Justice and Being in a Position to Complain Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen (lippert@ps.au.dk) Abstract: It is sometimes assumed that if no one has a complaint, there is no injustice. However, whether anyone is in a position to complain depends on factors that do not bear upon the justice of the situation, or on factors that do so bear, but also bear independently thereof upon anyone’s being in a position to complain. Sometimes one might not be in position to complain even if one suffers injustice. I explore some of the factors that determine whether one is in a position to complain drawing on recent work on being in a position to blame. The main upshot of the article is that it is unhelpful to explain justice in terms of absence of complaints. 1. Introduction It is sometimes assumed that if no one has a complaint, there is no injustice. An underlying idea may be that justice is or involves each of us being in such a relation to all others that no one holds a complaint against any other. Injustice, on the other hand, obtains when some of us hold complaints – of a specific, justice-relevant kind – against others. Presumably, the fact that you can rightly complain that I am not very generous has no tendency to establish injustice, since being generous involves going beyond the duties of justice and, accordingly, complaints about lack of generosity are not justice-relevant. Complaints are linked to justification in the following way: when no one is in a position to complain, the shape and terms of our interpersonal relations are not unjustified. The realization of this is what justice – or at any rate the absence of injustice – amounts to. Against this view, I argue that whether one is in a position to complain depends on factors that do not bear upon the justice of the situation or factors that do so bear, but also bear independently thereof upon one’s being in a position to complain (see next paragraph). Sometimes one might not be in a position to complain, even if one is being treated unjustly. For instance, if I reject the notion of human rights, I might not be in a position to complain on the ground that my human rights are being violated. Yet, if the principles of human rights are true, which, undeniably, they may well be despite my rejection of them, nevertheless it may be the case that I am being treated unjustly. In any case, one does not have human rights in virtue of (or even partly in virtue 1 of) the fact that one does not reject them – were that so, very many individuals would have no human rights – but this fact of rejection or endorsement is one in virtue of which one may or may not be in a position to complain about human rights violation. Admittedly, if I reject human rights and others who cherish them violate my human rights, I might be in a position to complain about their failing to live up to their own moral standards. But the object of this complaint is different from that of a complaint against a violation of human rights. It is commonly thought that an aggressor forfeits his right not to be killed if, say, he executes an intention to use deadly force against another, who can only defend herself through killing the aggressor. So the fact that I threaten to use deadly force against another may affect both what can permissibly be done to me – I forfeit my right not to be killed – and what I am in position to complain about – I am not in a position to complain about being killed. This may be taken to suggest that it is simply the permissibility of killing me that determines my not being in a position to complain about being killed. To see this is not so, suppose that I threaten to use what I falsely believe is deadly force, but in fact is harmless -- even beneficial -- to my intended victim. Now it is impermissible to kill me and yet I am in no better position to complain indignantly about being killed than I was in my initial version of the example. More generally, it appears that what I am in a position to complain about is more dependent on what I believe to be the case than justice and moral permissibility are. In this paper I will explore some of the factors that determine whether one is in a position to complain drawing on recent work on being in a position to blame. Along the way, I will point out various parallels to being in a position to blame, which I take it, is one particular species of complaining. In blaming someone for an action, necessarily one complains about it or/and them – in casu not about one’s own circumstances, but about the conduct of others – and just as one may not be in a position to complain about something in virtue of, say, the fact that in one’s private life 2 one treats that thing as a blessing, as several authors recognize there is a comparable phenomenon in cases where one is not in a position to blame others. My invocation of this parallel means that one way – not a promising one, I think – of objecting to parts of this paper is by denying that being in a position to blame and being in a position to complain are relevantly similar. The general upshot of my argument is that it may be harder to elucidate what justice requires through the notion of complaints than is widely assumed and that the broader understanding of justice as involving the kind of interpersonal relations briefly sketched in the first paragraph is flawed. 2. Justice and complaints I start by offering two examples of philosophers who expound justice in terms of complaints. The first example is comes from Jeffrey Reiman in relation to retributive justice and, specifically, the justice of capital punishment. Reiman offers a Kantian argument for why imposing the death penalty on murderers is not unjust. The argument goes as follows: whenever a rational agent acts, he thereby implicitly authorizes “having done to him action similar to what he has done to another, if he and the other are similar in relevant ways”.1 This premise follows from or constitutes the moral equality of persons. Capital punishment involves the murderer having done to him action similar in the relevant ways to what he has done to his victim(s). Moreover, one cannot validly complain of having done to oneself actions that one has authorized. Hence, a rational being who is a murderer cannot validly complain of his being put to death and “where there is no valid complaint, there is no injustice”.2 Accordingly, there is no injustice in imposing capital punishment on a murderer.3 My main concern here is neither the desirability of capital punishment – Reiman himself ultimately thinks that capital punishment should be abolished, because this is required by the “civilizing mission of modern states”4 – nor the soundness of Reiman’s argument per se. My 3 concern lies with the fact that a central premise in Reiman’s argument is the assumption that if no one has a valid complaint about some state of affairs, then that state of affairs involves no injustice. Call this the complaint principle. On a natural reading of Ronald Dworkin’s response to Jerry Cohen critique of his resourcist account of distributive justice also invokes the complaint principle. Cohen thinks that people who have bad price luck – i.e. they have expensive preferences and are not relevantly responsible for the expensiveness of their preferences – might be due, as a matter of justice, compensation from people who have cheaper preferences. Dworkin rejects this view. On Dworkin’s view, “it is our various tastes, convictions, and ambitions that define for us what a satisfying or gratifying life would be, and treating these as impediments to our realizing such a life would be incoherent”.5 An opera-lover, whose preference is expensive, “does not think his life goes overall worse with a taste for opera than without it” and he would not take a pill that would substitute a much cheaper preference for rock music for it, if it were available. So the opera-lover does not think that he is worse off than the lover of rock music, all other things being equal, and accordingly he cannot complain that he has been treated with less than equal concern and, thus, that in the absence of a transfer of resources in his direction his community treats him with less than equal concern: “[Equality of resources] proposes a politics that we can embrace as flowing from the rest of our convictions, a politics in which citizens can make and respond to claims of justice without switching to a special, made-for-politics morality. It allows us to cite, as disadvantages and handicaps, only what we treat in the same way in our own ethical life.”6 Admittedly, Dworkin does not use the term complaint in this passage. Still, the point he makes is that, say, the opera lover has no valid complaint on grounds of bad price luck, because he does not in his “own ethical life” see his preference for opera as a disadvantage or a handicap and accordingly it would be incoherent of him to represent this in the political sphere as a 4 disadvantage that grounds a complaint. Dworkin contrasts his own view with Cohen’s according to which justice might require, e.g., that we compensate people “whose religion imposes strenuous burdens” on their lives even though the premises of such compensation “would be rejected as abhorrent by those it is designed to benefit”.7 On Dworkin’s view, one cannot complain about something that one does not oneself think makes one’s life worse (not necessarily is a prudential sense – the person with strenuous religious beliefs might think that in a purely prudential sense, his life is worse than that of others) than the lives of others. As Matthew Clayton puts it, Dworkin’s seems committed to a “first-person test”. This test determines “whether one person is disadvantaged relative to another” in a way that engages a concern for justice. The test says that if a person “cannot in good faith propose a metric for interpersonal comparison that would treat himself as disadvantaged compared to” other individuals, then he is not so disadvantaged relative to this person.8 One cannot in good faith complain about a disadvantage that one does not in one’s personal life treat as such. In view of Reiman’s and Dworkin’s views, I contend that the complaint principle is an attractive principle and that it plays an important role in a number of arguments concerning the justice of states of affairs. In the rest of the paper, I shall challenge this principle. I want to show that factors other than those that determine the justice of situations determine whether one has a valid complaint and, accordingly, that it might happen that, despite the presence of injustice, no one has a valid complaint. Hence, my main claim here is that from the mere fact that one is not in a position to complain, it does not follow that one suffers no injustice. Two preliminaries: The kind of view I want to address is a view according to which the notion of complaint has a standing independently of an account of justice: a pre-justicial notion of complaint, as it were. That is, we have a grip of the notion of complaints that is not simply derived from an understanding of what justice requires. Rather, we understand what justice requires 5 partly through our understanding of the notion of complaints. To assume some such order of explanation is not, I think, unusual.9 People who use the notion of complaint differently take it that people can complain about something when and only when they are being treated unjustly, and they determine what justice requires independently of any consideration about complaints. In neither Reiman’s, nor Dworkin’s, case does the notion of complaint play such a purely derivative role. Second, in what follows I shall use two notions: “being in a position to complain” and “having a valid complaint”. If one is not in a position to complain about something, then, at least in one important sense, one does not have a valid complaint about it. However, there is a sense in which one might be in a position to complain about something, even if one has no valid complaint. So, by way of illustration, if I have a good reason to believe that a friend of mine has broken a solemn promise and if I have an impeccable record of keeping all of my promises myself, there is a sense in which I am in a position to complain about his having broken his promise even if I have no valid complaint, since, as a matter of fact, he has not broken his promise. There is nothing that, independently of whether my friend has broken his promise, undermines my position to complain about his having broken it. 3. Being in a position to complain While complaints are often rebutted with the reply that the complainer has no grounds of complaint, it is no less common for a target of complaints to reply that the complainer is not in a position to voice complaints over her target – henceforth: the complainee.10 So when the US complains about Chinese human rights violations, the response typically offered is not that no human rights violations take place in China or that human rights are “nonsense upon stilts”, but rather something along the lines embodied in the following news report: “China accused the United States … of using a double standard to judge human rights in other countries, adding to a list of nations 6 suggesting that the government that produced the Abu Ghraib prison abuses has no business commenting on what happens elsewhere. “No country should exclude itself from the international human rights development process or view itself as the incarnation of human rights that can reign over other countries and give orders to the others,” Premier Wen Jiabao's cabinet declared, three days after the State Department criticized China in its annual human rights report.”11 So, essentially, this reply to US complaints is indirect. It does not challenge that there are ground for complaints about the human rights situation in China, but challenges the US’ right to make this complaint given the US’ own dubious human rights record in the War on Terror.12 An exclusively indirect reply involves a refusal to take a stand on the injustice implied by the complaint and shifts attention to the putative fact that the complainer is in no position to complain to the complainee. Hence, the fact that someone is not in a position to complain to another about some object of complaint implies nothing about the justice of the object.13 An agent might be treated unjustly even if he is in no position to complain about the way he is being treated, e.g. because he has treated others in exactly the same way or because his conduct in his private life manifests that he does not consider the relevant treatment disadvantageous. Before I proceed I need to distinguish complaints in the sense I have in mind here from two different phenomena. First, complaining is different from deeming something to warrant a complaint. I cannot complain about being put to prison for my political views, when I did the very same thing to my political opponents when my party was in power, but I might still be in a position to deem the conduct of those who imprison me as something that warrants a complaint, e.g. because being the experience of political oppression has taught me a lesson and made me change my views about political liberty. When I complain about something, I am demanding a response from the complainee, whether that response consists in offering me reasons why I have nothing to complain about or consists in remedial action to address the disadvantageous situation that I complain about. I 7 demand an uptake, so to speak. When I calmly express my judgment to a third party, about whose conduct I am not complaining, I express my view that I have been treated in a way that is, as it were, complaint-worthy, but I do not complain in the sense I am after here. Second, there is a difference between publicly complaining about something – e.g. confronting the complainee and telling him off – and privately harbouring a complaint against someone that often occupies one’s mind – perhaps against one’s own willing – but one takes care to prevent from ever manifesting itself in public agonizing over the target. While I believe that one can fail to be in a position to have a private grudge against someone – e.g. because this person has even stronger grounds of complaint against oneself in the very same dimension as one’s grudge is located – for simplicity, I focus on publicly expressed complaints and then explore when one’s position to make such complaints is undermined. 4. Different ways of not being in a position to complain There are various ways in which one can fail to be in a position to complain, and correspondingly there are several kinds of indirect replies to complain. I now sketch some of these, although I do not take my remarks to offer a comprehensive overview of indirect dismissals. A common response to parental complaints involves pointing out that the parent did not complain in equally strong terms to the child’s sibling for an act that was no less blameworthy than the action of the first child (illa quoque). In contrast with cases where the tu quoque reply is appropriate, where the parent herself does what she complains about the child doing, the incoherence here lies not in the clash between one’s own norm-violating behaviour and one’s complaining about the other person’s less serious violation of the very same norm, but in the clash between one’s complain over one child’s violation and one’s omitting to complain about the other child’s equally or more serious violation of the very same norm. Politically speaking, the relevant 8 parallel would be if China dismisses US criticisms of human rights violations in China by pointing to the fact that US do not condemn human rights violation in countries playing a useful role as allies in the War of Terror. A related confounder of complaints is hypocrisy. The hypocrisy here lies in specifically motivated selectiveness in the complainer’s application of the norm to which she is appealing. No such selectiveness need be involved in cases where the tu or illa quoque replies are in order, yet these cases and the case of hypocrisy are easily confused. The key difference is this. In the tu and illa quoque replies an appeal is made to faults that the complainer or third parties actually have, whereas the charge of hypocrisy appeals to what the complainer believes (or ought to believe) to be faults the blamer herself, or a relevant third party, has. No doubt, in most cases the complainer is aware of her own faults (which is in part why the tu quoque charge and the charge of hypocrisy are easily confused). But suppose a complainer has simply forgotten about a certain fault of hers and complains about someone else’s identical fault. In this case, the complainee might dismiss the complaint using the tu quoque reply, though she cannot charge the complainer with hypocrisy. The complainer might be extraordinarily conscientious about identifying own faults and about not complaining about others having faults that she believes herself to have. The reverse situation is also possible. Suppose the complainer believes that she herself has a certain fault, but in fact does not. In that case, the tu quoque reply is out of order.14 However, it remains hypocritical of the complainer to condemn the complainee. The impropriety involved in complaints that can be dismissed in part because they are vulnerable to variants of tu quoque and the charge of hypocrisy consists in a clash between the content of the principles the complainer is applying and (how she thinks of) her own conduct (or the conduct of relevant others).15 In cases where I complain about someone’s minor fault in the presence of a relevant other whose fault is greater there is only a prima facie incoherence. For, in 9 most cases, the standard the violation of which I complain about does not in itself tell us whether or how we should complain about those who violate it, and we might have other norms implying that, in some cases, one should complain about someone’s minor fault and not complain about another’s greater faults. An example of this latter kind of norm is the principle that one should not complain counterproductively: in the case at hand, complaining about the latter’s greater fault might be counterproductive because the complainee would respond defiantly. There are other cases where one’s position as a complainer is undermined by principles that are external to those on which the relevant complaint is based. I shall refer to these as cases of incoherence-free complaints. Clear examples of incoherence-free failure include occasions where one’s position to complain is undermined by one’s not having sufficient warrant (e.g. “You cannot imagine what pressure a soldier is subjected to in the heat of battle and thus are in no position to pass moral judgement on a soldier in such a situation”) and cases where one is not in a position to complain about someone because one is not relevantly affected by this person’s conduct (e.g. since I know neither you, nor your spouse, it is none of my business to complain about your not keeping promises you made to your spouse). He one dismisses a complaint, not because one thinks that the complainer has no complaints, but because one is not the right addressee of the complaint. Two incoherence-free cases are less easily distinguished from the category that is the focus of this talk. First, one’s entitlement to complain may be undermined by one’s having played a causal role in bringing about the conduct of someone else.16 Often this charge of complaintundermining involvement involves what we might call a global incoherence charge as well. Local incoherence arises where the complainer applies the very standard to which she appeals in her act of complaining incoherently. Global incoherence occurs where the complainer applies a set of standards, of which the standard to which she appeals in her complaint is a member, incoherently. Suppose I complain about someone’s lying where I helped this person to lie, and that I hold lying to 10 be wrong because I accept some more basic moral principle that also implies that helping others to lie is wrong. This case involves a global incoherence, in my application of my standards, that undercuts my position as a complainer, since the principle which, in my view, motivates the specific principle to which I appeal in my complaint also forbids my helping the complainee to do what I complain about her doing. However, I may not be in a position, morally speaking, to complain about someone’s lie the production of which I am involved in even if the incoherence charge does not go through: that is, I might still not be in a position to complain about someone’s doing what I have helped her to do even though neither the moral principle that motivates complaint nor the deeper moral principles from which it derives forbid me from helping to assist the complaintworthy act. So when Western countries complained about the cruelty of Saddam Hussein’s treatment of the Kurds (among others), many felt given that they had been selling arms to him that were used to oppress the Kurds knowing that these might well be used for internal repression, they were in no position to complain, even though many others definitely were, e.g. the Kurds. The second case I have in mind is one in which I am not in a position to complain about your failing to comply with a certain principle, because I do not accept it. This case involves the incoherence of appealing to a certain principle and at the same time not endorsing it. However, this incoherence does not involve a clash between the content of principle one endorses, or professes to endorse, and one’s conduct, so it still differs from the tu quoque and hypocrisy charges. John Rawls makes a comparable point in relation to complaints: “A person’s right to complain is limited to violations of principles he acknowledges himself”. 17 A Jihadist cannot complain of the lack of democracy in Egypt, given that he himself rejects principles of democracy. The fact that one’s position as a complainer can be undermined for a variety of reasons suggests that there may be no general account of why one’s position to complain is undermined. In the remainder of this paper I focus on the two incoherence-based cases. These are 11 the cases, mentioned above, where complaints are undermined by the sort of incoherence pointed out in the tu quoque and hypocrisy charges. 4. Dimensions of incoherent complaints I now want to consider four dimensions bearing on one’s being in a position to avoind the charge of incoherent complaining: (1) whether the faults of the complainer and the complainee are of the same kind (quality); (2) how their faults compare in terms of severity (quantity); (3) how the faults that the complainer would manifest under merely possible circumstances affect her position to complain (modality); (4) how the past or future faults of the complainer affect her position to complain (temporality). (1) On a very restrictive view of the quality factor – on what we might call the ‘faultidentity view’ – the complainer’s position to complain is undermined only if her faults are of the same kind as the faults of others about which she complains. Gerald Dworkin accepts this view: “What seems crucial is that the fault one is criticizing is the very same fault one has.”18 A similar view may be embodied in Reiman’s notion of an action that is “similar in relevant ways”, i.e. a rapist cannot complain about being raped, but he may be in a position to complain about being robbed, since rape is relevantly different from robbery and in raping one does not authorize robbing. Quite how much the fault-identity view narrows the scope of the tu quoque and hypocrisy replies will depend on how faults are individuated. The richer the descriptions under which we identify flaws, the harder it becomes for the complainer to have the same fault as the complainee.19 However, for rather standard ways of distinguishing faults, the fault-identity view is false. Sexual harassment and rape are different faults, yet a rapist is in no position to complain about the conduct of his sexually harassing victim. 12 The alternative to the fault-identity position is the view that the complainer’s and complainee’s faults need not be of the very same kind. This view comes in different versions. One – the genus view – holds that the critic’s faults need not be of the same species as the addressee’s to undermine her position to complain. It suffices, and is required, that the two faults are of the same genus. So if I complain about your pick-pocketing and I myself have a spotless pick-pocketing record, you may reject my complaints on the ground that I myself often rob people at gunpoint and that this is a worse species of stealing. It speaks against the genus view, however, that, in the absence of an unusually undemanding understanding of when faults are of the same genus, there are contexts in which faults might undermine one’s position to complain even if they are not of the same genus, e.g. a person who has just beaten up his spouse cannot then turn to the kids and indignantly complain about their being lazy at school. In the light of the objections to the faulty-identity and the genus view, I accept a contextualist version of the non-identity view. On this view the context of complaint determines whether the critic’s faults have to be of the same kind as the faults she deplores in the target of her criticism. The context is set by (i) the critic’s moral principles, and especially those which in the eyes of the critic render complaint improper, and (ii) the target of the complaint. By (ii) I have in mind whether the complaint specifically concerns a particular act or is directed more broadly against the person who performed that act on the ground that it shows her character as a whole to be at fault.20 Hence, if I complain about your lying, and if I consider lying wrong because it is a way of being disrespectful of people and endorse the principle that one ought not to be disrespectful of other people, any act of mine that is disrespectful may serve you as a ground to deny that I am entitled to complain about your lying on pain of global incoherence (see Section Three). However, if I hold no moral principles connecting the fault about which I complain with other faults, then for 13 my position as a complainer to be undermined by my faults, these faults must be of the very same kind as those of the person’s that I complain about. (2) The significance of the severity factor given the self-other asymmetry thesis – or the ‘favourable comparison view’ – is this: you can complain about someone only if your faults are in some sense less serious than those of the complainee.21 Some such view is embodied in both Reiman’s and Dworkin’s views on complaints – a murderer, unlike a pickpocket, cannot complain about capital punishment and one cannot complain when one is no worse – perhaps even better – off than others in one’s own view, albeit one might be able to complain if one is less well off. This view is unsatisfactory. First, the favourable comparison view does not state a sufficient condition for being in a position to complain. If I persuaded you to lie and this involvement of mine conflicts with the underlying moral principle – e.g. that acts of lying are morally undesirable – on which my complaint is based, I may not be in a position to complain even if my fault at having persuaded you to lie is smaller than your fault for lying. More seriously, the necessary condition for being in a position to complain should be strengthened so that what we can call the very favourable comparison view requires not just a smaller fault but a substantially smaller fault. Complaining about someone’s killing two persons seems different when it comes from one who has herself killed exactly one person than when it comes from someone who is not a killer. The reply “Look who’s talking!” seems appropriate in the former case even if the complainee concedes that the fault of killing once – however great a fault that is – still is less of a fault than the fault of killing twice. Finally, the favourable comparison view should be revised to accommodate the fact that, generally, one can put oneself in a position to complain by applying a suitable dose of selfreproach for one’s own, perhaps not significantly lesser, but relevantly similar, flaws (where selfreproach involves more than simply judging oneself to be at fault).22 In fact, at least in the case of some faults one may even be in a position to complain about another whose faults are smaller 14 provided that one’s complaint is accompanied by a suitably harsher self-condemnation. For example, if I severely and sincerely reproach myself for serious lies I told in my past, and if I initiate my act of blaming you for a particular act of lying by conceding that I have done much worse myself, I seem to be in a position to complain about you. The view motivated by these considerations – the self-reproach-sensitive, very favourable comparison view – says that you can complain about someone only if your faults are significantly smaller than those of the complainee, unless your complaint is accompanied by a suitably calibrated dose of self-reproach. (3) Turning to the modality of faults, one might think, initially, that it is only actual faults that affect one’s position to complain. However, this cannot be right. If I complain about a particular objectionable action and I have not myself performed any relevantly similar objectionable actions, it still seems possible to the complainee to retort with the counterfactual tu quoque that if I had been in her circumstances, I would have acted (or I presently endorse my acting) no differently (or worse), and that it is merely my good luck that I am not in her circumstances. 23 No doubt, it will often be hard to know what a person would do were she in someone else’s shoes when she has never been in these shoes, so it will often be hard to tell if a counterfactual tu quoque is successful. However, this is no reason to doubt that it is in principle perfectly coherent. One issue that modality raises is whether what matters is what the critic would in fact do were she in the relevant counterfactual situation or whether, instead, the relevant factor is what she believes (or ought to believe) she would do were she in the relevant counterfactual situation. To prise these apart imagine a critic who, in a sense germane to the present discussion, reasonably believes that she would behave differently and much better were she in the complainee’s shoes, but who would in fact behave even worse. Accordingly, the counterfactual tu quoque, which concerns how the critic would act were she in the criticized person’s shoes, should be distinguished from a 15 closely related counterfactual hypocrisy charge which concerns what acts the critic believes she would perform were she in the other’s shoes. 24 The analogue to the counterfactual tu quoque may play an important role in relation to justice complaints. For instance, when untalented people complain that talented people demand incentives to make extra efforts that they could make in the absence of incentives, talented people might respond: “You would have done the same had you been in our shoes”. And if they are right, this might, I think, undermine the untalented people’s complaint, albeit it might not undermine the resulting injustice of the resulting inequality. (Perhaps it reduces the injustice of the inequality, but I do not see why it should remove it altogether.) As Jerry Cohen puts it: “A slave need not be impressed when a master says: “Had you been born into slaveholder class, you too would have lived well and treated your slaves like slaves”. Such counterfactual predictions do not show that what people at a certain social level typically choose to do is justifiable.”25 In fact, I think Cohen wants to make a stronger claim. I think he means that such counterfactual tu quoques do not show that what people at a certain social level do, without exception, is justifiable. At least, this is what the reply he puts into the mouth of the anti-apartheid advocate – “Quite: I’m sure it does blind one’s vision” -- to the white South African – “You would see things differently if you were in my position”.26 This reply does not lose its force, even if being in the relevant pair of shoes blinds everyone and not just most people. (4) Temporality raises two issues. First, whether the complainer’s future faults can undermine her standing as a legitimate complainer about the present or past faults of others; and second, whether the complainer’s past faults can undermine her standing as a complainer. In relation to the first issue it should be noted initially that, as in the case of the counterfactual tu quoque, it is often difficult to know which future faults the complainer will develop, and for that reason the future-fault tu quoque is rarely employed. Moreover, consideration of cases in which the 16 blamer, after condemning the complainee, acquires the very same fault herself supports the temporally neutral view of the relevance of faults. It is normal for complainers in such situations to come to regret their past condemnation. When confronted with the complainer, the blamee here might retort with force: “You once took me to task for this!” If one’s standing as a legitimate complainer is unaffected by one’s future faults, this is hard to explain. The second issue with regard to temporality concerns past faults of the complainer. The baseline position here is that these are relevant to one’s being in a position to complain. However, arguably, there are ways in which an agent can restore her right to complain despite past faults, even if those faults were greater ones – namely, if the agent disidentifies with – e.g. feels genuine and proportionate regret or compunction about – these faults and acts to avoid similar faults in the future.27 This possibility does not undermine the temporal neutrality view of the relevance of faults to being in a position to complain, because presumably one can complain now even if one will acquire the relevant kinds of fault in the future provided that one disidentifies oneself with the kind of person one will become in the future. 5. Infelicitous complaints: Scanlon So far I have considered various reasons why one’s position to complain can be undermined through incoherence and a number of dimensions relevant to incoherence. I now want to consider three accounts of what it is about incoherent complaints that undermine their force; Thomas Scanlon’s, Jerry Cohen’s, and my own. I have two interests. First, I am interested in the question for its own sake. Second, I am interested in it because of what it implies for whether one can be a victim of injustice that one is in no position to complain about. To pre-empt the conclusion, let me say that all of the three accounts, this – that one can be a victim injustice even though one is in no position to complain -- seems to me to be a possibility. Also, I should add a reservation: both 17 Scanlon and Cohen discuss being in a position to blame, not being in a position to complain. For the general reasons already offered (see Section One), and for more specific reasons offered below, their analyses and claims are applicable to being in a position to complain as well and, accordingly, I will discuss these as such. Consider Scanlon’s account of being in position to blame.28 On his account, to blame someone for an action “is to take that action to indicate something about the person that impairs one’s relationship with him or her, and to understand that relationship in a way that reflects this impairment… To blame a person is to judge him or her to be blameworthy and to take your relationship with him or her to be modified in a way this judgement of impaired relations holds to be appropriate.”29 An analogous point applies to complaints. If you complain to someone else about how she has treated you, you certainly seem to take “your relationship with him or her to be modified in a way this judgement of impaired relations holds to be appropriate”. Something similar to this, I think, is the case even if you do not blame the other person for the way in which she has treated you, e.g. you think she has treated you unjustly even though she cannot be faulted for having so done, but now that you state your complaint you certainly indicate that your relations have been modified, and if no action is taken by the addressee of your complaint your relations will have been impaired. One attractive implication of Scanlon’s account (and of the implied account of complaining) is that blame is personal in the sense that what it amounts to depends on the relationship you have with the person you are blaming. Blaming your spouse for betrayal differs from blaming a business partner for betrayal. Another attractive aspect of Scanlon’s account is that on his view, “if praise is the [mere?] expression of a positive appraisal, it is not the opposite of blame.”30 An attitude similar to blame, though with the opposite valence, must involve “awareness that one’s relationship” with the person towards whom one has this attitude “has been altered by 18 some action or attitude on that person’s part”. Scanlon suggests that gratitude is the “clearest example” of a “positive correlate of blame.” It involves not just a positive appraisal, but a change in the sort of relationship that one now considers appropriate. When, for example, one is grateful one typically has “a greater readiness to help a person who has gone out of her way to help [one], should the occasion arise”, and to think that such help is required by the nature of their relationship.31 Scanlon thinks that his account captures an important part of the moral impropriety of blaming someone when one’s own faults are greater: “I cannot claim that the attitudes revealed in your willingness to stand me up constitute an impairment in our relations, because the mutual expectations and intentions that constitute those relations were already impaired by my own similar attitudes, revealed repeatedly in my past conduct… In blaming you I would be holding that your willingness to behave in this way makes you someone toward whom I cannot have the intentions and expectations that constitute normal moral relations, such as the intention to trust you and rely on you. But insofar as these normal expectations and intentions are mutual, my own conduct already reveals me to be a person who cannot be a participant in these relations… So there is something false in my suggesting that it is your willingness to act in ways that indicate untrustworthiness that impairs our moral relationship.”32 In short: part of the moral force of tu quoque and the hypocrisy charge derives from the fact that, in blaming and, more generally, complaining, the incoherent complainer implies a false claim about what impairs the moral relationships between the complainer and the complainee. There are at least two reasons why Scanlon’s account is unable to explain the impotence of incoherent complaints. First, incoherent complaining need not imply any false claims about what impairs the complainer-complainee relationship. So much emerges in a case of hypocrisy where the complainer falsely believes that her faults in a certain dimension are greater 19 than the complainee’s and where, accordingly, the hypocritical complaint implies a true claim about what impairs their moral relationships: namely, that the faults of the complainee do so.33 Note also that the scenario just described shows why Scanlon’s account is incompatible with the complaint principle. So let us return to Dworkin’s response to Cohen’s criticism of resourcism. Suppose I have false beliefs about my ambitions in life. I am under the illusion that certain expensive preferences of mine define what a worthwhile life is. Suppose that as a matter of fact I have the very same ambitions as someone else, who given these ambitions, is much better off than I am. Given my false beliefs about my own ambitions I may not be able, in good faith, to complain about my being worse off, but justice might well condemn the inequality between me and the other person provided I am not at fault for having false beliefs about my ambitions. So here we have a case where the features in virtue of which I am not in a position to complain about being worse off are not features in virtue of which it is not unjust that I am worse off. This is inconsistent with the complaint principle which says that the absence of complaints is sufficient for absence of injustice. Second, consider cases where the person who complains has different and greater faults than the complainee and the following two facts obtain: (i) the complainer’s faults are isolated in the sense that they in no way suggest that this person cannot engage in all sorts of other unimpaired moral relationships to which the relevant greater faults are irrelevant, and (ii) the complainee’s faults are much smaller when considered on their own, but are tied to a whole range of other faults in a way that suggests she cannot engage in all sorts of other unimpaired moral relationships. For instance, a person who steals from her parents has acted in a way that is much less blameworthy than a person who has stolen much more, and much more often, from the parents of others.34 I take it that, intuitively, the latter is not in a position to blame the former for stealing. Yet Scanlon’s account seems to suggest otherwise, because the theft of cash from one’s own parents 20 impairs all personal relationships with the agent as a result of what it indicates about her, whereas stealing from strangers does not indicate any comparatively severe impairment of the agent’s ability to enter into normal relationships with others. Hence, if the more serious thief here blames the less serious one she implies no false claims about what impairs their relationship. As we have seen, there are reasons to be sceptical of Scanlon’s account of incoherent complaints. But whether these reasons are compelling, his account seems incompatible with the complaint principle. 6. Infelicitous complaints: Cohen Cohen proposes a different account according to which “what explains the force of tu quoque is… something to do with a certain form of inconsistency”.35 He does not propose this account as an analysis of what makes incoherent complaints morally inappropriate, but he seems to think their moral inappropriateness has at least something to do with their inconsistency. Whatever Cohen’s explanatory purpose is, it is worth exploring the role inconsistency plays in relation to the moral impropriety of incoherent complaints – partly because inconsistency is their distinctive trait, and partly because of the problems, explored in the previous section, tied to an attempt to provide an account in terms of the moral impropriety of implying a falsehood. The inconsistency account has pleasing implications with regard to the scope of tu quoque. First, it explains the effectiveness of the strategy of what we might call concessive complaints. If my faults are greater than yours I may nevertheless complain about yours provided that my other-directed condemnation is supplemented with self-directed condemnation such that differences in self- and other-directed condemnation fit differences in the strengths of the relevant complaints. With this proviso met there is no longer any incoherence between the stance I adopt towards you and the stance I adopt towards myself. Moreover, the inconsistency account implies that tu quoque is inappropriate for the same reason as illa quoque, i.e. the case where, for no good 21 reason, I single out and complain about one person for something I know a relevant other has done as well. In both cases it is the inconsistent application of the norm appealed to that explains the inappropriateness of complaints. No doubt inconsistency is what explains the root inappropriateness of incoherent complaints, but it plays no fundamental role per se in an account of why incoherent complaints are undermined when they are. For consider the case where someone condemns herself because of the mote in her own eye, but fails to consider the beam in her sister’s eyes. This case involves the same inconsistency (or, as I prefer to put it, incoherent application of a standard) as the admittedly more common case in which a person condemns her sister for the mote in her eye but fails to notice the beam in her own. Yet, unlike in the standard case, we do not take the presence of the more serious sinner to show that it is morally improper for the less serious sinner to condemn the mote in her own eye. It seems that it is only when other-directed inconsistency is involved that a prospective condemner deprived of the entitlement to condemn. We do not say “Look who’s listening!” as a way of exposing the moral impropriety of another’s scorching and disproportionately harsh selfcriticism.36 Similarly, one cannot insinuate that a saint is denied the right to praise someone for a minor good deed by the doer of that deed by exclaiming “Look who’s talking!” These facts confirm that inconsistency alone is not the full explanation of the force of tu quoque. It might be suggested that what matters is not whether the inconsistency is otherdirected, but whether it is motivated. Normally, when inconsistency is other-directed it is motivated: a desire to have a positive self-image will often be part of the larger psychological background. When the inconsistency is self-directed, by contrast, it is unmotivated: the condemner simply fails to keep in mind the fact the interlocutor has even greater faults. While this is a competing explanation, and one that will often explain the same cases as the self-other asymmetry thesis, if we pry the explanations apart we will see that it is the latter 22 that matters. I am morally entitled to put forward motivated self-criticism in front of a person whose faults are greater, and I am vulnerable to tu quoque when I complain about the mote in another’s eye while omitting, in a non-motivated way, to complain about the beam in my own. I cannot then note that I have no ulterior motive and proceed with the criticism. Note, finally, that even if Cohen were right, it would seem to follow that what explains the undermining of one’s position to complain – that one believes or ought to believe that one has violated the norm to which one appeals in one’s complaints against others in an equally or even more serious way than those others whom one complains about – is a fact that is irrelevant to moral obligations that others have to one. As I have already pointed out: my false beliefs about my violations of norms bear on my position to complain but they do not bear on what others may permissibly to do me. 7. Infelicitous complaints: demeaning others In view of the discussion presented in the two previous sections, I suggest that incoherent complaints are morally problematic when they demean others. The basic idea here is that it is prima facie morally wrong to demean others and that incoherent complaints are often, though not always, demeaning to the person whose faults are condemned in the presence of a greater sinner. So, for instance, in blaming someone for a fault that I have to a much greater extent I am acting as if, and thereby communicating the message that, I am in an elevated position: the position is such that the complainee must account, and possibly apologize, to me for her faults, whereas I am under no comparable obligation with regard to my own similar, or greater, faults.37 So it is as if – to put this point in Reiman’s terms – I did not by my own faulty behaviour authorize others to engage in comparable or even less faulty behaviour and withholding such authorization would seem to involve a denial of others status as moral equals given what I have authorized myself to do. 23 This account captures the intuitive moral character of incoherent appraisals. First, it delivers self-other asymmetry mentioned in my discussion of Cohen’s account, since incoherent self-reproach in the presence of another whose faults are greater, but one refrains from complaining about, might be demeaning of oneself, but intuitively one does not act immorally by demeaning oneself.38 Incoherent self-praise tends to demean others and is morally problematic. True, incoherent self-reproach can be demeaning of others too when it signals that one holds oneself to much greater standards than others with a sense of one’s own superiority, but in those cases incoherent self-reproach becomes morally problematic – at least, to the extent that it involves a vice – exactly for this reason. Second, incoherent, or prima facie incoherent, complaints need not always be demeaning, and it seems that in cases where they are not, nor do they seem to be morally wrong. Praising a child for a deed that is surprisingly good, for a child, in the presence of an adult whose deed is better than the child’s (when one abstracts from facts about the age of the agents) is not demeaning to the latter, since there is a reason in this case why praise is not calibrated to the goodness of the deed, and this renders the praise coherent. This reason involves no denial of the adult’s equal moral standing, but rather the view that you can reasonably expect more from an adult than you can from a child, and perhaps the view that, instrumentally speaking, it is more effective, and thus more important, to praise children than it is to praise adults. Third, the account casts light on the dimensions of incoherence examined in Section Four. It seems, for instance, to cohere well with the contextualist view of the quality of faults. If the context within which a particular criticism of me is made concerns a very specific issue and the complainer explicitly denies that this fault bears on other issues, it is not demeaning to me that the complainer’s more serious, but in the present context irrelevant, faults are unaddressed. Indeed, to deny someone, such as a convicted killer, the right ever to make very specific criticisms of non24 killers’ faults on the ground that her overall faults are greater would seem to demean her by depriving her of her status as someone who can not only be subjected to, but also subject others to, warranted moral criticism. Finally, this account explains why some others are relevant others, while other others are not, e.g. I cannot dismiss your complaints about my lying with accusing your of failing to complain about the much more serious lies of Hitler. In complaining over someone, I invite them to convey to me their regret over their wrongdoing. This is demeaning if there is someone present to whom such an invitation is more warranted because he was involved in greater wrongdoing. But such an invitation makes no sense if it is extended to, say, evil dictators long dead, however more serious their faults were; and this explains why, normally, such persons are not relevant others for the purpose of determining the propriety of blame. 8. Conclusion The topic of what is involved in being in a position to complain is relatively uncharted territory. Incoherent complaints involve the incoherent application of the standards appealed to – a form of inappropriateness that we encounter outside morality, e.g. in relation to incoherent application of norms of humour. This does not go to the heart of the matter, however, which is that, in a wide range of context, incoherent complaints over others demeans them. Incoherent complaints very often involve a specific way of demeaning others. This involves elevating oneself (or one’s favourites) above one’s complainee by presenting him in an unwarrantedly negative light, comparatively speaking. This is what makes incoherent complaints morally wrong, when they are. The main upshot of my paper is that we should reject the complaint principle, i.e., the thesis that if no one has a valid complaint about some state of affairs, then that state of affairs involves no injustice the reason being that factors that do not determine the injustice thereof may 25 undermine my being in a position to complain. Hence, absence of complaints is not sufficient for justice. Whether presence of complaints is sufficient for injustice is another interesting question, but not one that I have addressed in this paper.39 1 Jeffrey H. Reiman, “Justice, Civilization, and the Death Penalty: Answering van den Haag”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 14.2 (1985), pp. 115-148, p. 125. 2 Reiman, “Justice”, p. 124. 3 Saul Smilansky explores a similar line of argument in his Ten Moral Paradoxes (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2007), 90-99, p. 95: “wrongdoers cannot complain when treated as they have legislated”. However, he thinks this is paradoxical because it is also a commonsense truth that “if wronged one can complain, and... if one cannot complain about an act done to one, then presumably that act may be done to one”, p. 98. 4 Reiman, “Justice”, p. 115. 5 Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000), p. 293. 6 Dworkin, Sovereign, p. 294. 7 Dworkin, Sovereign, p. 295. 8 Matthew Clayton, “The Resources of Liberal Equality”, Imprints 5.1 (2000), 63-84, pp. 77-78. 9 Cp. Larry Temkin on complaints in his Inequality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), p. 15. 10 Compare G. A. Cohen, “Casting the First Stone: Who Can, and Who Can’t, Condemn the Terrorists”, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 81 (2006), 113-136, p. 120. 11 http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/articles/A3840-2005Mar3.html 26 12 Of course, nothing prevents the complainee from offering a direct as well as an indirect response to complaints, e.g. “There are no human rights violations in China, and even if there were, the US is in no position to point fingers at us”. 13 However, compare Smilansky, “Paradox”. 14 An analogous point applies to the illa quoque reply. 15 By “(im)proper” and “(im)propriety” I mean the same as I mean by “(in)appropriate” and “(in)appropriateness”, respectively, and in the interest of stylistic variation I use both pairs of terms. 16 Cohen, “Casting”, p. 127. 17 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, revised edition (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000), p. 190. 18 Dworkin, “Morally Speaking”, p. 185. 19 Cohen, “Notes”, p. 4. 20 I return to this in Section Six in the course of discussing Scanlon’s views. 21 Compare Cohen, “Notes”, p. 2. Dworkin endorses the favourable comparison view: see “Morally Speaking”, p. 185. 22 Dworkin might accept this view, since, as already mentioned, he allows for infelicity cancellers (p. 184). 23 Compare Cohen, “Casting”, p. 123n17. 24 Compare the discussion of the relationship between hypocrisy and tu quoque in the third paragraph of Section Three. 25 Jerry Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2008), p. 61 26 Cohen, Rescuing, p. 61n32. See also “Casting”, p. 123n17 27 27 Compare Cohen, “Casting”, p. 127, n.21. 28 I discuss Scanlon’s views more fully in Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, “Motes and Beams: Who Can Praise or Blame Whom for What?” in Michael Kühler and Nadja Jelinek (eds.), Autonomy and the Self (Dordrecht: Springer, forthcoming). 29 Scanlon, “Blame”, p. 122-123, 128-129. 30 Scanlon, “Blame”, p. 151. 31 Scanlon, “Blame”, p. 151. 32 Scanlon, “Blame”, pp. 176-177. 33 Recall my discussion of the relationship between hypocrisy and tu quoque in the third paragraph of Section Three. 34 Even more problematic are cases where the greater faults are indicative of their possessor being a more trustworthy participant in normal moral relationships. 35 Cohen, p. 8. Later in the notes he suggests that inconsistency is not the whole explanation: respect enters the picture as well. 36 If we do, it is in order to change the self-reproacher’s view of the seriousness of her faults, not to deny her the right to reproach herself. 37 Apart from the element of sending a message, this is true even in the case of complaining in foro interno. Arguably, such complaints do not wrong the complainee, but it still reflects a vice of the blamer’s, e.g., vainglory or partiality. 38 Some philosophers, including Kantians perhaps, might affirm a moral duty not to demean oneself. However, they might still accept that the right account of the morality of incoherent complaints should be based on considerations having to do with the wrongness of demeaning someone, since presumably they will think that incoherent self-reproach is morally wrong and demeaning to the person incoherently reproaching herself. 28 39 Jerry Cohen’s interpersonal test suggests that, on his view, presence of complaints implies injustice. Elsewhere, I have suggested that the mere fact that people are in a position to complain something, e.g. because they hold false but reasonable beliefs about their situation, it does not follow that injustice obtains, see “Inequality, Incentives, and the Interpersonal Test”, Ratio 21.4 (2008), pp. 421-439. 29