Notes on the Myth of Jones: 1. Sellars’ Myth begins with section XII of EPM, ‘Our Rylean Ancestors’. The aim of this section is to lay out the resources that Jones will have available to him at the outset. This includes, we soon discover, not only a language for describing ‘the properties of public objects located in space and enduring through time’ (178), but also logical apparatus including truth functions, quantification and subjunctive conditionals (conditionals describing what would happen if something else were to occur or be done), and the ‘vagueness’ and ‘open texture’ of a natural language. 2. The puzzle, for Sellars, is how a language like this could come to include talk of ‘inner episodes and immediate experiences’. His view is that this apparatus, together with semantical discourse (which our Rylean ancestors apply to overt language), is enough to allow our ancestors to invent, as a kind of theory, an account of inner episodes corresponding to thoughts and immediate experience (sensations). (Recall here that for Sellars talk of meanings, denotations, naming, etc. is primarily translational in force, linking words and sentences whose roles in the normative system of a language correspond in a certain way. This is the material we need to be able to talk about intentionality, which brings us very close to talking of thoughts. ) 3. Contemporary Ryleans have drawn the line here, and declared that talk of thoughts is just (complex, hypothetical/subjunctive) talk about overt speech. But the classical tradition has instead made thoughts and their intentionality primitive, and relegated overt speech’s intentionality to secondary status: language, the tradition holds, is intentional only because it expresses thoughts, which are truly, intrinsically intentional. Sellars aims towards an account that differs from both of these, one which accepts thoughts (and sensations) as real (occurrent/categorical) inner episodes, but which holds the intentionality of language comes first and is not derivative from the prior intentionality of thoughts. 4. Here Sellars turns to an account of ‘Theories and Models’. His reasons for this short aside are pretty straightforward. There is a sense in which Sellars regards thoughts and sensations as theoretical entities—but there is also a sense in which they are clearly not theoretical entities. As I see it, the line is drawn at the straightforward use of talk of thoughts and sensations in reports (i.e. claims made without inference or use of bridge rules). When a ‘theory’ acquires a well-fleshed out reporting use, it is no longer merely a theory. 5. Two important points about theories are made along the way. First, with analogy (and metaphor) we use systems of familiar objects interacting in familiar ways to construct (with the help of commentaries qualifying the resemblances and differences involved) to construct theories (rather than construct pure, abstract structures by explicit postulation). Second, Sellars believes that this sort of theorizing is nothing new, but rather a (refined) version of something that has been going on in ordinary language and thought forever. The upshot is that, if we think of these inner episodes not as occurrent ghosts of hypothetical/dispositional properties, but as theoretical entities posited to explain certain facts about human behaviour (and later acquiring the reporting use they now have), we are clearly not confused or making a category mistake (as we might be if we reified the mere dispositions involved in a strictly Rylean account of talk about thinking). 6. Another aside follows, this time about behaviourism. It’s in this section that we first meet Jones, the hero of Sellars Myth. Jones is explicitly identified here as a behaviourist. But Sellars’ methodological behaviourism is not nearly as restrictive as some other forms that behaviourism has taken. 7. First, philosophical or analytical behaviourism has held that common-sense mental discourse (talk of thoughts and of sensations) should be analysed in terms of behaviour (both actual behaviour and hypothetical/conditional behaviour). Methodological behaviourism does not demand such an analysis. Neither does it hold that introspection (i.e. the ability to report our own thoughts and sensations without needing to observe our own behaviour) is somehow fishy and to be rejected as a source of knowledge. But it does note that the resulting reports make use of a vocabulary that we learned at mothers’ knee, and that is not the product of a refined, critical scientific effort to understand human behaviour. So the methodological behaviourist adopts a reserved stand, and proposes to make only guarded use of ordinary mentalistic discourse while developing concepts that can be part of a more scientific account of human behaviour. 8. On the other hand, behaviourism does require that these new, scientific concepts have some sort of connection to behaviour. Some suppose that they, at least (if not ordinary mentalistic discourse) should be analysable in terms of behaviour. But Sellars regards this requirement as far too restrictive. Physics, in particular, does not require that its theoretical concepts all be analysable in terms of the concepts we use to report the phenomena physical theories aim to explain. Instead, Sellars declares, ‘The behaviouistic requirement that all concepts should be introduced in terms of a basic vocabulary pertaining to overt behaviour is compatible with the idea that some behaviouristic concepts are to be introduced as theoretical concepts.’ (185) 9. Not only are these theoretical concepts not defined in terms of behaviour, they are also not defined in physiological terms. While we expect some relation to emerge in the long run, connecting behavioural concepts to the details of neurophysiology, these concepts begin as part of a distinct and separate science (see the discussion of reduction and relations between different sciences in PSIM on page 21f) and don’t include any assumptions about this in their own right. In this regard, considered as ‘pure’ concepts for a theory concerning human behaviour, there is no assumption here at all regarding how they will relate to the concepts of other theories we employ to describe human beings in other respects. 10. Finally, we’re ready for Jones’ theory, ‘according to which overt utterances are but the culmination of a process which begins with certain inner episodes. And let us suppose that his model for these episodes which initiate the events which culmjinate in overt verbal behaviour is that of overt verbal behaviour itself. In other words, using the language of the model, the theory is to the effect that overt verbal behaviour is the culmination of a process which begins with ‘inner speech’.’ (Nb. This ‘inner speech is not verbal imagery—at this point verbal imagery is not even a concept Jones, or his fellows, has.) These inner episodes are then invoked to account for intelligent behaviour in general, not just speech. And one feature that carries over from the model (overt speech) to the theory (thought episodes) is the semantical characters of speech. So thoughts have meanings, may denote or name things, and so forth: thoughts, in broad, are intentional—but not because they have some special magic about them; they are intentional because they are modeled on overt speech, which we already recognize and treat as intentional. 11. Finally, when we begin to describe ourselves in terms of this language, we find that individuals can learn to describe themselves successfully (here various predictions /vindications come in) in its terms without requiring the (full) behavioural evidence that others require to arrive at the same descriptions. That is, it turns out (as a matter of fact) that (in practice) individuals have a kind of privileged access to their own thoughts. ‘What began as a language with a purely theoretical use has gained a reporting role’ (189). 12. The upshot is that the privacy of thought is not the puzzling fundamental sort of privacy that underwrites skepticism regarding other minds. The concepts of these inner episodes are intersubjective first, and come to have a private aspect as a matter of (vindicated, successful) practice evaluated in terms of these intersubjective criteria. ‘(T)he fact that overt behaviour is evidence for these episodes is built into the very logic of these concepts, just as the fact that the observable behaviour of gases is evidence for molecular episodes is built into the very logic of molecule talk.’ (189) 13. Finally Sellars turns to impressions (or sensations), which he regards (as you should recall from PSIM and BBK) as modeled on the sensible features of ordinary (MI) objects. This is Sellars’ answer to the question, what (aside from what he has called the propositional content) is in common between “I see a red triangle over there”, “I see a triangle over there that looks red”, and “It looks as though there is a red triangle over there”, i.e. what is the common descriptive content of these reports? The answer is (in the same in-between sense as for thoughts) a kind of theory, a theory according to which ‘replicas’ of objects perceived occur in us when we look at/touch/etc things in the public world under standard conditions, and such replicas can also occur under non-standard conditions, when objects ‘similar or corresponding to’ the replicas are not actually present. (Sellars emphasizes that these replicas are what occur in us, not seeings of such replicas, which would lead us to assimilate sensations to cognitive states & thoughts in general.) 14. Since impressions are introduced as theoretical entities, they are taken to have their own intrinsic characteristics (modeled on, but certainly not to be confused with, the sensible characteristics of MI objects). So they are not just picked out by definite descriptions as “the sort of sensory state caused in standard conditions by ___ and in other conditions by …, ---, ***, etc”. But the way in which the theory is built on and connected to the Rylean language that Jones starts with ensures that there is a logical connection between the language we use to describe these impressions and the sensible properties of objects viewed (sensed) under standard conditions. 15. Sellars rejects again the appeal to ‘ostensive definition’ as the source of our understanding of these intrinsic characteristics of impressions. Once again, this notion is just the myth of the given all over again. (Recall here Descartes’ notion that our awareness of our own states of mind is in terms of adequate conceptions/ ideas of them, which Sellars rejects in BBK. The fact that as with thoughts, we find ourselves able to report these states in ourselves without needing the overt behavioural evidence our fellows need to reach the same conclusions provides a reporting use for this theory, and makes it more than just a theory for us. But this does not show that we have a better grasp of these characteristics (let alone an absolute and fixed and indispensable set of concepts in terms of which to describe our impressions) than we have of the sensible properties of public objects. Quite the reverse is true, in fact—our concepts of these features of our impressions are grounded in our prior grasp of these features of public objects, and our understanding and use of them is, like our understanding and use of ‘thought-talk’, grounded in the public realm where interaction with our fellows can put the requisite norms in place. 16. How these impressions relate to science, and in particular to micro-physics, is considered on pages 193f. We’ve already seen some aspects of this story in PSIM, and there’s not much more to say about it here. The story finishes with Sellars final diagnostic remarks on sense-data theory and the myth of the given. The idea there is that the sense-datum theorist learns to report (with greater and greater detail and refinement) the features of these impressions (as we all can do), but ‘confuses his own creative enrichment of the framework of empirical knowledge, with an analysis of knowledge as it was’ (and goes on to try to reconstruct ordinary sensory knowledge of the world on the thin basis of these descriptions of his impressions). Sellars concludes ‘It is in the very act of taking that he speaks of the given.’ 17. In the end, Sellars endorses his own myth: ‘does the reader not recognize Jones as Man himself in the middle of his journey from the grunts and groans of the cave to the subtle and polydimensional discourse of the drawing room, the laboratory, and the study,…’ (196).