Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy The essence of Government is power; and power, lodged as it must be in human hands, will ever be liable to abuse. [James Madison (1829) Speech at the Virginia Constitutional Convention. The Writings of James Madison: 1819-1836 (1910), ed. Galliard Hunt, p. 361. (KL 4548).] Public choice theory has been the avenue through which a romantic and illusory set of notions about the workings of governments and the behavior of persons who govern has been replaced by a set of notions that embody more skepticism about what governments can do and governors will do. ... [P]ublic choice offers a theory of governmental failure that is fully comparable to the theory of market failure that emerged from the theoretical welfare economics of the 1930s and 1940s. [James Buchanan (1984) “Politics without Romance, in Buchanan, J. M. and R. D. Tollison (Eds.) The Theory of Public Choice II. University of Michigan Press.] I. Introduction: Can Politics be Ethical? This chapter explores the role of ethics in governance, especially that subset of ethical dispositions that support both democratic governance and commerce. Internalized ethical dispositions affect voter assessments of policies alternatives and the performance of those holding high offices, as well as preferences over types of governments. Ethical dispositions partially determine how policies are implemented and the consequences of those policies though effects on the behavior of the persons charged with creating and enforcing those policies and those affected by them. A law is more 1 likely to be implemented as intended by a bureaucracy staffed by dutiful rule-following persons with a strong work ethic and some practical wisdom. A service is easier to provide if the persons using them are honest and respectful of other persons sharing the service. A new regulation is more likely to bind behavior if persons in the community regard law-abiding behavior to be virtuous and praiseworthy. The utilitarian case for government interventions beyond civil law assumes that internalized ethical dispositions (and bargaining) fail to resolve externality and public goods problems in the private sector, but do so in the public sector. In such cases, there are a broad range of externality, public goods, and coordination problems that can potentially be reduced through government interventions that alter private incentives. Remedies can make a commercial society more attractive by reducing both losses and unrealized gains associated with such problems. If, however, governmental policy makers are not utilitarians and are not driven by social or electoral pressures to behave as if they were so, the case for intervention is weaker. In such cases, government interventions may reduce rather than increase aggregate utility over that which emerges in a commercial society under laissez faire with a supportive civil law system.1 That counterproductive policies are possible for authoritarian regimes seems obvious, but may be less so for democratic regimes. However, in either case pragmatic policy makers and those who have internalized norms that tend to undermine commerce often have reasons to adopt polices that reduce the extent and scope of value-increasing competition and innovation, and thereby material sources of satisfaction and happiness in their communities. This problem is not simply a matter of whether policymakers are ethical or not. A wide variety of possible formal legal and regulatory systems can Here I use laissez faire in the sense used by Mill rather than Spencer, as allowing for modest regulations, support for education, and social insurance programs. It is used to contrast with the broader scope of authority delegated to contemporary mixed and social democratic states. The continuum of the potential delegation of authority to a government may be usefully divided into three intervals: laissez faire, a state with relatively little authority beyond protecting the rights defined by civil law; mixed or intermediate: a state with substantial but limited authority to intervene in markets and life in general, and social democratic: a state with essentially unconstrained authority to intervene as seems useful. page 1 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy undermine commerce and democracy. Many of these have ethical foundations. For example, Aristotle’s argument against interest on money loans can be (and have been) incorporated into law. Strict laws against usury reduce or eliminate the banking and finance industries. The potential demand for and supply of credit still exists, but only cumbersome legal (and illegal) workabouts for realizing those gains are possible under such laws. These increase higher transactions costs and risks for lenders and borrowers. Such laws reduce commerce beyond the financial sector through effects on the demand for final goods, intermediate goods, and input markets. Markets for housing and automobiles and their capital and labor inputs are all smaller than they would have been without well-functioning credit markets.2 With respect to political institutions, ethical dispositions may support, undermine, or rule out democratic governance and equality before the law. Many absolute ethical principles tend to narrow the scope for dissent and debate. Tolerance may be deemed evidence of dereliction of duty rather than intellectual and moral modesty. Openness to alternative ideas may be regarded as sacrilegious rather than evidence of thoughtful deliberation or tolerance. Families rather than individuals might be regarded as the proper center of responsibility and virtue. Privileged rights to participate in governance may be regarded as proper rewards for a family’s past contributions to their society, rather than unearned or unjust privileges. Elections may be regarded to be inferior to and less honorable than expert governance or rule by elites. The remainder of the chapter explores the extent to which well-functioning democracies, like commercial societies, may be said to have ethical foundations. It demonstrates that without ethical support, democratic governments are likely to be indecisive, poor, and corrupt. In such cases, democratic governments are unlikely to remedy the monopoly, externality, public goods, and income distribution problems of concern to utilitarians. If governments do not routinely do so, then utilitarian conclusions about the proper scope for government authority have to be modified to take government failures into account. Additional caveats have to be added to Pigou’s analysis of remedies for market failures. Again, the conclusion that democratic systems of governments require supporting ethical dispositions is not to suggest that societies without those dispositions lack ethical theories or are necessarily unethical. It is simply to point out communities without such supporting ethical and legal systems are less likely to have well-functioning democratic systems of governance and so less likely to have democratic governance. It is interesting to note that both von Mises and Rawls who represent the right and left ends of the liberal spectrum of the twentieth century agreed that ethical dispositions are even more important for democratic politics than for markets. If elections are accepted as an appropriate means of collective decisionmaking, conclusions about the ideal breadth of suffrage and obligations to vote or not clearly vary with ethical theories, as does the proper line between community authority and individual autonomy within a given democratic regime.3 The observance of the moral law is in the ultimate interest of every individual, because everyone benefits from the preservation of social cooperation; yet it imposes on everyone a sacrifice, even though only a provisional one that is more than counterbalanced by a greater gain. To perceive this, however, requires a certain insight into the connection between things, and to conform one’s actions in accordance with this perception demands a certain 2 See Kuran (2010) for an overview of the financial methods of Moslem countries in which charging interest on loans is illegal. See Blitz and Long (1965) for a short history of usury laws and an economic analysis of their consequences. Glaeser and Scheinkman (1998) argue that moderate usury laws may serve as an indirect vehicle for social insurance. 3 That a subset of supreme values may undermine democracy is an argument made many times by Bernholz (2001, 2004). page 2 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy strength of will. [Mises, Ludwig von (1927 / 2012-01-02). Liberalism (p. 34). Ingram Distribution.] The leading political actors are guided therefore in part by what they regard as morally permissible’ and since no system of constitutional checks and balances succeeds in setting up an invisible hand that can be relied upon to guide the process to a just outcome, a public sense of justice is to some degree necessary. [John Rawls (1999) A Theory of Justice. Harvard University Press. Epub edition, page 430.] Ethical predispositions are arguably more important for systems of governance than for systems of commerce, because malfeasance in the application of the law can undermine both political and economic systems. Prudent officeholders will deliberate on the choices before them and act in a manner consistent with moderation, honesty, and temperance. Imprudent leaders will act on impulse, take needless risks, accept bribes, and be apt to adopt policies that are neither moderate nor temperate. The results of policies chosen by virtuous men thus tends to be better--at least on average--than those chosen by immoral men, other things being equal. A wise and moral man or woman can be trusted to make good choices, that is to say policies consistent with the personal ethics of their supporters.4 for the convenience of the rulemaking group. The dominant group might, for example, reduce all others in the community to slavery or serfdom. (The lives of slaves and serfs are normally both rule bound and unpleasant.) A. Ethics in Authoritarian Regimes It might seem “obvious” that authoritarian regimes operate without internalized ethical dispositions, but this is unlikely to be the case. Military organizations routinely promote virtues such as honor, discipline, toughness, and bravery through praise, esteem, medals, status, and rank. The military theory of distributive justice include such platitudes as: “to the victor go the spoils,” “power grows out of the barrel of a gun,” and “might makes right.” These are not simply statements of the facts associated with victory, but a theory of just deserts. The fruits of victory should go to the clever, strong, and brave. Chapter 6 implies that a military organization composed of persons without such internalized norms would be less effective than ones with them, and so less likely to emerge victorious in military contests. Indeed Montesquieu argued that particular ethical dispositions ground both democratic and authoritarian regimes. II. A Digression on the Role of Ethics in the Emergence of Government Insofar as the aim of an authoritarian regime is power and plunder, the rules imposed on persons outside the organization are likely to differ from those inside the ruling group. Many will conflict with both utilitarian and contractarian theories of law and governance and in this sense be unethical, although they may be consistent with military ethics and advance the goals of military organizations. What might be described as pragmatic or authoritarian governments may emerge from an organization to intimidate persons within “their” territory with threats of violence. Such groups may organize a military and use it to impose rules on others. Rules in such systems would be adopted When slavery is not possible or less profitable than more open systems, despotic groups may adopt laws that promote economic development, because such laws ultimately provides them with greater wealth and power than the alternatives (Tullock 1972). Such “stationary bandits” have what Olson (2000) terms an encompassing interest in the economic resources of 4 A model of moral voting behavior and evidence of morality-driven policy choices in the United States are developed in Congleton (2007b). See Gotwalt (2002) for evidence on the effects of religion-based ethics on voting in the United States with respect to state policies on abortion. See Fedderson et. al. (2009) for experimental evidence of ethical voting. page 3 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy B. Ethics and the Emergence of Non-Authoritarian Regimes their societies. Laws that promote economic development increase long-term expected revenues from taxation, rent extraction, and extortion. Nonetheless, one rarely observes well-functioning markets in dictatorships. This is partly because the tenure of dictators is highly uncertain.5 The uncertainties of power tends to induce the authoritarian rulers to live for today rather than plan for the future. It is also partly because the support necessary to hold on to power is often produced with laws granting special privileges to persons, families, and towns that support the central government. Moreover, a ruling group is more likely to retain power if its opponents are poor rather than well financed.6 Such rules reduce economic prosperity by reducing competition and blocking innovation from both unfavored and disfavored individuals and organizations. Of course, it is possible that a dictator could be a utilitarian—on possible version of what Plato scholars term a philosopher king—but such instances are very rare historically--so rare that they are beyond the scope of this chapter. That the commercial society emerged from more or less democratic societies (and vice versa) is a sufficient reason to focus the remainder of the chapter on the many roles that ethics play in democratic systems of government. The emergence of a formal system of laws and law enforcement does not necessarily begin with a military organization, although they are often useful. A community government may emerge informally as, for example, meetings of persons affected by problems gather to discuss and adopt rules that are informally enforced through agreement, praise, shame, and internalized ethical dispositions. Such informal rulemaking bodies may gradually become more formally organized as the groups record their decisions, adopt written rules for their decision-making procedures, and create procedures for enforcing their rulings. Decisions about new rules or interpretations of old laws may be reached via consensus or majority rule at informal council meetings or assemblies such as the ancient tings of Scandinavia or grand councils of England. Such decision making bodies may be regarded as governments when they combine law-choosing procedures and law-enforcing authority.7 Being consensus based, the rules adopted by such community governments tend to reflect the preexisting ethical dispositions of community members. Many of their laws thus simply reinforce the informal norms already internalized by most members of the community. In such cases, the law may be said to have a moral character and to be grounded in ethics, as argued by Aristotle, Locke, Bentham, and Kant among many others. Through time both the informal and formal laws would be subject to evolutionary pressures of the variety that Spencer and Hayek discuss.8 5 See Bienen and Van de Walle (1989) for evidence of high turnover among dictators. 6 See Tullock (1972) for a short exposition on this idea or Mesquita, Smith, Silverson and Morrow (2003) for a more thorough development. 7 Many early colonial towns and villages in the New England colonies of North America exhibited such foundings and transitions. A few instances are discussed in Congleton (2011b). 8 Locke and Kant suggest that even in the case in which a community is grounded in a social compact or universal law, many laws would lack a foundation in ethics. They may be adopted simply to solve problems of life in a community, such as rules for walking or driving on the right. Bentham argues that there are also ethical rules that should not be codified in law because the benefits of doing so would be smaller than the costs. In other cases, the laws may conflict with ethical theories. page 4 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy Only rules that tend to (or at least appear to) increase prospects for long term survival tend to be transmitted across the centuries.9 Such emergent governments tend to have moral legitimacy from both contractarian and utilitarian normative theories, insofar as they advance the shared interests of their residents. The contractarian theory of the state does not require a formal constitutional convention and unanimous vote, but rather the assent of the governed to the core procedures and constraints of government. Insofar as a government advances shared interests, such an assent may be presumed. Emergent states can also be consistent with normative theories that stress voluntary relationships, as with many natural rights doctrines.10 Indeed, Locke’s political theories were informed by the experiences of the North American English colonists. C. Ethics and Governance in the Long Run After a government is established, a variety of considerations determine its durability and tendency to evolve in particular directions. In other work, I have emphasized that marginal constitutional gains to trade are commonplace, and that most governments therefore are gradually reformed by those with the authority to do so. Formal and informal reforms are adopted when mutual advantages from minor reallocations of authority emerge as circumstances, organizational goals, and the persons holding positions of authority change. Amendment procedures also tend to combine written and unwritten aspects, which determine how legitimate reforms can be adopted. laws and adopt new laws, and constraints on their policy making authority. Many of these tend to align the interests of office holders with the laws that brought them to office. The laws that did so are likely to be considered good or just in the minds of those rising to high office. In addition to procedures that determine who holds what offices, however, most constitutions define at least in a loose way the domain of authority associated with specific offices. In most democracies, they also require regular elections and include rules against censorship, against the taking of private property without compensation, assurances that particular services will be provided, and so on. The implementing laws for such restrictions are often complex, although they can often be summarized with a few sentences or paragraphs. That ethical dispositions can substitute for formal rules has been mentioned several times in previous chapters. The same logic applies to constitutional governance. Indeed, it can be argued that ruleful governance is especially dependent on the internalized norms and ethical dispositions of persons with authority. As the Latin expression, Quis custodiet ipsos custodes? implies, constitutional laws are unlikely to be directly policed even in those rare cases in which a supreme court exists with authority to do so. Constitutional law is most likely to be faithfully followed if those most persons directly subject to it have internalized supportive ethical dispositions. This is most likely when the selection process tends to favor persons with particular norms, when those norms are reinforced by those in authority, and when the constitution is consistent with the ethos of the community of interest.11 Written constitutions describe the procedures used to select persons for government office, the procedures that those officials use to refine existing 9 The multiplicity of ethical theories and institutions around the world suggest that a broad range of rules can advance a community’s survival prospects. That same evidence suggests that only a relatively small subset of those formal and informal rules are supportive of democratic governance or commercial societies. 10 For example, Nozick (1974, ch.5) discusses how a centralized enforcement authority might emerge from a society that initially used only informal procedures for self defense, rather than through the imposition of laws by a dominate military organization. 11 For a relatively detailed assessment of governmental institutions from contractarian and utilitarian perspectives, see Buchanan and Tullock (1962). Congleton (2011) page 5 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy Changes in norms can thus induce changes in constitutional law. For example, the decline of royal power in most Western European countries during the late nineteenth century was at least as much a consequence of shifting norms as of formal reforms of their written constitutions. For example, until just a few years ago, all laws in Norway were officially proclamations of the king, although the king had long internalized the unwritten rule that he would proclaim only what the Norwegian legislature “recommended” to him. Unwritten rules are arguably more important than the written ones, although both clearly matter. A written constitution can be ignored and elections canceled by rulers who lack internalized dispositions supportive of democracy and constitutional governance. This has, of course, been demonstrated numerous times in the past century in Europe, Africa, and South America.12 Among the civic virtues for legislators are duties to create only laws that advance the general welfare, to adopt rules that apply to all, to follow the laws adopted, and to conduct regular and honest elections. As in the case of other areas of ethics, these unwritten laws are rarely enforced by the courts, but are reinforced through electoral pressures, praise and shame, and internalized supporting ethical dispositions. All this is not to say that written constitutions are unimportant, but it is to say that internalized ethical dispositions that support those documents are also important. III. Ethics and the Feasibility of Democratic Governance Many contemporary theories of democracy assume that governments grounded in majority rule are always feasible and the results always desirable, or at least superior to those of authoritarian regimes. There are several precondition for such conclusions; however, several of which are more likely to be satisfied when particular ethical or normative dispositions are internalized by voters and their representatives. Two fundamental problems are reviewed in this section: the cycling problem and the redistributive poverty trap. The early public choice literature showed that majority decision making is not always consistent, which reduces the stability of democratic regimes. There is also the risk that when choices are made, the prosperity of a community may be undermined by redistributive polices that eliminate incentives to work and save. A. Ethical Dispositions and Majority Cycles To illustrate why widely shared norms may be a precondition for democracy, imagine a village located in a territory where roving bandits exist. The community decides that a defensive wall would solve problems associated with such raiders. Suppose that the wall will cost 12 lira. Now consider efforts to divide the cost of the wall among three groups, shepherds, masons, and merchants. One proposal for financing the wall would be to simply divide up the costs equally among the three groups. Such an apportionment may be plausibly justified by the common interests advanced by the wall. The distribution of the tax burden can be written as (Tshepherd, Tmason, Tmerchant) which in this case is (4, 4, 4). A second proposal for funding the wall's construction might be based on comparative advantage. Perhaps, the wall should be provided by those best able to provide the needed services, which in this case would be those already skilled at wall construction. Some might argue that "clearly" the middle class masons should be public spirited and construct the wall for the city, ( 2, 8, 2). Another proposal might be developed based on differences in the ability of the townspeople to pay for the wall. Proponents of that view might reason that the community should take account of physical or wealth differences among citizens. After all, some persons can more readily shoulder the burden than others ( 1, 4, 7). A fourth proposal might account for the fact that the shepherds could benefit from learning the craft of masonry, and, moreover, have more free time available for undertaking the required work. The shepherds thus have suggests that the fine grained nature of constitutions allows a variety of “constitutional gains to trade” to exist, which allows constitutions to be revised through time both formally and informally. 12 See Gordon (2009) for an overview of the role of civil culture (civil ethics) in constitutional governance and the durability of political institutions. page 6 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy the most to gain and the least to lose by undertaking most of the work. Indeed, it could be claimed that the merchants were already carrying the burden of expanding the town's cathedral ( 6, 5, 1). Since all four tax systems are sufficient to finance the public good of interest here, any will serve. Note, that majority rule cannot chose among them. There is a majoritarian cycle. The first proposal loses to the second, the second by a vote of two to one. The second similarly loses to the third, the third to the fourth, and the fourth to the first. Thus, no defensive wall may actually emerge from democratic deliberations. As a consequence, the town will continued to be ravaged by the roving bandits or may be annexed by one of the neighboring dictatorships. If only one tax system is supported by a community’s dominant normative theory, the others would be rejected because they yield burdens that are “improper” or “unfair.” In effect the tax shares of other divisions are reinforced by a guilt or shame tax, that more than offset the lower tax payments associated with a less ethical divisions of tax burdens. For at least one of the two groups that benefit from such immoral or unfair proposals, the cost of violating their internalized norms must be greater than their material benefits. In cases in which community norms do not lead directly to particular policy outcomes, norms may limit the domain of policy alternatives in a manner that helps assure stability. For example, a consensus that taxes should be based on ability to pay limits tax systems to a relatively small subset of those which can fund the desired services, although it does not imply a unique distribution of tax burdens.13 Similarly, one could imagine a customary method of finance existing, and deference to custom can also reduce cycling problems. Cycles may also be curtailed by procedural norms. For example, it may be widely regarded as improper, unfair, or 13 14 unsportsmanlike to reintroduce tax schemes that have already been rejected or to use other than whole numbers in one’s proposals, deliberations might end with the fourth proposal.14 In this manner, shared norms can provide a super-constitutional foundation for decisive majoritarian decision making. They can do so at both the constitutional and day-to-day levels of democratic politics. Such norms may subsequently be formalized as constitutional law. B. The Median Voter, Redistribution, and the Poverty Trap The diversity in the faculties of men, from which the rights of property originate, is not less an insuperable obstacle to a uniformity of interests. The protection of these faculties is the first object of government. From the protection of different and unequal faculties of acquiring property, the possession of different degrees and kinds of property immediately results; and from the influence of these on the sentiments and views of the respective proprietors, ensues a division of the society into different interests and parties. [Hamilton, Alexander; Jay, John; Madison, James (1980 / 1787/2011-06-09). The Federalist Papers (Annotated) (Kindle Locations 1014-1020). ] Both utilitarian and contractarian logic support some redistribution of income by governments; although in each case the extent to which a democratic government should be given the authority to do so depends on the expected results. Redistribution, per se, is not a good. It should either increase aggregate utility or decrease support for the post-constitutional society. Usher (1981) demonstrates that tax systems that preserve the pretax rank order of income tend to be more stable under majority rule than those which do not. This cycle is partly contrived for purposes of illustration. However, such cycles are always associated with “dividing a pie” among pragmatists under majority rule. If each voter wants a larger slice of the pie (or smaller part of the tax burden to pay for it), there is always another division of the pie that can achieve it and which is supported by a majority--albeit not simultaneously for all. The four divisions of tax burden used characterize only one of the infinity of possible cycles. page 7 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy There are several potential practical problems with majoritarian redistribution. First, there is the cycling problem noted above. An unconstrained redistributional authority tends to generate endless cycles. Either no choices may emerge or a series of radically different patterns of redistribution, rich to poor, poor to rich, middle to poor and rich, etc. Second, if one constrains redistributional policies to particular tax and transfer instruments or assumes that ethical considerations limit the domain of “acceptable” redistribution so that the cycling problem is avoided, too much or too little redistribution may occur. Problems with noncyclic redistributive choices can be illustrated with a few equations and a diagram.15 Suppose that a demogrant program is considered. A demogrant program is financed with a uniform tax on everyone’s income of t percent and the proceeds are used to provide equal lump sum payment to each person in society. Each voter would have after-demogrant income of Xi = (1-t)Yi + G, where Yi is voter I’s pretax income, t is the tax rate, and G is the demogrant. Since G is paid for through taxes, NG = tYi which after dividing both sides by N implies that G = tYA , where YA is average income. If individuals act as pragmatic income maximizers, they will favor the tax that sets their marginal benefits from the demogrant equal to their marginal tax cost. However, this equality, perhaps surprisingly, may never occur. Figure 11.1 illustrates a median voter’s net benefit maximizing choice under two scenarios. In the first, taxes do not affect work effort or income in which case the marginal benefit from the tax is simply tYA and its marginal cost is simply Yi. If a voter has below average income, Yi < YA, the optimal tax is 100%. In that case, the marginal benefit from the demogrant exceeds the marginal cost of the tax over the full 0-100% range. If a voter has above average income, the reverse holds, and his or her optimal tax is 0%. If the median voter has below average income, as is 15 16 usually the case, the tax chosen will 100% and the demogrant will cause every voter’s income to be the average of the community.16 In the second case, work, saving, and investment are all affected by returns from those activities, thus a tax and redistribute system tends to reduce effort and average income. This incentive effect tends to change the median voter’s ideal tax rate. The marginal benefits of higher taxes are lower because it reduces work effort and income levels. Marginal benefits are now MB=YA+tYAt withYAt < 0. The marginal cost is now, MC = -Yi +(1+t)Yit. which is higher than before, because the voter will work less him or her self and so have lower pretax income. Figure 11.1 The Transfer Poverty Trap MB=YA MB=YA + tYAt i MC = Yi + (1-t) Y t MC = Yi T* 100 Tax Rates Given the incentive effect of very high taxes, the median voter’s preferred tax is likely to be less than a hundred percent even if they have This demogrant program is a slightly simplified version of that used in Meltzer and Richards (1981). The analysis assumes that the information problems confronted by voters are solved through aggregation. The Condorcet Jury Theorem implies that if a sufficient number of voters are diligent policy analysts and gather enough information to cast reasonably intelligent votes (e.g. ones that are likely to advance their pragmatic and moral interests), competitive electoral outcomes provide unbiased estimates of the policies that most advance the interests of the median voter (Congleton, 2007a). page 8 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy below average income. However, the poorer the median voter is relative to average income, the higher taxes tend to be, and there are cases in which the median voter will still prefer a hundred percent tax rate. When taxes will be high, work effort will be low, and average income will also be low. As taxes approach 100%, personal income levels may approach subsistence levels and commerce declines to a pittance. Consequently, demogrants also fall to subsistence levels. (A somewhat more general analysis of such a tax system is undertaken in the appendix.) One possible solution to this poverty trap is a series of constitutional constraints on taxation similar to those analyzed by Brennan and Buchanan (1980). By restricting tax rates and the tax base, such constitutional constraints reduce the problem by narrowing the tax base available for transfer programs and limiting tax rates. However, there are few if any historical examples of such constraints beyond the “takings” clauses of most liberal constitutions. inappropriate types of taxation or transfers. The greater the guilt or loss of self esteem is at the margin, the lower the optimal tax is for the median voter, now represented as T**, with T**<T* < 100. Such norms affect the size and scope of markets indirectly through effects on government policies, rather through direct effects on market output. Given such norms, tax and transfer programs may be ruled out entirely, or only worse case outcomes addressed through social insurance programs rather than extensive tax and transfer programs. For example, government income support programs may be targeted at persons experiencing bad luck (unemployment or ill health), rather than below average income. 17 Figure 11.2 Escaping the Transfer Poverty Trap What appears to be more common in democracies with extensive commercial economies are internalized tax and fairness norms that reduce the domain of redistribution. For example, it may be widely believed that market rewards reflect just deserts, that transfers undermine the virtue of recipients, or that private property is sacred and tax and transfer programs tantamount to theft. As one violates such internalized norms by increasing the scope for redistribution, there is a virtue or guilt premium that must be borne. Excessive tax and transfer systems may also be reigned in through internalized utilitarian or contractarian norms. If the median voter has internalized such norms, less redistribution will be tolerated, taxes tend to be lower, and economic output higher. Figure 11.2 illustrates the effects of such internalized norms on the above demogrant program. The norms internalized by moderate voters increase their personal marginal costs for tax and transfer programs by amount v(t), which represents the guilt or loss of self esteem associated with 17 i MC = Yi + (1-t) Y t + v(t) MB=YA A MB=Y + tY A t i i MC = Y + (1-t) Y t MC = Yi T** T* 100 Tax Rates Brennan and Lomaski (1997) argue that voters tend to vote expressively, which implies that their moral theories will tend to have greater weight in the voting booth than in ordinary life. Although they are most interested in cases in which problems emerge from such voting behavior, insofar as market supporting ethical theories are applied, the results will be policies that are more supportive of markets than self interest alone would have generated. page 9 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy IV. The Median Voter and More Modest Democratic Failures After the cycling and poverty traps are overcome, democracies may operate tolerably well, indeed far better than their authoritarian alternatives. However, this is not to say that majority rule works perfectly from the vantage point of ethical theories that use indices other than majoritarian ones to assess the merits of policy choices. For example, even a well-functioning democracy is unlikely to adopt or implement the policies recommended by welfare economics. To see this recall that “middle of the road” voters tend to determine policy choices under majority rule according to the median voter theorem. Consider the policy preferences of a pragmatic voter over public service levels. Each favors the service level that maximizes his or her net benefits given the cost sharing rule. Because of differences in their marginal benefits from the service, their ideal points differ. Differences in marginal benefits may reflect differences in income, tastes, health, or time available for leisure. Figure 11.3 illustrates the ideal service levels of three different persons, Anthony, Duncan, and Gordon who share the costs of some public good or service. These three ideal points can be used to illustrate the process of voting among net-benefit maximizing persons. Voters with linear marginal benefit and marginal cost curves act as spatial voters, that is to say they will vote for the alternative that is closest to their own ideal point. As drawn, Anthony’s ideal point is the highest of the three (A*), followed by Duncan’s (D*). Gordon prefers 0 over the other possibilities under the assumed equal cost-sharing arrangement. Note that in pair-wise elections, D* can defeat any other alternative, because Duncan is the median voter, the voter whose ideal point is the median of the distribution of ideal points. Anthony and Duncan will vote 18 for D* over any service level below D* and Gordon and Duncan will voter for D* over any service level greater than D*. If D* is on the ballot, it will be the outcome. The same logic can be extended to any odd number of spatial voters in a one-dimensional choice setting. The welfare economics used in the previous chapter to evaluate market Figure 11.3 Selection of a Public Service Level via Majority Rule $/Q MC = SMC MB-A SMB MB-D MC/3 MB-G G* Q**D* A* Q outcome can also be used to evaluate median voter outcomes. If the public service of interest is a pure public good, the social marginal benefit (SMB) curve is the vertical sum of the individual marginal benefit curves. If the marginal production cost curve (MC) includes all costs, then it is the social marginal cost curve. Together these assumptions imply that social net benefits are maximized at Q**, which in this case is a bit less than the median voter favors.18 If public production generated negative externalities, that the social marginal cost curve would be higher than that curve, and so the optimal level of the public service would be lower. The early tests of nuclear weapons, for example, left large tracts of radioactive land and generated significant fallout. Military aggression imposes costs on persons living in the area under dispute. Highway, metro, and office construction generates noise and congestion. We ignore such nontrivial externalities here to focus on decisions comparable to those analyzed in chapter 10. page 10 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy Note that majority rule may be said to have “failed” in the same sense that the private provision of public services did. Majority rule fails to maximize aggregate utility or net benefits. Nonetheless, in this case, the result is arguably an improvement over the former. More social net benefits are realized at the median voter’s choice than in the private choice. Other ethical theories can also be used to judge the outcomes of majoritarian decision making. For example, from the point of view of private ethics, some might argue that the effect of this policy on Gordon is unethical. A natural right-based theory might note that the taking of revenues from Gordon for use in this project without his consent, resembles theft. Contractarians might insist that if coercion is wrong among private parties it is also wrong for governments. Unanimous decisionmaking, when possible, is superior to majority rule.19 In this case, a consensus about service levels can be obtained by changing the cost sharing rule. A Lindahl tax, for example, tends to generate unanimous support for the social net-benefit maximizing service level.20 V. Agency Problems: Privileges, Interest Groups, and Rent Seeking Problems associated with democracy are not exclusively those associated with majority rule itself. In large democratic polities, considerable authority is delegated to elected representatives and appointed bureaucrats. As in any large organization there are a variety of agency problems that have to be overcome if large governmental organizations are to be effective mechanisms for advancing the interest of the residents in the territories governed. These problems are arguably more severe for governments than for economic organizations because the productivity of government employees and agencies is more difficult to assess. There is rarely a balance sheet that can be used to assess productivity in the same manner that money profits allow for economic organizations.21 Overcoming the agency problems of governmental organizations are thus arguably even more dependent on the internalized ethical dispositions of their employees than are solutions in the private sector. If an agency is well managed, staffed by hardworking and trustworthy persons, and advances shared citizen interests “government” can be trusted to adopt and implement good rules and regulations. If not, it cannot be. A. Rent Seeking and Rent Seeking Losses Among the most serious agency problems are ones associated with the rent seeking activities of narrow interest groups and factions. The right to assemble and petition government allows groups to form for all manner of political, social, and economic purposes. Organized groups attempt to affect policy indirectly through persuasive campaigns The policies favored are often narrow ones that confer benefits on their members and costs on persons outside the group in the form of higher prices, increased transactions costs, or higher taxes. Commercial groups, for example, often lobby for entry barriers of various kinds to shield their membership from competition. Examples include explicit grants of monopoly privilege, protective tariffs, regulations with grandfather clauses (which impose higher 19 James Buchanan often made this point, insisting on what he called “Wicksellian unanimity” as the proper way to choose public policy. A Lindalh tax has marginal tax rates equal to the marginal benefits of the each voter at the utilitarian ideal service level, hence each tax payer prefers Q** to other service levels in that case. Nonetheless, there may no be unanimous agreement to provide Q** over that provided with different financing. 20 Under a Lindahl tax system each person pays a tax (marginal cost share) equal to his or her marginal benefits at Q**. With these marginal cost curves, there would be complete agreement about the optimal service level, namely Q**. 21 In principle, an encompassing ethical system such as utilitarianism or cost-benefit analysis might be used, but both aggregate utility and net benefits are often difficult to measure. page 11 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy costs on new entrants), licensing, and a variety of subsidies. In many of these cases, there is competition between groups seeking to be the beneficiary of such privileges. In other cases, groups proposing and opposing a new program, tax, fee, license etc. expend resources for opposite purposes. Arye Losses from such activities have long been recognized. Models of those losses, however, were post-world war II phenomena. Analytical models of interest group activities were developed by Olson in 1965 and of the losses associated with them by Tullock in 1967. The latter came to be called rent seeking, a term coined by Anne Krueger in 1974. To an economist, a rent is an unearned income, rather than an amount paid to use a room or house. Tullock argued that resources are consumed by the process of seeking policy reforms that reduce the national dividend or social net benefits, and that those resources should be regarded as part of the deadweight loss of market restricting policies. Table 11.1 illustrates the escalating tendency of lobbying contests and the effects that competition among interest groups have on their profits from engaging in such contests. The Nash equilibrium implies relatively high lobbying efforts and relatively low profits from such contests. In evenly matched contests of the sort illustrated, each organization would benefit if each would agree to limit the extent to which resources can be invested in this process. However no other outcome is stable. Each can potentially benefit from violating such informal agreements to limit their efforts, assuming that the others adhered to it.22 Table 11.1: The Rent Seeking Contest Gordon 1 Lobbyist 10 Lobbyists 50 Lobbyists 1 lobbyist (A ,G) (6, 6) (A, G) (4,8) (A , G) (1, 10) 10 lobbyists (8, 4) (5,5) (2, 6) 50 lobbyists (10,1) (6,2) (3, 3) When economic interest groups succeed in their efforts to obtain privileges, those outside the contest are often harmed by the results through higher prices, higher taxes, or less variety--all of which tend to reduce the size and scope of commerce. Perhaps surprisingly, the “crony capitalism” that tends to emerge from rent-seeking contest tends to reduce the extent of the commercial society.23 B. Ethical Interest Groups Of courses, not all interest group activity is aimed at increasing profits. What might be called ethical interest groups advocate policies that they believe advance virtuous ends. A long series of economic and political reforms in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries were advocated by such groups. In the West, these reforms created the legal framework for commercial societies and democratic governance. Public interest lobbying may also partially counter the efforts of profit maximizing rent seekers, by undermining their arguments and pointing out the narrow interests being advanced. However, not all ethical groups have goals or use only methods that are consistent with the aims of welfare economics or utilitarian ethics. Contests between ethically motivated groups also consumer resources and do not 22 For a mathematical examination of differences between ideological and pragmatic interest groups see Congleton (1991). 23 For an accessible overview of the rent-seeking literature see Congleton and Hillman (2015). page 12 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy always benefit others outside the contest. Whether net benefits or losses are produced depends on the magnitude of the benefits produced for others and the resources consumed by the rival groups. The ethical dispositions of individuals in a community often encourage morally-based lobbying efforts. Participating in such campaigns maybe considered praiseworthy or virtuous behavior. Internalized ethical dispositions may also tend to reduce personal incentives to engage in rent seeking insofar as profiting from government privileges is considered illegitimate or immoral. Firm owners, for example, might prefer to earn their money “honestly” rather than as a consequence of a government privilege or subsidies. Such norms may also discourage politicians and bureaucrat from adopting laws that create privilege access to markets or direct subsidies. Anti-rent-seeking norms are unlikely to eliminate all rent seeking campaigns. Nonetheless, as dispositions against theft and murder reduce losses from those crimes, dispositions against rent seeking tend to reduce losses from such political activities. Another consequence of norms against rent seeking is that it is often difficult to determine whether a particular group is a rent-seeking or an ethical interest group. Moral narratives are nearly always part of the persuasive campaigns of interest groups. Pragmatic groups often find it useful (more persuasive) to argue that their preferred policies are public spirited, rather than part of their strategies for maximizing profits or power. It is a very rare group that will publicly argue that a particular policy is good simply because it increases their profits. Moreover, coalitions of ethical and pragmatic groups often lobby for the same policies. Normative arguments would not be used, of course, unless it was widely believed by interest groups that such arguments were persuasive; which is most likely when the relevant ethical dispositions are commonplace within the electorates of interest. C. Ethics, Corruption, and Agency Problems Of course, any laws adopted have to be implemented by government employees who normally have some discretion over how a policy is implemented. For example, employees in law enforcement and judicial agencies have the authority to arrest persons that appear to have violated the law, to conduct trials to determine whether or not the accused has actually done so, and to impose punishments if that is the case. By doing so, a legal system creates incentives for persons in a community to follow a law, whether they accept the legitimacy of a particular law or not. At each step in this chain the law enforcers are supposed to follow formal procedures, diligently collect evidence, and exercise good judgment. Officials within both national and local governments normally have some discretion to determine whether to arrest, prosecute, or punish individual transgressors. This discretion can be used to reduce losses associated with laws in the exceptional case. It can also be used to shield friends, families, and the powerful from the laws others must follow. The latter, as opposed to the former, undermines the principle of equal protection of the law. Corruption occurs when illegal methods are used to obtain privileged exemptions from the law, as when a a policeman, district attorney, or judge are bribed or threatened, and particular laws left unenforced. In general, the further up the chain of responsibility for creating and enforcing the law one goes, the more difficult it is to punish favoritism and corruption. This is in part because the methods of bribery and extortion employed at higher levels tend to be more round about, the trading of favors, the opening or closing of doors of opportunity, job offers and the like. The more subtle the means, the more difficult it is to write laws that block them, and the harder it is to enforce the laws adopted. It is unlikely that a pragmatic bureaucrat would enforce the laws and regulations as intended by legislators. Indeed, without internalized norms page 13 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy against taking bribes or trading regulatory favors, legislation may well be adopted with opportunities for rent-extraction and graft in mind.24 Ethical considerations, as with ideas about the good life or good society, are relevant for each level of normative analysis. The analysis to this point also implies that the ethical dispositions of persons in the community of interest partly determine the performance of both markets and political systems. VI. Ethics, Politics, and the Proper Scope of Authority for Government When particular ethical dispositions are commonplace in the communities of interest. Majority voting is less likely to cycle and voting is less likely to produce a poverty trap. The bureaucracy will more diligently and honestly implements the policies chosen. Anti-rent-seeking and equality before the law norms, tend to reduce the creation of rents and privileges that undermine both democratic politics and extensive commercial networks. Just as the regimen of the healthy is not suited to the sick, one must not try to govern a corrupt people by the same Laws as those that suit a good people. Nothing proves these maxims better than the long life of the Republic of Venice, which still retains a simulacrum of existence, solely because its laws are suited only to wicked men. [Rousseau (1997/1755) The Social Contract. p. 135] All the above implies that democratic governments are not necessarily benevolent instruments for increasing aggregate utility. There are dilemmas associated with majority rule, there are a variety of agency problems, and the median voter herself may have interests other than maximizing social welfare or aggregate utility. Clearly, the consequences of pragmatic and unethical policy makers should be accounted for when thinking about the optimal delegation of authority to a democratic regime. There are at least three levels at which citizens may evaluate their governments and proposals for reforms: (i) at the level of specific officials or policies, (ii) at the level of the typical nature of the officials and policies, and (iii) at the level of constitutional choice. Assessments at each of the three levels have implications for the others, although those at the constitutional level are arguably most important. For example, some unfortunate policies may be deemed acceptable because of conclusions reached about decision-making procedures. To favor majority rule is to accept that some policies deemed inferior or immoral by some voters will at least occasionally be adopted. 24 The remainder of this chapter suggests that the ethical dispositions of the community of interest also have implications for constitutional design. That cultural support enhances prospects for democracy has long been recognized. Montequieu (1748) argued that every type of government has a specific ethical foundation. Ostrom (1998) provides an overview of how norms can increase the feasibility and productivity of collective action. Rousseau (1755) suggests that constitutional designs are also partly determined by the ethical dispositions of a community. What is new in what follows is the use of welfare economics to analyze the extent to which authority should delegated to a democratic regime. A. A Digression on the Use of Personal Ethics for Assessing Officials, Policies, and Institutions Of course, welfare economics is not the only method for evaluating politics or political institutions. Personal ethics were used to assess both policy makers and policies. Most internalized codes of conduct allow one to assess both the virtues of one’s own behavior and also that of as noted by Smith. In this respect, all personal ethical systems are generalizable. As a consequence, personal ethics have long been used evaluate governments, officials, and policy. See McChesney (1987) for illustrations of such rent-extracting policies in the United States, a relatively well-run and honest government. page 14 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy For example, character assessment can be used to assess policy makers. The terms “noble” and “ignoble” can be used to describe either one’s family lineage or one’s character. La Court (1662) regarded the nobility of the Netherlands to be ignoble. They could not generally be trusted to pay their debts, deal courteously with women, or exercise self-discipline with respect to drinking or public policy. Inferior lords usually and without scruple take possession of their paternal estates without paying any debts; and all young and healthy lords are violently inclined to women. ... [I]ndeed two of these having either never married at all, or not until they were of a considerable age, and could not have been guilty of so many crimes if they had been engaged in marriage. respects to be able, willing and necessitated to bear an universal slavery, by granting and promising to a child the future succession of all his father’s offices; and whether the said prince William the second, who was continually conversant with foreigners, and other slavish courtiers, had any better education or conversation with men than other ordinary monarchs use to have. To grant authority to a child without knowing how he will grow up is the height of imprudence, risking both incompetent leadership and worse. [(1662) la Court, The True Interest and Political Maxims of the Republic of Holland. (p. 13).] Dutch policy makers of the mid seventeenth century took risks that a prudent man would not. As to the profusion and excess of drinking used in their court, to the great diminution of its revenues, ’tis a thing so universally practiced, especially in the Northern parts, that none of these princes ought to be so much blamed for it. By the mid nineteenth century, Bastiat was able to use commerce-supporting norms in his critique of taxation in France. But when John Q. Citizen gives a hundred sous to a Government officer, and receives nothing for them unless it be annoyances, he might as well give them to a thief. [In contrast] prince Maurice deserves to be commended for the frugality and sobriety of his family. [1662] Pieter de la Court, The True Interest and Political Maxims of the Republic of Holland.. (P. 10) Liberty Fund It is nonsense to say that the Government officer will spend these hundred sous to the great profit of national labor; the thief would do the same; and so would John Q. Citizen, if he had not been stopped on the road by the extra-legal parasite, nor by the lawful sponger. [Bastiat (1850) “That Which Is Not Seen,” The Bastiat Collection (p. 9).] Although most nobles in the Netherlands were of poor character, La Court argues that Prince Maurice was an exception. He was noteworthy because of the relative frugality of his own lifestyle, and his prudent choices in clothing and entertainment. Public policies can often be assessed in more or less the same manner. Policy choices may be considered unethical because they violate norms associated with life in a community or with virtuous conduct in general. Again, quotes from La Court serve as an illustration. [T]he governors of the United Provinces, who seemed willing to give up the liberty of their country; and in all The rhetoric of political and lobbying campaigns still draws heavily on the internalized personal ethics of voters to critique and support alternative candidates and public policies. The character and trustworthiness of potential office holder are often highlighted in the advertising campaigns and speeches of rivals for high office. Policies involving war and peace or page 15 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy environmental quality also tend to be assessed substantially by their moral appeal. B. Welfare Economics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes [I]n general terms, the practical question, where to place the limit — how to make the fitting adjustment between individual independence and social control — is a subject on which nearly everything remains to be done. All that makes existence valuable to any one, depends on the enforcement of restraints upon the actions of other people. Some rules of conduct, therefore, must be imposed, by law in the first place, and by opinion on many things which are not fit subjects for the operation of law. What these rules should be, is the principal question in human affairs. [Mill, John Stuart (1859/2013). On Liberty from the Complete Works of John Stuart Mill (Kindle Locations 39783-39787).] We now return to what Mill argued was the principle question in human affairs, the extent to which authority should be delegated to a community government. For both utilitarians and contractarians, the proper domain of democratic authority varies with the expected outcome. In cases in which outcomes are likely to be improved via majority rule (aggregate utility increased), both utilitarians and contractarians will prefer democratic interventions. In other cases, authority to intervene should be withheld. There is thus no unique answer to the optimal delegation issue from a utilitarian perspective, although the factors to be considered are clear.25 A perfect utilitarian government with no administrative costs--the model of government often used in public economics--should be given the authority to solve any problem where the potential aggregate benefits are greater than the costs of the solution. If administrative overhead adds an 25 additional 10 percent to the costs of government action, then only problems where the benefits are more than 110% of the costs should be delegated to government. If in addition to administrative costs, agency problems and rent seeking losses further increase average costs, then the ideal delegation of authority shrinks further. For example, if administrative, agency, and rent-seeking costs approximately double the cost of public policies relative to an idealized utilitarian planner, then only problems were the potential benefits are at least twice the costs should be authorized. The greater the expected costs of government action--whether simple overhead, corruption, or voter biases (as with fiscal illusion)--the smaller the ideal scope of government is from a utilitarian perspective. From a contractarian point of view, the issue are similar, although the argument differs. Given a democratic government and legal system that supports a commercial society, the line between the authority of government and the private sector is chosen to obtain unanimous consent from the individuals in the community of interest, given considerable uncertainty about the policies that will be adopted and their place in the society that emerges. If voter are risk neutral, the government will be delegated responsibilities for goods, services, regulations in those areas in which average benefits are expected to increase. If voters are risk averse, authority will be delegated only in the policy areas in which the risk adjusted average are expected to increase. In either case, the better governmental systems are anticipated to be, the broader will be that authority. The worse, the narrower will be the ideal scope of governmental authority. Particular conclusions about the dividing line are conditional. One consideration is the strength and type of internalized ethical dispositions of fellow community members and persons likely to hold office. The more ethical and hence trustworthy one’s fellow citizens are, the greater the ideal delegation of authority to democratic governments tends to be, other things being equal. When constitutional design improves or For example, chapter 6 noted that Bentham and Spencer supported laissez faire. Mill also did, but acknowledged the possibility of externality problems. From Pigou onwards, however, utilitarians supported increasingly broad government authority to intervene in markets. page 16 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy constitutional norms evolve in a manner that tends to reduce the risk of governmental malfeasance, the ideal domain of authority tends to increase, and vice versa.26 Excellent Character of Market Outcomes Mediocre C. An Illustration: Utilitarian Choices Among PoliticalEconomy Systems Poor At the level of system choices, there is an irreducible element of uncertainty because both our information and science is far less than perfect. This uncertainty, as well as true ignorance, implies that a careful catalogue of every possible area of government authority is not possible. Instead, only some general rules or constitutional principles may be possible. Some light can be shed on such principles by focusing on a few broad categories of possible government and market failures and possible delegations. Table 11.2 illustrates some possible utilitarian conclusions about the proper domain of political authority under different assumptions about the relative performance of democratic politics and markets. Three rough categories of market and governmental performance are used and choices are limited to three political-economy systems are laissez faire (relatively little intervention in markets beyond enforcement of civil law), mixed (many interventions, but mostly for large market failures), social democracy (substantial regulatory and tax interventions and redistribution). Table 11.2: Market-Politics Tradeoffs Character of Democratic Policy Decisions Excellent Mediocre Poor Laissez Faire Laissez Faire Laissez Faire Mixed Laissez Faire Laissez Faire Social Democracy Mixed Laissez Faire The conclusions are illustrative, rather than closely reasoned. They draw on the arguments of Von Mises and Rawls, who agree that good governance is more dependent on ethical dispositions than effective markets. Thus, when ethical men and woman are equally influential in both systems, relatively less intervention is called for and laissez faire is supported. There will be fewer externalities, lower crime rates, and better quality products, and less need to intervene. In cases in which governments generally improve on market outcomes, rather than worsen them, a clear utilitarian case for more extensive government interventions exists. How much authority for intervention should be delegated in that case varies with the magnitude of the problems to be addressed and the average effectiveness of government. In cases in which market outcomes are always poor (large externalities) and government policies always excellent, very broad authority should be delegated to government. In cases, in which market outcomes are poor, but government policies are imperfect, less authority should be delegated. In cases in which policies are also poor, either because of random errors, ignorance, systematic bias, or rent seeking, a watchman state is likely to do the least damage. Analysis from a contractarian perspectives tends to reach similar conclusions. If citizens generally expect government policies to increase their own net benefits, which in most cases will be correlated with social net benefits, they will be disposed to delegate more authority to their 26 Evidence of such a tradeoff is provided in the empirical political science and political economy of trust literature. See, for example, Miller (1974) and Blanco (2013). page 17 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy community government. If significant agency problems exist or voter ignorance, governments would be delegated authority only in cases in which gains appear to be largest and most likely. These would be partly conditional on the performance of markets and the extent of externality and public goods problems. In cases in areas in few or no personal net benefits are anticipated, no delegation would take place. Redistribution would be limited to various community insurance programs that are likely to advance the interests of all subscribers. In cases in which government officials are expected to be less ethical than their counterparts in the private sector, government failures tend to be more likely and arguably more severe than market failures. Government officials may be corrupt, lazy or overbearing and markets relatively benevolent, but for government intrusions in such cases. Which of these characterizations best describe particular political-economic systems varies by time in place. Thus, no unique conclusions can be drawn about the best system or dividing line between private autonomy and public authority. Other ethical systems might well reach different conclusions about the optimal delegation of authority to intervene in markets or lifestyles. Many egalitarians, for example, would support far greater community control and far less personal autonomy in order to force equality in opportunities and outcomes, as in More’s utopia. Not all ethical systems are supportive of commerce or liberty in private lives or in society. In the abstract, it may be argued that the natural starting point is one in which “people are people” and there is little systematic difference among the employees of public and private sector employees or agencies. Insofar as consumers and voters favor ethical firms and politicians, both economic organizations and government agencies have reasons to adopt ethical rules and higher ethical employees. Nonetheless, in cases in which ethical dispositions conflict or are weakly held, the choice tends to be among imperfect systems. And, some areas of life are likely to be better served by one than the other. VII. General Conclusions about Ethics, Governance, and Commerce Given a constitutional and civil law framework, market and political competition ultimately determine the precise boundaries between private autonomy and private authority, although the result may not be ideal from either utilitarian or contractarian perspectives. Overall, it is clear that personal ethical dispositions play a role both in the performance of markets and democratic governments. Personal ethics also play a role in the assessments of political-economy systems, and through conclusions reached provide social support for particular constitutional systems and/or reforms. If government officials are generally believed to be more ethical than those in private organizations, market failures may be omnipresent and governments can be expected to remediate those problems through thoughtful and effective policies. If there is no essential difference between the ethics of persons in governmental and private organizations, both organizations will tend to exhibit similar patterns of organizational success and failure. There will be governmental externalities as well as private ones. There will be agency problems within each organizations. In such cases, governmental externalities and agency problems may generate significant problems as often as they resolve them. The analysis of the roles of ethics in this chapter and the previous ones imply only a subset of ethical dispositions tend to be supportive of democratic institutions, and only a subset of those ethical dispositions tend to support the rules and regulations that allow a commercial society to flourish. Insofar as a community’s prevailing ethos are more durable and less portable than technology or goods and services, it may be said that the variation in the internalized norms among communities accounts for much of the variation in the effectiveness of political-economy systems. Historically, the ethics that supported open commerce also tended to supported democratic politics and vice versa. These were largely the ethics of what nineteenth century politicians and political theorists termed liberalism. They include the usual virtues of honest, prudence, diligence, the pursuit of excellence, with civil ethical theories that emphasize tolerance page 18 Market Supporting Democracy Supporting Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy and equality of opportunity or rights--what Spencer termed the equal liberties principle. Excellence is most likely when strong internalized supportive ethics inform the decisions of policy makers, businessmen, voters and consumers.27 Worse results are anticipated from what are otherwise similar legal and constitutional systems when supporting norms are less common or weaker. Policy makers may be mostly pragmatists or have internalized norms that do not support democratic governance and/or commercial enterprises. In the former case, rent-seeking rather than democratic processes or civil law are likely to determine public policies and the scope of commerce in such cases. In the latter, elections may ultimately determine policy choices. In both cases the commercial sector will be smaller and the material standard of life lower as regulations increase risks and transactions costs, and weaken pecuniary incentives for trade, production, and innovation. Market supporting ethical dispositions Democracy supporting ethical dispositions Universe of ethical dispositions Universe of all dispositions including ethical and pragmatic ones and so forth. Both democratic politics and the commercial society are supported by an overlapping set of ethical beliefs and norms. Democracy is not a prerequisite for a commercial society, nor do democracies necessarily support a commercial society. However, the correlation between relatively democratic societies and commerce is historically fairly strong. This is likely to reflect the fact that the ethos and political theories that support democratic governance also tend to support relatively open commercial systems., and vice versa. For example, an ethos that induces persons to internalize the rules and duties associated with employment in large organizations is likely to improve the performance of both economic and political organizations. Persons who respect the rules of their organizations are also likely to respect the rules of their community. Those who value the fruits of their labor will tend to regard the distribution of income generated by markets to be earned and essentially just, if not perfect. Similarly, a government staffed by persons elected in competitive open elections will tend to regard office holders to be legitimate and their policies, even when distasteful for particular individuals, to be on average as good as possible. Ethical perspectives that oppose political privileges and anti-privileges also tend to oppose economic privileges and anti-privileges, 27 See chapters 5 and 6 for a discussion of the ethical theories of protoliberals and liberals. See McCloskey (2010) for a more literary overview of what she terms bourgeoisie ethics. page 19 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy Buchanan, J. M. and G. Tullock (1962) The Calculus of Consent, Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. References Arrow, K. J. (1951) Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: Wiley. Black, D. (1948) “On the Rationale of Group Decision-Making,” Journal of Political Economy 56: 23-34. Blitz, R. C. and M. F. Long (1965) “The Economics of Usury Regulation,” Journal of Political Economy 73: 608-19. Brennan, G. and L. Lomasky (1997) Democracy and Decision: The Pure Theory of Electoral Preference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bernholz, P. (2001) “Ideocracy and Totalitarianism: A Formal Analysis Incorporating Ideology,” Public Choice 108: 31-75. Bernholz, P. (2004) “Supreme Values as the Basis for Terror,” European Journal of Political Economy 20: 317-33. Blanco, L. (2013) “The Impact of Crime and Insecurity on Trust in Democracy and Institutions,” American Economic Review 103: 284-288 Congleton, R. D. (1991) "Ideological Conviction and Persuasion in the Rent-Seeking Society," Journal of Public Economics 44: 65-86. Congleton, R. D. (2003) “Economic and Cultural Prerequisites for Democracy,” in Rational Foundations of Democratic Politics. Breton, A., Galeotti, G., Salmon, P., and Wintrobe, R. Eds. New York: Cambridge University Press pp. 44-67. Brennan, G. and Buchanan, J. M. (1980) The Power to Tax: Analytic foundations of a Fiscal Constitution. Cambridge: Cambridge Univerity Press. Bienen, H. and N. V. de Walle (1989) “Time and Power in Africa,” American Political Science Review 83: 19-34. Buchanan, J. M. and R. D. Tollison (Eds.) (1980) The Theory of Public Choice II. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Congleton, R. D. (2007a) “Informational Limits to Democratic Public Policy: The Jury Theorem, Yardstick Competition, and Ignorance,” Public Choice 132: 333-352. Congleton, R. D. (2007b) “The Moral Voter Hypothesis: Economic and Normative Aspects of Public Policy and Law within Democracies,” Journal of Public Finance and Public Choice 25: 3-30. Congleton, R. D. (2011) Perfecting Parliament: Liberalism and the Rise of Western Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Congleton, R. D. (2011b) “Why Local Governments Do Not Maximize Profits: On the Value Added by the Representative Institutions of Town and City Governance,” Public Choice 149: 187-201. Congleton, R. D. and A. L. Hillman (Eds.) (2015) Companion to the Political Economy of Rent Seeking. Cheltenham UK: Edgar Elgar. page 20 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy Mesquita, B. B. de, A. Smith, R. M. Siverson, and J. D. Morrow (2003) The Logic of Political Survival. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Fink, A. (2011) “Under What Conditions May Social Contracts Arise? Evidence from the Hanseatic League,” Constitutional Political Economy 22: 173-99. Feddersen, T.,Gailmard, S., and Sandroni, A. (2009) “Moral Bias in Large Elections: Theory and Experimental Evidence,” American Political Science Review 103: 175-192. Glaeser, E. L. and J. Scheinkman (1998) “Neither a Borrower Nor a Lender Be: An Economic Analysis of Interest Restrictions and Usury,” Journal of Law and Economics 41: 1-36. Miller, A.H (1974) “Political Issues and Trust in Government: 1964–1970,” American Political Science Review 68: 951-972. Mueller, D. C. (2003) Public Choice III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nozick, R (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books Olson, M. (1965) The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge Mass: Harvard University Press. Gotwalt, E. (2002) Moral Determinants of Rational Behavior With an Application to State Abortion Restrictions. George Mason University Dissertation. Olson, M. . (2000) Power and Prosperity: Outgrowing Communist and Capitalist Dictatorships. New York: Basic Books. Gordon, S. (2009) Controlling the State: Constitutionalism from Ancient Athens to Today. Cambridge Mass: Harvard University Press. Hunt, G. (Ed.) (1910) The Writings of James Madison: 1819-1836. New York: Putnam. Kuran, T. (2004) Islam and Mammon: The Economic Predicaments of Islamism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rawls, J. (2009) A Theory of Justice, Revised Edition. Cambridge Mass: Harvard University Press. Usher, D. (1981) The Economic Prerequisite to Democracy. New York: Columbia University Press. Tullock, G. (1972b) “The Edge of the Jungle,” in Tullock (Ed.) Explorations of the Theory of Anarchy. Blacksburg, VA: Center for Study of Public Choice. McChesney, F. (1987) “Rent Extraction and Rent Creation in the Economic Theory of Regulation,” The Journal of Legal Studies 16: 101-18. Von Mises, L. (1927/2002) Liberalism in the Classical Tradition. San Francisco CA: Foundation for Economic Education. McCloskey, D. N. (2010) The Bourgeois Virtues: Ethics for an Age of Commerce. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Meltzer, A. H. and S. F. Richards (1981) “A Rational Theory of the Size of Government,” Journal of Political Economy 89: 914-27. page 21 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy Mathematical Appendix: A Simple Model of Redistribution with and without Ethical Constraints Consider the following model of redistribution based on the Melzer and Richard assumptions. Suppose that people have identical tastes but vary by income and that a proportional tax is to be imposed and used to fund a “demogrant,” an equal grant to all persons in society. Assume initially that tastes are simply a matter of leisure (L) and material gratification (C), U = u(T-L,C) , and that people simply consume what they earn after taxes and receive from the demogrant program. This can be thought of as a lifetime pattern of consumption for simple egoists with T hours to allocate between leisure and gainful employment in the commercial society. Consumption is Ci = (1-t)wiLi+ G with G = tYA. Substituting allows utility to be written as U = u( T-Li, (1-t)wiLi+ G). For a given tax and demogrant, each voter will choose to work his or her utility maximizing number of hours, which satisfies: -UL + UC ( 1-t)wi = 0 If the second derivatives are assumed to be small relative to the first derivatives, the intuitive results can be obtained. In that case, labor increases with wage rates (L*w > 0) and decreases with income taxes (L*t < 0). One convenient special case in which this holds is that in which the utility function is separable with constant marginal utility. In that case, however, the derivatives of labor supply with respect to size of the demogrant and time to be allocated are both zero. In either case, a voter’s optimization problem with respect to taxes and demogrants can be written as maximize: U = u( T-L*, (1-t)wiL*+ tYA*). The median voter’s receives the median wage rate, wv. Her preferred tax rate satisifies: U = u( T-L*, (1-t)wiL*+ tYA*). -UL(Lt + LG YAt) + UC [( 1-t)wi (Lt + LG YAt) + YA +t(YAt+YAG ] = 0 where subscripts denote partial derivatives. If we take the case in which second derivatives are zero, this the derivatives with respect to G disappear and we are left with: The solution to which can be written as L* = l(w,t,G,T) with partial derivatives: -UL(Lt ) + UC [( 1-t)wi (Lt ) + YA + t(YAt)] = 0 L*w = [-ULC ((1-t)Li) + UC ( 1-t) + UCC( 1-t)2 wiLi] / -ULL These terms can be separated into marginal benefits and marginal costs, with L*t = [ULC wiL - UCwi - UCC( 1-t) wi2Li] / -ULL L*G = [-ULC + UCC( 1-t) wi] / -ULL < 0 MB = -UL(Lt ) +UC YA L*T = [ULL + ULC( 1-t) wi] / -ULL > 0 The last two partial derivatives can be signed using the conventional assumptions about utility functions (UL > 0, UC>0, UCL>0, ULL<0, and UCC<0). The first two are ambiguous, with these assumptiosn alone and depend upon the relative sizes of the first derivative and second derivative effects. Demogrants tend to reduce work effort and time available tends to increase it, but whether after tax wage rates increase or decrease labor varies with the relative size of the first and second derivatives. and MC = UC [( 1-t)wi (Lt ) + t(YAt)] The marginal benefits come from increased leisure and income from the demogrant, whereas the marginal costs come from reductions in income from working and through economy-wide effects on the tax base associated with similar declines in work effort by everyone in the community of interest. As noted in the geometric illustrations, there is no assurance that page 22 Ethical Foundation of Capitalism Chapter 11: Ethics and the Delegation of Authority to Democratic Regimes: Laissez Faire as a Second Best Policy an interior solution exists. The ideal tax could easily be one hundred percent if the labor responses to taxation are small. It could be zero if they are very large. In a broad range of cases, taxes may be relatively high and economic activity lower than optimal from a utilitarian perspective. In such cases, internalized tax norms or distributive norms can produce better results than self interest alone. For example, citizens may have internalized norms that approve of wage based income differences or disapprove of transfer payments except for those involving extreme need and bad luck. A completely idealistic voter would simply favor their personal tax ideal, T , without regard to self interest. A pragmatic voter would not have personal tax norms, and would simply vote for the norm that maximized his or her utility, which in this case is approximately the tax system that maximizes their personal net of tax and transfer income. N Poverty traps are, of course, very likely in this last case insofar as median income is below average income, a point neglected in the original Meltzer and Richard (1981) analysis of the equilibrium size of a transfer state. The influence of such norms can be incorporated into sufficient number of voters utility function that they are also part of the median voter’s calculation. (Not all voters need have such internalized norms for them to affect electoral outcomes.) U = u( T-L*, (1-t)wiL*+ tYA*, [tN-t]). The tax norm may be the result of a utilitarian calculation, a fairness consideration, or other norms. The median voter is not necessarily the voter with the median ethical disposition towards taxes, but remains the voter with the median ideal tax rate. In this case the optimal level of taxation satisfies: -UL(Lt + LG YAt) + UC [( 1-t)wi (Lt + LG YAt) + YA +t(YAt+YAG - YN] = 0 These terms can again be separated into marginal benefits and marginal costs, with MB = -UL(Lt ) +UC YA and MC = UC [( 1-t)wi (Lt ) + t(YAt)] - YN In this case, the tax norm raises the marginal cost of taxation which tends to reduce taxation and under the assumptions adopted above increase average income. page 23