An Actor Manages: Actor Training and Managerial Ideology Dr Broderick D.V. Chow Lecturer in Theatre Brunel University London Kingston Lane, Uxbridge, UB8 3PH broderick.chow@brunel.ac.uk Introduction What is an actor’s work? Is it the process of creating and presenting a character? Or is it the business of managing a career? While the former attracts people to the business, the latter is essential. As Michael Simkins (2013) in the Guardian estimates, 92% of actors in Britain are out of work at any one time. The precarious nature of the business therefore means that actors must combine the unremunerated labour of auditions, promotional material and managing finances with one or more non-acting based jobs – often casual or part-time and flexible enough to allow time off for auditions – as well as creating showcase pieces and their own work during those fallow times when an actor is euphemistically said to be ‘resting.’ The business of acting is often set in opposition to the actor’s ‘craft’, a term that resonates with philosopher Richard Sennett’s conceptualization of craftsmanship as undivided skill and attention for its own sake. ‘Working on my craft’ was how I justified handing over 300 Canadian dollars for eight weeks of scene-study classes while a working (and resting) actor in Vancouver. Though nearly all of 1 us in the class had already completed training at a university or drama school, it was understood that working on one’s craft was a lifelong process. Eventually, the glorious moments in scene studies of the American greats became the thing itself, far superior to any job. In an industry nicknamed ‘Hollywood North’, dominated by commercials and two lines as a cop on Smallville, it could sometimes seem like the acting in class, not the stuff out in the industry, was real acting. In this article I will argue that the business of acting and its creative craft are two sides of the same coin. Psychologically-based actor training stems from an ideology of individual self-management – mental, physical, and emotional – that accompanies the emergent practice of management in the twentieth century. By reading the theories and techniques of Stanislavskian and postStanislavskian actor training against changes in the organization of work in North America and Europe in the 20th century, I outline a citational network between discourses of acting and business management. I analyze three stages in the development of organizational management – Taylorism, Management by Objectives, and Human Resources Management – leading to the current moment of the ‘new economy’ where a rhetoric of the ‘creative industries’ dominates, which I suggest is a culmination of nascent ideological tendencies. The three earlier stages of organizational management are an instrumentalisation of tacit knowledge that resembles the development of 2 Stanislavsky-based actor training. Acting and organizational management brought an increased focus to emotion, empathy, and social relations and how these could be produced, maintained, and instrumentalized by waged labour. 1 Systematic actor training (Jonathan Chambers’ term for derivations of Stanislavsky’s ‘System’) reaches its apotheosis of usefulness in our current historical situation of ‘precarity’ in which the worker no longer has recourse to forms of structure and security enjoyed under Fordism and must self-manage – a role that the actor has long prefigured. My method follows Jon McKenzie’s study of ‘performance’ in Perform or Else. Drawing together three discursive fields – cultural performance, organizational performance, and high-performance technology – McKenzie identifies three interlinked principles: efficacy, efficiency, and effectiveness. In this citational network, performance is concerned with whether or not something ‘works.’ Performance is a generalized principle applied to both the functioning of a copper wire and a human being in everyday life, and is therefore a normative and even terrorizing ‘mode of power and knowledge’ (McKenzie 2001: 164). Here, I develop upon McKenzie’s reading together of cultural performance and organizational management to argue that the discursive resemblance between actor training and management theory represents an ideological Empathy, within the theatre, can refer to both the actor and the spectator’s identification with the character. Within the literature of management, however, we see that this human process can be mobilized to industrial ends. 1 3 imperative to ‘act the part.’ This imperative demands that one identifies with one’s job on a personal, emotional, and even spiritual level. By thinking critically across fields I hope to raise difficult questions regarding creative labour in today’s precarious labour economy. Bits and Objectives: Scientific Management and the Detailed Division of Labour Since the 1990s many governments have turned to the ‘creative industries’ as a key player in the ‘new economy.’ The UK Department of Culture, Media and Sport (DCMS) was influential, bundling together a number of industries including advertising, publishing, and (together with music and visual arts) the performing arts, as the ‘creative industries’ (DCMS 2001). The creative industries, Kate Oakley (2004) points out, bear a heavy burden, charged with the revival of entire cities and communities without sufficient evidence that they are up to the task. Justin O’Connor (2012), in an extended critical review of Terry Flew’s The Creative Industries (2011), points out that what began as a policy to secure more funding for culture was uncritically expanded as a way of redefining other forms of work. Within this ‘creative industries’ ideology, ‘creativity’ takes on a dual meaning. On the one hand, it is mainly associated with what we tend to think of as ‘artistic’ labour. On the other hand, today, creativity is also thought of as a general feature of work, artistic or not. In this 4 vein is Chris Bilton’s work on ‘creative management’ (2006, 2010), which aims to manage and nurture innovation, while negotiating uncertainty. But adopting the rhetoric of creativity also risks adopting creative labour’s precarious conditions and a high-level of personal and emotional investment in one’s labour (see Hesmondhalgh and Baker 2009, 2011; McRobbie 2002). While theatre is only one of a series of creative industries today, the ‘actor’ is the figure that haunts the history of management. Management increasingly resembles the acting labour of the Western modern theatre, in which actors create characters with believable psychological interiority. My argument focuses on Stanislavsky’s system and subsequent adaptations, which remain a backbone of most training regimes in the English-speaking theatre, though they are by no means the only forms practiced today in conservatoires or universities. Alison Hodge notes that actor training is a phenomenon of the modern, director-led theatre, which resulted in ‘a more objective examination of the nature of the actor’s work’ (2000: 2). As well as being motivated by these shifts in the European theatre, Konstantin Stanislavsky’s experiments also determined the shape of the theatre industry to come by systematizing and professionalizing the actor’s work. His experiments at the Moscow Art Theatre (MXT) in the early 1900s correspond with practices at the beginnings of 5 modern organizational management, which were taking place in America a decade or so earlier, specifically Frederick Winslow Taylor’s development of the paradigm of Scientific Management, commonly known as Taylorism. Taylor argued that managers must gather knowledge of the entire production process in order to divide the process into tasks for the worker (hence, as the political economist Harry Braverman points out, the huge expansion from 1890s to 1950s of degrees in engineering). Scientific management separates ‘conception’ from ‘execution’, as managers assume a ‘monopoly over knowledge’ (Braverman 1974: 113). A ‘task-based’ management theory, Scientific Management parallels other performance practices. As a number of scholars have argued, Vsevolod Meyerhold’s system of biomechanics was directly inspired by Taylorism’s Soviet adaptation while also ‘humanising’ it (Pitches 2003; Evans 2009). What has not been acknowledged, however, are the parallels between Taylor’s work and Stanislavsky’s. These are not similarities in terms of specific practices so much as ideological similarities; a drive to systematize and rationalize embodied knowledge. A ‘craft’ is a skill or process that an individual performs, whether the portrayal of a character or repair of an engine. Craft is what Scientific Management seeks to break down. Dividing a process among several workers (what Braverman calls a ‘detailed division of labour’) directly benefits the capitalist in terms of economy and control. As labour is the source of surplus value, and 6 the accumulation of value the driver of capitalism, the capitalist is driven to economize on the overall wage bill by dividing a process into tasks. The capitalist can then pay lesser-skilled workers less money to perform the easier tasks, whereas the minimum pay of the worker who performed all operations of the process would be by default the highest pay for the most difficult task (Braverman 1974: 77-80). This economizing creates greater output for less input, and improves the efficiency of production processes (as in Henry Ford’s assembly line). At the same time, separating planning from doing further alienates the worker from the products of his/her labour. The designation ‘Scientific’, therefore, is not neutral, but ideological – it naturalizes the imperative of maximizing surplus value, regardless of the human cost. The destruction of traditional craftsmanship entrenched class divisions (Braverman 1974). By concentrating ‘knowledge’ in the minds of managers, a workforce of laborers with specialist knowledge became unnecessary; a process Braverman calls ‘deskilling.’ By ‘destroying the craft as a process under the control of the worker’, Braverman writes, ‘[the capitalist] reconstitutes it as a process under his own control. He can now count his gains in a double sense, not only in productivity but in management control, since that which mortally injures the worker is in this case advantageous to him.’ (1974: 78).Therefore, Scientific Management represents the destruction of embodied knowledge and a division of knowledge between the head and the hand. 7 Management (despite the etymological link to the Latin manus, or hand) is demarcated as an intellectual exercise – the head can understand what was previously known by hand. The detailed division of labour does not seem immediately applicable to the creation of individual, singular characters – while a director could economize by dividing up Keira Knightley’s performance to forty-four child laborers – she is probably not going to. But both Taylor’s practices at the Midvale Steel Works in the 1880-90s and Stanislavsky’s practices at the Moscow Art Theatre a decade later attempted to capture knowledge that was at first glance tacit, embodied, natural, and mercurial, in the form of method – understandable, transmissible. When embodied or intuitive practices are broken down, whether they are the mechanic’s craft or the actor’s work, they can be understood and perfected. Both Taylor and Stanislavsky were outsiders to closed, guild-like practices. Taylor’s apprenticeship in the factory was, as Braverman points out, an act of youthful rebellion against his wealthy father; Stanislavsky was an amateur actor, who, as his biographer Jean Benedetti notes, was pretty bad at acting. In Stanislavsky’s case, having viewed foreign actors such as Eleonora Duse and Tommasso Salvini in Moscow, he sought to capture what his biographer Jean Benedetti describes as the ‘ease, naturalness and flow of the actor of genius’ (2000: 3) by means of a method. 8 Unlike the factory worker, the actor does not simply carry out the tasks set by a director but engages herself in a complex process of planning. The emphasis on planning is at the heart of Stanislavsky’s system and was, in some ways, a theatrical revolution. Compare the 1896 staging of Chekhov’s The Seagull with the MXT’s fabled production two years later. In the first, Sharon Carnicke argues, actors would learn their parts on their own, and meet for ‘a few’ rehearsals; in the latter, Stanislavsky’s actors ‘put eighty hours of work into thirty-three rehearsals’ (Carnicke 2000: 12). The labour of the actor shifts behind the closed doors of the rehearsal room, with the actor analyzing the play and dividing it into a ‘score’ of actions. ‘If our preparatory work is right’, Stanislavsky wrote, ‘the results will take care of themselves’ (Stanislavsky qtd. in Carnicke 2000: 25). Reading Stanislavsky through Taylorism, the actor is both a manager who plans a series of actions, and a worker who executes them. The Stanislavsky ‘event’ transformed the modern theatre, most would say, for the better. By systematizing the ‘nature’ of the actor’s creativity, Stanislavsky inspired a century of Western actor training and democratized the profession. The MXT and its ensemble mode of working replaced the Russian theatre’s star system, meaning anyone, in theory, could learn to be an actor. But it is tempting to see this moment of the actor’s autonomy as the beginning of the profession’s precaritization. 9 In the next phase of management the skills of the actor enter into the remit of the manager. What Taylor overlooked was the role emotion played in organizations and workplaces. Taylorism’s monopoly on planning degraded the worker’s psychological and emotional wellbeing – to maintain productivity management would also need to mediate antagonisms brought on by the degradation of skilled labour. Management theorists from the 1930s onwards would address this oversight, including the focus of the next section, Peter F. Drucker. Performing (Self) Control: Managerial Ideology and Labour as Dressage Managers hold control and power, but they are not the same as owners. In the early phases of industrial capitalism, this lack of (literal) ownership was viewed as a problem. Adam Smith, in The Wealth of Nations, worried that because directors of ‘joint-stock companies’ were managers of other people’s capital, they would not employ the same vigilance as if it were their own (1776, in Fournier and Grey 2000: 8). The manager is therefore a median figure that requires its own role and corresponding ideology to justify its existence. Willard Enteman calls this ideology managerialism: an ideology in which ‘the fundamental social unit is neither individuals nor the state, but organizations’ (1993: 154). Managerialism views the individual as a rational actor, who can 10 nevertheless sacrifice his/her own self-interest for the team. Following an Althusserian reading of ideology, however, we know that ideology is not merely a matter of personal worldview. In his most famous essay, Louis Althusser writes that when an individual is ‘hailed’ on the street by a police officer, and turns around, the ‘mere one-hundred-and-eighty-degree physical conversion’ interpellates him as a subject: ‘Because he has recognized that the hail was “really” addressed to him, and that “it was really him who was hailed”’ (Althusser 1971: 48). Paraphrasing religious philosopher Blaise Pascal – ‘Kneel down, move your lips in prayer, and you will believe’ (1971: 42) – Althusser notes the way ideology is not embedded in a subject’s beliefs, but his/her practices, or, perhaps, performances. Managerialism therefore is both an ideology of organizations, and the practice by which the individual affirms or performs his/her commitment to an organization. Therefore, the practice of management lies at the intersection of organization, performance, and emotional investment. The manager’s labour is not directly productive, in that it does not directly create use values. Instead, the manager indirectly improves productivity and organizational performance (i.e. efficiency), extracting as much surplus value from the worker as possible. One of the earliest management theorists, Henri Fayol, noted that ‘Whilst the other functions [of the organization] bring into play material and machines, the managerial function operates only on the 11 personnel’ (1916[1971]: 181). Fayol’s principles branch out from the division of labour to more intersubjective principles (known as ‘soft skills’ in today’s MBA programmes) such as ‘Initiative’, ‘Esprit de corps’, and ‘Discipline.’ The substance of a manager’s labour is already ‘performance’, therefore, in two senses (which, according to McKenzie, are intertwined). A manager is responsible for the quality performance of an organization, and to ensure this is required to perform a certain way. Contra McKenzie, performance has not replaced discipline, rather, the manager performs discipline. Jackson and Carter, drawing on Foucault, call this ‘labour as dressage’: ‘non-productive, non-utilitarian and unnatural behaviour for the satisfaction of the controller and as a public display of compliance, obedience to discipline’ (1998: 54). Dressage means both ‘discipline’ and ‘taming’, but it also refers to the show of performance of a disciplined and tamed horse. The only function of labour as dressage is to demonstrate or show compliance2. Here we can return to Adam Smith’s quandary: why would a middle-ranked employee agree to this performance of compliance (without a stake in ownership)? Precisely because managerialism provides a role to inhabit. This is a mechanism of ideological interpellation akin to Stanislavsky’s holistic The question of course becomes: ‘who is the audience for this show’ of compliance? Slovenian philosopher Slavoj Žižek’s body of work from 1989 onwards would answer: The Big Other – the network of socio-symbolic rules that guarantees our intersubjectivity, but crucially, doesn’t really exist. 2 12 approach to character. The manager’s role is best explored through the work of Peter F. Drucker, the Austrian-born theorist of management, and one of the first to try to define the ‘function’ of the manager. Despite at times being incorrect in his predictions, Drucker remains a benchmark for organizational theory, bringing together Scientific Management with an interest in human behaviour.3 Drucker recognized that Scientific Management’s exclusive concern with productivity meant it was poorly placed to address the problem of worker motivation. A purely Taylorist organization diminished worker flexibility and adaptability, and increased resistance to change: ‘[Scientific Management] knows how to organize the present job for maximum output but only by seriously impairing output in the worker’s next job’ (1977: 232). Denying the human dimension of management hindered economic performance. In this way, his theories brought Taylorism together with Elton Mayo’s human relations movement, which ‘recognized that the social-psychological climate of an enterprise is as much a factor in productivity as technical capability’ (Locke 1996: 24). Drucker’s innovation is known as ‘management by objectives’ or MBO. MBO sets goals for an organization and distributes these goals in objectives to be accomplished by individual workers or teams. What is In the 1970s, Drucker argued that the United States was seeing the retrenchment of corporate power. Naïvely, he suggested that top CEOs would no longer be household names, an idea that Bill Gates, Jeff Bezos, Rupert Murdoch, and many others have since belied. 3 13 distinctive about MBO, however, is that objectives cannot stand on their own as singular tasks, but must be integrated into a ‘job.’ ‘The human being does individual motions poorly’, Drucker writes, but a job, allows the worker to invest in his/her work personally or emotionally (Drucker 1977: 230). A human is not a tool, Drucker argued. Therefore, management must make use of a worker’s ‘will, personality, emotions, appetites and soul.’ (1977: 230). Drucker gave little advice on ‘soft-skills’, leaving this task to be taught in business schools. His concern was more structural than psychological. However, his management theory points to an important feature of the ideology of managerialism: the instrumentalisation of emotion. In his seminal text The Practice of Management, Drucker gives a surprising insight: rather than instructing readers on how to manage others through manipulation or guile, Drucker suggests that the manager’s first object should be his or her self. He writes: ‘The greatest advantage of management by objectives is perhaps that it makes it possible for a manager to control his own performance. Self-control means stronger motivation’ (1955: 112). The desires of the manager must become consonant with the goals of the organization – they must take on the objectives for themselves. A manager who is managed by self-control and objectives ‘acts not because somebody wants him to but because he himself decides that he has to – he acts, in other words, as a free man’ (1955: 117) – in other words, he has to want it. 14 It is easy to see the parallels between MBO and Stanislavsky’s System of bits and objectives. Both actors and managers begin their planning by identifying a ‘super-objective’ of sorts, and devising smaller objectives that lead to this overall goal. Here, the new paradigm of actor training seems to influence management: while Taylor prefigured Stanislavsky’s analysis of the text into action, MBO draws on Stanislavsky’s mobilization of human desire through the analysis of the text in terms of character objectives. While desire is utilized in Stanislavsky’s system to creative and artistic ends, and in Drucker’s system to improve the firm’s efficiency, ultimately, the result is the same: desire becomes part of a new form of labour that is utilized in production, whether this production is theatrical, physical, or cognitive/immaterial. In other words, since Drucker demands not only the manager’s intellect but also her desire, by performing her compliance with the norms and desires of the corporation this new manager is doing the labour of the actor. In a way, Drucker addressed the alienation of the work in the Fordist factory. But his work led to a different kind of alienation – the alienation of the emotions, and of the self. Today, this alienation is so characteristic of modern work it often goes unnoticed. Jackson and Carter write that today it is: ‘[…] considered inadequate simply to work but required that when one worked one should self-actualize […] we are required to be empowered’ (1998: 59). Tony J. Watson’s ethnographic research with managers notes that managers use ‘self-concepts’ and 15 discursive formations such as ‘the sort of person I am’ (1997: 150) in order to identify with the organization. In social psychology this is called ‘identity work’, a performative and discursive construction of the self. The job of the manager is not only to make the employee or colleague believe in the organization but to make oneself believe. Only in this way can the manager ‘make clear to the world that there is no division between the manager as a human being and the manager as a functionary’ (Watson 1997: 150). Emotion as Material: Strasberg and Carnegie The increasing emphasis in management theory on the management of one’s self in order to create favourable interactions with others accompanied the shift in the economies of the West from the manufacture of goods to the renting of intellectual property and accumulation of surplus value through brands and symbolic capital. Drucker predicted this shift by conceiving of the ‘knowledge worker’ and the Italian autonomist philosopher Maurizio Lazzarato (1996) uses the term ‘immaterial labour’ to describe these new forms of work. But while immaterial labour does not produce material commodities of the sort analysed in chapter one of Das Kapital, such as coats or chairs, its practice certainly involves a familiar material: the body and its affective and emotional capacities. 16 Lee Strasberg, Stanislavsky’s disciple and the originator of what is today known as American Method Acting, understood that ‘emotion’, or ‘feeling’ was a material that could be worked on and disciplined. Strasberg studied at the American Laboratory Theatre under the tutelage of Maria Ouspenskaya and Richard Boleslavsky, both students of Stanislavsky at the Moscow Art Theatre. As artistic director of the Actor’s Studio, which trained numerous American actors including Paul Newman, Dustin Hoffman, Anne Bancroft and Sally Field, Strasberg has had enormous influence on American acting. The radical departure in Strasberg’s training was ‘the Method actor’s uncompromising search for “truth” and “authenticity”’ (Counsell 1996: 53). Strasberg stressed the use of ‘affective memory’ (sometimes incorrectly known as ‘emotional memory’), that is, evoking a specific emotion within the given circumstances of the dramatic text by remembering a corresponding feeling from the actor’s own past. All artists, he argues, use their sensual memories of previous experiences, but only actors must do so ‘in the presence of the audience at a particular time and place’ (1988: 116). This is a fundamental transformation to our approach to truth and sincerity. The System and the Method are means of disciplining and manufacturing spontaneous emotion, but this is not the same as pretending. No, in fact, both the System and the Method emphasise the ‘truth’ of the moment, and this discourse is not limited to theatre professionals; ‘emotional truth’ and ‘believability’ are frequent 17 (empty) clichés in the evaluation of actors’ performances by the general public. The idea that genuine emotion can be instrumentally manufactured radically elides false and true, and parallels other ideological changes. While Strasberg was formulating his Method with the Group Theatre, Dale Carnegie, a former actor turned self-help lecturer and entrepreneur, published How to Win Friends and Influence People. He provides advice on interpersonal communication and leadership, illustrated with anecdotes in an upbeat, folksy narrative voice. Chapters titles are Machiavellian: ‘How to Change People Without Giving Offense or Arousing Resentment’, however, Carnegie does not advise using guile or manipulation. Rather, his advice oscillates between selfinterest and sincerity. One must ‘arouse in the other person an eager want’ (1936: 69) and ‘talk in terms of the other person’s interests’ [in order to get them to like you] (1936: 110). But at the same time, you must actually mean it. Honesty and sincerity run through his principles, for example: ‘Make the other person feel important — and do it sincerely’ (1936: 121). Carnegie doesn’t resolve the contradiction between authenticity and manipulation – he simply pretends it doesn’t exist. Both Carnegie and Strasberg effectively give the same advice: don’t deceive, but engage in a careful process of feeling management. 18 William Whyte’s The Organization Man (1957)[2002], an ethnographic study based on interviews with top American CEOs, shows feeling management in action: ‘the calm eye that never strays from the other’s gaze, the easy, controlled laughter, the whole demeanour that tells onlookers that here is certainly a man without neurosis and inner rumblings’ (Whyte 1957[2002]: 155-6). Organization Man ‘must not only accept control, he must accept it as if he liked it’ (Whyte 1957[2002]: 151, my emphasis). This is not the same as deceit. It is wilful self-deception. Whyte’s ‘as if’ reminds us of Stanislavsky’s ‘magic If.’ Stanislavsky’s fictional surrogate, the acting teacher Tortsov, tells his students: “‘In this process the magic “if” and Given Circumstances, when they are properly understood, help you to feel and to create theatrical truth and belief onstage. So in life there is truth, what is, what exists, what people really know. Onstage we call truth that which does not exist in reality but which could happen’” (Stanislavsky 2008: 153). Grisha, a student, challenges Tortsov by pointing out the contradiction between ‘truth’ and theatre’s fictional nature. In reply, Tortsov tells Grisha: ‘“Decide what is more interesting, more important to you, what it is you want to believe, that the material world of facts and events exists in the theatre and in the play, or that it is the feeling which is born in the actor’s heart, stirred by a fiction, that is genuine and true?”’ (2008: 154). Feelings, in other words, are ‘true’, because they arise from the actor’s self. But this truth can be manipulated through a process of ‘justification’ in reference to the Given Circumstances; this creative work 19 ‘“satisf[ies] your sense of truth and your belief in the genuineness of your experiencing”’ (2008: 154). Transposed to the corporate world, this passage takes on a different cast. As in the world of a play, the Given Circumstances of the corporation are largely out of the actor’s control. Unlike a play, the actor’s work of generating true feeling becomes a means for the manager to submit freely to control.4 Acting styles are never neutral, but reflect and refract ideologies and larger social and historical changes. The discursive coincidence between actor training and organizational management is not metaphorical but quite actual. The two practices share techniques and processes, which is demonstrated through the increasing importance of ‘transferrable skills’ in the prospectus pages of university drama courses. ‘Acting’ is not simply a useful metaphor for understanding new forms of emotional and affective labour (cf. Hochschild 1983). In fact, ‘the actor’ is a metonym for the alienation of the self within work in the 20th century, and prefigures the ideal, self-managed subject: the freelancer. Self-Management for Precarious Labour Arlie Russell Hochschild notes this similarity in The Managed Heart, her study of ‘emotional labour’ in the service industries (specifically among flight attendants and debt collectors), making use of Stanislavsky’s theories to conceptualize her distinction between ‘surface’ (feigned) acting and ‘deep’ acting (1983[2003]: 37-38). 4 20 Taylorism sought to separate planning from execution, while the school of MBO supported by Drucker attempted to reintegrate individual tasks into a ‘job’, which supported personal investment and self-actualization. In the contemporary firm we see, in the words of Alan McKinlay and Phil Taylor, an ‘emergence of a new language of work [which] has been paralleled by the rise of teamworking, a form of work organization in which groups of employees assume responsibility for complete production processes, including administrative and organizational functions’ (1998: 173, my emphasis). This is a larger shift from a hierarchical, Fordist model, to a more lateral model of (self) control. The single manager is no longer solely responsible for ensuring performance. Rather, each employee assumes a management function; they must all perform. As suggested earlier, the creative industries drive this shift. Not only are the creative industries seen as an ideal area of expansion within the post-Fordist economy, they also provide a model for organizational management. Thus, Robert Hewison, John Holden and Samuel Jones engage with theatre practices in their study of the RSC (2010), and their use of the ‘ensemble’ as both a rehearsal practice and an organizational tool. More generally, Bilton (2006) argues that management in itself is a creative act, facilitating the conditions for creativity and moving the concept away from the Romantic idea of the individual artist to creativity within systems and organizations. In one sense, 21 collective creativity is a positive thing, as are the increasing autonomy and possibilities for self-actualization to be found within the collective. But within the new economy, collectives are often arranged around specific projects, constantly being restructured and rearranged. The value of the creative collective should be questioned if it is not supported by institutional structures that give it security and stability. Hesmondhalgh and Baker argue that creative industries policy does not take into account the specifics of artistic labour: ‘policies that argue for a radical expansion of [the cultural industries] under present conditions, without attention to the conditions of creative labour, risks fuelling labour markets marked by irregular, insecure and unprotected work’ (2009: 5). While the ‘individualization of work’ (McRobbie 2002: 518) may be perceived as flexible and exciting, it comes with the removal of forms of labour security enjoyed under Fordism. Scholars in diverse disciplines have called this precarity, a pervasive adoption of short- or fixed-term contracts, zero-hour contracts, and billable freelancing. In an individualized labour economy, success requires constant self-management: ‘what individualization means sociologically is that people increasingly have to become their own micro-structures, they have to do the work of the structures by themselves, which in turn requires intensive practices of self-monitoring’ (McRobbie 2002: 518). 22 Without conflating ‘acting’ with all artistic labour, nor suggesting that actor training is responsible for today’s freelance economy, it is striking that it prefigures one key area of this shift: self-exploitation. McRobbie notes the very high level of self-exploitation in the creative industries, due to a combination of passion and pleasure. The rewards for creative labour are presented as ‘inherent’; one’s work becomes reconceptualised as one’s craft. The ideologies become intertwined: ‘self-exploitation’ also doubles as a description of the actor’s work in Stanislavsky-derived actor training, which asks the actor to work on her emotions, body, and spirit. In other words, the positive, ‘actorly’ sense of self-exploitation as artistic mining of the self becomes ambiguously folded in with McRobbie’s usage of the term ‘self-exploitation’ as long hours, exhaustion, and low remuneration. The training of the actor is also useful for what we might call acting’s ‘externalities’, that is, the business of it all, in which the self is packaged and sold in order to find (temporary) employment. Aside from the minimal amount of time spent actually ‘on-the-job’, acting involves enormous periods of unremunerated labour, or rather, labour that is paid for by the promise of eventual remuneration. This includes those performances that never come to be – auditions and castings, which involve reading from the sides, but also, networking with casting directors, agents and producers. Actors also self-manage their life-narratives and personal portfolios, mining aspects of their personal history and image in order to present a flexible but unique and hire-able self. In a typical audition, an actor must ‘slate’ 23 (USA/Canada) or do an ‘Ident’ (UK), stating their name and agent, give ‘profiles’ (the casting equivalent of a mug shot), and usually summarize themselves in a few pithy sentences. At the same time as an actor is meant to mine their inner self for emotional truth, they must also create an attractive packaged self that can be sold. This, we should make no mistake, is another form of labour, but it is not remunerated as such. Rather, actors are happy to take it on. These externalities increasingly resemble the work freelancers must do. But the insecurity and self-exploitation of the job have long been accepted as part of the actor’s lot. The actor is at the vanguard of the new economy. Conclusion: Reviving the Naturalist Project Our citational network between Stanislavsky-derived actor training and organizational management is now complete. By comparing similarities between features of practices I have looked for shared ideologies. This process of ‘reading together’ draws attention to the way in which positive aspects of one field (the liberation of the actor’s creative potential, for example) may at the same time support exploitative or damaging aspects in another. While my aim has been primarily critical, having drawn attention to the ideological overlaps between actor training and organizational management, a number of possibilities for action emerge that could have positive benefits both for actors as well as creative industries workers. 24 Firstly, by pointing to actor training’s overlap with the world of business management, the citational network I have drawn demystifies the craft and demands we consider acting labour as labour. Without denying the ‘art’ of acting, a critique of actor’s working conditions is essential at a time when the profession is more precarious than ever. We might draw attention to the discursive way in which unpaid labour is accepted and naturalized in the profession (when Sanford Meisner calls line-learning and substitution exercises ‘homework’ (1990), he blurs labour and leisure). An investigation into unpaid or poorly paid working conditions might have implications for arts funding policy as well as Actor’s Equity guidelines. Furthermore, Hesmondhalgh’s suggestion (2010) that creative industries policy requires detailed empirical analysis of individual creative industries should apply to the special case of acting. Actors do not work in one creative industry, they work across many (theatre, film, television, music, publishing, advertising), their underemployment marking them out as what Marx calls an ‘industrial reserve army’ (Marx 1867[1976]: 784). Why actors would accept these precarious conditions would best be ascertained through empirical research, which might demonstrate the way desire and passion are increasingly mobilized in the creative industries as a means of control. 25 Finally, I agree with Jonathan Chambers’ call for more ‘historical thinking’ in acting (Chambers 2010). Academic theatre departments, by integrating practice and theory, are best placed to lead here. Naturalism was intended to depict the human within the larger social and historical forces that determine his being: this was the aim of Zola, Ibsen, and Chekhov in the late 19th and early 20th century, which was carried into Strasberg and Meisner’s work with the Group Theatre in the 1930s, which staged Clifford Odets’ seminal piece of trade union theatre, Waiting for Lefty, in 1935. But as Colin Counsell (1996) suggests, the process of creating realism on the stage, as interpreted by Stanislavsky and his inheritors is bound up in an ideology of bourgeois individualism. The notion of ‘realist drama’ is a historically and culturally constructed synthesis. The root of drama is ‘action’, and ‘realism’ is meant to reflect life. But life is not constant action in pursuit of objectives. Realist drama therefore reflects life as defined by productivity, managerial ideology at its purest. Perhaps by re-evaluating the ideology of naturalism we might inject some ‘idleness’ into the theatre. Instead of succumbing to the relentless drive of productivity, perhaps the stage is the place where the actor might down tools, and go on strike. References 26 Althusser, Louis (1971). ‘Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses’ in Althusser, Louis (1971). On Ideology. London: Verso, pp. 1-60. Benedetti, Jean (2000). Stanislavsky: An Introduction. London: Methuen. Bilton, Chris (2006). Management and Creativity: From Creative Industries to Creative Management. Hoboken and London: Wiley-Blackwell. — (2010). ‘Manageable Creativity.’ International Journal of Cultural Policy. 16:3, pp. 255-269. Braverman, Harry (1974). Labor and Monopoly Capital: The Degradation of Work in the Twentieth Century. New York: Monthly Review Press. Carnegie, Dale (1936). How to Win Friends and Influence People. London: Vermilion. Carnicke, Sharon Marie (2000). ‘Stanislavsky’s System: Pathways for the actor.’ In Hodge, Alison (ed.). (2000). Twentieth Century Actor Training. London: Routledge, pp. 11-36. Chambers, Jonathan (2010). ‘Actor Training Meets Historical Thinking.’ In Margolis, Ellen and Lissa Tyler Renaud (eds.). (2010). The Politics of American Actor Training. London: Routledge, pp. 31-45. Counsell, Colin (1996). Signs of Performance: An Introduction to TwentiethCentury Theatre. London: Routledge. Department for Culture, Media and Sport. (2001). Creative Industries Mapping Documents 2001. Online. Available at: https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/creative-industries-mappingdocuments-2001. Accessed 12 February 2014. Drucker, Peter F. (1955). The Practice of Management. London: William Heinemann. — (1977). People and Performance: The Best of Peter F. Drucker On Management. London: William Heinemann. Enteman, Willard F. (1993). Managerialism: The Emergence of A New Ideology. Madison and London: University of Wisconsin Press. 27 Evans, Mark (2009). Movement Training for the Modern Actor. London: Routledge. Fayol, Henri (1916)[1971]. ‘General Principles of Management.’ Trans. Storrs, Constance. In Pugh, D.S. (ed). Organization Theory: Selected Readings. London: Penguin. pp. 181-202. Fournier, Valérie, and Chris Grey (2000). ‘At the Critical Moment: Conditions and Prospects for Critical Management Studies.’ Human Relations, 53:1, pp. 732. Hesmondhalgh, David (2010). ‘Normativity and Social Justice in the Analysis of Creative Labour.’ Journal for Cultural Research. 14:3, pp. 231-49. Hesmondhalgh, David and Sarah Baker (2009). ‘“A very complicated version of freedom”: Conditions and experiences of creative labour in three cultural industries.’ Poetics. 38, pp. 4-20. — (2011). Creative Labour: Media Work in Three Cultural Industries. London: Routledge. Hewison, Robert, John Holden and Samuel Jones. (2010). All Together: A Creative Approach to Organisational Change. London: Demos. Hochschild, Arlie Russell (1983). The Managed Heart: Commercialization of Human Feeling. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Hodge, Alison (2000). ‘Introduction.’ In Hodge, Alison (ed). (2000) Twentieth Century Actor Training. London: Routledge. Jackson, Norman and Pippa Carter (1998). ‘Labour as Dressage.’ In McKinlay, Alan and Ken Starkey (eds) (1998) Foucault, Management and Organization Theory: From Panopticon to Technologies of the Self. London: SAGE, pp. 49-64. Lazzarato, Maurizio (1996). ‘Immaterial Labour.’ In Virno, Paolo and Michael Hardt (eds.), Radical Thought in Italy: A Potential Politics, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 133-150. Locke, Robert R. (1996). The Collapse of the American Management Mystique. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Marx, Karl (1867)[1976]. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume I. London: Penguin. 28 McKenzie, Jon (2001). Perform or Else: From Discipline to Performance. London: Routledge. McRobbie, Angela (2002). ‘Clubs to Companies: Notes on the Decline of Political Culture in Speeded Up Creative Worlds.’ Cultural Studies, 16:4, pp. 516-531. Oakley, Kate (2004). ‘Not So Cool Britannia: The Role of the Creative Industries in Economic Development.’ International Journal of Cultural Studies. 7:1, pp. 67-77. O’Connor, Justin (2012). ‘Surrender to the Void: Life After Creative Industries.’ Cultural Studies Review. 18:3, pp. 388-410. Pitches, Jonathan (2003). Vsevelod Meyerhold. London: Routledge. Simkins, Michael (2013). ‘Paul Bhattacharjee and Cory Monteith deaths: is acting today just too tough?’ Guardian Online [Online] Available at: http://www.theguardian.com/stage/2013/jul/23/paul-bhattacharjee-corymonteith-acting [Accessed 2 August 2013]. Stanislavski, Konstantin (2008). An Actor’s Work: A Student’s Diary. Trans. Benedetti, Jean. London: Routledge. Strasberg, Lee (1988). A Dream of Passion: The Development of the Method, London: Methuen. Watson, Tony J. (1997). ‘The labour of division: the manager as “self” and “other”.’ In Hetherington, Kevin and Rolland Munro (eds) (1997) Ideas of Difference: Social Spaces and the Labour of Division. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 139-152. Whyte, William (1957)[2002]. The Organization Man. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. 29