Chapter 19 SOCIAL WELFARE AND PUBLIC CHOICE A. The Social Welfare Function .................................................................................... 1 1. The Pareto Criterion................................................................................................ 2 Pareto Optimality ........................................................................................................ 2 2. Compensation ............................................................................................................ 2 3. Potential Compensation ............................................................................................. 2 Kaldor Criterion .......................................................................................................... 2 Scitovsky criterion ...................................................................................................... 2 4. Arrow's Impossibility Theorem ................................................................................. 3 (1) Efficiency and the Pareto Rule. ......................................................................... 3 (2) Comprehensive Applicability............................................................................ 3 (3) Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives ........................................................... 3 B. Theory of the Second Best ............................................................................................ 4 The Pigovian Approach .............................................................................................. 4 The Coasian Approach ................................................................................................ 5 transaction costs ........................................................................................................ 6 C. Constitutions and Voting Rules .................................................................................. 7 Robert's “Rules of Order ............................................................................................. 8 1. Unanimity .......................................................................................................... 8 2. Dictatorship ........................................................................................................ 8 3. Majority Rule ..................................................................................................... 8 4. Plurality Rule ..................................................................................................... 8 5. Ladders:........................................................................................................... 9 6. Condorcet Procedure .......................................................................................... 9 7. Social Rankings ................................................................................................. 9 In making collective choices, two questions must be addressed; what choice should be made (the normative question) and what choices are made (the positive question). In examining the collective choices made through our legal system economists try to establish what normative criteria to use in deciding collective choices (sections A and B below). They also study in Public Choice theory, what choices are actually made (section C). To illustrate such choices it is useful to examine the case of the Montreal Protocol which banned CFCs (chlorofluorocarbons) and how Dupont, one of the chief producers of CFCs had to react. A. The Social Welfare Function Economists have tried to find a way to determine the optimum choices for society. Ideally, we would want a social welfare function which for any set of alternatives would be able to rank the alternatives according to their contribution to social welfare. With such a ranking, it would then be possible to choose the best social choice. 1 1. The Pareto Criterion There are a few criteria which have gained acceptance as the basis for social choices. The Pareto criterion has unquestioning acceptance. It states: A change is desirable for society if it makes at least one person better off without making anyone worse off. If society is at a point where no further Pareto changes can be made then it has achieved Pareto Optimality. Such a criterion is acceptable as far as it goes, but it does not go very far. How many important issues provide a choice where no one is made worse off compared to the other choices? If there were such a choice, it wouldn’t be an issue that would take much time to solve. Society needs to make decisions on many issues where someone will be made worse off for each alternative choice. The CFC phaseout is an example of such an issue; to make the world safe against ultraviolet radiation the producers and consumers of CFCs have to make substantial sacrifices. 2. Compensation If someone is to be made worse off, it might be possible to compensate them for a socially desirable change. In other words, a choice might be structured where the people who are made worse off receive enough money that they are happy with the change. But the issue returns back to the Pareto criterion; taking into account the compensation, is everyone better off with the change or not? Compensation involves its own burden; there are costs of making transactions including the costs of transferring resources from one group to another, the costs of deciding who should receive the transfers, and the costs of studying the problem in the first place. Compensation can actually make society less efficient, causing some people to be worse off than if no action were taken. In the CFC issue, the government could compensate Du Pont, other producers, and even users for their material losses due to a CFC prohibition. However, such compensation might be too costly and make compensation impractical. 3. Potential Compensation Perhaps, a social change might be considered desirable if it could be shown that losers could potentially be compensated. Compensation would not actually have to be made. This criterion, is often referred to as the Kaldor Criterion. However, suppose compensation were made and then the losers could find a way to return the compensation to get their way back again. The problem of such contradictory directions in compensation can be corrected by the Scitovsky criterion. Scitovsky suggested that a change could be superior if it met the Kaldor criterion and it was not possible for the losers to compensate back to stop the change. 2 Society could decide that it would be willing to pay $200 billion to compensate the producers and users of CFCs for ending CFC use. If the producers and users were willing to accept such compensation for ending production then the Kaldor criterion would be satisfied. If compensation were not actually made, society might be potentially better off without the CFCs, but be simultaneously actually worse off by failing to compensate the producers and users. If the producers would not be willing to compensate all of those losing their lives if CFCs were continued to be used, the Scitovsky Criterion would declare in favor of regulating CFCs. But suppose, after receiving $200 billion, the producers and users could turn around and compensate everyone made ill by CFC production. Now both the Kaldor Criterion and the Scitovsky Criteria would fail to make a choice. 4. Arrow's Impossibility Theorem Kenneth Arrow, a winner of the Nobel prize in Economics, has shown that it is not possible to establish preference rankings for a group of individuals based solely on the preference rankings of the individuals in the group. He introduced several basic criteria that should not be violated by any such social preference ranking: (1) Efficiency and the Pareto Rule. If everyone prefers one choice to another, then the social preference ranking should correctly choose that rule. This means that the social preference ranking should be efficient in choosing what all individuals unanimously rank as most desirable. (2) Comprehensive Applicability. The social preference ranking should apply to any combination of possible individual preference rankings. (3) Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives. The choice between any two alternatives should be decided only on the basis of individual preferences for the two choices and should be independent of any other alternatives. For example, vote trading and logrolling practiced by legislators would not be possible by this criterion. The only rule which satisfies these criteria is the rule of dictatorship. However, such a rule is clearly a socially and politically undesirable way to run a household, a corporation or a government. Without the possibility of defining a social welfare function, it is no longer possible to define what the “public interest” might be. This is potentially a problem when crucial cases, such as Munn v. Illinois, which are the cornerstone to legal economic regulatory theory define and depend upon the concept of “public interest.” Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem leads to the conclusion that there will be some point at which an arbitrary decision must be made which determines what the public interest is. From a legal perspective, such arbitrariness means that it may not be possible to determine what is in the best interest of society, even if we were to know the desires and priorities of every member of society- which, of course, we almost never know anyway. American legal practice has evolved through time in how the public interest is to be 3 defined. Attempts by the court to determine what is in the public interest have been frequent and have frequently been failures. For example, the attempt to define a “fair” rate of return in Smyth v. Ames1 resulted in decades of complex judgments and confusion until the court finally relented in Hope Natural Gas.2 As a result, the court increasingly defers to the judgments of agencies in the Executive Branch of government to make determinations of what is in the public interest. When such agencies fail to use “due process” in determining what is in the public interest they may be accused of “arbitrariness and capriciousness.” In other words, in their role as the dictators who determine the public interest they are not using adequate procedures for deciding public choices. B. Theory of the Second Best Can there be any system of law or public choice if the public interest- and social welfare- cannot be defined? Even if a welfare function could be defined, we might not be able to use it- virtually any change would require a revaluation of all possible choices to determine how the public interest changes. Instead we must look for “second best” solutions which can be used without requiring constant recalculation of social welfare. Rather than trying to redistribute all resources with every change in social welfare, it is more reasonable to choose incrementally- in other words, to choose what departures are to be made from the current distribution of resources and wealth, which are called “endowments.” Such changes in endowments recognize that people have property rights in resources that must be respected and that any departures from the current endowment must meet certain criteria. But what criteria should be used? While it may not be possible to argue from a global perspective what is in the best interest of a community when examining a range of different choices, it may be possible to use an efficiency argument for determining responsibilities of members of a society. In this section two economic approaches are presented. One, the approach of Pigou, simply defines what property rights are and assigns responsibility for property losses on the basis of what private party causes the property loss. Such an approach is efficient because it is relatively simple to determine. The other, the approach of Coase, seeks to minimize social costs when property rights must be violated, which can become quite complex, particularly private costs are intangible. 1. The Pigovian Approach 1 Smyth V. Ames, 169 U.S. 466 (1898) 2 Federal Power Com'n v. Hope Natural Gas Co., 320 U.S. 591 (1944) 4 Arthur Pigou3 provided a “second best” approach to the public interest in defining how negative externalities should be treated. He suggested that the person who causes an externality should be the person who pays for getting rid of that externality. Economists refer to this as the internalization of externalities. It can be accomplished through taxation, prohibition, or any number of other government interventions, but it also can be taken care of by simply compensating the third parties who are affected by the externalities. However, the problem of externalities depends upon two people, not just one. For example, a pioneer in the early days of the West might pollute a river with the waste of farmyard animals without anyone feeling the effect of the externality. It is not until someone moves in downstream who must use the polluted water that the externality becomes a problem. Pigou’s criterion would require the polluter to pay the downstream user or stop polluting. If the polluter doesn’t pay then the downstream user experiences costs. Someone must lose out. 2. The Coasian Approach Table A. Options for Solving the Rancher-Cowboy Problem using the Coase Approach transaction Cost Cost Homesteader owns land Cowboys have right to graze (res communes) a. Allow cattle to roam (cowboy pays damages) b. Put up fences c. Pay homesteaders not to plant d. Don't run cattle through ranches MIN social cost a. Allow cattle to roam (homesteader suffers damages) b. Put up fences c. Don't plant crops d. Pay cowboys not to run cattle. MIN social cost Total Cost 90 110 0 0 90 110 100 0 100 200 0 200 90 90 110 100 0 0 0 90 110 100 200 0 200 90 Ronald Coase recognized that the different solutions to such a problem lead to different social costs. The social cost of a solution is the sum of the private costs to the different parties. Coase recommended that the social cost be minimized. For example, Table A represents a problem faced in the Midwest during the last half of the 19th century. Ranchers wanted to put up barbed wire to protect their property from grazing by passing herds being run between Texas and Kansas by Cowboys. Suppose the Ranchers are entitled to the right to enclose their land in barbed wire. Then four options might be 3 Arthur Pigou. The Economics of Welfare 9New York: AMS Press, 1978 [1924] 5 those shown in the top four rows in Table A. On the other hand, the same options shown in the bottom four rows of that table apply to the situation where the Cowboys are entitled to the use of the land. Minimizing total cost is the same regardless of who has the entitlement! If the parties to the transaction have complete information and there are no “transaction” costs- costs of researching, deciding and making any compensations or exchanges-, Coase was able to show that entitlements didn’t matter to the minimum social cost solution. It would result in the same choice- although there would be a change in who would be compensated (ie. There is a change in endowments). On the other hand, Table B shows what might happen if there are transaction costs. Now the minimums of total costs are different, depending upon who owns the property right to the land. Table B. Change in Choices with transaction costs. Options Homesteader owns land a. Allow cattle to roam (cowboy pays damages) b. Put up fences c. Pay homesteaders not to plant d. Don't run cattle through ranches Cost 90 Transaction Cost 25 Total Cost 115 110 100 200 0 25 0 110 125 200 MIN social cost Cowboys have right to graze MIN social cost 110 a. Allow cattle to roam (homesteader suffers damages) b. Put up fences c. Don't plant crops d. Pay cowboys not to run cattle. 90 0 90 110 100 200 0 0 25 110 100 225 90 In Table B each of the four options have a different transactions cost, depending upon who owns the entitlement to the use of the land. For example, option “a” which allows the cattle to roam might involve $25.00 of transaction costs to the ranchers because they would have such a high cost of getting the cowboys to pay. But if the cowboys had the entitle to roam, they would need to do nothing; the only costs would be the private costs of the ranchers who would have to pay for the damages from the grazing. On the other hand, option “d” which would require the farmers to pay the cowboys for not running cattle would be tough to collect by the cowboys. But, if the farmer owned the entitlement, there would be no compensation needed if the cowboys didn’t run their cattle. These differences in transaction costs depend upon who owns the entitlement. Now entitlement ownership does make a difference in which option is chosen. Even defining who has an entitlement has transaction costs. Legal cases often are about defining property rights and legal costs are important transaction costs. Choices by 6 legislatures usually involve issues of defining entitlements. Lobbying often imposes large transaction costs. Decision making in the legislature imposes large transaction costs on society, if not the direct parties to a dispute. Because of large transaction costs the socially optimal choice may never be made and many potentially beneficial compensations may never occur. C. Constitutions and Voting Rules Combined with Arrow's Impossibility theorem, the compensation principles provide an inadequate basis for justifying cost-benefit analysis or other types of government studies. The lack of theory has not slowed the evolution and development of new types of government studies. Each agency has developed its own format for different kinds of studies. Because of the large number of different kinds of studies, Cost benefit analysis or any other type of study are rarely the final word to decision making because decision making is inherently a political process. A general manager must be adept in this political process, but there often is little in the experience in lower tiers of a firm which prepares a manager for the political battles that face the firm. Irv Shapiro of Du Pont once characterized the difference as follows: "In the business world, we optimize; in the political world, we compromise. In business, you look for efficiency. The financial analysis tells you that if you do this, you will get these results; if you do that, you will get other results. At that point, a businessman makes a decision."4 But in the political world, that's just the beginning of the analysis. Then you ask, 'Where are the political pressures? What is the political interest? What are the constituency groups? How do you respond to everybody's aspirations?' And so you're always working out compromises. In business, your goals are more precise and measurable. Everybody in a company has the same objective. “... it's quite different than it is in the public sector, where compromise is the only way to make progress."5 In this process of compromise, the general manager must find allies, convert others to the firm's point of view, and decide what the firm must give up to get what it needs. The focus on the number of people needed to reach an agreement is not a choice on the merits of a decision, but a choice about the procedure used to make a decision. In a football game, the question is not which team is better (decision on the merits), but rather which rules should they play by (decision on procedure). In fact the appeals procedure in our judicial system is designed not to review the merits of a case, but only to analyze whether proper procedure was used to decide the case. Decisions about procedure are decisions about how to make choices, not decisions about what choice to make. 4 5 Shook, op. cit. p. 226 Shook, op. cit. p. 226 7 Often the choice of the way to make decisions will determine the outcome of decisions. This is as true for the political process outside of the firm as it is for the political process within the firm. A manager must understand how to set up and control the rules of how decisions are made in order to maintain control over the content of the decisions. The format for decision making is established by a constitution. The constitution may take the formal shape of the U.S. Constitution in our political system, the Robert's “Rules of Order” in a parliament or meeting, or the standard operating procedures (S.O.P.) of a firm. A constitution sets out priorities for handling different issues and the voting procedures for coming to agreement. Unfortunately economists have found that no one voting procedure can be efficient in making the correct, socially most desired choice, decisive in insuring that a choice is in fact made, and equitable in the treatment of all individual decision makers. In fact organizations use a variety of different rules for making group decisions, each of which has at least one deficiency in meeting the criteria of efficiency, decisiveness, and equity: 1. Unanimity: All members of the group must agree. This is the criterion implicitly required by the Pareto rule. While it is the best rule for the purpose of efficiency and equity, it rarely leads to decisive choices. Unanimity may allow any individual to impede everyone else and to extract a payment for cooperation. Unanimity is so obstructive to action that it often breeds the frustration which overturns it, and replaces it with its opposite, dictatorship. 2. Dictatorship: When one individual dictates the choices for the whole group, decisiveness is achieved. However, such decision making is completely inequitable, since no one else has a contribution to make. It is also highly inefficient since there is no channel for taking into account the preferences of others. Dictatorship is popular in wars or battles for the survival of companies, but over long periods of time it is likely to breed corruption and inefficiency. 3. Majority Rule: Fifty percent of the population plus one person can determine a social choice. However, if that many people are not able to come to an agreement on matters, then the majority rule becomes indecisive. The rule is inefficient since as much as 50% minus one person do not have preferences that are consistent with the social choice. The rule is inequitable to the extent that these people can be ignored if the majority so decides. 4. Plurality Rule: Whoever receives the highest vote wins. It is usually decisive. This rule is identical to the majority rule whenever there are only two choices. However, when there are more than two choices, then the choice backed by a strident minority can win, even though a majority would have chosen one of the other choices in any two-way 8 election. Plurality is therefore extremely inefficient. It is also inequitable since it potentially excludes an even greater population than the majority rule. 5. Ladders: In football, baseball, tennis and many other sports, playoff ladders are used to successively eliminate teams in a series of playoffs that eventually narrow to a winner; such ladders are decisive. However, ladders often produce winners who few people would consider the best teams or the best players. Perhaps the winner had an "easy draw" of opponents in one side of the ladder or perhaps the best player was eliminated early because of a bad day and never had a chance to play the eventual winner. The ladder is therefore inefficient and often inequitable. To improve equity and efficiency, the Condorcet procedure should be used. 6. Condorcet Procedure: Every possible pairing of choices is made and the choice that wins in all of its paired contests wins. Unfortunately it's rare that someone wins in all contests which means the rule is indecisive. However, the rule is efficient in reflecting the truly desired choice and is equitable in allowing all possible choices to be considered. 7. Social Rankings (Borda Count): Different choices can be ranked by different members of an organization and then these ranks can be combined and compared for each possible choice. While being fairly equitable, such rankings permit extensive gaming by individuals who learn how to give rankings that do not reflect their actual preferences but which will give added likelihood for their choice to win; such rankings can therefore be inefficient in reflecting what is socially desirable. Between the extremes of dictatorship and unanimity there is a range of choices about how many people are needed to decide an issue. The majority rule requires that any choice be made by 50% of the people plus one. However, some decisions, such as the changing of the U.S. Constitution requires a 3/5 vote of the states. To start a meeting it is sometimes necessary to have a certain minimum number of people in attendance, called a quorum. In each of these cases, a choice has been made about where the cost minimum can be achieved when both the costs of gathering people together to agree and the external costs of excluding people are considered. In the social choice on the CFC issue, we can see examples of several of the voting procedures. The Montreal Protocol set down a voting rule by which countries would ratify the phaseout of CFCs. If eleven countries ratified the treaty and those eleven accounted for at least 2/3 of CFC production then the Protocol would go into effect.6 Such a rule reflected the tension between considering countries as political units and considering the size of their impact© a tension reflected in the set up of the U.S. Congress which distinguishes between the Senate (the political units) and the House of Representatives (chosen on the basis of the size of population). Philip Shabecoff."Industry Acts to Curb Peril in Ozone Loss" in ”The New York Times” (March 21, 1988) p. 11 6 9 When the Senate considered the Montreal Protocol it voted 83-0 in favor of ratifying the Protocol. Such a unanimous decision was not required; only two-thirds of the senators were needed to ratify a treaty. Here we have a rare example of a unanimous decision. The very fact of the unanimity in the Senate suggests what a lopsided issue the problem of CFCs had become by 1988. Nevertheless, from the point of view of Du Pont, the issue was not so clear. A firm favors a much more decisive decision making process than U.S. society as a whole. Usually they appoint a CEO who seems to have the powers of a dictator. But let's look at a the decision making process at Du Pont as described by the late former CEO Irv Shapiro: In all companies ,...., the chief executive has a board that's looking over his shoulder and holding him accountable. If he tried to play the game of creating short-term gains that would make him look good but would hurt the company years from now, the directors would soon raise the question, 'Are you doing the right thing?' So he'd be held accountable. But if the selection process has worked properly, the person in the job knows better than to play the game that way, in any case. 7 We have evidence here of something less than dictatorship. The board is a representative of the stockholders. If the board exerts its power, a firm can rapidly be governed by a representative government, not a dictatorship. It was Du Pont's chairman of the board, R. E. Heckert, who announced to the U.S. Senate that it was premature for Du Pont to end CFC production. It was also R. E. Heckert, who two weeks later, after the meeting on the Montreal Protocol and more evidence from the National Air and Space Administration (NASA) on ozone damage, who reversed Du Pont's position. Du Pont agreed to phase out its CFC production. One of the advantages of a dictatorship or a small number of decision makers is the speed with which action can be taken. 7 op. cit. pp. 211-2 10