Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2015 Lecture 12 Announcements Office hours cancelled this week, should be back to normal next week HW2 scores online MT2 scores should be online in the next day or two, I’ll send out an email when they are Bluebooks will be returned on Wednesday OK, back to contract law… 1 So far in contract law… What types of promises should be binding contracts? Breach of contract Reliance How liability for breach creates incentive for both, paradox of compensation Default rules C&U: impute the rule the parties would have wanted and apply that That’s whatever rule would have been efficient – allocating each risk to whoever can bear it most cheaply Ayres/Gertner: use default rule to “penalize” one or both Create incentive for one party to reveal information, or for both parties to address contingency in contract 2 Discussion question Old urban legend: A man bought a box of extremely rare and expensive cigars, and insured them against loss or damage. After smoking them, he filed an insurance claim, saying they had been destroyed in 20 separate small fires. The insurance company refused to pay, the man sued and won. But as he was leaving the courtroom, he was arrested on 20 counts of arson. Serious question: If the intent of a contract is clear, but different from the literal meaning, which should be enforced? 3 Wrapping up “penalty defaults” 4 Penalty defaults Ian Ayres and Robert Gertner, “Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules” Sometimes better to make default rule something the parties would not have wanted To give incentive to address an issue rather than leave a gap Or to give one party incentive to disclose information “Penalty default” 5 Penalty defaults: Hadley v Baxendale Baxendale (shipper) is only one who can influence when crankshaft is delivered; so he’s efficient bearer of risk If default rule held Baxendale liable, Hadley has no need to tell him the shipment is urgent, so Baxendale doesn’t know and bad outcome is reached If default rule didn’t hold Baxendale liable for unforeseen damages, Hadley would have to tell him about urgency… …leading to Baxendale making more efficient choices (trading off cost vs speed/reliability correctly) Even though it’s efficient for Baxendale to bear risk, efficient default rule might instead “penalize” Hadley for withholding information! 6 When to use penalty defaults? Look at why the parties left a gap in contract Because of transaction costs use efficient rule For strategic reasons penalty default may be more efficient Similar logic in a Supreme Court dissent by Justice Scalia Congress passed a RICO law without statute of limitations Majority decided on 4 years – what they thought legislature would have chosen Scalia proposed no statute of limitations; “unmoved by the fear that this… might prove repugnant to the genius of our law…” “Indeed, it might even prompt Congress to enact a limitations period that it believes appropriate, a judgment far more within its competence than ours.” 7 When should a contract not be enforced? 8 When should voluntary trade not be allowed? Going back to property law… Coase Theorem: to get efficient outcomes, we should let people trade whenever they want to But also saw some exceptions – some trades that aren’t, and shouldn’t, be allowed Selling enriched uranium to a terrorist Similarly with contract law… First day: to get efficient outcomes, enforce any contract both parties wanted enforced But next, we’ll see exceptions – contracts which shouldn’t be enforced, due to externalities or market failures/transaction costs 9 Example of an unenforceable contract: a contract which breaks the law Obvious: contract to buy a kilo of cocaine is unenforceable 10 Example of an unenforceable contract: a contract which breaks the law Obvious: contract to buy a kilo of cocaine is unenforceable Less obvious: otherwise-legal contract whose real purpose is to circumvent a law Legal doctrine: derogation of public policy Derogate, verb. detract from; curtail application of (a law) Applies to contracts which could only be performed by breaking law… …but also to “innocent” contracts whose purpose is to get around a law or regulation 11 Derogation of public policy – example Labor unions required by law to negotiate “in good faith” Recent NBA labor troubles Old CBA: 57% of “basketball-related income” went to player salaries Owners were offering less than 50%, players demanding 53%... Imagine the following contract: “For the next 50 years, if the NBAPA accepts a CBA paying less than 55% of BRI in player salaries, then we also agree that all non-retired players will work for you as coal miners every offseason at federal minimum wage.” Purpose is purely to “bind hands” in negotiations with ownership Contract would not be enforced 12 Derogation of public policy In general: a contract is not enforceable if it cannot be performed without breaking the law Exception: if promisor knew (and promisee didn’t) I’m married, my girlfriend in California doesn’t know; I promise her I’ll marry her, she quits her job and moves to Madison My company agrees to supply a product that we can’t produce without violating a safety or environmental regulation Keeping either promise would require breaking the law… …but I’d still be liable for damages for breach Like in Ayres and Gertner: default rule penalizes betterinformed party for withholding information 13 Default rules versus regulations Talked earlier about default rules Default rules apply if no other rule is specified… …but can be contracted around Rules like “derogation of public policy” cannot be contracted around Parties to a contract can’t say, “even though this type of contract would normally not be valid, this one is” Rules which always apply: immutable rules, or mandatory rules, or regulations Fifth purpose of contract law is to minimize transaction costs of negotiating contracts by supplying efficient default rules and regulations. 14 Ways to get out of a contract 15 Formation Defenses and Performance Excuses Formation defense Claim that a valid contract does not exist (Example: no consideration) Performance excuse Yes, a valid contract was created But circumstances have changed and I should be allowed to not perform without penalty Most doctrines for invalidating a contract can be explained as either… Individuals agreeing to the contract were not rational, or Transaction cost or market failure 16 One formation defense: incompetence Courts will not enforce contracts with people who can’t be presumed to be rational Children Legally insane Incompetence One party was “not competent to enter into the agreement” No “meeting of the minds” 17 So… If courts won’t enforce a contract signed by someone who wasn’t competent… What if you signed a contract while drunk? You need to have been really, really, really drunk to get out of a contract (“Intoxicated to the extent of being unable to comprehend the nature and consequences of the instrument he executed”) Lucy v. Zehmer, Virginia Sup Ct 1954 18 Lucy v. Zehmer Zehmer and his wife owned a farm (“the Ferguson farm”), Lucy had been trying to buy it for some time While out drinking, Lucy offers $50,000, Zehmer responds, “You don’t have $50,000” “We hereby agree to sell to W.O. Lucy the Ferguson Farm complete for $50,00000, title satisfactory to buyer.” 19 Lucy v. Zehmer Zehmer and his wife owned a farm (“the Ferguson farm”), Lucy had been trying to buy it for some time While out drinking, Lucy offers $50,000, Zehmer responds, “You don’t have $50,000” “We hereby agree to sell to W.O. Lucy the Ferguson Farm complete for $50,00000, title satisfactory to buyer.” 20 Lucy v. Zehmer So, you can be pretty drunk and still be bound by the contract you signed Might think “meeting of the minds” would be impossible But imagine what would happen if the rule went the other way 21 Lucy v. Zehmer So, you can be pretty drunk and still be bound by the contract you signed Might think “meeting of the minds” would be impossible But imagine what would happen if the rule went the other way Borat lawsuits Julie Hilden, “Borat Sequel: Legal Proceedings Against Not Kazahk Journalist for Make Benefit Guileless Americans In Film” Moral of the story: don’t get drunk with people who might ask you to sign a contract 22 Another formation defense: dire constraints 23 Dire constraints Necessity I’m about to starve, someone offers me a sandwich for $10,000 My boat’s about to sink, someone offers me a ride to shore for $1,000,000 Contract would not be upheld: I signed it out of necessity Duress Other party is responsible for situation I’m in “I made him an offer he couldn’t refuse” Contract signed at gunpoint would not be legally enforceable 24 Duress source: http://news.yahoo.com/man-sues-former-hostages-saysbroke-promise-190902970.html 25 Friedman on duress Example Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $100 You write him a check Do you have to honor the agreement? “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable” He did – he wants your $100 You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed So why not enforce it? Makes muggings more profitable leads to more muggings Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior 26 Friedman on duress Example Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $100 You write him a check Do you have to honor the agreement? “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable” He did – he wants your $100 You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed So why not enforce it? Makes muggings more profitable leads to more muggings Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior 27 What about necessity? Same logic doesn’t work for necessity You get caught in a storm on your $1,000,000 sailboat Tugboat offers to tow you to shore for $900,000 (Otherwise he’ll save your life but let your boat sink) Duress: if we enforce contract, incentive for more crimes Necessity: if we enforce contract, incentive for more tugboats to be available to rescue sailboats Why is that bad? 28 What about necessity? “Should I motor around looking for sailboats to save?” Social cost = private cost = value of my time Social benefit = probability x (value of boat – cost of tow) Private benefit = probability x (price I can charge – cost of tow) If tugboat captain can charge the whole value of the boat, he spends efficient amount of time saving sailboats! So maybe we should enforce this contract… 29 What about necessity? “Should I sail today?” Suppose tugboat is there to rescue me if there’s a storm Social benefit = private benefit = how much I enjoy sailing Social cost = probability x cost of tow Private cost = probability x price he can charge If tugboat captain can only charge cost of tow, I sail efficient amount If he can charge the whole value of the boat, I undersail! 30 Friedman’s point Same transaction sets incentives on both parties Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other “Put the incentive where it would do the most good” Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm! 31 Friedman’s point Same transaction sets incentives on both parties Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other “Put the incentive where it would do the most good” Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm! So makes sense for courts to overturn contracts signed under necessity, replace them with ex-ante optimal terms More general point Single price creates multiple incentives May be impossible to get efficient behavior in all dimensions 32 Real duress versus fake duress Court won’t enforce contracts signed under threat of harm “Give me $100 or I’ll shoot you” But many negotiations contain threats “Give me a raise, or I’ll quit” “$3,000 is my final offer for the car, take it or I walk” The difference? Threat of destruction of value versus failure to create value A promise is enforceable if extracted as price of cooperating in creating value; not if it was extracted by threat to destroy value 33 Example: Alaska Packers’ Association v Domenico (US Ct App 1902) Captain hires crew in Seattle for fishing expedition to Alaska In Alaska, crew demands higher wages or they’ll quit, captain agrees Back in Seattle, captain refuses to pay the higher wages, claiming he agreed to them under duress Court ruled for captain Since crew had already agreed to do the work, no new consideration was given for promise of higher wage 34 A performance excuse: impossibility 35 Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility When performance becomes impossible, should promisor owe damages, or be excused from performing? A perfect contract would explicitly state who bears each risk Contract may give clues as to how gaps should be filled Industry custom might be clear But in some cases, court must fill gap 36 Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach But there are exceptions Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made” 37 Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach But there are exceptions Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made” Efficiency requires assigning liability to the party that can bear the risk at least cost How to determine who that is? 38 Who is the efficient bearer of a particular risk? Friedman offers several bases for making this determination Spreading losses across many transactions Moral hazard: who is in better position to influence outcome? 39 Who is the efficient bearer of a particular risk? Friedman offers several bases for making this determination Spreading losses across many transactions Moral hazard: who is in better position to influence outcome? Adverse selection: who is more aware of risk, even if he can’t do anything about it? “…The party with control over some part of the production process is in a better position both to prevent losses and to predict them. It follows that an efficient contract will usually assign the loss associated with something going wrong to the party with control over that particular something.” 40 That’s why Hadley v Baxendale was “surprising” Baxendale (shipper) could influence speed of delivery, Hadley could not So Baxendale was efficient bearer of the risk of delay Court ruled he didn’t owe damages for lost profits, forcing Hadley to bear much of this risk Only makes sense as a “penalty default” Rule creates incentive for Hadley to reveal urgency of this shipment 41