A response to the skeptic Phil 2233, Fall 2007 Some things I know about the past • I had scrambled eggs for breakfast this morning. • John F. Kennedy was assassinated in 1963. • Glaciers spread across northern Europe and North America within the last 20,000 years. • Trilobites were arthropods that thrived during the Paleozoic era. Justifying such claims • I remember eating the eggs • I remember JFK’s assassination and that it took place during the year I was in grade 2, i.e. in 1963. • I’ve directly seen evidence of glaciation (striations, polished pavements, kettle lakes, moraines, drumlins, etc.) and I’ve also read a lot about the evidence, its history, and the conclusions geologists have drawn from it. • I’ve seen fossils of trilobites and read about them as well. Their place in the geological column is securely settled (they only occur in Paleozoic strata), and they are classified as arthropods because they have certain features that are shared with, and only with, other arthropods. The skeptic’s response • Someone defending a general skepticism about the past looks for some assumption that plays a role in all these justifications, a vulnerability that they all share. • And they do have something in common: They all depend on assumptions about processes linking facts about the present situation to some fact(s) about the past. Historical evidence • When it comes to documented historical events a number of different processes are involved. Events occur; some people perceive them, report them, and they are subsequently recorded in various kinds of documents. • These documents may persist into the present, or we may only have copies of copies of copies. But so long as the processes involved in making those copies reliably preserve reliable information originally encoded in the first records, we can reach conclusions about the past by reading these records. Geology • The same goes for geological evidence: processes take place during glaciation, when an organism is fossilized, as sediment is laid down, etc. These processes leave traces that persist[1] over time. • Then we can find out about glaciation, past life and etc. by studying the traces that exist today. • In general, a present trace encodes information about a past event because of a process linking that event and certain facts about it to the present existence and features of the trace. • [1] Note that persisting is really just another kind of process. The Skeptical Argument • Processes take place over time. So any knowledge we have about processes depends on having knowledge about the past. • To justify my knowledge claims about the past, I need more than just knowledge of the present traces. I also need knowledge of the processes that produced them. • So I need knowledge of the past to justify knowledge claims about the past. • We are stuck in a circle—to justify a claim about the past, we must already know something about the past. So if our knowledge about the past must be founded exclusively on knowledge about the present, we can’t have any knowledge of the past at all. Radical skepticism about the past • No matter what we now observe, we can’t justify inferring anything about what has happened before. • In particular, from this point of view nothing rules out the infamous ‘five minute hypothesis’, which holds that the entire world came into existence only five minutes ago, with all our ‘memories’, ‘historical records’, ‘fossils’ (both in the ground and in the museums), and other traces of the ‘past’ just as we find them to be. Comments on the 5-minute hypothesis • We cannot prove that this silly story is fiction using only our present observations. • Without claims about past processes to draw on, we can’t make any inferences from present evidence to conclusions about the past. • The five minute hypothesis is logically compatible with our present evidence, including the evidence we normally regard as clearly demonstrating certain facts about the past. The five minute hypothesis blocks all our common-sense inferences about the past. From this perspective, present evidence imposes no constraints at all on what might have happened in the past. The Criterion • Skeptical circles like this are familiar puzzles. They go back to an ancient argument called ‘the wheel,’ also known as the problem of the criterion. • The wheel argument is far more general than our puzzle about the past: It asks, “how can we have knowledge of truth?” • We do take certain claims to be true, and we reject other claims as false; if someone asks us how we decide what claims are true (and what claims are false), we must describe some method(s) we use to separate these truths and falsehoods. Let’s suppose that the methods we come up with really do support the claim we’ve made. The trap • Next, our questioner asks how we know that our criterion is a good one. This simple question puts us in an awkward position! • We can say that there is some higher-order criterion (a criterion for good criteria) that this criterion meets. But then our questioner will ask how we know this new criterion is a good one, and we’re off on a regress that seems to be endless. Or we can say the criterion is a good one because it picks out sentences we know are true. But then the skeptic points out that we invoked the criterion in the first place to justify our choice of sentences. Therefore it’s circular for us to appeal to our sentences to justify the criterion. At this point it seems all we can do is to look dazed and sorry. Back to the past • It seems that we cannot justify our claims about processes without appealing to facts about what has happened in the past. Further, we cannot justify claims about the past without some knowledge of the processes linking present evidence about the world to past facts about the world. • The result of taking such arguments to be conclusive is wholesale skepticism, and wholesale skepticism is very unattractive. Far better to find a response to the skeptic’s challenge that preserves a healthy common sense account of what we know and what we don’t. Resisting the skeptic • Resistance begins with a diagnosis of where things have gone wrong. • If we assume that we start with no idea at all of what is true or how to tell truth from falsehood, then the problem of the criterion is serious trouble. • If we have no idea what’s true or how to tell if a sentence is true, then there’s nothing for us to go on. In fact, from this empty point of view we have no idea of what ‘true’ (or ‘the past’) might mean, and no idea of how to find out! • But you can’t find something out unless you have some idea of how to tell when you’ve got it right. You can’t even begin when you have no idea what you’re looking for. A better approach • We’re better off if we start with a reasonable list of things that we think are true, and some criteria for truth. • Then we have something we can build on: We can compare the things we take to be true with what we get by applying the criteria we have to decide what’s true and what isn’t. • We can improve on our criteria by considering the results of applying various criteria and examining how they fit with what we take to be true. And we can improve on what we think is true by applying our criteria and adjusting our beliefs to fit the results of applying them. Applying this to the past • Similarly, we can study processes as they occur, and study the detailed physics and chemistry involved in them as well. And we can compare this information against what we already believe about the past. • Over time this allows us to extend and improve the fit between our criteria and our beliefs: We come to describe ourselves, our methods and their results in rich and detailed ways that fit together to support the conclusion that by using these methods we can reliably know these this about our world.