STETSON UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF LAW 22ND ANNUAL NATIONAL CONFERENCE ON LAW AND HIGHER EDUCATION Clearwater Beach, Florida (February 18-20, 2001) PROFESSORIAL SPEECH AND ACADEMIC FREEDOM: Implications of the Fourth Circuit’s decision in Urofksy v. Gilmore, 216 F.3d 401 (4th Cir. 2000) (cert. denied, 2001) Alison Paige Landry* Assistant Attorney General * The views expressed in this Article are those of the author and do not necessarily represent the views of the Attorney General of Virginia. The author thanks and acknowledges the indispensable contributions of William H. Hurd, Virginia’s Solicitor General, who spearheaded the Governor’s defense, and who first shared with me the lovely dicta of Justice Holmes: “A word is not a crystal, transparent and unchanged, it is the skin of a living thought and may vary greatly in color and content according to the circumstances and the time in which it is used.” Towne v. Eisner, 245 U.S. 418, 425 (1918). In the Beginning . . . “That all power is vested in, and consequently derived from, the people, that magistrates are their trustees and servants, and at all times amenable to them.” Virginia Constitution, Art. I, § 2. Authored by George Mason in 1776, these words from the Virginia Declaration of Rights remain a cornerstone of governance in the Commonwealth and in our nation. The importance of this fundamental principal is magnified by the rise of modern bureaucratic institutions, whose employees number in the thousands. It is magnified yet again by the advent of computer technology, and especially by the arrival of the internet, “arguably the most powerful tool for sharing information ever developed.” Urofsky v. Allen, 995 F. Supp. 634, 638 (E.D. Va. 1998) (“Urofsky I”).1 The Urofsky case was brought by six state employees who sought to create a new constitutional right to autonomy in using the power of state computers. Under the guise of free expression, they sought the right to receive and transmit sexually explicit materials, not just as private citizens, nor even as academics, but as state employees in the conduct of state business. To that end, they brought a facial and an “as-applied” challenge to Va. Code § 2.1-804 et seq., a statute that directs state employees not to use state computers for sexually explicit materials unless their agency has determined that such materials are needed for a bona fide agency purpose. (Appendix.)2 1 For purposes of this article, the district court opinion will be called Urofsky I, the panel decision will be designated Urofsky II, and the en banc opinion shall be called Urofksy III. References to “Urofsky” refer to the lawsuit, in general. The final opinion is published in the Appendix along with a copy of the Act and its definitions. 2 The Act’s provisions applied only to computers, owned or leased by the Commonwealth and used by state employees to discharge their communicative duties. It had no impact on what public employees did in their own time, or on their own dime, or by using their own resources. Early in litigation, plaintiffs renounced any claim to use state computers for “personal entertainment or enlightenment.” They based their claim “solely” on what they claimed were their “professional-employment-related needs.” Joint Appendix at 56 (available upon request). 2 No penalties are provided for violating the Act. It is instead, merely a legislatively adopted personnel rule, the enforcement of which is left to various state agencies and the employee disciplinary procedures ordinarily in force. The Act anticipates and provides for academic exemptions. Indeed, a few had been granted. None were denied. None of the six plaintiffs, all of whom claimed to need sexually explicit materials to carry out their responsibilities, ever requested an exemption under the Act. Almost everything the Commonwealth does in its 111 diverse agencies involves a communication of some sort. Yet it’s also self-evident that: “Government has no mouth, it has no hands or feet; it speaks and acts through people. Governmental employees must do what the state cannot do for itself because it lacks corporeal existence; in a real sense, they are the state.”3 The internet was but a technical excuse unto which plaintiffs attached themselves so they might assert “the dangerous notion that government employees have a personal stake in the words they utter when they speak for the government,” id. at 962, an idea that would inevitably “turn government employment into a platform for endless attacks on government policy and governance into a tug of war between those who make the laws and those who enforce them.” Id. at 962. The Evidentiary Record The Urofsky lawsuit erupted in the Fall of 1996 when Paul Smith, a self-proclaimed masochist and fetishist, used his position as a professor to access George Mason University’s 3 Arizonans for Official English v. Arizona, 69 F.3d 920 at 960 (9th Cir. 1995) (J. Kozinski and Kleinfeld, dissenting), vacated as moot, 520 U.S. 43 (1977). The Yniguez dissenters foreshadowed Urofsky when they wrote: “When confronted with what will come to be known as Yniguez challenges, states…will have to prove that their laws are worth the candle; courts will routinely make judgments traditionally reserved for the legislature and the people themselves. By comparison, Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), will seem like a paean to judicial restraint.” Id. at 962 (Kozinski J., dissenting). 3 (“GMU’s”) website, where he posted a collection of hardcore pornographic photographs. Smith’s lascivious display did not go unnoticed. A group of female students saw the exhibition and lodged protests with University administration. Female faculty and staff also complained, objecting to GMU’s complicity in the distribution of pornography and the resulting hostile educational environment for women on campus. Acting in response to these concerns and relying in part on the Act, the University directed its computer technician to block transmission of the photographs from the University website. Paul Smith’s peep show, submitted into evidence in the case and described by the Court in its opinion, includes the following photographs: a naked man in bondage; the bare buttocks of a woman whose hands were chained and locked behind her; a naked woman hanging spread-eagle in bondage; a naked man stroking his erect penis; a woman exposing her pierced and gaping rectum and vagina; and a woman anally penetrating a man using a strap-on dildo. Another photograph, not submitted into evidence, but which Smith posted on GMU’s server, showed former child pornography star, Traci Lords, engaged in sexual intercourse. 4 Smith was then joined by five other state-employed professors who sought to use their computers for more mundane purposes, including some purposes that were not covered by the Act. Each of the plaintiffs claimed that they had been harmed in their ability to use state In their pleadings, plaintiffs asserted that they could not figure out what “sexually explicit content” meant. They also asserted a few paragraphs later that “sexually explicit content” was precisely what they needed to fulfill their professional duties. Plaintiffs also contended, without shadow of turning, that none of their “sexually valuable” forays into cyberslums ran afoul of obscenity laws. 4 4 computers to conduct internet research and/or to check the work of students citing internet sources. They claimed that deliberately or inadvertently, such use of their state issued computers might lead to their accessing sexually explicit materials covered by the Act. Disdaining any supervision from their institutions, none of the six plaintiffs requested an exception as provided for by the Act, nor did any of the plaintiffs prove that it would have been futile to make such a request. Their position was tantamount to a claim that state employees have a constitutional right to disregard supervision over the content of their work, a position with anti-democratic implications that have now been made apparent. Confronted with the implausibility of their position, plaintiffs and their amici constructed a fallback theory, which they labeled “academic freedom.” By its own terms, this theory could not apply to thousands of non-academic employees. Upon examination, the Commonwealth argued, it was a theory wholly without merit even for state employees in academia. Legal Machinations In the district court, plaintiffs, (represented by the New York ACLU), did not limit their claim to their own academic endeavors. Instead, they presumed to assert what they contended are the First Amendment rights of all 101,000 state employees in Virginia to use state computers for sexually explicit materials. Yet this was not a class action. Claiming that there was a vast universe of what they termed “sexually valuable” materials passing through the electronic arteries of government, plaintiffs protested that the Act dammed this critical river of information. This stunning contention made discovery a veritable dragnet. The Commonwealth argued that the explicit terms of the Act contemplate pornographic materials, i.e., “lascivious” stuff, which, 5 according to the Virginia Supreme Court means “a state of mind that is eager for sexual indulgence, desirous of inciting to lust or of inciting sexual desire and appetite.”5 The Act’s definitions of “sexual conduct” were imported from a Virginia criminal statute restricting sales and displays to juveniles, an act that had previously been challenged by a group of book publishers. After a labyrinth of state and federal litigation, the Fourth Circuit Court of Appeals affirmed the Act as constitutional. American Booksellers Ass’n v. Commonwealth, 882 F.2d 125, 126 (4th Cir. 1989).6 The lurid laundry list of sexual depictions imported from Va. Code § 18.2-390, are stark and astonishingly specific, particularly for a personnel rule. Compare to Arnett v. Kennedy, 416 U.S. 134, 160 (1974) (upholding against both a vagueness and overbreadth challenge an act permitting removal of federal employees only for “such cause as will promote the efficiency of the service.”). In response to this proffered narrowing construction, plaintiffs countered by saying that they did not know what “lascivious” meant. In the same breath (and mindful of the Commonwealth’s skepticism about standing), plaintiffs also alleged that lascivious materials were exactly what they needed and that besides, lasciviousness is a viewpoint. Citing criminal cases like United States v. X-Citement Video, Inc., 513 U.S. 64, 78-79 (1994) (rejecting claim that the term “lascivious” is unconstitutionally vague), the Commonwealth showed that lasciviousness is not a viewpoint, that porn can be left-wing, right-wing or ideologically neutral, and that to speak of discussing subject matter from a “lustful viewpoint” is semantic overkill, at best. General Media Communications Inc. v. Cohen, 131 F.3d 273, 287 (2nd Cir. 1997) 5 Pedersen v. City of Richmond, 219 Va. 1061, 1065, 254 S.E. 2d 95, 98 (1979), quoting McKeon v. Commonwealth, 211 Va. 24, 27, 175 S.E. 2d 282, 284 (1970). See also Dickerson v. City of Richmond, 2 Va. App. 473, 479, 346 S.E.2d 333, 336 (1986) (The term “lewd” is synonymous with lascivious and indecent). 6 When Virginia’s General Assembly recently amended § 18.2-391 to include digital materials, a group of on-line publishers sued local prosecutors claiming the amendment infringed upon their First Amendment rights and violated the Commerce Clause. In August, 2000, Judge Michael enjoined enforcement of the Act. PSINET v. Chapman, 108 F. Supp. 2d 611 (W.D. Va. 2000). The parties are currently preparing to resolve the case on its merits. 6 (“lascivious” is not a viewpoint).7 To show that under canons of “plain meaning,” the world at large (if not the plaintiffs), understood that “sexually explicit” denotes pornography, the Commonwealth’s briefs contained a randy sampling of web-based materials one gets when searching “sexually explicit” anything. A slew of enticements to the Kitty Kat Lounge, but no medical textbooks or National Geographic spreads emerged. Rather than take comfort from the narrowing construction posited by the Commonwealth, plaintiffs insisted that the statute swept into its orbit, not just the lascivious, but also the banal, the benign and the utterly boring. Their ever-pliable interpretation of the Act (a view shared by the district court and the pre-amendment panel decision), applied, for example, not only to pornographic videos of Traci Lords, but also to lab reports documenting genital warts and legal briefs urging that a rape conviction be upheld. As for exceptions, plaintiffs complained that they were “unworkable.” The “sunshine clause” (stating that exemptions were “public documents”), they insisted, inhibited research involving sexual themes in art, literature, law and philosophy. These divergent views about the scope and meaning of the Act inspired a flurry of motions involving the proper scope of discovery. While the Commonwealth argued that a facial challenge required plaintiffs to prove that the Act could not be applied constitutionally to anyone, the ACLU cleverly resolved to make a series of “as-applied” challenges, agency by agency, then string these mini-challenges together and call it a facial challenge. It also became apparent that plaintiffs sought to discover each and every potentially “sexually explicit, professionally-necessary” communication passing in or out of the electronic infrastructure of each and every state agency in Virginia. Seeking to compare this vast universe of “PNSEM” – “professionally necessary sexually explicit material,” with non- See Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, 455 U.S. 489, 498-99 (1982) (noting “greater tolerance of enactments with civil rather than criminal penalties because consequences of imprecision are qualitatively less severe”). 7 7 electronic sexual communications, plaintiffs argued that there was no good reason for Virginia’s General Assembly to legally differentiate between Robert Mapplethorpe on paper and Robert Mapplethorpe on-line. One defense motion challenged how far and deep into the electronic pathways of state government the ACLU should be allowed to go to prove its case. Legal polemics like this inspired several absorbing field trips to Virginia’s science and fine arts museums for a guided tour of their “raunchiest” offerings, which turned out to be limited fare, indeed. Several Greek and Egyptian phalli later, it was determined that some kind of art, Buddhist Tantric art, for example, is meant to be, and in some cases can be deemed lascivious. Anatomically correct drawings of the human reproductive tract at the science museum, were, on the other hand, decidedly nonlascivious.8 First Amendment Feeding Frenzy Because the parties disagreed about the scope of the Act, there were contentious debates about whether several plaintiffs even had standing in the case. One gentleman, for instance, taught basic composition at a community college. How sexually graphic can that be? As long as one plaintiff, Smith, could tripwire the Act (and he did), the Commonwealth resolved that elimination of the additional five plaintiffs for lack of standing would be of limited utility. During discovery and motions practice, the parties argued about everything, including the following: canons of statutory construction, how many different agency heads the ACLU could depose (no more), whether the plaintiffs could deploy FOIA requests for the same materials targeted by discovery (no), whether “lesbian literature” was necessarily sexually 8 These sexual scavenger hunts through state government to find lascivious materials may remind one of recent Taco Bell ads wherein satisfied patrons eating new zesty tacos survey various passing scenes and declare them “zesty” or “not zesty.” The vast majority of materials examined in Virginia’s libraries and museums were of the latter category. 8 explicit (no), and whether remote allusions to homosexual romps in Victorian poetry (understood by a handful of academics like William & Mary English Professor Terry Meyers), ran afoul of the Act (no). Certification as a strategic maneuver, was always looming as a possible procedural digression.9 The parties, under time constraints imposed by Virginia’s federal “rocket docket,” entered into some interesting stipulations as to what was, and what was not covered by the Act. As arduous discovery requests rolled through gads of government agencies, new and difficult questions arose. Was the law content-based? Viewpoint-based? Was it unduly vague? Who, exactly, was enforcing the Act? How precise must its language be when applied to public employees? Did the law require an appeals procedure? Did the doctrine of “prior restraint” operate on this law? What about the secondary effects doctrine? If the U.S. Supreme Court permitted adult theaters to be zoned out of existence because of their deleterious effect on persons, property, law and order, couldn’t a public employer zone out of its own workspaces the same sexually explicit materials? Was the exemption for “bona fide agency projects and undertakings” an unconstitutional burden or the statute’s saving grace? When a professor conducts research for a book she plans to write, is she acting in her “citizen capacity,” her “professional capacity,” or both? What legal test applies to expressive activities by public employees when they are seemingly acting in a dual capacity? Does the public have a right to know in what capacity a public employee speaks? Are workplace computers public fora? If an 9 Certification is a procedure by which a state court, in its discretion, may answer questions certified to it by a United States Court of Appeals. By rule, an appellate court may also request a state’s highest court to render an opinion on a potentially dispositive interpretation of state law. At every stage of litigation, the Commonwealth urged the federal court to avail itself of certification if it felt the act’s proper interpretation by the Virginia Supreme Court was potentially dispositive. Certification of novel questions of state law allows a federal court to “save time, energy, and resources and helps build a cooperative judicial federalism.” Lehman Bros. v. Schein, 416 U.S. 386, 391 (1974). This is especially true when the constitutionality of a state statute is at issue. See Arizonans for Official English v. Arizona, 520 U.S. 43, 64 (1997). 9 employer can prevent its employees from using computers for “non-official” purposes, why can’t that employer go further and advise employees just what kind of materials (porn), are considered “non-official?” Isn’t that exactly what this Act does? Would due process require an employer to forewarn its employees of materials considered controversial or high-risk? Did the provision making all exemptions subject to sunshine laws cast a chill on sexual speech? Or did it further democratic values by enlightening the public about how their resources are being used? If workplace efficiency is the rationale for the Act, why does it merely target sexual material, and not the other kinds of electronic digressions like games, stock quotes and chain letters? These were the kinds of imponderables that filled our days and sometimes nights. Clash of the Titans After the burdensome murk of discovery finally closed over, a pack of hardcore First Amendment voluptuaries argued about what constitutional test applied to such a law. Plaintiffs demanded strict scrutiny, the highest barrier. The Act, they argued, was an overbroad, unnecessary, content-based and viewpoint based overreaction, a classic “prior restraint” that was too vague to comprehend and too standardless to enforce. While claiming that thousands of public employees badly needed “sexually valuable” materials to carry out their workplace responsibilities, plaintiffs failed to produce a single affidavit from a “rank and file” public employee stating that he or she needed sexually explicit materials to carry out their duties. Relying on the wellworn template of employment law, the Commonwealth said that whatever doctrinal tool is deployed, “reasonableness” alone is the appropriate constitutional test. As to the scant number of exceptions granted under the Act, the Commonwealth opined that the paucity of requests showed that state employees and their supervisors did not share the 10 ACLU’s imaginative renderings of the Act. The ACLU, on the other hand, theorized that so few exceptions indicated that the Act was extremely chilling and/or that it was simply being ignored. Whose Speech is it? At summary judgment, the Commonwealth’s legal quiver contained four dependable arrows, any one of which could prove fatal to plaintiff’s case. First, it was argued that government may control its own speech and that state employees have no constitutional right to disregard the instructions of their employer. Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173 (1991) ( upholding Title X regulation that restricted private grantees from promoting abortion as a method of family planning); Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 833 (1995) (“[W]e have permitted the government to regulate the content of what is or is not expressed when it is the speaker or when it enlists private entities to convey its own message.”) Next, it was argued that regardless of how indispensable computers may be as an expressive medium, state computers issued to state employees are not public fora and that abuse of computer resources is plain old misconduct, not pure expression. Perry Education Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37 (1983); Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Educ. Fund, 473 U.S. 788 (1985); Loving v. Boren, 956 F. Supp. 953 (W.D. Okla. 1997) (holding that state university computer and internet services are not a public forum) aff’d. on narrower grounds, 133 F.3d 771 (10th Cir. 1998). Borrowing a practical tool from case law governing adult entertainment establishments, the Commonwealth argued that the “secondary effects” of sexually explicit speech in the workplace may be effectively zoned under Renton v. Playtime Theatres Inc., 475 U.S. 41 (1986). The final contention was that that even if public employees had a personal constitutional stake in what they say on the job, and even if the Picketing/NTEU balancing test applied, a proper 11 weighing of the factors lead to a result in favor of the Act’s validity. Laced throughout these arguments, of course, was the contention that the Act, on its face, and according to its plain meaning, was all about porn. Ultimately, the Fourth Circuit majority embraced the first argument, never reaching the latter three.10 “NTEU” The Plaintiffs and the district court relied heavily on a case styled U.S. v. Nat’l Treasury Employees’ Union, 513 U.S. 454 (1995) (“NTEU”). Their reliance on that case was particularly odd since the facts of that case belie any suggestion that it affirms the rights of public employees to speak in their professional capacity qua public employees. NTEU involved an honoraria ban that applied to writing and other expressive activities having no nexus to an employee’s federal employment.11 Justice Stevens, who wrote the majority opinion in NTEU, took pains to emphasize the fact that NTEU’s employees staked no constitutional claim involving their official duties: They seek compensation for their expressive activities in their capacity as citizens, not as Government employees. They claim their employment status has no more bearing on the quality or market value of their literary output than it did on that of Hawthorne or Melville. With few exceptions, the content of [the employees’] messages has nothing to do with their jobs and does not even arguably have any adverse impact on the efficiency of the offices in which they work. They do not address audiences composed of co-workers or supervisors; instead, they write or speak for segments of the general public. Neither the character of the authors, the subject matter of their expression, the effect of the content of their expression on their official duties, nor the kind of audiences they address has any relevance to their employment. Id. at 465 (emphasis added). Judge Wilkinson, in his concurrence, attempted to balance the interests and concluded that the Commonwealth’s interests outweighed the employees’ interests. 11 A postal employee in NTEU, for instance, sought compensation for lectures he gave on the Quaker religion. An aerospace engineer had been compensated to lecture on black history. There was an FDA microbiologist who critiqued dance performances, a Nuclear Regulatory Commission lawyer who penned articles about Russian history and a tax examiner who wrote articles about the environment. 10 12 The ACLU’s mantra-like recital of NTEU did nothing to establish that plaintiffs and the federal employees in NTEU were similarly situated. In fact, it turned out that rather than being controlled by NTEU, Urofsky was more like NTEU’s evil twin because in Urofsky, plaintiffs asserted only a right as government employees to use state computers to access sexually explicit materials and to do so unconditionally. This demand simply bit off too much and flew in the face of constitutional precedent affirming a public employer’s prerogative to manage its employees. “When someone who is paid a salary so that she will contribute to an agency’s effective operation begins to do or say things that detract from the agency’s effective operation, the government employer must have some power to restrain her.” Waters v. Churchill, 511 U.S. 661, 675 (1994). For these same contextual reasons, it was ludicrous to condemn the Act as a prior restraint.12 Undergirding the Commonwealth’s arguments in Urofsky was the recurring theme that government must be kept amenable to the people. This means not only that elected officials must be responsible to the electorate, but that government employees must be subject to supervision and direction by those elected officials. The argument was straightforward and compelling: those hired by government to do its work may not substitute their own messages for the ones they are professionally obliged to deliver. Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173 (1991); Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 833 (“[W]hen the government appropriates public funds to promote a particular policy of its own it is entitled to say what it wishes.”). Public employees, like all citizens, remain free to pursue their own use of sexually explicit materials when not on the job using state computers. When, however, their access to the computer is made possible only 12 Among an array of First Amendment platitudes, certain ones get little airplay, but are critically important to a balanced understanding of the Bill of Rights. One of these platitudes, brought into high relief by this case, is that nothing in the Constitution prevents the state from restraining itself. 13 because they are state employees, then the speech transmitted online in furtherance of those professional duties is not “citizen speech,” as contemplated by Connick/Pickering,13 but governmental speech. Plaintiffs never really came to grips with the fact that employment law governed the case. Instead, they characterized the Act as silly and politically meddlesome as though these were constitutional defects. Refusing to the end to concede that employers can and do make contentbased decisions all day long, plaintiffs condemned the Act for being both under-inclusive and over-inclusive, thus terribly (rather than narrowly), tailored. Casting aside wellworn caselaw affording public employers significant discretion to control speech on the job, plaintiffs extolled the wonder and the virtues of the internet ala ACLU v. Reno,14 arguing that the Act cast a pall of orthodoxy over academic research and other important intellectual work undertaken by public employees. Their best argument was that “citizen speech,” as contemplated by Connick/Pickering, need not be “official” speech to warrant First Amendment protection. On the other hand, they claimed that the “citizen/employee” distinction articulated in Pickering and Connick was simply shorthand for a determination whether an employee’s speech is “on matters of public concern” (and therefore shielded by the First Amendment), or is upon “matters only of personal interest.” Connick, 461 U.S. at 147. But the question, “whose speech is it?” has three possible answers, not just two. Where the speech at issue could be government speech, focusing on a two-part 13 14 Connick v. Myers, 461 U.S. 138 (1983); Pickering v. Bd. of Educ., 391 U.S. 563 (1968). Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844 (1997) (striking down various provisions of the Communications Decency Act). 14 distinction between citizen speech and employee speech is not “shorthand”; it is a short-circuit in the analysis.15 In the District Court On cross motions for summary judgment, the District Court, Judge Leonie Brinkema, a former librarian, accepted Plaintiff’s broad characterization of the Act’s sweep and decided that state employees are constitutionally entitled to ignore supervision from their employer and to follow their own personal views on what is required to conduct public business. The district court opinion recognized that the Commonwealth had a right to promote workplace efficiency and to prevent creation of a sexually hostile environment. It also acknowledged that public employees transfixed on pornography that is unrelated to their professional duties are in neglect of theirs. The Court discounted these interests, however, flyspecked the Act and spied at every turn a hodgepodge of constitutional hobgoblins. The Court, for instance, declared the Act to be “no improvement” on “content-neutral” rules already in place. But, the Commonwealth protested, there is no reason why a statute, to withstand constitutional scrutiny, must constitute an improvement on pre-existing law. The district court criticized the Act because it failed to target materials that were racially, ethnically or religiously offensive. Yet, there is no constitutional requirement that a legislature eradicate all workplace distractions in one comprehensive act. Semler v. Oregon State Bd. of Dental Examiners, 294 U.S. 608, 610 (1935) (Lawmakers need not “strike at all evils at the same time or in the same way.”). Even the law enforcement exception was belittled by the Court as “strange.” Why is it strange, the Commonwealth replied, that law enforcement officials entrusted to conduct criminal Attempting to define what is, and what is not, “citizen speech” within the meaning of Pickering/Connick is, concededly, the densest underbrush in the case and was the primary focus of the parties’ arguments for and against a writ of certiorari. 15 15 investigations into the ephemeral medium of cyberspace be permitted to do so without any condition or possible delay? The District Court criticized the Act for its absence of appeal rights. Yet the U. S. Supreme Court has ruled that even criminal defendants sentenced to prison terms have no constitutional right to appeal from their convictions. Abney v. U.S., 431 U.S. 651, 657 (1977). What theory of the Constitution required greater protection for state employees denied an opportunity to read pornography at taxpayer expense? The District Court even decried the FOIA clause, which expressly designated exceptions as public documents. That Virginia’s legislature took pains to expressly state that such documents can be reached by FOIA was surely not a constitutional infirmity, was it? Urofsky I was applauded by many, then appealed to a more favorable climate, the Fourth Circuit Court of Appeals. On appeal, the Fourth Circuit, sitting as a three-judge panel, then later, en banc, disagreed with the District Court and upheld the Act as constitutional. Urofsky II. Unsatisfied with Urofsky II, plaintiffs then requested a rehearing en banc, i.e., full panel review. In what initially appeared to signal receptivity to the “as-applied” portion of the lawsuit, the full panel requested further briefing on “academic freedom.” After more briefing and captivating oral argument, in which research issues loomed large, the full panel, like the three judge panel before, upheld the Act as constitutional. Urofsky III, 216 F.3d 401 (4th Cir. 2000) (en banc). On January 8, 2001, the United States Supreme Court declined to review Urofsky III. The Act has been in effect in Virginia since March of 1999. Legislative Intervention Between the time the three-judge panel heard the case and the time the full panel reheard it, Virginia’s General Assembly “got into the act.” Shortly after the three-judge panel rejected the Commonwealth’s limiting construction of the Act, the legislature amended it so that it 16 expressly applied only to materials “whose predominant theme is lascivious.” This mid- litigation amendment clarified and narrowed the scope of materials targeted by the Act. The amendment was yet another factor that may have persuaded the Court that the statute struck the proper constitutional balance between the competing interests of the university and its faculty.16 After the lasciviousness amendment became law, the parties got to argue what it meant all over again. By this time, however, it was clear that the Act would not rise or fall based on its intricate sexual semantics. Rather, the Connick/Pickering balancing test, or lack of it, would prove dispositive. In Urofsky III, like Urofsky II, the majority found nothing substantive on the “citizen” side of the equation to balance.17 Wielding the unsteady Pickering scales (and getting a blistering attack from Judge Luttig for having undertaken the task), Judge Wilkinson too concludes that the Commonwealth’s interests in workplace efficiency outweigh whatever citizen interests are implicated. Academic Freedom: Two Concepts Urofsky v. Gilmore is often referred to as a case about academic freedom, and it is. By reminding us what academic freedom is not, the decision points to what academic freedom must be. Much of the discussion by plaintiffs about academic freedom consisted of lofty panegyrics that did not provoke disagreement so much as they left one wondering about their utility in the hard analysis of specific cases. No one doubts the value of academic freedom, but its precise 16 In a strategic move that can only be described as an attempt to suppress the opinion in Urofsky II, plaintiffs suggested, mid-litigation, that the new amendment rendered the panel decision moot, that the panel decision should be vacated (wiped from the books), and that the case should begin all over again in the district court. This coup d'etat also failed. Ultimately, the Fourth Circuit reviewed both the old and the new versions of the statute, and found them both constitutional. 17 Judge Wilkinson’s concurrence in Urofsky III insists that there must be some kind of “citizen speech” to balance, but he never quite identifies the kind of speech subject to protection. His opinion appears, at times, to conflate the computer with the internet, which is somewhat like comparing a boat with the sea. 17 contours may be the subject of legitimate debate. Moreover, as any discussion of academic freedom should acknowledge at the outset, the term is used in two very different ways.18 First, there is the concept of academic freedom as developed and advocated by academics through professional associations such as the American Association of University Professors (“AAUP”). See, e.g., AAUP, 1940 Statement of Principles on Academic Freedom and Tenure. While the official statements of the AAUP may govern the employment of professors at institutions that have adopted them, their enforceability is a matter of contract law, not constitutional law. Second, there are cases in which the application of the First Amendment in the context of academia have been discussed under the name of “academic freedom.” While there may be some overlap between the two concepts, it is only the latter concept that concerned the court in Urofsky. The starting point for discussing the constitutional dimension of academic freedom is Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U.S. 234 (1957). There, in a concurring opinion, Justice Frankfurter quoted approvingly the following description of a university: It is the business of a university to provide that atmosphere which is most conducive to speculation, experiment and creation. It is an atmosphere in which there prevail ‘the four essential freedoms’ of a university — to determine for itself on academic grounds who may teach, what may be taught, how it shall be taught, and who may be admitted to study. Id. at 263, quoting “The Open Universities in South Africa, 10-12.” Using the framework adopted by Justice Frankfurter, constitutional cases involving academic freedom can be divided into two groups: (i) cases dealing with the conditions that government may place upon hiring and retention, i.e., “who may teach,” and (ii) cases dealing with the content of curriculum, i.e., “what may be taught [and] how it shall be taught.” The 18 See, e.g., Walter P. Metzger, Profession and Constitution: Two Definitions of Academic Freedom in America, 66 TEX. L. REV. 1265 (1988) (arguing that definition and boundaries on constitutional academic freedom are significantly different from those concepts of academic freedom formulated by the academic profession itself). 18 problem with plaintiffs’ argument, in a nutshell, is that they confused these two distinct concepts, just as they confused the distinction between AAUP Declarations of Principles and the U.S. Constitution. Hiring and Retention Not Implicated Here In Sweezy, the State Attorney General sought to conduct an investigation into an individual who had lectured at the University of New Hampshire. The alleged authority for the investigation was a state Subversive Activities Act, which made “subversive persons” ineligible for employment in state government, including public educational institutions. Sweezy refused to answer questions about the Progressive Party of New Hampshire or about an allegedly proMarxist lecture he had given. His refusal led to a finding that he was “in contempt” of court. The Supreme Court held that the state had acted unconstitutionality by penalizing him for its failure to answer its questions. In so doing, the Supreme Court made clear that the facts of the case did not raise an issue of state authority over curriculum: The state courts upheld the attempt to investigate the academic subject on the ground that it might indicate whether petitioner was a “subversive person.” What he taught the class at a state university was found relevant to the character of the teacher. The State Supreme Court carefully excluded the possibility that the inquiry was sustainable because of the state interest in the state university. The sole basis for the inquiry was to scrutinize the teacher as a person, and the inquiry must stand or fall on that basis. Id. at 249 (emphasis added). Given this context, the Supreme Court went on to say that Sweezy’s First Amendment rights had been violated: Merely to summon a witness and compel him, against his will, to disclose the nature of his past expressions and associations is a measure of governmental interference in these matters. These are rights, which are safeguarded by the Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment. We believe that there unquestionably was an invasion of petitioner’s liberties in the areas of academic freedom and political expression — areas in which government should be extremely reticent to tread. *** 19 Our form of government is built on the premise that every citizen shall have the right to engage in political expression and association. This right was enshrined in the First Amendment of the Bill of Rights. Exercise of these basic freedoms in America has traditionally been through the media of political associations. Any interference with the freedom of a party is simultaneously an interference with the freedom of its adherents. Id. at 250. Thus, Sweezy was vindicated by the Supreme Court because the state had sought to use the fact of his university employment as an occasion to pillory him for his political views. Later, in Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589 (1967), the Court struck down a loyalty oath as a requirement for employment at a public university. The basic principle enunciated in both Sweezy and Keyishian is that government cannot condition employment on political viewpoint. While the principle was first recognized in the context of academia, where there was no tradition of political patronage, it was later expanded to cover public employees in jobs where such patronage was long established as a common practice. See Elrod v. Burns, 427 U.S. 347 (1976), and Branti v. Finkel, 445 U.S. 507 (1980). In the context of this broadened First Amendment jurisprudence, it is not clear what may be added by use of the term “academic freedom” other than to make the point that professorial positions do not constitute “policy” positions subject to a patronage exception under the Elrod/Branti line of cases.19 In Urofsky, the principle that professors may not be hired or fired based on their political views was clearly not implicated. The Act did not address hiring or firing. Moreover, so long as professors do not use state computers, the Act leaves them free to say or read whatever they wish with complete impunity. Paul Smith may replicate pornography on the internet all night long, so long as he does it on his own computer. Indeed, he may even do so on the state computer, so long as his university agrees that it is required for his work. 19 It was, perhaps, a recognition of this fact that led the Supreme Court recently to describe the McCarthy-era, subversion cases as “so-called academic-freedom cases.” University of Pa. v. EEOC, 493 U.S. 182, 197 (1990) (emphasis added). 20 The Institution Controls Curriculum The second category of academic freedom cases deals with the content of the curriculum, or, to use Justice Frankfurter’s formulation, “what may be taught [and] how it shall be taught.” According to Justice Frankfurter, these are freedoms that belong to the university. They do not give individual university professors a constitutional right to autonomy in their professional work. It may well be true that some institutions have adopted AAUP principles or other policies in which tenured faculty have a larger measure of independence; but, these are contract issues, not constitutional issues. As far as the Constitution is concerned, decisions about university policy or the use of university resources by individual professors remain subject to the control of the university as the arbiter of its own educational mission.20 The Fourth Circuit is not the first court to recognize this principle. Case Study: Bishop v. Aronov Bishop v. Aronov, 926 F.2d 1066 (11th Cir. 1991), for instance, involved a dispute between the University of Alabama and a professor of exercise physiology whose Christian beliefs were reflected in his teaching in a way the University administration found objectionable. Although he never prayed in class nor read the Bible there, he advised his students of his Christian perspective. He also offered voluntary, after-class meetings to discuss evidences of God in human physiology and the resulting conclusion that man was created by God. When the University sent him a memo exhorting him to stop mentioning his faith in class and to cease conducting after-class meetings, Bishop filed suit, claiming that his First Amendment rights were being violated. The Eleventh Circuit disagreed with Bishop, siding instead with the University’s position that the memo was a reasonable restriction on a professor’s rights of academic freedom. The court identified the salient question as “to what degree a school may control classroom 20 Not everyone agrees with this conclusion, of course. See, J. Peter Byrne, Constitutional Academic Freedom in Scholarship and in Court, The Chronicle Review, January 5, 2001 at B13, in which one commentator declares that the Urofsky decision “sickens” him. One scholar’s nausea is another’s euphoria. 21 instruction before touching the First Amendment rights of a teacher.” Id. at 1072. In answering that question, the court said that “the school’s administration may at least establish the parameters of focus and general subject matter of curriculum.” Id. (internal quotation marks and citations omitted). While acknowledging the importance of academic freedom in the Keyishian context, the Court explained that “pronouncements about academic freedom in that context, however, cannot be extrapolated to deny schools command of their own courses.” Id. at 1075. The Court then went on to say: Though we are mindful of the invaluable role academic freedom plays in our public schools, particularly at the post-secondary level, we do not find support to conclude that academic freedom is an independent First Amendment right. And, in any event, we cannot supplant our discretion for that of the University. Federal judges should not be ersatz deans or educators. Id. (emphasis added). Bishop v. Aronov is one in a long line of cases which recognize that the university, not individual faculty, are the arbiters of educational germaneness and appropriate management of university resources. By assigning to state agencies — including educational institutions — the final authority to decide what is required for their work, the Act adopts these principles. Surely, if academic freedom is not violated when a university restrains one professor’s search for Jesus, it is not violated if another university restrains a professor’s search for Traci Lords.21 See Clark v. Holmes, 474 F.2d 928 (7th Cir. 1972), cert. denied, 411 U.S. 972 (1973) (affirming university’s right to control content of biology professor's health course); Lovelace v. Southeastern Massachusetts Univ., 793 F.2d 419, 426 (1st Cir. 1986) (“The first amendment does not require that each non-tenured professor be made a sovereign unto himself.”); Hetrick v. Martin, 480 F.2d 705, 708-709 (6th Cir. 1973 ), cert. denied, 414 U.S. 1075 (1973) (university need not renew contract of professor whose pedagogical attitudes and teaching methodologies did not conform to institutional standards); Megill v. Bd. of Regents, 541 F.2d 1073 (5th Cir. 1976) (professors do not escape supervision in the manner in which classes are conducted or in assignment of grades); Wirsing v. Bd. of Regents of Univ. of Colorado, 739 F. Supp. 551, 553 (D. Colo. 1990) (“Academic freedom is not a license for activity at variance with job related procedures and requirements.”); Keen v. Penson, 970 F.2d 252 (7th Cir. 1992) (university did not violate faculty member’s First Amendment rights by directing him to make a written apology to student and to change her grade); Scallet v. Rosenblum, 911 F. Supp. 999 (W.D. Va. 1996), aff’d on other grounds, 1997 U.S. LEXIS 1465 (4th Cir. Va.) (Jan. 29) (unpublished), cert. denied, 521 U.S. 1105 (1997) (business school, not individual faculty member, controls course content). 21 22 The Act merely creates a requirement of germaneness, not unlike the germaneness limitation that even the AAUP recognizes in the context of its own concept of academic freedom.22 This germaneness requirement is found in the provisions of the Act that allow the use of sexually explicit computerized material when “required in conjunction with a bona fide agency-approved research project or other agency-approved undertaking.” Va. Code § 2.1-805. Indeed, whatever may be Paul Smith’s academic need for pornography in his course on cultural studies, it is difficult to imagine how pornography would be relevant, say, to a calculus or astronomy professor. Consistent with the principle that an institution is the arbiter of its own educational mission, the Act vests the institution — not some outside official — with the authority to determine when such materials are so required.23 The Act does not violate principles of academic freedom, but is wholly consistent with them.24 No Prof is an Island The AAUP and the Act both recognize that professors should claim no personal stake in speech that does not relate to their respective subject matter. Just as a physics professor is contractually obliged to teach physics and not art history, so too a professor can stake no constitutional claim to go off-course, regardless of how fascinating or important to some those digressions might be. Paul Smith contended that as a professor of Cultural Studies, he researches pornography and its effects on popular culture. If the peepshow published on GMU’s server can The AAUP 1940 Statement of Principles on Academic Freedom and Tenure admonishes faculty “not to introduce into his teaching controversial matter which has no relation to his subject. As [an] educational officer, he should make every effort to indicate that he is not an institutional spokesman.” 23 Even if the authority to make these decisions were vested outside the institution, it is by no means clear that there would be a violation of academic freedom. When “government attempts to direct the content of speech at public educational institutions, complicated First Amendment issues are presented because government is simultaneously both speaker and regulator.” University of Pa. v. EEOC, 493 U.S. 182, 198 n.6 (1990). 24 This conclusion is not changed by the provision of the Act that allows the public to obtain information about agency approvals. These are, after all, public institutions and if the taxpayers are going to be so harnessed, they have a right to know what load they are pulling. To suggest that university employees have a constitutional right to keep their professional activities secret — for fear the public may not approve — is an idea as novel as it is antidemocratic. 22 23 be called “research” unaccompanied by text, without scholarly explanation, and without ideation, then it may well be germane. But that is for GMU to decide, not Smith. Power to the People, Not Necessarily the Professors Urofsky teaches that academic freedom is not synonymous with a right to eschew institutional oversight. Regardless of the contractual insularities of tenure, under the First Amendment, no professor is a sovereign unto him or herself, at least when his professional agenda conflicts with his employer’s. This may sound self-evident, but it has yet to sink in, because frankly it is counter-intuitive, running contrary to the academic zeitgeist. More to the point, it makes professors look more and more like ordinary employees. Between the majority opinion, three separate concurrences, Judge Luttig and Chief Judge Wilkinson’s “symposia,” and a snappy, sometimes angry dissent, the decision contains one of the most detailed explications on academic freedom that can be found in any American judicial opinion to date.25 But light is not necessarily heat. Ultimately, the opinion gently places the sacred cow of academic freedom back into its box, then focuses on an equally transcendent principle. The Court reassures us that public accountability for electronic resources, even in higher education, preserves, rather than corrodes the democratic values advanced by the First Amendment. The court holds today, as has been uniformly recognized by the Supreme Court through the years, only that there is no constitutional right of free inquiry unique to professors or to any other public employee, that the First Amendment protects the rights of all public employees equally. Neither the value nor the contributions of academic inquiry to society are denigrated by such a holding. And to believe otherwise is to subscribe to the fashionable belief that all that is 25 The lively, often pointed exchange between Judge Luttig and Chief Judge Wilkinson, is one of the great reads in First Amendment jurisprudence. See also Judge Luttig’s landmark opinion in Rice v. Paladin Enterprises, Inc., 128 F.3d. 233 (4th Cir. 1997), cert denied, 523 U.S. 1074 (1998) (First Amendment does not shield publisher of “Hitman,” an assasination manual, from tort liability. Publisher may be answerable for the wrongful death of victims slain according to manual’s directives.). 24 treasured must be in the Constitution and that if it is not in the Constitution then it is not treasured. But precisely because it is a constitution that we interpret, not all that we treasure is in the Constitution. Academic freedom is paradigmatic of this truism. Academic freedom, however, is also paradigmatic of the truism that not all that we treasure is in need of constitutionalization. No university worthy of the name would ever attempt to suppress true academic freedom – constrained or unconstrained by a constitution. And, if it did, not only would it find itself without its faculty; it would find itself without the public support necessary for its very existence. The Supreme Court has recognized as much – be it through wisdom, prescience, or simple duty to the Constitution – for over two hundred years now. It has recognized that, in the end, the academic can be no less accountable to the people than any other public servant. His speech is subject to the limitations of the First Amendment certainly no more, but just as certainly no less, than is the custodian’s. That we should all be accountable to the people, and accountable equally, should cause none of us to bridle. Id. at 425 (J. Luttig, concurring). In the Fourth Circuit’s view, free wheeling inquiry by faculty members and the university’s right to guard its productivity and its communicative priorities are not constitutionally incompatible. Nor should they be. Supervision and professional autonomy can and do co-exist in many other intellectual professions, including the practice of law. This fundamental concept, that in the employment context, somebody gets to steer the ship, was accepted by the Fourth Circuit which had previously recognized that “[a] government employer, no less than a private employer, is entitled to insist upon obedience to the legitimate, day-to-day decisions of the office without fear of reprisal in the form of lawsuits from disgruntled subordinates who believe that they know better than their supervisors how to manage office affairs.” DiMeglio v. Haines, 45 F.3d 790, 806 (4th Cir. 1995). Urofsky merely reaffirms that the First Amendment is not carte blanche for “those who know better,” including faculty, to set 25 the university’s expressive agenda.26 Whether framed in terms of what the state’s message is to be, or how the state’s work is to be performed, or how state property is to be used, the Fourth Circuit suggests that these are the kinds of decisions that the people have a right to answer through the ballot box. They should not have to fear being undone by dissenters who have the inside advantage of being on the government payroll, nor should those in public service be required to endure sexually explicit materials in the offices where they earn their livelihoods. The law of the Fourth Circuit is that even professors, armed with the revolutionary internet, may not hijack a public university’s academic prerogatives. Urofsky’s judgment is fairly narrow, but its dicta, and its ramifications for the millennial age, are refreshingly apparent. The case dramatically underscores the ever-widening chasm between “professional” (“AAUP redbook”) definitions of academic freedom and constitutional ones. Yet, when moored to its factual pier (professional duties discharged on state-supplied resources), Urofsky III offends neither the professional norms as conceived by the AAUP, or the constitutional one as contemplated by the United States Supreme Court. Public Employee Elitism Some may say that Urofsky III is a judicial rejection of public employee elitism, a resounding affirmation of the equality of all public employees in the shadow of the First Amendment. To the extent that some academics really do believe that professors have “more” 26 Due in large part to an earlier Fourth Circuit precedent, Boring v. Buncombe County Bd. of Educ., 136 F.3d 364 (4th Cir.), cert denied, 525 U.S. 813 (1998), Urofsky III appears to lay to rest any lingering doubt, at least in the Fourth Circuit, as to “who owns” curriculum in public universities. Because Boring involved high school teachers, not academicians, the ACLU argued that the rules of academic freedom did not apply. Boring, however, proved the Commonwealth’s case with respect to non-academic employees who comprise the overwhelming majority of the state workforce. 26 constitutional rights than other employees, Urofsky III dramatically rejects that view, taking pains to level the playing field of free expression between professors and custodians. Id. at 425 (J. Luttig, concurring). Where Do We Go From Here? Perhaps Urofsky can breathe new life into the concept and the practice of “academic supervision,” a notion that struck the professor-plaintiffs in Urofsky as problematic, if not oxymoronic. Urofsky’s fundamental premise, that a public employer, particularly a university, may direct the content of its employees’ professional communications, should not startle or unnerve. Universities, as a practical matter, often delegate broad, content-based discretion to their faculty in any number of areas. This will continue to be the case. As the United States Supreme Court and the Fourth Circuit remind us, however, the wisdom of a practice does not require that it be constitutionalized. Minnesota State Bd. of Community Colleges v. Knight, 465 U.S. 271, 287 (1984) (acknowledging the prudence of shared governance, but concluding that faculty have no First Amendment right to participate in academic policymaking.). Intra vs. Extramural Speech While most faculty members will tell you that it is their in-class speech that is most protected by the First Amendment, the exact opposite is true, at least in the Fourth Circuit. Moreover, when it comes to divining what kinds of utterances “touch upon matters of public concern,” Urofsky III utterly rejects the view that what professors have to say is categorically more important than what other public employees have to say. Contrary to the position argued by plaintiffs in this case, there is no constitutional presumption that everything said and done by university professors is necessarily of “public concern.” As the Fourth and Fifth Circuit have recognized: 27 Because almost anything that occurs within a public agency could be of concern to the public, we do not focus on the inherent interest or importance of the matters discussed by the employee. Rather our task is to decide whether the speech at issue in a particular case was made primarily in the plaintiff’s role as citizen or primarily in his role as employee. In making this determination, the mere fact that the topic of the employee’s speech was one in which the public might or would have had a great interest is of little moment. DiMeglio v. Haines, 45 F.3d 790, 805 (4th Cir. 1995) quoting Terrell v. Univ. of Texas Sys. Police, 792 F.2d 1360, 1362 (5th Cir. 1986), cert. denied, 479 U.S. 1064 (1987). In order, therefore, to find themselves in the protective cloak of the First Amendment, university faculty must be speaking as ordinary citizens, or even about their job duties, but not in discharge of their professional duties. This legal axiom contradicts the “received wisdom” on academic freedom, which tends to fixate on in-class utterances as a constitutional safe harbor of sorts. “Not Zesty” Fortunately for Virginia’s taxpayers, despite its seemingly provocative mix of porn, the web and higher education, alas, Urofsy III, as precedent, is not as sexy as it seems. When viewed through the humdrum lens of public employment law, the opinion is an unremarkable affirmation of the Connick-Pickering balancing test, three-decade-old jurisprudence. That, in essence, was what the Commonwealth recently argued in opposition to plaintiffs’ petition for writ of certiorari; that the case may be zesty, in fact, but insofar as breaking new legal ground, it is not zesty, therefore, “uncert-worthy.” This final legal strategy, to make the case as uninteresting to the United States Supreme Court as possible, apparently worked. Conclusion While the ACLU has catastrophized the impact of Urofsky III, the opinion is a measured recognition that public agencies, including universities, must be kept amenable to the people. What then is the practical fall-out of the case? In the wake of Urofsky III, all Paul Smith needs 28 to do if he wants to publish pornography on the university website is to walk down the hall and ask his Dean. That never happened in this case. It never got a chance to happen. Whether it will happen in the future is anyone’s guess. It is not up to the Commonwealth, as sovereign, to decide if Smith’s graphic display constitutes bona fide research; that is for his academic supervisors to determine. In so doing, at least in the Fourth Circuit, administrators in higher education need not wring their hands about the First Amendment. ********** 29