The Construction of Issues: Pleading Theory and Practice, Relevance in Pragmatics, and the Confrontation Stage in the Pragma-Dialectical Theory of Argumentation1 SEBASTIAN MCEVOY Groupe de Sociologie Politique et Morale Ecole des hautes études en sciences sociales, 105 boulevard Raspail, 75006 Paris, France ABSTRACT. Legal theory and practice, particularly on the exchange of pleadings, are referred to as a means of examining current thinking in pragmatics on relevance. The rules of pleadings suggest that the concept of relevance as used in pragmatics is emptied of any meaning and that theories of argumentation have not sufficiently taken into account the preliminary construction which issues to be argued about require. KEY WORDS: Pleading, pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation, relevance The background claim, a twofold or triple one, posits that relevance is a multiple context-bound norm, and not – as pragmatics has tended to make it out – a single, built-in discourse constraint (Moeschler, 1985) or communication principle (Sperber and Wilson, 1986). There are innumerable situations in which the issues to be discussed have been set down beforehand. And this preliminary definition of the questions at issue restricts what the participants can say: they must stick to the agenda of the meeting. There are also innumerable situations in which the restriction of what is to be discussed is implicit. If I walk into a shop and ask for some change for the parking-meter, I may feel myself obliged to justify or excuse this in some way, not if I want to buy an article which the shop carries. The restriction in that example is written into the setting of the exchange. Relevance, understood in this way, is indeed a norm, and not – as pragmatics has claimed since Grice (who did not view it as such, Grice, 1975) – a built-in conversational constraint or principle. The restriction on the relevant issues acts as a rule which participants must observe or else justify their departure from, failing which they may be ill-treated in some way or another. If I am not careful about how I do it, the shop-keeper may be rather hostile at my asking him for change. Moreover, the norm of relevance varies in strictness: it is not one but multiple. The shop-keeper may well not be hostile after all. And there are Argumentation 13: 43–52, 1999. 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. ARGU DISK, CP ART. NO. 50 PIPS. NO. 182287 44 SABASTIAN MCEVOY situations, such as a dinner, in which if you stick to a point, you may well be thought a bore, even if abrupt departures from what others say is offhand. The foregrounded claims will be, first, that accounts of the conditions of relevance in pragmatics are insufficient to explain the striking out of a statement as irrelevant and, second, that argumentation theory has not sufficiently considered the preliminary construction which the local implementation of a norm of relevance requires. In other than judicial contexts also, utterances may be declared irrelevant and the issues relevant in the given discussion may have been predefined in a preparatory meeting – itself governed by pre-established rules on turn-taking and voting force – organised to set up the agenda of the meeting proper; and the rules controlling that preliminary meeting may themselves have been instituted in the course of yet another ruled-governed dispute, and so on. But here, common law pleading theory and practice will be referred to as support for the two claims.2 The common law makes out getting parties to agree on which question(s) to resolve at the trial to be – at least sometimes – no easy thing. There must be pre-trial, ruled-governed proceedings, called the exchange of pleadings, to force them into that minimal agreement or, in technical language, to join issue. Otherwise the parties, uncertain as to which standpoint to attack or defend, would have nothing to guide themselves by in their quest for arguments, and, similarly, the court would be at a loss as to which question(s) to resolve. The rules governing the exchange of pleadings suggest that relevance is not a built-in communicational constraint or principle: it is a norm of conduct, from which parties can deviate, intentionally or unawares, but which they must be made to observe, if their conflict is to be brought to a close fairly and economically. The main reference for pleading theory and practice will be Stephen’s Treatise. The principles have remained the same (Harwood and Harwood, 1960), even if the rules have changed considerably since the nineteenth century. The main account of relevance in pragmatics will be Moeschler’s. Van Eemeren’s and Grootendorst’s pragma-dialectical theory (1992), which like Moeschler’s theory integrates the interactional approach to discourse, will be the reference for the theory of argumentation. 1. RELEVANCE IN THE LAW AND IN PRAGMATICS The contrastive analysis of a few examples will show how pragmatics, concerned with ordinary conversation, can make out what is irrelevant in the law seem relevant and cannot account for the striking out of an utterance as irrelevant in the law, which thus appears as having another standard THE CONSTRUCTION OF ISSUES 45 of relevance. This should be sufficient to show that relevance is not a single standard. Moreover, the fact that irrelevance in pleadings is possible and may lead to an amendment of the pleadings at the cost of the party whose pleadings have been struck off shows that the standard here is a norm, not a mere constraint. Following that first argument, the contention will be that the account of relevance in pragmatics empties the concept of meaning. It will be assumed here that what Moeschler (Moeschler, 1985, pp. 115– 119) calls cotextual appriopateness (appropriété cotextuelle) makes for what Sperber and Wilson call relevance. I Cotextual appropiateness involves an ordered set of conditions. First, it requires (A) and (B), the latter being a weaker requirement than the former: (A) cohesion. (B) coherence. Second, conversational (A) cohesion and (B) coherence – both within an exchange and within the interventions constituting an exchange – must fulfill respectively, on the one hand, (A1) and (A2) and, on the other hand, (B1) and (B2), (B2) being a weaker and less general requirement than (B1): (A1) a thematic condition. (A2) a propositional content condition. (B1) an illocutionary condition. (B2) an argumentative-(co)orientation condition. A responsive allegation in an exchange of pleadings – or, in Moeschler’s terminology, a reactive intervention – can fulfill conditions (A1), (A2) and (B1), and yet be held irrelevant, or as pleading theory and practice say not pertinent or immaterial, which means – if Moeschler’s account is satisfactory – that the standard of relevance in ordinary conversation is weaker than in pleadings. (Condition (B2), which is a constant requirement for a coherent intervention, need not be retained for the analysis of relevance in pleadings, because it is not a requirement for a coherent exchange: it is a requirement only for the positive resolution of an exchange, that is when the speakers come to an agreement. The joinder of issue, which the exchange of pleadings aims to achieve, means that the parties have come to an agreement as to what they do not agree about: to simplify, let us say, in Moeschler’s terminology, that pleadings are designed to bring about a negative but a restricted negative resolution of the exchange.) Taken from Stephen’s comment on rules which tend to secure the materiality of the issue (Stephen, 1838, p. 269), exchange [1],3 in which P stands for the plaintiff and D for the defendant, concerns an action in tort for assault and battery: 46 SABASTIAN MCEVOY [1] (P1) D agressed P. (D1) A judgement was recovered (obtained) and execution issued thereupon against X; and P, to rescue X’s goods from the execution, assaulted the bailiffs (court officer); and in aid of the bailiffs, and by their command, D molliter manus imposuit (‘gently’ or justifiably laid hands) upon P, to prevent P’s rescue of the goods. (P2) The bailiffs did not give the command. Is (P2) pragmatically relevant? (A1), the thematic condition, is fulfilled, as the discursive theme in (P2) is also present in (D1): the bailiffs’ command. So is (A2), the propositional content condition. For this be fulfilled, there must be a semantic relationship between (D1) and (P2), which can either be oppositive (contradiction), implicative (inference) or paraphrastic (synonymy). Here (P2) contradicts (D1): by the bailiffs’ command/not by the bailiffs’ command. What about (B1), the weaker illocutionary condition? (D1), viewed here as an initiative intervention, is an assertion which calls for either a positive or a negative evaluation in the reactive intervention, which evaluation in turn can either be on the utterance (énoncé) or on the act of uttering (énonciation): here (P2) can be characterized as a negative utterance evaluation on part of (D1) (by their command). (P2) therefore fulfills all the required conditions for pragmatic relevance. Is (P2) legally relevant? The rules of pleading have more specific names for the different turns in the exchange (McEvoy, 1991, pp. 252–254). (P2) is a replication to (D1), which is a defence against the plaintiff’s initial declaration (P1). Moreover, the rules of pleadings specify the categories of moves which the opponent’s prior move allows (McEvoy, 1991, p. 255). (D1) could have consisted either in (I), (II) or (III): (I) a traverse (a denial of the allegations in (P1)). (II) a plea of confession (of (P1)) and avoidance (of the usual legal consequences of (P1) through an allegation of new facts). (III) a demurrer (an objection that (P1) does not allege actionable facts, has no legal effect). And in fact, (D1) amounts to (II). (P2) could have consisted either in (I9) a traverse of the new facts alleged in the plea of confession and avoidance or in (III9) a demurrer to that plea of confession and avoidance (an objection here that the law does not allow the avoidance on those new facts, which are therefore without legal effect). And in fact consists in (I9), a partial denial of the new allegation. What happened after (P2)? The defendant demurred, and (P2) was held to be bad. Why? Because it was immaterial or not pertinent, that is devoid of legal effect: for even without the command of the bailiffs, says Stephen, the defendant might lawfully interfere to prevent a rescue, which is a breach of the peace. THE CONSTRUCTION OF ISSUES 47 II The requirement of relevance is then stricter in pleadings than in ordinary conversation. The point to be contended now is that the account of relevance in pragmatics, which posits that it is a built-in conversational constraint, empties the concept of all meaning. For the concept to have meaning, one should be able to strike off as irrelevant at least some utterances; but for relevance to be a built-in conversational constraint, the striking off of an utterance as irrelevant should be, at worst, exceptional. There are clear instances of utterances which are prima facie irrelevant. But the theory of indirection allows their being held, after all, in some way relevant. That is the case with (2) in exchange [2], modelled on (2) in exchange [3], one of Moeschler’s examples (Moeschler, 1985, p. 116): [2] (1) Do you like caviar? (2) I don’t like Rolls-Royces. [3] (1) Do you like haddock? (2) I don’t like smoked fish. Is (2) in [3] relevant? Moeschler uses it to illustrate the fulfilment of (A2), the propositional content condition for cohesion, which requires a semantic relationship between interventions of an exchange and between the constituants of an intervention. There is prima facie no semantic relationship between (1) and (2). But Moeschler claims that there is: there is an indirect semantic relationship. All one needs to have for this relationship to become apparent is assumption (a): [3] (a) Haddock is smoked fish. The assumptions reinforce the fulfilment of both conditions (A1) and (B1): as for (A1), the common discursive theme turns out to be not only my likes and dislikes but my liking haddock; as for (B1), I am not only answering a request for information but providing the requested information. On those lines, surely (2) in [2] is also relevant. All I need claim is that there is an indirect semantic relationship between (1) and (2) on the ground of assumptions (a) and (b): [2] (a) Caviar is a luxury. (b) Rolls-Royces are a luxury. The only difference in the analysis is the number of required assumptions but Moeschler does not state that beyond a certain number of required assumptions, an intervention can be struck off as irrelevant. The analysis of relevance in pragmatics thus empties the concept of all meaning. Sperber and Wilson (1986), of course, have brought in an economic principle: the cognitive effort required must be proportionate to the contextual effect obtained; but, first, there are as many steps of assump- 48 SABASTIAN MCEVOY tions in examples Sperber and Wilson give and, second, there is no way of assessing either the effort nor the effect. The consequence is that any intervention or utterance can be interpreted as being relevant, and striking off an intervention or utterance as irrelevant may always be objected to. 2. RULES FOR THE CONSTRUCTION OF ISSUES Modern argumentation theory has devoted no more attention than ancient rhetoric to a preparatory condition for argumentation: the agreement of the parties in conflict on the question(s) about which they have different standpoints. Ever since the Middle Ages, common law civil procedure has required that the parties reach a preliminary out-of-court agreement on the question(s) to be argued at the trial and to be resolved by the court. In technical language, the parties must join issue before their case can be argued and judged. The rules for the exchange of pleadings are simpler today, but their traditional complexity suggests that the joinder of issue is not easily reached. To take the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation, the rules of pleading make out the first stage in a conflict-resolution aimed discussion, the confrontation stage, to be exposed to ills other than the argumentum ad baculum and argumentatum ad hominem fallacies and lead one to view differently rule 3, the relevance rule, and rule 10, the linguistic usage rule, which are valid at all discussion stages: Rule 1. Parties must not prevent each other from advancing standpoints or from casting doubt on standpoints. Rule 3. A party’s attack on a standpoint must relate to the standpoint that has indeed been advanced by the other party. Rule 10. A party must not use formulations that are insufficiently clear or confusingly ambiguous and a party must interpret the other party’s formulations as carefully and accurately as possible. Stephen (1838), in chapter II of his Treatise, attempted to rationalize the rules of pleading which he gleaned from the Reports and the treatises or abridgments on the the English law: the first sections (I–IV) are titled as dealing with rules aimed at obtaining an issue, and an issue having certain features; the others (V–VII), as dealing with rules which the drafting of pleadings must observe; but the distinction is immaterial, as the features of the issue result from those of the pleadings. I The purpose of pleadings is to have the parties join issue (section I), the moves for which the analysis of exchange [1] gave an opportunity to describe, and moreover to ensure that an issue has the following features: it must be material or legally relevant (section II), a point also seen in the THE CONSTRUCTION OF ISSUES 49 analysis of exchange [1], it must be single (section III) and certain (section IV), that is place, time, quantity, etc. where relevant must be stated. Let us consider the second feature: singleness, which is also pursued at later stages of judicial proceedings. The issue was to be single, or more precisely there was to be a single issue per claim, which means that for a same claim,4 there could not be several declarations nor several defences, except if there were several defendants who might each put forward a separate defence. But where several distinct claims were allowed to be pursued cumulatively in the same suit, as when several trespasses had been committed, the pleadings could result in a separate issue on each cause of action.5 Such was the general rule against doubleness or duplicity. Baker (Baker, 1979, p. 77) understands it as a means of preventing the nightmarish possibility of having pleadings multiply in geometric progression. Today, and since the statute 4 Anne, c. 16, s. 4, it is lawful for a defendant to plead several matters. In terms of Van Eemeren’s and Grootendorst’s classification of disputes, the change may be expressed in the following way. The old rule allowed the joinder of issue on a single claim to constitute a single mixed dispute, involving a positive standpoint (+ p) and a negative standpoint (– p) with respect to the proposition meant to support the claim, or inversely (– p/+ p). The new rule allowed multiple mixed disputes (+ p/– p; + q/– q; etc.). The attempt to reduce a case to a single point, despite these changes, is still current, and can be observed at later stages in judicial proceedings. In Read v. Lyons (1947), for example, Viscount Simon was of the opinion that strict liability is conditioned by several elements, among which (i) and (ii): (i) escape from the land of something likely to do mischief if it escapes. (ii) non-natural use of the land. But he added immediately: It is not necessary to analyse this second condition on the present occasion, for in the case now before us the first essential condition of “escape” does not seem to me to be present at all.6 And there are many instances such as these in the Reports, opinions on questions thus set aside being one category of obiter dicta, i.e. opinions that cannot bind future decisions: the move makes for economy, and sometimes elegance in decision-making. II Curiously, Stephen comes up with headings in his sections on pleadings (V–VI), rather than those on the issue (I–IV), which anticipate Grice’s classification of conversational maxims (especially the subclassification 50 SABASTIAN MCEVOY under the maxim of manner) and rules 3 and 10 of the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation quoted previously: Section V. Of rules which tend to prevent obscurity and confusion in pleading. Section VI. Of rules which tend to prevent prolixity and delay in pleading. Seeing their head-titles, these rules should correspond to Grice’s stylistic maxims of manner and the rules in section V also to Van Eemeren’s and Grootendorst’s rule 10 requiring clarity. In fact, a closer look brings out that they are also related to the other Gricean maxims, particularly as a verbally brief utterance, complying with one of Grice’s maxims of manner, can be substantially prolix, and thus infringe upon Grice’s manner of quantity. I have discussed this point elsewhere (McEvoy, 1993, pp. 118–123). There is one rule from section V which is of particular interest for pragmatics, and for the theory of argumentation: Rule III. Pleadings must not be argumentative. In other words, Stephen (Stephen, 1838, pp. 411–412) comments, pleadings must advance their positions of fact in an absolute form, and not leave them to be collected by inference and argument only. Now this rule is quite contrary to van Eemeren’s and Grootendorst’s rule 10, as they do allow implicatures, i.e. indirect statements of standpoints, while also pointing out the fallacies they may entail (Van Eemeren and Grootendorst, 1992, pp. 196–207). Stephen’s rule rests on the distinction between pleas and arguments: pleadings must advance only pleas, and arguments must be left for the hearing in court. That is so even when the argument clearly implies the plea, which is the case for (D1) in [4], an exchange of pleadings involving an action of trespass (Stephen, 1838, pp. 412–413): [4] (P1) D took and carried away P’s goods. (D1) P never had any goods. Clearly, if P never had any goods, D could not have taken and carried them away, which amounts to a traverse of the declaration. But the court remarked: “this is an infallible argument that the plaintiff is not guilty, and yet it is not a plea”. The prohibiting of argumentativeness evinces the characteristic formalism of pleadings, and more generally the forms of action proceedings upon which common law was founded: it is as if the rules of pleading denied the inferential competence of the parties, or as if the legal system of which pleadings were a part could not cope with anything but the explicit. There is another reason to Stephen’s rule against argumentativeness, which he states for the rules in section VI on prolixity: the risk it creates of delaying the emergence of an issue or of closing the exchange on an irrelevant point. In [4], (P1) alleges actionable facts, since (D1) does not THE CONSTRUCTION OF ISSUES 51 demur. P could have traversed (D1), as in (P2), but the clash of standpoints (D1) and (P2) would have meant slipping from the relevant issue (I1) to the irrelevant issue (I2): [4] (P2) P did have goods. (I1) Did D take and carry away P’s goods? (I2) Did P have any goods? There is then behind the rule against argumentativeness the fear of obtaining an irrelevant issue or of slipping from one question to another indefinitely. The purpose of the rules of pleading, this rule shows again, is to force the parties as quickly as possible into what Van Eemeren and Grootendorst call a single mixed dispute or, in more recent practice, a multiple mixed dispute on the main propositions, and not on subordinate arguments. And this as a prerequisite for the holding of a resolvable critical discussion. * Legal theory and practice, and in particular on pleadings, have been used here to examine current views in pragmatics and the theory of argumentation, and in particular the theory of relevance.The confrontation has led, first, to criticize the criteria of relevance in pragmatics as being too loose and making the striking out of interventions or utterances as irrelevant theoretically unjustified (although a common practice in innumerable situations) and, second, to bring out the complexity involved in the construction of an issue, that is the question by which the relevance of arguments is to be assessed, a point which the theory of argumentation, more concerned with the argumentation stage, has tended to set aside. NOTES 1 The first version of this article was read at the Third International Conference on Argumentation (1994) in Amsterdam and published in the Proceedings of the conference, Amsterdam: Sicsat, 1995. For further development on rule-governed disputes: McEvoy 1998. 2 Founded on centuries of thought on judicial conflict-resolution, legal theory and practice are here used as a means of examining current thinking in pragmatics. There is possibly some form of circularity in this. Legal theory and practice become relevant to pragmatics because pragmatics has constructed issues and concepts which allow a reading of legal theory and practice in terms which happen to make them relevant to pragmatics. 3 The examples of pleadings are here simplified: in Latin till 1731, they remained extremely formal until the second half of the ninenteeth century when demurrers for lack of form ceased to be allowed. 4 In law, the term claim is ambivalent: it can refer either to what P asks for (e.g., damages) or to the reason why he is, or thinks himsef, entitled to it (i.e., the cause of action). Here, it is to be taken in the first sense. 5 The declaration was then made up of different parts or counts corresponding to the cause of action for each claim or part of the total claim. 6 Read v. Lyons (1947) A.C., 156, at 168. 52 SABASTIAN MCEVOY REFERENCES Baker, J. H.: 1979, An Introduction to English Legal History, 2nd edition, Butterworths, London. van Eemeren, F. H. and R. Grootendorst: 1992, Argumentation, Communication and Fallacies, Lawrence Erbaulm, Hillsdale, New Jersey. Grice, H. P.: 1975, ‘Logic and Conversation’, in P. Cole and J. L. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics III, Academic Press, New York, pp. 41–58. Harwood B. A. and G. F. Harwood: 1960, Odgers’ Principles of Pleading and Practice in Civil Actions, 17th edition, Stevens and Sons, London. McEvoy, S. T.: 1991, ‘Issues in Common Law Pleading and Ancient Rhetoric’, Argumentation 5, 245–261. McEvoy, S. T.: 1993, ‘Pleadings: procédure pour un accord minimal’, in C. Thomasset, R. Côté et D. Bourcier (eds.), Le droit saisi par l’ordinateur, Y. Blais, Cowansville (Québec), pp. 111–130. McEvoy, S. T.: 1995, L’invention défensive: poétique, linguistique, droit, Métailié, Paris, 382 pp. McEvoy, S. T.: 1998, ‘A propos de la rationalité procédurale’, in A. Borzeix, A. Bouvier and P. Pharo (eds.), Sociologie et connaissance: nouvelles approches cognitives, C.N.R.S. éditions, Paris, pp. 229–245. Moeschler, J.: 1985, Argumentation et conversation, Hatier, Paris. Sperber, D. and D. Wilson: 1986, Relevance: Communication and Cognition, Blackwell, Oxford. Stephen, H. J.: 1838, A Treatise on the Principles of Pleading in Civil Actions, 2nd edition, Saunders and Benning, London.