Consequentialist Options

advertisement
Consequentialist Options
1. Act-consequentialism (AC) is a combination of two elements. According to the
first axiological element, when an agent faces a set of options, they can be ranked in
virtue of how good their consequences are. According to second deontic element, an
act is right if and only if it is an option that is evaluated as one of the best in the
previous ranking.
According to a classic objection, this view fails to leave sufficient room for
moral freedom. As I am currently writing this paper, I could continue doing so, go
out for a walk, meet my friends, travel to France, and so on. None of these actions
would be morally wrong, other things being equal. Yet, according to AC, these
options are permissible only if none of the other options have better consequences.
All the abovementioned options could then be morally right only if they each had
equally best consequences.
However, it does not seem likely that this could be the case. Considerations
such as pleasure, knowledge, aesthetic enjoyment, biodiversity, and so on can make
the consequences of actions good. Whichever options we compare, it seems that
there must be a difference in how much of these goods the options will bring about.
That a whole range of options would bring about an equal amount of these goods
would be a cosmic coincidence. As a result, simple act-consequentialism seems
unable to accommodate the intuitive moral options.
This appearance is mistaken, or so I will argue. Consequentialism can
provide far more morally permissible options than previously thought.
1
2. Consequentialist responses to the freedom-objection fall into three categories. The
first response is denial. It is claimed that, on this issue, our common-sense morality
is mistaken. The options it permits do not bring about most value to the world. But,
to bring about less value than possible would be ‘profoundly irrational’ (Pettit 1984,
172), and therefore wrong. Thus, on this view, the actions that seem optional to us
are really impermissible.
This rejection of the intuitive options can be made more appealing. It can
be argued that our moral intuitions should be disregarded unless they can be
vindicated by a consistent moral theory. It can then be claimed that any theory
which recognises moral options would be internally inconsistent (Kagan 1989, 19–
42). If this were the case, the act-consequentialist could claim that we should ignore
our intuitions about the options.
It could also be argue that there is a difference between act’s wrongness
and the agent being criticisable for it. Some suboptimal actions (which intuitively
are permissible) could be morally wrong actions for which agents are not
condemnable (Pettit 1996, 164–8). This would mean that no harm is done by calling
them wrong. I have no objection to these strategies, except that, if my argument
below is right, then they are based on mistaken view about how many options
consequentialism creates.
The second set of responses tries to make room for options by revising the deontic
element of consequentialism. Some have tried to add an explicit permission to
pursue some sub-optimal outcomes in addition to the optimal ones. This is called as
the hybrid view (Scheffler 1982). One is permitted to bring about suboptimal
outcomes when the optimal outcomes would require sacrificing one’s own important
2
projects and commitments. Such permissions can be motivated by the need to
protect the integrity of agents. Again, this strategy to revise consequentialism seems
to be unmotivated if it can be shown that consequentialism itself creates enough
options. This is what I hope to show below.
There is also another way of revising the deontic element of actconsequentialism to accommodate options. This response is a view called satisficing
act-consequentialism (Slote 1982). On this view, right actions have ‘good enough’
consequences. One is free to choose any action such that either (i) the value of its
consequences does not fall below a certain threshold, or (ii) the value of the
consequences is reasonably close to the value of the best consequences. The hope is
that most intuitive moral options satisfy these criteria.
Unfortunately, satisficing act-consequentialism provides wrong kind of
options (Bradley 2006). In some cases, an agent will be able to bring about enough
value by either harming some people or by actively preventing more value to be
brought about. Under the satisficing views, these actions would be permissible
options. Having to say this is a high of a price for the intuitive options.
The third possible responses to the freedom objection try to save the intuitive moral
options by concentrating on the axiological element of consequentialism.
I have assumed so far that the axiology of AC is complete and finegrained. This means that evaluative ties between outcomes and cases where their
value is incomparable are rare. An act-consequentialist could reject these
assumptions. If value of the outcomes was a coarse-grained and incomparable
matter, then there could often be many optional actions such that they would not
have alternatives with better consequences (Vallentyne 2006, 26).
3
This move would fail to save all the intuitive moral options. For each one
of the evaluative properties, there will a distinct set of basic properties in virtue of
which things have that evaluative property. The cases in which actions have these
basic properties to different degrees will be problematic for the considered view.
It seems plausible that the consequences of actions have one sort of value
in virtue of the pleasure they contain. Now, it is permissible for me to watch
television for either 45 or 60 minutes, other things being equal. As a result, I would
experience, say, either 9 or 12 units of pleasure when there are no other relevant
differences between the outcomes. In order to say that both of these actions are
permissible, the act-consequentialist under discussion would have to say that neither
of these outcomes is better than the other.
This could not be because the value of the two outcomes is incomparable.
The situation is such that the only difference between the outcomes is the amount of
one basic property that gives rise to only one kind of value. It must be comparable
how much that value the outcomes have. So, the defender of the view would have to
claim implausibly that the outcomes have an equal amount of that value. If pleasure
makes outcomes good, the additional 3 units of pleasure must make the other
outcome better than the other. For this reason, a coarse-grained and incomplete
axiology will not be able to save all the intuitive moral options.
Another form of act-consequentialism tries to accommodate moral options by
relying on many evaluative rankings (Portmore 2003). According to Portmore’s
dual-ranking proposal, we can rank the consequences of the agent’s options from
her perspective in terms of both moral and all-things-considered value.
4
For instance, saving a child from a burning building whilst risking one’s
life may bring about states of affairs that are from one’s perspective morally
speaking the best but not the best all-things-considered. This is because potential
losses in one’s own well-being do not make resulting states of affairs morally worse
from one’s perspective. Yet, these losses make the same consequences worse allthings-considered.
Portmore claims that an action is permissible if and only if it does not have
an alternative that would bring about more of both moral and all-things-considered
value from one’s perspective. This explains why it is permissible both to save the
child and not to do so. Neither one of these options have an alternative that would
have more of both moral and all-things-considered value.
Portmore’s proposal faces a problem when we consider basic actions that
are suboptimal on both accounts. Some of these actions are permissible options.
Think of watching your television either for 45 or 60 minutes with a friend of yours.
She is made happier by the first option but even more so by the second option. The
happier you make your friend the better the resulting outcome is morally from your
perspective. You will also be happier the happier your friend is. Thus, watching
television with your friend for 60 minutes would also be better all-things-considered.
In this situation, according to Portmore’s dual-ranking view, it would not
be permissible watch your television with your friend for only 45 minutes. You have
an option that brings about more of both moral and all-things-considered value.
However, our common-sense morality would permit this. This makes me think that
all the previous proposals to respond to the freedom-objection are either mistaken
about how many options consequentialism creates or problematic in some other
way.
5
3. I want to then explain how whether an agent is required to do some action or
permitted to choose it from many permissible options can affect how much value the
consequences of that action have. Furthermore, I want to claim that the fact that an
agent is permitted choose some action out of many permissible options can make the
consequences of that action better in three ways (Dworkin 1988, 78–80).
The consequences of an action having been chosen from many permissible
options would have instrumental value if the action would bring about, as a result of
having been chosen from many permissible options, other things which are
intrinsically good. First, it could be claimed that individuals want to be able to
choose between different permissible options and they find making such choices
satisfying and pleasurable.
Being able to choose an action from many permissible options can also
enable us to learn things about ourselves. If one wants to know whether one is
courageous or cowardly, one can do so only by seeing what kind of choices out of
many permissible options one makes in certain kind of situations of risk. If one
were always required to choose some particular action in the relevant kind of riskscenarios, then there would not be room for the type of practical deliberation in
those situations that is required for acquiring self-knowledge about one’s character.
It could also be argued that the fact that an act can be chose from many
permissible options has intrinsic value as such. Being able to choose to do an action
out of many permissible options would in this case be desirable for its own sake. If
this were true, the same action would bring about more value when one can choose
to do the action from many permissible options.
6
This is because one of the
consequences of the action in that situation would be that an intrinsically valuable
choice out of many options took place before the agent did the action.
The consequences of an action that is done after a choice between many
permissible options can also have constitutive value. The idea here is that choices
between many permissible options can be in part constitutive of larger, more
complex wholes which can have intrinsic value.
Some choices out of many permissible options have ‘representative value’
in this way (Scanlon 1988, 252). If a poet writes a poem, the value of the outcome
does not solely depend on the poem’s aesthetic qualities or on how much the
audience appreciates it. The same poem could have been randomly generated by a
computer. Yet, in that scenario, the existence of this poem would not be equally
good.
The poem gets additional significance from the fact that the poet chose the
words out of many permissible options to express her beliefs, desires, and emotions.
The poem, as a result of the prior choices between many permissible options, comes
to represent the poet’s thoughts. The poem is now a part of a more complex whole
which includes the poet’s thoughts, the world which these thoughts represent, and
the audience’s appreciation of the poem as a representation of the world. This
complex whole has intrinsic value, and therefore the poem has constitutive value.
Choices between many permissible options can also have constitutive
value called ‘symbolic value’ (Scanlon 1998, 253). We intuitively take otherwise
similar outcomes to be better if they result from our choices between many
permissible options. This is easiest to see in the case of one’s own actions. I would
value my career, friends, and house considerably less if they had been chosen for me
instead of having resulted from my choices between many permissible options.
7
They all would be much less valuable if they were a result of a strict path chosen for
me by someone else. Thus, choices between permissible options as such can make
things better.
Why would this be? Compare the situation where we are free to make all
these choices between many permissible options to the one in which others would be
making the same choices for us. The removal of our ability to choose between many
permissible options can be understood as a judgment that we are incapable of
making reasonable choices ourselves. Granting someone a freedom to choose from
many permissible options is thus a way of recognising her abilities to make
decisions.
One could then argue that this kind of recognition of our rational
faculties is an intrinsically valuable whole, and that having a choice between many
permissible options is a constitutive part of this whole. This is another reason why
choices between many permissible options could have constitutive value, and why
having a free choice to do a given action can itself create more value to the world.
In the following, I will assume that choices between permissible options
can have value in all these ways.
4. My proposal based on the previous assumption about the value of choices begins
from the thesis that a consequentialist has good reasons, on purely consequentialist
grounds, to accept that some sub-optimal action is a morally permissible option for
an agent when it is better that the agent has an option to do this sub-optimal action,
whichever permissible action she ends up doing. If a sub-optimal action A is such
that, even if the agent ends up performing that action, things are better than if she
performed some other permissible action without A being an option, then it makes
8
sense for the consequentialist to accept that A is a permissible option for the agent.
After all, that A is a permissible option can make things better in this situation.
This account can be formalised in the following way. Assume that an agent
could only do either action A1, or A2, or …, or Ax. Each one of these actions would
have some definitive consequences when there was a requirement to do it. Let us
assume that A1 would have the best consequences if the agent were required to do it,
A2 would have the second best consequences if the agent were required to do it, and
so on.
Let us use curly brackets for alternative sets of permissible actions. So, if
the agent would be free to choose between A1 and A2 her option-set would be {1, 2},
if the agent would be free to choose between A1, A2, and A3 her option-set would be
{1, 2, 3}, and so on. My proposal then is:
Consequentialist Options: An action An is a permissible option just in case
the value of the consequences of An given the option-set {1, ... , n} is at least
as great as the value of the consequences of An-1 given the option-set {1, …, n1} where An-1 is the least optimal action in {1, …, n-1}.
To see how this proposal works in, let us assume that the table below represents the
actions which Jill could choose to do and the value of their consequences.
Action
A1
Charity-work
Value of consequences when
required
200u
A2
Go to Paris
150u
210u
A3
Visit parents
100u
215u
…
…
…
…
An-1
Stay in bed
20u
240u
An
Ignore Joe’s call
-30u
100u
9
Value of consequences of Aφ
given the option-set {1,…,φ}
200u
In this situation, the traditional interpretation of act-consequentialism would require
Jill to do charity-work. This is because that action has the best consequences when
we compare all the actions as required ones.
However, we can apply the
Consequentialist Options principle, when we ask whether morality understood in
consequentialist terms should grant Jill also an option to go Paris. On this proposal,
morality should not deny Jill this additional option on consequentialist grounds if
her going to Paris (the initially suboptimal action) would have better consequences
when she is able to choose between it and the charity-work option than her doing the
optimal action (charity-work) when that action is required.
The value of the consequences of Jill choosing to go to Paris when it would
have been also permissible to do charity-work is 210u. The consequences of going
to Paris are 60u better when this action is a consequence of a choice between Paris
and the charity-work than they would have been had that action been required.
Thus, the consequences of Jill choosing to go to Paris given the option-set {charitywork, going to Paris} are better than the consequences of her doing charity-work
when she would have been required to do so. This entails that morality should, for
consequentialist reasons, grant her the additional option of going to Paris.
At this point, Jill’s permissible options are either to do charity-work or to
go to Paris. Should morality, understood in consequentialist terms, also grant her a
third option of visiting her parents? In order to answer this question, we should
again consult the Consequentialist Options principle. The table above shows that, if
Jill visits her parents when she it is permissible for her to do so, go to Paris, or do
charity-work, the value of the consequences will be 215u. We should then compare
this amount of value to the value of Jill going to Paris when she would have only the
10
slightly smaller option-set of either going to Paris or doing charity-work. The value
of the consequences of that action in those circumstances is 210u.
This means that Jill having also the third option of visiting her parents has
better consequences, whatever she ends up doing, than if she were only free to
choose between the previous two options we already granted her and she then chose
the least valuable option. This is why morality should grant her also the third option
of visiting her parents. By iterating this process, we can step by step determine
which options Jill has on consequentialist grounds.
According to the table above, morality would stop granting her more
options on consequentialist grounds when we come to Jill’s action of ignoring Joe’s
call. If Jill were able to freely choose to ignore Joe (when also having the more
valuable options), the consequences of this action would be 100u in total. If she
chose to stay in bed when not being allowed to ignore Joe (the least valuable action
of the smaller option-set), the consequences would be better, 240u. This means that
Jill would only be permitted to choose between staying in bed and all the other
actions she could do which would have better consequences when chosen from the
relevant option-set.
We should recognise that the Consequentialist Options principle itself is merely a
formal principle for determining which actions are morally permissible in the
consequentialist framework.
The previous example also illustrates how that
principle on its own cannot tell us which actions are permissible. That depends on
how much more valuable (if at all) the consequences of actions are when the agent is
able to choose those actions from different sized sets of permissible options.
11
The previous section tried to explain certain considerations which could, on
occasion, make the consequences of actions resulting from choices between many
permissible options more valuable. However, already the previous example shows
how complex issues we are dealing with at this point.
I merely selected, for
illustrative purposes, the values of the consequences of different possibilities so as to
get the right intuitive options for Jill. If this were an actual choice-situation, in order
to fill in the table correctly, we would need to know (i) whether Jill enjoys making
choices between many permissible options, (ii) what kind of representational value
her choices could have, (iii) which choices are necessary for the recognition of her
abilities for making reasonable choices, and so on. All this information would be
required for knowing which actions would be permissible given the Consequentialist
Options principle.
However, the point of introducing that principle is more structural than
practical.
According to the freedom-objection, we always have more morally
permissible options than act-consequentialism would entail.
However, if the
Consequentialist Options principle holds, then how many options we have depends
on how much better the consequences of our actions are when these actions would
belong to our option-sets. If choices between many permissible options can make
the consequences of actions a lot better, then we will have a lot of options. In
contrast, if no additional value is gained from choices between many permissible
options, then consequentialism would still not create many options.
All of this means that whatever options we intuitively think we have in a
given situation, there will be a version of consequentialism that entails that very
number of morally permissible options. There will be a way of assigning additional
value for the consequences of actions which can chosen from sets of permissible
12
options such that (i) the consequences of the agent-having that option-set (no matter
which action the agent chooses from it) are not worse than the agent doing the least
valuable action from the more limited option-sets, and (ii) giving the agent a more
extended option-set could have worse consequences.
If this right, then there cannot be an objection to consequentialism per se
that it does not provide enough options. This means that the freedom-objection
debate will then be no longer be about consequentialism, but rather about whether
the views of the value of choices. If the required view about the value of choices
between many options that has the right results does not turn out to be plausible,
then one could argue that at least the most plausible versions of consequentialism do
not provide all the options we think we have.
However, at this point, the
consequentialist could claim that she has been able to make her view compatible to
most of our intuitions about moral options.
5. Let me finish by making two observations. The first one of these concerns the
axiology which the consequentialist would need to be able to defend to get a
sufficient number of moral options. Consider the permissible actions A1 (charitywork) to An-1 (staying in bed) in the previous example. If we ignore the value of
these actions resulting from choices between many options, A1 has the best
consequences, A2 has slightly worse consequences, and so on, all the way to the
almost neutral consequences of An-1. Yet, every time Jill is granted a new option (an
action less valuable in itself), the results of Jill doing this action out of a choice
between many options would have been better than the results of her doing the
previous action in the ranking from the slightly smaller option-set.
13
This requires that, when we go down the scale of actions and towards the
larger option-sets, more value must be added to the consequences of actions as a
result of them having been chosen from the slightly larger option-set.
The
difference in value between doing A2 when required and doing it with the option-set
{1, 2} was 60u, the difference between doing A3 when required and doing it with the
option-set {1, 2, 3} was 115u, and so on.
To some extent, such pattern of increases in the value of choice is plausible.
If one has only two options, one would want to have more of them, one’s actions
would not really be representative of one’s thoughts, one’s deliberation-abilities
wouldn’t really be recognised, and so on. So, being able to choose the second option
out of an option set of two would not add that much value to the consequences of
that action. However, if one had three choices instead, maybe one would get a bit
more of the choices one wanted, the results of one’s actions would be a bit more
representative of one’s inner world, one’s abilities would be a bit more recognised,
and so on. Similar increases would presumably take place if we added a fourth
choice, a fifth choice, and so on.
However, at some point, the added value of the new options would begin to
decrease due to the diminishing marginal utility of having more permissible options
to choose from. The value added to the consequences of actions by the fact that
there were more options to choose from would at that point stop compensating for
the fact that the other consequences of these actions are always a bit less valuable. It
is rather difficult to assess whether this would happen too quickly so that the
consequentialist framework could still not create enough permissible options.
The second observation I want to make is that the previous proposal does
require revising the deontic element of act-consequentialism. However, I hope that
14
this change is motivated on purely consequentialist grounds. It is true that the basic
act-consequentialism requires, by definition, that all agents always to do whatever
action has the best consequences in the given situation. My claim is that the
consequentialist should not say this, if she thinks that whatever moral requirements
we have is determined by whichever moral requirements would have the best
consequences. If morality is understood by using this basic consequentialist idea,
then agents can only be required to choose between actions which belong to the
options-sets which are optional according to the Consequentialist Options principle.
Bibliography
Bradley, Ben (2006): “Against Satisficing Consequentialism”. Utilitas 18, pp. 97–
108.
Dworkin, Gerald (1988): The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press).
Kagan, Shelly (1989): The Limits of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Pettit, Philip (1984): “Satisficing Consequentialism”. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, Suppl. Vol. 58, pp. 165–176.
Pettit, Philip (1996): “The Consequentialist Perspective”. In Baron, M., Pettit, P. &
Slote, M.: Three Methods of Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 92–174.
Portmore, Douglas (2003): “Position-Relative Consequentialism, Agent-Centred
Options, and Supererogation”. Ethics 113, pp. 303–332.
Scanlon, T.M. (1998): What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Ma.: Belknap
Press).
Scheffler, Samuel (1982): The Rejection of Consequentialism (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Slote, Michael (1982): “Satisficing Consequentialism”. Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, Suppl. Vol. 58, pp. 139–164.
Vallentyne, Peter (2006): “Against Maximizing Act Consequentialism”. In Dreier, J.
(ed.): Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 21–37.
15
Download