Department of Economics MPhil/PhD Proposal Form Applicant (Student) Please enter your full correspondence details here: Details Title (Mr, Miss, Mrs) Forename Surname Telephone No. Fax No. Email Address Postal Address Applicant(s) (College Staff) Please enter full correspondence details for primary NUIG supervisor(s) who will act as supervisor(s) for the project: Details College Primary Supervisor Title Dr. Forename Ashley Surname Piggins College Supervisor 2 Telephone No. Fax No. Email Address ashley.piggins@nuigalway.ie Department/School Postal Address 1 Co-Applicants (Institution/Research Centre) Please enter full correspondence details for Institution Co-supervisors(s) who will act as cosupervisor(s) for the project:* Details Institution Supervisor 1 Institution Supervisor 2 Institution Supervisor 3 Title Forename Surname Telephone No. Fax No. Email Address Department/School Centre Postal Address Individual Rights in the Face of Population Growth: Externalities and Social Choice Project Title Where applicable some institutions such as Teagasc are involved in co-supervision Research Centre Location for Project: Galway Start Date: Finish Date: September 2011 June 2015 Is the project externally funded?: If yes please name the sponsor: TBD Breakdown of Funding Year 1 Year 2 Year 3 Fellowship Stipend* Other Project funds Total 1. PROJECT ABSTRACT (300 words max.) People often manifest their disapproval with this or that occurrence of environmental degradation with a plea that the environment be protected “for their children”. But this request seems without regard to or, at best, ignorant of the possibility that it is precisely because they are producing too many children that environmental degradation is occurring. With increased environmental degradation, and the appearance of cumulative effects of anthropogenic damage on the environment, it seems we may have exceeded an optimal world population size, akin to that identified by average utilitarianism, beyond which the externalities caused by the addition of another human being exceed the benefits that may ensue to society (Samuelson 1975; Brian Arthur and McNicoll 1977). 2 Much of the literature in population ethics seems to be concerned with the well-being of the individual being brought into existence and this is made central to the decision of whether or not to add them to a utility-unaffected population (Blackorby, Bossert and Donaldson 2005). However, little direct attention is given to the impact of a new individual on existing members of society, when it is in fact possible that, while having children is utility-increasing to parents, the addition of new individuals may be utilityreducing to other members of society. The principles do allow for the effects of externalities into the determination of whether or not to add an individual, however, there are certain cases where the incidence of externalities does not preclude an increase in the population size. The aim of this research is to render central the question of negative externalities resulting from the addition of new individuals to the population. By introducing a do-no-harm axiom as a criterion for deciding whether or not to add an additional individual, and putting into question the rights of a decisive coalition comprised of parents, the impact of new individuals on existing members of society can be given more importance. Under this premise, the research will also introduce questions of fairness when the fertility choices of parents impose consumption externalities on others, in the case, for example, of the consumption of impure public goods (non-exclusive, but rival), such as space, but also in the case of pure externalities, such as noise. Formulating a do-no-harm axiom in a variable-population model will thus capture the intuition that existing members of the population need protection from the potentially negative consequences on the rest of society of parents’ decisions to have children. The research will employ the axiomatic method in the context of variable-population social choice to prove a number of propositions to establish properties of population principles in the presence of externalities. 2. PROJECT DESCRIPTION 2.1 Title: Individual Rights in the Face of Population Growth: Externalities and Social Choice 2.2 Objectives: (100 words max.) To address the following question: Given that, in some cases, variable-population utilitarian principles allow the ranking of alternatives as superior although they are not Pareto-superior in the presence of externalities, can we produce social choices that will limit, or acceptably deal with, the addition of new individuals who would impose negative externalities on members of the existing population? 2.3 Justification (e.g. economic, gaps in existing knowledge, expected benefits) (400 words max.) In western countries, where policies aimed at increasing the birth rate and augmenting the population through immigration, for which the arguments in favour are known (pensions, social security, etc.), the question arises as to whether these policies account for the increased incidence of environmental externalities resulting from higher levels of population. This is relevant for existing individuals and their well-being, but beyond the Malthusian concern of simply feeding the world’s population. One cannot ignore the ethics related to the impact of the flourishing human species on the natural environment, which other beings require to live. Indeed, non-biodegradable waste, e.g. plastics, climate change, and 3 habitat destruction to accommodate more humans, e.g. roads, housing, factories, airports, agriculture, are life impeding to other animal species and plants (Matheny and Chan 2005; Blackorby and Donaldson 1992; Sidgwick 1966). Golosov, Jones and Tertilt (2006) present scenarios in which externalities are potentially endured by society due to fertility decisions, even though these decisions may be efficient within the family unit. In line with Harford (1998) and others (e.g. Jöst and Quaas 2006), they argue in a welfarist context that in the case where fertility choices result in additional pollution, then a tax per child is necessary to regain efficiency since Pigouvian taxes do not suffice to do so in an intertemporal setting. These same authors also claim that the perceived externalities of ‘land crowding’ do not exist since the property and rental markets internalize the cost of additional population. This last argument is remiss in that it does not account for non-exclusive goods that are rival in consumption, such as, roads, parks, parking and footpaths, especially those just wide enough to accommodate a baby stroller, or habitat that supports the existence of other species. Moreover, this point of view does not account for subsidies in the form of transfer payments and tax credits for children, when such monetary transfers would be particularly distortionary to property and rental markets since parents require additional housing space to accommodate their larger family. In addition, transfer payments earmarked for children (baby bonus, tax credits) or fee reductions in favour of families (in public transportation, museum entrance fees, e.g.) serve to further increase parents’ utilities. The funds for these transfer payments are of course obtained through levies. Those individuals without children receive no such transfer payments, although they pay taxes to support payments to parents. Thus, not only is their utility potentially reduced by externalities caused by the addition of new individuals, but it is, for the same reasons, further reduced by taxation aimed at increasing the welfare of those who have caused their reduction in utility. In a population that has reached the optimal size where the marginal net benefit of an additional individual is zero, fertilityencouraging subsidies are inefficient and those who make reproductive decisions that benefit society by not adding individuals are doubly penalized – 1) by externalities caused by further increases in population, 2) by monetary levies destined to be transferred to parents. In short, those who suffer from the externalities caused by reproducing individuals are the ones who pay to help generate the externality that is imposed upon them. More generally, since existing principles rely on the sum of utilities to compare the relative ‘goodness’ of alternatives of different population sizes, they sometimes permit the ranking of an alternative, in which externalities are present, as superior to one in which they are not. As such, it may be possible to make better population choices by imposing an axiom that ensures the respect of the minimal rights and wellbeing of someone who would be negatively affected by the addition of another individual. 4 2.4 Methodology and other details: (Please ensure that sufficient details are provided to enable the reviewers to establish: hypotheses, the relevant/appropriateness of methodologies being proposed.) (1,500 words max.) The proposed approach to address these issues is to employ the axiomatic method, based on desirable societal criteria, within the framework of variable-population social choice theory, and to explore the implications of introducing externalities within this framework. Social Choice Principles that Incorporate Externalities With the addition of new individuals, space being a limiting factor of production, production increases at a decreasing rate and average utility decreases (Razin and Sadka, 1995, Ch.5). Hence, there is an optimal population size beyond which additions to the population are utility-reducing to members of society. As such, average utilitarianism, whose value function for the addition of a new individual is average utility, precludes the advocacy of population increases as sensible beyond a certain size. However, this is not the case with classical utilitarianism, where the increase of total utility resulting from the addition of a new person leads to the repugnant conclusion (Parfit, 1984), that is, the increase in total utility, no matter how small, caused by the addition of a new individual always warrants his addition even though this eventually leads to everyone living in abject poverty. Blackorby, Bossert and Donaldson (1984, 2003, 2005) introduce Critical-level utilitarianism in an attempt to elude the repugnant conclusion by shifting the poverty threshold upward and requiring a minimum level of utility upon the addition of individuals. However, although in their introduction (2005), these authors clearly state the consequences of overpopulation: environmental degradation, increased relative scarcity of resources and low average standards of living, their population principle still allows for the addition of an individual who would impose externalities on members of the existing population in some cases. The reason for this is that they continue to compare the sum of utilities between two alternatives of different population sizes without regard to how the utilities of the individuals that contribute to the sums are affected. As a result, critical-level utilitarianism is deemed to respect the Pareto principle because when the alternative violates Pareto, that is, when someone is made worse-off without making someone else better-off, the alternative is rejected. However, critical-level utilitarianism, as well as others, can prescribe the addition of an individual when someone is made worse-off, as long as some have been made better-off in excess of the reduction in utility of others, since in that case, the alternative is neither worse nor better according to the Pareto principle. Indeed, C. Blackorby, W. Bossert, D. Donaldson and M. Fleurbaey do show that to avoid the repugnant conclusion one needs to relax the Pareto-plus axiom. Moreover, P.-A. Jouvet and G. Ponthière (2010), under the analogy of the Earth as a spaceship (Boulding 1996), propose an analysis that takes into account longevity, fertility and congestion to show that classical utilitarianism doesn’t necessarily lead to the repugnant conclusion. The contribution I propose is to impose an axiom that would enforce the respect of an individual’s rights to suffer no harm. The expected result is that this would not only preclude the addition of individuals that reduce others’ utility, but possibly also allow the avoidance of the repugnant conclusion. Y.-K. Ng (1972) introduces the possibility of modifying social welfare functions to account for externalities in The Bergson Welfare function with Externality, D.E. Campbell and J.S. Kelly (1997) discuss the conflict between Pareto and minimal liberalism in Sen’s Theorem and Externalities, and in Negative Externalities and Sen’s Liberalism Theorem (Saari and Petron 2006), a decisive agent affects minimal liberalism by his ability to 5 impose externalities on other agents, thus leading to a dysfunctional society. Using the ideas and results from these papers, in which the reasoning takes place in a fixed-population context, it would be interesting to pursue them under variable population to generate new results upon which to base the decision of whether or not to add new individuals to the population. Fairness in the Presence of Externalities Existing literature seems to be concerned with efficiency within the family unit and discussion is given around whether fairness is maintained within it. However, in addition to inefficiencies endured by society when families give rise to externalities, there is a question of whether transfer payments paid by nonchildbearing individuals to enhance the utility of child-endowed families is fair. As such, it is worth assessing whether in the presence of externalities, increases in population, whether they be policyinduced or not, lead to fair allocations according to fairness criteria (Velez 2010a&b, Moulin 2003, Shapley 1953, Foley 1967, Kolm 1972, Diamantras 1991, Thompson 2006, Thrall and Lucas 1963). For example, one could determine whether population-monotonic allocations of non-exclusive rival goods that satisfy axioms of fairness are achievable when the addition of a new individual causes externalities. If such solutions are not achievable, then it would moreover follow that direct and indirect transfer payments to parents are unfair. With recent developments in Germany where the government deciding to cut child-benefit payments has resulted in the outrage of some, it is worth asking whether the sense that childbearing should entitle one to special privileges is indeed justified by principles of efficiency and fairness. These are the questions that I will address in the thesis. References Arrow, K. J., Sen, A. K., Suzumura, K. (Eds.), 2006. Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare. Vol. 2. NorthHolland, Amsterdam. Becker, G.S., Lewis, H.G., 1973. On the interaction between the quantity and quality of children. Journal of Political Economy 81, S279-288. Bernholz, P., 1982. Externalities as necessary conditions for Cyclical Preferences. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 97, No. 4, 699-705. Blackorby, C. and Donaldson, D. 1984. Social Criteria for evaluating population change. Journal of Public Economics 25, 13-33. Blackorby, C. and Donaldson, D., 1992. Pigs and Guinea Pigs; a note on the ethics of animal exploitation. Economic Journal 102, 1345-1369. Blackorby, C., Bossert, W., Donaldson, D., 2003. The Axiomatic Approach to Population Ethics. Politics, Philosophy & Economis, vol. 2, no. 3. Blackorby, C., Bossert, W., Donaldson, D., 2005. Population Issues in Social Choice Theory, Welfare Economics, and Ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Blackorby, C., Bossert, W., Donaldson, D., Fleurbaey, M., 1998. Critical Levels and the (Reverse) Repugnant Conclusion. Journal of Economics, Vol. 67, No. 1, 1-15. 6 Brian Arthur, W. and McNicoll, G., 1977. Optimal Time Paths with Age-Dependence: A Theory of Population Policy. The Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 44, No. 1, 111-123. Broom, J., 1996. The Welfare Economics of Population. Oxford Economic Papers, Vol. 48, 177-193. Campbell, D.E., Kelly, J.S., 1997. Sen’s Theorem and Externalities. Econometrica 64, 375-86. Diamantras, D., 1991. Envy-free and efficient allocations in large public good economies. Economics Letters 36, 227-232. Foley, D., 1967. Resource allocation and the public sector. Yale Economic Essays 7, 45–98. Harford, J. D. (1998), `The Ultimate Externality', American Economic Review 88(1), 260-265. Jöst, F. And Quass, M. F., 2006. Environmental and Population Externalities. Discussion Paper Series No. 427, University of Heidelberg, Department of Economics. Jouvet, P.A. and Ponthière, G., 2010. Survival, reproduction and congestion: the spaceship problem reexamined. PSE Working Papers 2010-15, PSE (Ecole normale supérieure). Moulin, H., 2003. Fair Division and collective welfare. The MIT Press. Ng, Y.-K., 1972. The Bergson Social Welfare Function with Externality. The Economic Record, Vol. 48, No. 4, 517-26. International Union for Conservation of Nature (IUCN), 2010. About Biodiversity. http://www.iucn.org/what/tpas/biodiversity/about/ Kolm, S.-C., 1972. Justice et Equité. Editions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Paris. Matheny, G. and Chan, K. M. A., 2005. Human Diets and Animal Welfare: The Illogic of the Larder. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 18, 579-594. Räikkä, J., 2001. Coercive population policies, procreative freedom and morality. Philosophy and Geography, Vol. 4, No. 1. Razin, A. and Sadka E., 1995. Population Economics. The MIT Press. Samuelson, P.A., 1975. The optimum growth rate for population. International Economic Review 16, 531538. Shapley, L. S., 1953. A value for n-person games. In H.W. Kuhn and A.W. Tucker, editors, Contributions to the Theory of Games, volume II of Annals of Mathematics Studies 28, pages 307–317. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Sidgwick, H., 1966 (originally published in 1907), The Methods of Ethics, Dover, New York. Thomson, W., 2006. Fair allocation rules. In: Arrow, Sen, and Suzumura (2006). Thrall, R.M. and Lucas, W. F., 1963. N-person games in partition function form. Naval Research Logistics Quarterly 10, issue 1, 281-298. 7 Velez, R., 2010a. Fairness and externalities, Mimeo, Texas A&M University. (http://econweb.tamu.edu/rvelezca/files/Fairness-nad-externalities-RVelez-June-10-2010.pdf ) Velez, R., 2010a. Are incentives against economic justice, Mimeo, Texas A&M University. (http://econweb.tamu.edu/rvelezca/files/Are-incentives-against-economic-justice-RVelez.pdf ) 2.5 Workplan and Timescale: (The objective here is to clearly demonstrate that thought has been given the major components of the workplan rather than being overly prescriptive). Task Title Timescale Number 1 2 Text (500 characters) Complete NUI MPhil Development and presentation of advanced research proposal Literature review of population principles 1st contribution: Evaluation of existing population principles under a do-no-harm axiom Review of social choice literature that incorporates externalities 2nd contribution: Establish the link between literature on externalities and variable population principles Review of economic literature on rights of other species and environmental ethics 3rd contribution: Application of above results to environmental policies and animal ethics Summary of results and final conclusions, proposition for further research Number of Months 8 4 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 Any other relevant information Text (750 characters) 4 7 4 8 4 6 3 2.6 Expected outcomes: (e.g. deliverables) (400 words max.) 3.1 AFFIRMATION Signature of applicant (student): ____________________________________ Date:___________________ (Attach list of any relevant publications or reports if applicable for the applicant) Master’s thesis available on-line at: http://gillian.salerno.perso.sfr.fr/Master/SALERNO_MASTER.pdf 3.2 AFFIRMATION Signature of primary NUIG supervisor (supervisor): ____________________________________ Ashley Piggins Date: (Attach list of 5 most recent peer-reviewed scientific publications for main college applicant) 8 “Non-manipulable social welfare functions when preferences are fuzzy” (with Juan Perote-Peña), Journal of Logic and Computation (2009) 19, pp 503-515. “Evaluating opportunities when people are uncertainty averse” (with Ruvin Gekker) Economic and Social Review (2009), vol 40, pp 109-116. “Manipulating an aggregation rule under ordinally fuzzy preferences” (with Conal Duddy and Juan Perote-Peña), Social Choice and Welfare (2010), vol 34, pp 411-428. “Freedom, opportunity and uncertainty: a critical review” (with Ruvin Gekker) Homo Oeconomicus (2010), vol 27, pp 321-325. “Arrow’s theorem and max-star transitivity” (with Conal Duddy and Juan Perote-Peña), Social Choice and Welfare (2011), vol 36, pp 25-34. Signature of Institution Co-supervisor: ___________________________________________________________ (Attach list of 5 most recent peer-reviewed scientific publications for Institution Co-supervisor) 9