Zapatista movement(p,338) (organs without bodies, 217) As the Zapatistas create autonomous zones, establish their own farming communities, instill certain values, and so on (which is argued to be a response to the evils of neoliberalism), they are wholly dependent on neoliberal superstructures to form these spaces. Zizek, commenting on the Zapatista movement, notes: “It is clear that such a structure can function only as the ethico-poetic shadowy double of the existing positive state power structure” (“Blows against the Empire?”). The slogan “Another World is Possible” always express the idea that we do not want to name the world we are struggling; that we just know that we don’t want the same old world, that we know what we oppose. As the Zapatista encuentros declared earlier, we are organizing “against neo-liberalism and global capitalism.” We are anti-capitalist, anti-militarist, anti-globalization, anti-WTO, anti-IMF, anti-racist, anti-sexist, anti-hierarchical, anti-statist, anti-sweatshop, anti-x. The most antigeneration in modern political history is in the streets... Simon Critchley’s recent book, Infinitely Demanding The response of some critics on the postmodern Left to this predicament is to call for a new politics of resistance. Those who still insist on fighting state power, let alone seizing it, are accused of remaining stuck within the ‘old paradigm’: the task today, their critics say, is to resist state power by withdrawing from its terrain and creating new spaces outside its control. This is, of course, the obverse of accepting the triumph of capitalism. The politics of resistance is nothing but the moralising supplement to a Third Way Left. Simon Critchley’s recent book, Infinitely Demanding, is an almost perfect embodiment of this position.[*] For Critchley, the liberal-democratic state is here to stay. Attempts to abolish the state failed miserably; consequently, the new politics has to be located at a distance from it: anti-war movements, ecological organisations, groups protesting against racist or sexist abuses, and other forms of local self-organisation. It must be a politics of resistance to the state, of bombarding the state with impossible demands, of denouncing the limitations of state mechanisms. The main argument for conducting the politics of resistance at a distance from the state hinges on the ethical dimension of the ‘infinitely demanding’ call for justice: no state can heed this call, since its ultimate goal is the ‘real-political’ one of ensuring its own reproduction (its economic growth, public safety, etc). These words simply demonstrate that today’s liberal-democratic state and the dream of an ‘infinitely demanding’ anarchic politics exist in a relationship of mutual parasitism: anarchic agents do the ethical thinking, and the state does the work of running and regulating society. Critchley’s anarchic ethico-political agent acts like a superego, comfortably bombarding the state with demands; and the more the state tries to satisfy these demands, the more guilty it is seen to be. In compliance with this logic, the anarchic agents focus their protest not on open dictatorships, but on the hypocrisy of liberal democracies, who are accused of betraying their own professed principles. motivational deficit As he states, ‘it might be claimed that there is a motivational deficit at the heart of liberal democratic life, where citizens experience the governmental norms that rule contemporary society as externally binding but not internally compelling’[x]. Identifies a “motivational deficit” in secular democracy and proposes an alternative theory of anarchism as ethical practice He says a "moral deficit" and a "motivational deficit" make meaningful political life and action impossible (7, 8). He calls this crisis of belief and action a bad case of Nietzschean nihilism. To begin changing this situation, Critchley insists that the ethical experience remains the best means for achieving selfhood and subjectivity. Even after decades of political failure, he argues that ethics and politics each constitute the condition of possibility for the other. SC: The main claim I make is that there is a motivational deficit in secular liberal democracy, in its institutions, its habits. This is the problem or crisis in normal politics: a demotivation in multi-party politics and parliamen-tary politics. On the other hand, there is a remotivation at the level of non-governmental or non-parliamentary politics. New forms of politics have emerged - forms that I call ‘neo-anarchist’ - and that are successfully mobilizing political anger that no longer resonates with classical forms of politics. Critchley (philosophy, Univ. of Essex, Colchester; Things Merely Are) argues that philosophy begins not from a sense of wonder but from disappointment. What concerns him especially is political disappointment, the common belief that something is radically amiss with the world. One response to disappointment is nihilism, the denial that the world has value. Passive nihilists, e.g., political theorist John Gray, whose Straw Dogsis a counterpoint to Critchley's book, accept the loss of value with resignation. Active nihilists, by contrast, wish to destroy the present world through revolutionary violence, hoping that something better will emerge. Critchley rejects both kinds of nihilism. Instead, he favors an ethics in which the ethical subject is split "between itself and a demand it cannot meet." Critchley has been influenced in this view by French philosophers Alain Badiou and Emmanuel Levinas and Danish thinker Knud Logstrup, and he gives a clear exposition of their ideas. In political practice, his ethical perspective leads to a form of anarchism: he calls for resistance to the "ideological moralism" of current American foreign policy. A stimulating analysis; highly recommended for philosophy and political theory collections.