its age and its rarity add to its value, making it worth more than when new. Old records have degrees of value dependent on their condition as well as their rarity and the market demand for their music; the range of prices is enormous, from thirty-five cents to $350 or more. But the old CD is just a used CD; it either works or it does not. Malfunctioning CDs are thrown away; working ones are nearly all the same price, varying only a few dollars according to the popularity of the artist. Even limited press runs, early issues, imports, multiple versions, and misprinted labels—all things that have produced the greatest excesses of the record-collectors' market— have failed to produce any speculative price increases, any hoarding or trading among CD buyers.40 260 The Musical Quarterly Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 The record-collectors' market is not entirely sustained by pursuit of the rare and the unusually well preserved. There is a thriving market for old records that cost about the same or a little less than the same music on new CD reissues. We do not have the audience studies that would be necessary to speak confidently about who buys these records and how they use them. But surely they are music lovers. Our own experience is that when listening counts for more than convenience, old music works better on old records. It is better to listen to Sarah Vaughan on a record printed while she was alive than on the CDs reissued after her death. The original seventy-eights of Billie Holiday, then, are valuable not only because they are rare and fragile but because they are the best available medium for time travel. Our position is not simply that of fetishists—those who elevate a peripheral organ to a beloved object. We are concerned about something deeper: the securing of meaning. For it is precisely in the circumstantial details that we can drop our anchor in the sea of signs. To favor phonography is to favor a particular kind of hermeneutic, one attentive to conditions of embodiment. Following Ricoeur, we call this a hermeneutics of testimony.'*1 Witnessing is a practice based in the mortality of the witness that aims not just for credibility but for proof, not just for lovely tropes but for incontrovertible tokens. It depends upon singularity and uniqueness. Perhaps there is no "there" there in any ultimate sense to be witnessed. But before we abandon that claim to a kind of discourse that is not fancy but fact, not invention but reality—however archaic or conservative it may seem as a model for the social life of signs—we ought to count the cost. In Homer's Odyssey, Odysseus tries to get home to his wife Penelope. In one long interlude, he is detained by the goddess Calypso, and they have a languid affair. When he finally comes to and is given a choice to stay or leave by Calypso, he admits to her that Penelope could never compare to her in grace or form, and yet he still longs for Penelope. He leaves his immortal lover, knowing that time and aging will make Penelope lovable in a way impossible for Calypso. The meaning that needs mortality, feeding off of fading things, is nourished by phonography. The music from the phonograph is a sound from the other side; it speaks out of the grave. We commune with the dead and dying in it and rediscover private memories in the accidents of history (which we now can understand the phonograph itself to be). A sign system that recognizes our links to the accidents of our bodies and histories versus one that does not—this is what matters in the apparently insignificant differences between phonography and digital. Defining Phonography 261 Notes 1. We do not distinguish between Edison's phonograph (which used cylinders) and Berliner's gramophone (which used discs). A term such as gramophony would, technically, be more apt. We use phonography as an umbrella term for a family of historically evolving techniques of sound recording that involve analog inscription on a mechanically rotating medium (wax, copper, vinyl, tape, etc.). 2. G. W. F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 23. 3. "Analog Corner," Stereophile (July 1995): 45ff; and Edward Rothstein, "Past Is Present, and the Sound Is Classic," New York Times, 22 Oct. 1995, sec. 2, pp. 1, 40. 4. Laura Dearborn, The Good Sound (New York: William Morrow, 1987), is a good source and example: Stereophile and Absolute Sound are the major journals of audiophilia. Relevant historical analysis is provided by Joseph O'Connell, "The Fine-Tuning of a Golden-Ear: High-End Audio and the Evolutionary Model of Technology," Technology and Culture 33 (1992): 1-37, and Keir Keightley, " 'Turn it Down!,' She Shrieked: Gender, Domestic Space, and High Fidelity, 1948-59," Popular Music 15 (1996): 149-77. 5. T. W. Adorno, "The Form of the Phonograph Record," trans. Thomas Y. Levin, October 55 (Winter 1990): 56-61. 6. Friedrich A. Kittler, Discourse Networks: 180011900, trans. M. Metteer (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1990), 245. 7. On the history of phonographic technique, see Michael Chanan, Repeated Takes: A Short History of Recording and Its Effects on Music (New York: Verso, 1995), 23-36; Andre Millard, America on Record: A History of Recorded Sound (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 17-36; Walter L. Welch and Leah Brodbeck Stenzel Burt, From Tin/oil to Stereo: The Acoustic Years of the Recording Industry, 1877-1929 (Gainesville: University Press of Florida, 1994); and Jacques Perriault, Memoires de I'ombre et du son: Une archeologie de laudiovisuel (Paris: Flammarion, 1981). 8. Evan Eisenberg, The Recording Angel: The Experience of Music from Aristotle to Zappa (New York: Penguin, 1987). See also Chanan, and Dave Laing, "A Voice without a Face: Popular Music and the Phonograph in the 1890's," Popular Music 10 (1991): 1-9. 9. Adorno, 58. 10. Paddy Scannell and David Cardiff, A Social History of British Broadcasting, vol. 1 (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991), 221. 11. Perriault, 201. Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 The first draft of this paper was written while Rothenbuhler was Scholar-in-Residence at the Center for the Advanced Study of Telecommunication (CAST) at Ohio State University, January through March 1992. He thanks the codirectors of the center, Jane Fraser and Thorn McCain, and also Bruce Gronbeck for negotiating a leave from Iowa. An earlier version appears as CAST Working Paper 1992-01. A later version was presented at the Conference on Refiguring the Human Sciences: New Practices of Inquiry, at the University of Iowa, June 1995, and received an illuminating response from Rick Altman. Peters thanks Michael Raine, Mark Sandberg, and Jim Lastra for helpful suggestions. 262 The Musical Quarterly 12. These contrasts are most important for listening to orchestra, choir, and band music; for singers and players of handheld instruments as well as body percussion, music has always been portable. 13. Satie and Hindemith anticipated this development. See also Joseph Lanza, Elevator Music: A Surreal History of Muzak, Easy-Listening, and Other Moodsong (New York: St. Martins, 1994). 14. Raymond Williams, Television: Technology and Cultural Form (New York: Schocken, 1974). 16. James Lastra, "Inscriptions and Simulations: Representing Sound, 1780-1900," paper given at Sound Research Seminar, Dept. of Communication Studies, University of Iowa, 21 Apr. 1995, usefully discusses forms of "autographic" sound production before phonography. Es War Emma!. . . Spieldosen- und Drehorgellddnge, Claves Records, 1989, CD 50-815, provides a variety of examples. 17. Thomas A. Edison, "The Phonograph and Its Future," North American Review 126 (May-June 1878): 527-36, at 530. 18. Mark Bennion Sandberg, "Missing Persons: Spectacle and Narrative in Late Nineteenth-Century Scandinavia" (Ph.D. diss., University of California at Berkeley, 1991). 19. The waveforms are in their turn related to the more complex waveforms constituting music by the mathematical transformations of Fourier analysis and the engineering application of Nyquist's theorem. For overviews of digital recording and CD technologies, see Ken C. Pohlmann, The Compact Disc: A Handbook of Theory and Use (Madison, Wis.: A-R Editions, 1989), and John Strawn, ed., Digital Audio Engineering: An Anthology (Los Altos, Calif: William Kaufmann, 1985). 20. Sony and Phillips are the two companies that independently developed much of the technology of digital recording and compact discs and then took the lead in establishing an industry convention for equipment compatibility. The participation of Matsushita was key; the rest of the industry followed their lead. 21. The rhetoric of fidelity followed the phonograph from the beginning: see Emily Thompson, "Machines, Music, and the Quest for Fidelity: Marketing the Edison Phonograph in America, 1877-1925," Musical Quarterly 79 (1995): 131-71. Edison, 528, provides a good example of such rhetoric. 22. A 1916 advertisement for the "Aeolian-Vocalian" phonograph boasts that it "is a true musical instrument—an instrument to control, to play, an instrument which anyone may use to exercise the natural instinct for musical expression with which everyone is gifted to some degree." The basis of this claim? The volume control. Thanks to Mark Sandberg for finding and providing a copy of this ad. 23. For what it is worth, our local observations are that filmmakers are freest in their manipulation of sound, happy to turn a recording of ocean waves into a sound to accompany pictures of a thunderstorm, for example. The uses of film throughout its history, of course, have required more manipulation and been less subject to an aesthetic of fidelity than have the uses of audio recording. Most of the students working in radio and audio use the software as if it were a magically convenient piece of analog recording gear, capable of instantaneous and minutely precise edits. Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 15. Max Weber, "The History of the Piano," in Max Weber: Selections in Translation, ed. W. G. Runciman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), 378-82. Denning Phonography 263 24. The psychedelic light shows of the 1960s depended on either an electromechanical system using analogs of the sound to drive the lights or a human operator using metaphor, simile, trope, and other rhetorical devices, as well as accident and inspiration. 25. These three views are expressed, respectively, in Nicholas Negroponte, Being Digital (New York, Knopf, 1995); Herbert Schiller, Information Inequality: The Deepening Social Crisis in America (New York: Routledge, 1996); and Friedrich A. Kittler, Grammophon, Film, Typewriter (Berlin: Brinkmann und Bose, 1985). 27. Walter Benjamin, "The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction," trans. Harry Zohn in Illuminations (New York: Schocken, 1968), 217-51. 28. The fundamental stance toward the sacred, said Levi-Strauss, is one of microadjustment (microperequation): everything must be just right and in place. The Savage Mind (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1966), 10. 29. See, for example, Dearborn, and "Analog Corner." This claim is common in equipment reviews and essays in Stereophile, Absolute Sound, and other such journals, though other critics defend the quality of recent CDs and CD players. No one defends the quality of the first couple of generations of CDs and players. 30. Walter Benjamin, "Theses on the Philosophy of History," trans. Harry Zohn, in Illuminations (New York: Schocken, 1968), 253-64. 31. James F. Lastra, "Reading, Writing, and Representing Sound," in Sound Theory/Sound Practice, ed. Rick Altman (New York: Routledge, 1992), 65-86. 32. T. W. Adorno, "The Radio Symphony: An Experiment in Theory," in Radio Research, 1941, ed. Paul F. Lazarsfeld and Frank N. Stanton (New York: Duell, Sloan, and Pearce, 1942), 110-39. 33. Alan M. Turing, "Computing Machinery and Intelligence," Mind 59 (Oct. 1950): 433-60. Though this test was developed to discern the difference between artificial and human intelligence, a precursor is the Edison-sponsored "tone tests" inviting auditors to discern human from phonographic vocalists; see Thompson. 34. Kittler, Grammophon. 35. Wayne Koestenbaum, The Queen's Throat: Opera, Homosexuality, and the Mystery of Desire (New York: Vintage, 1993). 36. Roman Jakobson, "The Metaphoric and Metonymic Poles," in Critical Theory Since Plato, ed. Hazard Adams, (New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich, 1971), 1113-16. 37. Carlo Ginzburg, "Clues: Roots of an Evidential Paradigm," trans. John and Anne C. Tedeschi, in Myths, Emblems, Clues (London: Hutchinson Radius, 1990), 96-125, 200-14. 38. CD players try to reread obscured data from damaged CDs. The result is either refusal to play at all, a rapidly repeating, distorted sound, or one of a variety of unpleasant computer noises. 39. Walter Benjamin, "Unpacking My Library," trans. Harry Zohn, in Illuminations (New York: Schocken, 1968). Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010 26. Digital code puts immensely more demands on the bandwidth of a storage medium than do the analog waves of conventional recording, so the same music that fits on a compact cassette as a recorded analog will not begin to fit on it when recorded digitally. 264 The Musical Quarterly 40. See Goldmine, various issues. Bootleg CDs, however, do command considerably higher than normal prices—perhaps in time their circulation will become limited and their value will escalate. 41. Paul Ricoeur, "The Hermeneutics of Testimony," Anglican Theological Review 61, no. 4 (Oct. 1979): 435-61. Downloaded from http://mq.oxfordjournals.org at McGill University Libraries on July 8, 2010