Page i Putting Choice Before Democracy Page ii SUNY Series in Political Theory: Contemporary Issues Philip Green, Editor nlReader.dll?BookID=5235&FileName=Page_ii.html Page iii Putting Choice Before Democracy A Critique of Rational Choice Theory Emily Hauptmann State University of New York Press nlReader.dll?BookID=5235&FileName=Page_iv.html Page iv Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 1996 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever with- out written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, address State University of New York Press State University Plaza, Albany, N.Y., 12246 Excert from "A Worker Reads History" in SELECTED POEMS by Bertolt Brecht, copyright 1947 by Bertolt Brecht and H. R. Hays and renewed 1975 by Stefan S. Brecht and H. R. Hays, reprinted by permission of Harcourt Brace and Company. Production by Diane Ganeles Marketing by Nancy Farrell Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Hauptmann, Emily Putting choice before democracy : a critique of rational choice theory / Emily Hauptmann. p. cm. — (SUNY series in political theory. Contemporary issues) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0–7914–3028–6 (PB : acid-free). — ISBN 0–7914–3027–8 (CH : acid-free) 1. Democracy. 2. Rational choice theory. I. Title. II. Series. JC423.H377 1996 321.8'01—dc2095–37347 CIP 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Page v For my mother Page vii Contents Acknowledgments ix Introduction 1 Chapter 1 The Political Frustrations of the Rational Chooser: The Structure of Elections, the Two-Party System and the Politics of Interest Groups 7 Chapter 2 The False Paradox of Choice in Rational Choice Theory 37 Chapter 3 Democracy without the Rational Chooser: The Lottery System in Ancient Athens 59 Chapter 4 Against an Economic Explanation of Politics 73 Conclusion 91 Notes 95 Bibliography 125 Index 135 Page ix Acknowledgments There are a number of people whose encouragement, advice, and criticism helped me think about, improve, and finally complete this book. First, I should like to thank my dissertation committee, Hanna Pitkin, Norman Jacobson, and John Harsanyi, for their many years of support. I especially thank Hanna Pitkin for her close readings of all of my many drafts and for encouraging me to rethink and refine many sections I would have liked to consider finished. I also thank John Harsanyi for prodding me to give fuller and fairer accounts of rational choice theory. And Ernst Haas, who was the first to urge me to acquaint myself with the rational choice literature, encouraged me to believe I could put together a critique others might read and take seriously. Many people also read and commented upon parts of this project at various stages. I owe a great deal to Deborah Achtenberg, Ron Brecke, Elizabeth Collins, Bill Eubank, Richard Flathman, Jill Frank, Philip Green, Andy Gould, Joann Goven, Jack Gunnell, Phillip Harding, Jim Johnson, Michael Rogin, Ian Shapiro, Laura Stoker, and Brian Weiner in this regard. The Josephine de Karman Foundation and the sponsors of the Jefferson Lectures Fellowship supported my work in its early stages; Clay Morgan at SUNY Press helped me make a book of it. A special note of thanks is owed to several others: to my father, who taught me to love the academic life; to Jonathan Brewer, for his friendship and faith; and to Dan Aalbers, for making me think harder. Page 1 Introduction Rational choice theory has become one of the primary currents in American political science in the last twenty years. Because of its parsimonious theoretical structure, it is one of the few approaches to the study of politics that has generated specific, commonly recognized areas for further research. 1 Indeed, the influence or rational choice theory has been felt by all social scientists so that, as Jon Elster has put it, one may now encounter "… arguments purporting to show that murder, addiction, marriage, churchgoing, joining a revolutionary movement or writing Paradise Lost are all to be understood in terms of rational choice under constraints."2 For many of its adherents, the theory's ability to offer an explanation of such diverse phenomena confirms its power.3 Though the influence of rational choice theory has spread throughout the social sciences, it has been felt perhaps most strongly in political science, particularly in the study of American politics. In this area, older understandings of the behavior of political parties, elected officials, interest groups and voters have all been seriously challenged by the work of rational choice theorists.4 As a consequence, teachers of political science have begun to reflect upon how rational choice theory ought to be taught to undergraduates and to what degree doing so complements or undermines teaching students about civic responsibility.5 But what is rational choice theory? Although often spoken of as a unified approach, rational choice theory is a broad category whose adherents range from free market conservatives to Marxists.6 To complicate matters further, one often hears this body of work called "social choice" or "public choice" as well; indeed, the way these Page 2 terms are often used suggests they are interchangeable. The differences between them, however, provide useful points of reference for explaining why various theorists emphasize the things they do. Rational, social, and public choice theory, though closely related and sometimes indistinguishable, differ in emphasis if not in method. Social choice theory is concerned primarily with how individuals' preferences or choices can be translated into a coherent social policy or outcome. In its early and more general statement, in Kenneth Arrow's Social Choice and Individual Values, 7 social choice theory extends welfare economics' analysis of how governments make economic policy to how governments take their citizens' preferences into account in making policy of all kinds. When social choice theory is applied explicitly to politics (as it is in William Riker's Liberalism Against Populism) it focuses on various methods of structuring elections or counting votes.8 Public choice theory is virtually indistinguishable from social choice theory with respect to the political phenomena each examines. The difference between the theories comes from the different economic perspectives informing them; public choice theory relies upon free market economics, social choice theory upon welfare economics.9 Both apply economic principles to political science, as indeed does rational choice theory, but each strain of theory is distinguished by the specific economic principles it deems most relevant to political choice. Rational and social choice theorists focus on the paradoxes and pitfalls that accompany individuals' political choices, advocating a redefinition of democracy without any corresponding reform in current political practices and institutions. These theorists emphasize how, once one attends to the logical problems that accompany political choices, ideas like consensus, the common good or acting in the public interest cannot help one defend democracy coherently. Public choice theorists are even more pointedly critical of democratic theory, arguing that most democratic norms concerning equality are not only difficult to realize but not worth pursuing. On the strength of this view, public choice theorists recommend radical changes not only in the way we understand democracy, but also in many of its institutional features. While to distinguish between social and public choice theory one need only point to their different economic parents, characterizing Page 3 rational choice theory is more difficult. Rational choice theory, as a category, probably encompasses more theorists more readily than do either social or public choice theory, but for that very reason the category is less informative as a label. Rational choice theory is a general theory that seeks to explain a great deal of human behavior as the product of individuals' instrumentally rational choices. 10 Rational choice theorists are a highly diverse group which includes Marxists, political theorists and philosophers, game theorists and formal modelers, and political scientists who use rational choice theory in a wide range of empirical studies.11 If all of these people can call themselves rational choice theorists, then rational choice theory must not be the kind of theory that commits its adherents to study specific types of political phenomena from any sort of shared political perspective. Four of the works I examine, Kenneth Arrow's Social Choice and Individual Values, James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock's The Calculus of Consent, Anthony Downs's An Economic Theory of Democracy, and Mancur Olson's The Logic of Collective Action are widely regarded as among the best early statements of various aspects of rational choice theory. The fifth, William Riker's Liberalism Against Populism, published in 1982, is an exception. I include it because while Arrow, on whose work Riker draws, hesitates to apply social choice theory to any specific political practices or institutions, Riker demonstrates both how it can be used to analyze a variety of voting procedures and recast democratic theory. Although these theorists have much in common, noting their differences is instructive. In some cases, they explicitly articulate differences; in others, their differences arise out of shifts of emphasis rather than open disagreement. Anthony Downs and Mancur Olson, whom I regard as rational choice theorists, share neither Arrow and Riker's interest in how elections are structured, nor Buchanan's conviction that current political institutions ought to be reformed in favor of free market mechanisms. Nor do they share much with each other, except an interest in the logic of individual citizens' choices about whether to participate in politics. Although I will make much of these differences, it ought also to be emphasized that each of these theorists is aware of and interested in the work of the others.12 They speak, in many ways, a common language. nlReader.dll?BookID=5235&FileName=Page_3.html Page 4 nlReader.dll?BookID=5235&FileName=Page_5.html Powerful as its challenges to other ways of doing political science have been, rational choice theory has had its share of critics. Indeed, those who participate in its ''research program" often offer the most perceptive critiques, given that their work involves refining and elaborating areas in which the theory reaches inconsistent or unsatisfactory conclusions. 13 Many external critics of rational choice theory may be found as well.14 These range from those who find the explicitly economic basis of the theory poorly suited to its political ambitions to those who fault rational choice theory for privileging the liberal over the participatory in their theory of democracy. Many of these critics take on rational choice theory in the course of taking on something much larger, be it liberalism or utilitarianism. What I intend to offer here is a specific critique of rational choice theorists' attempt to redefine what we mean by democracy. How rational choice theorists conceive of choice—what it means to choose and the value of being able to do so—turns out to be central to understanding how they redefine democracy and why their definition fails. Important as it is to understand how rational choice theorists conceive of rationality and self-interest, focusing on their conception of choice takes us to the core of the puzzle of rational choice theorists' relation to democracy.15 This puzzle consists of the way in which rational choice theorists combine a thoroughly critical approach to democracy with an equally persistent affirmation of it.16 While an ambivalent relation to democracy need not be a puzzling one, rational choice theorists' is so because it is unclear whether they mean for us to love democracy in the cold light of more modest expectations or to focus on its inherent flaws. The source of this puzzle lies in the conception of choice upon which rational choice theorists rely and the way in which it serves as the defining feature of democracy in their work. It is the logic of choosing, elaborated by rational choice theorists that forms the unstable basis for their striking redefinition of what democracy is. Within this logic, we find two conflicting positions. On the one hand, rational choice theorists identify democracy with honoring individual choice, a norm they believe has been overshadowed by pursuing what to their minds are the dubious goals of securing the common good or increasing popular participation. On the other Page 5 hand, they also conclude that the choices citizens are given are not worth making because they are either too insignificant individually to make any difference or are offered and counted in ways that end up distorting the very things that were supposed to be honored. The second position ultimately undermines the first: the pared down theory of democracy rational choice theorists construct is too thin to stand. If democracy is merely the political system that respects individual choices, justifying it as a system, especially in the face of all of its failures to do just that, proves an impossible task. Chapter 1 examines how several prominent rational choice theorists explain the logic of choice in politics. Reducing democracy to choosing, they argue, gives us an accurate sense of what we can reasonably expect from such a system without engendering false hopes about it. But the project of redefining democracy in this way ends up producing deeply pessimistic results. For some rational choice theorists, voting methods, by distorting the effect of individual votes on outcomes, end up robbing individuals of the power to choose in an affirmative way—all voting outcomes can do is negate; as a result, those who do not vote choose in a way that is less ambiguous than those who do. For others, the logic of choice in politics makes it impossible or counterproductive to choose rationally to further one's self-interest. The conclusion that people's political choices are relatively poor tools for securing their political interests leads all of these theorists to assign such dismal expectations to contemporary democratic systems that they find themselves unable to say what is valuable about them. But can we say that most political circumstances allow us to choose in the first place? Chapter 2 explores the problems implicit in rational choice theorists' treating our capacity to choose as a ubiquitous given. For one, Aristotle's account of choice, or prohairesis, suggests how we might specify circumstances in which we cannot or do not choose. The chapter concludes with an ordinary language analysis of "choice" which reveals our implicit understanding of the boundaries and nuances of the concept. Such an analysis leads to the conclusion that our capacity to choose often depends on the situations in which we find ourselves. Therefore, what may seem to the rational choice theorist to confirm the frustrating properties of political choice may be taken instead to describe a situation that does not permit us to choose in the first Page 6 place or in which choices would be unlikely to conform to the pattern of instrumental rationality. Chapter 3 examines how positing choice as a defining feature of democracy shrinks the scope of what we could call democratic arrangements. To do so, this chapter returns to ancient Athens to explore the democratic justifications for the Athenian practice of selecting government officials by lottery rather than choosing them deliberately. The Athenian case illustrates that the value of individual choice is neither necessary nor sufficient to a justification of democracy. Indeed, democracy may be justified on the basis of the collective participation of randomly selected officials and unelected citizen-legislators instead. The central analogy upon which rational choice theory relies distorts what it compares. In comparing consumer choice to political choice, rational choice theorists both idealize the former and neglect important defining features of the latter. Consumers' choices are not always untroubled expressions of authentic preferences; people's choices in politics resemble their choices of market goods neither in their structure nor in their objects. Rational choice theorists declare the formation of preferences to be outside the bounds of their theory; yet, how people come to form and change their political allegiances is a crucial question in political analysis. As a result, chapter 4 argues that one cannot speak of political allegiances or commitments as the objects of rational choice. Rational choice theorists' conception of choice, central as it is to their project of giving a new account of democracy, is also responsible for the incomplete and distorted elements of that account. Although the critique developed here limits itself to one central aspect of rational choice theory, it has been undertaken with the great influence of rational choice theory in the contemporary social sciences in mind. Rational choice theory demands close attention, particularly on the part of political theorists not only because it has so many important adherents, but also because it offers a significant recasting of democratic theory. It is my intention to make this restatement of democratic theory explicit in order to reveal both its basic assumptions and its basic flaws. Page 7 Chapter 1 The Political Frustrations of the Rational Chooser: The Structure of Elections, the Two-Party System and the Politics of Interest Groups To many political scientists, rational choice theory is not political theory, but groundwork for empirical political science. To be sure, much of the work of rational choice theorists relies upon empirical data to explain the behavior of voters, public officials, or states. Yet in spite of rational choice theorists' absorption in empirical questions, many have theoretical ambitions as well. By "theoretical ambitions" I do not mean merely the ambition to articulate a guiding set of assumptions that help ask and answer empirical questions. Rational choice theorists could not do much without acknowledging the importance of that sort of theory. Rather, I mean that many rational choice theorists conceive of their work as providing a corrective to and perhaps even a replacement for political theory as it has been traditionally understood. This sort of challenge to political theory is not new. Many practitioners of political science have, for a variety of reasons, thought political theory peripheral to their discipline. It is the way in which rational choice theorists challenge political theory and the consequences of their doing so that are of interest here. Rational choice theorists are most likely to shrink from defining their work as political theory because that pursuit, in their terms, is a "normative" one. Normative pursuits, rational choice theorists insist, confuse the theorist's ideals with what is the case or what might be possible. Expectations raised by normative theory (about, for instance, the common good or popular consensus) are bound to be frustrated because they rely upon overly optimistic claims about Page 8 human capacities—claims that are never checked against, as William Riker puts it, an analysis of whether "the means are efficient for attaining the ends" (p. 4). 1 Criticizing political theory in this way, however, suggests that these particular critics do not scorn the sorts of questions political theorists have traditionally raised. Rather, they believe that political theory is worth doing right and that their approach reveals what a better political theory might be. Riker, for instance, is explicit about offering a new theory of democracy—one that meets the instrumental criterion given above. Downs claims that rational choice theory could function as a sort of litmus test for normative theories, exposing the weaknesses of those theories which prescribe living in ways that, while seemingly commendable, are grossly inefficient. These criticisms amount to one claim: political theorists have judged the merits of political communities by the wrong standards. Instead of asking how a political community is to be just or equal, one should ask, rational choice theorists believe, whether the ends a community seeks are efficiently attainable. Yet the force of the rational choice critique of normative theory leaves little firm ground upon which the theory's practitioners can construct their own visions of a democratic polity. Freed from the constraints of traditional democratic theory by dismissing any aspirations towards achieving the public good or consensus, rational choice theorists promise to set us down on the conceptual bedrock of a viable democracy. But of what does this bedrock consist? The rational choice revision of democracy is not rhetorically radical. Democracy, rational choice theorists say, is valuable because it strives to honor individuals and to honor them equally. The material out of which this unremarkable understanding of democracy is built, however, is the idea that individuals are honored in a democracy because they are given certain kinds of choices. The conceptual bedrock upon which the rational choice revision of democracy rests, therefore, consists entirely of a particular conception of choice. But it is this very conception of choice which, as rational choice theorists themselves so potently demonstrate, constructs a peculiarly unstable vision of democracy indeed. We must now consider in greater detail why rational choice theorists wish to reduce expectations about democracy. We shall see how a particular conception of choice, so critical to reducing