Presented April 2009 Dr. Rami Gabriel Psychology as human nature project Modern experimental psychology, although it is rarely explicitly acknowledged, is a human nature project – it aims to create a model of what it is to be human. Its method is piecing together empirical evidence about the abilities that every human possesses into a coherent picture of the functional structure of the human mind. Modern psychologists claim the mind is caused by, or grounded in, a biological substrate, the body and more specifically, the brain. Early evidence in favor of this approach in the last fifty years is the successful mapping of a coherent and species-wide anatomical model of the human brain. If the main characteristic all humans share is in fact the mind, then modern psychology is a human nature project because it is the study of the mindbrain. In this paper, I discuss the neural theory of human nature and some problems that this project must face up to. What kind of human nature project is the neural theory of modern psychology? We can start by delineating what kind of project it is not. The neural theory is not moralistic nor is it prescriptive, it is a description, so just like “little black box” is neither moral nor prescriptive, the neural theory of human nature only goes beyond description in two cases. It shades into a causal explanatory theory once we ask clinical questions, for example, if a human brain acquires a lesion in the temporal lobe, what effects might one encounter? An historical form of explanation is also available as the neural theory includes an evolutionary portrait of the adapted mindbrain.1 The neural theory is not totalizing, it simply describes the biological basis of the human form in terms of evolved mental capacities. This means that interactional and environmental factors remain to be studied by social scientists and ecologists.2 It also leaves room for a cultural sphere that emerges from the interaction of human beings, the study of which belongs most appropriately in the humanities as well as traditional social sciences (i.e. anthropology and sociology). The basis of psychology as a human nature project is ontological materialism and epistemological empiricism. It is only as politically involved as its institutions and researchers although the project may take on more of a political edge once it attains an undeniable level of certainty, which many think has already happened and thus its findings are already included in the court of law3 and in popular culture.4 1 Although this element of the neural theory of human nature is controversial as there are many difficulties in assessing whether a feature of the mindbrain is an adaptation or a evolutionary byproduct (see for example the Spandrels debate between Richard Dawkins and Stephen Jay Gould). 2 See the work of Richard Lewontin and other dialectical biologists. 3 Although see Curran and Gabriel (forthcoming, Journal of Consciousness Studies) on how cognitive neuroscience has been used in the court of law and some prescriptions for ameliorating how it is incorporated. 4 For example, Time magazine and New York Times frequently publish editorials or feature articles about the evolved nature of the brain, especially after a controversial paper comes out in Science, Nature, Nature and Neuroscience, or PNAS. 1 Presented April 2009 Dr. Rami Gabriel What does the project consist of? After describing the anatomy of the brain, the next step is delineating the functions, or the abilities, of the mindbrain. Within the latter task, a problem arises as to how to define what constitutes an “ability.” For example, peripheral vision is a general ability, whereas seeing a 3D hologram is a specific ability within vision. Where along this continuum of abilities should psychologists set their sights? This is referred to by some as the domain general vs. domain specific problem since it differentiates between abilities that target a specific adaptational problem and abilities that solve a range of adaptational problems. To put this into further perspective, consider; if psychologists aim to delineate a human nature, then at the level of abilities we must find a common ground across cultural and historical differences. This is a very hard and possibly irresolvable task since a sufficient explanation of human nature must take place at a level prior to “extrabiological” (i.e. cultural) factors, if this is possible. Transhistorical and transcultural “abilities” and behaviors are thus hard to demonstrate. That is why we suggest modern psychology change the level at which it aims the search for human nature from “abilities” to cellular and chemical processes that function prior to the level of conscious “abilities”. For example, although my cultural sphere is vastly different from a Japanese person who was alive in 1680, we do share the same set of brain chemicals (neurotransmitters), we are obviously different in many ways, but at the level of the genome and neural structure we are more or less the same. Jaak Panksepp, the founder of the field of Affective Neuroscience, suggests that there are a number of low-level general abilities that are shared across all humans and mammals: lust, play, fear, seeking, rage, care, and panic. These nonconscious abilities are biologically grounded in evolutionarily developed chemical neural systems. These basic processes are shared across all humans yet manifest, and configure, differently depending on cultural circumstances. It is these basic systems, rather than the specific domain general or domain specific abilities I spoke of earlier that are the most appropriate level at which to describe the neural basis of human nature. A notable element of using Panksepp’s basic affective processes as a basis for the neural theory of human nature is that we humans share these evolved processes and brain regions with all other mammals. Neural human nature can be further distinguished from the neural nature of other animals by our unique neocortical structures including the frontal lobe that seems to make possible our reflective, rational abilities. In general, the neural model of human nature has much to its favor including empirically testable claims, several viable future avenues of research, and a set of educational institutions for learning, teaching, and research. Caveats Modern psychology claims it is possible to ground human nature in neurochemistry because the latter is a biological level of reality prior to cultural factors. Like previous human nature projects – for example Sigmund Freud’s attempt to explain the structure and functioning of the human mind – there looms the problem of reification, that is, the simplification of reality into things, or concepts, that may not be real. The most obvious reifications in modern psychology are: 1) The use of the model of evolution to explain final causes, specifically, that the mind was designed for biological purposes based on what is most beneficial for survival of the organism and its genes. 2 Presented April 2009 Dr. Rami Gabriel 2) The positing of mechanical and computational processes or metaphors. 3) The religious connotations of the study of Nature qua Science in which scientists play the role of priests and Nature plays the role of God. And finally, 4) The claim that our concepts pick out natural kinds, that the human endeavor of science and rationality can carve nature at its joints. Some thinkers argue these four forms of reification endanger the validity of the neural model of human nature but there are convincing reasons why these worries are misplaced. First of all, evolution has considerable success in explaining the origins and structure of biological phenomena. Of course, to use evolutionary theory on the mind entails that the mind – that great glass temple of stars and shaky shibboleths – is entirely grounded in material phenomena. Yet, to the best of our knowledge, this seems to be correct. Also, evolution is a natural science and there are separate compelling reasons to welcome naturalism itself.5 The mechanical and computational reification is another worry but many in the field of psychology are going beyond computational models, or are expanding computational models to include a number of non-computational processes like volumetric and dynamic modeling. The true challenge for the future is to find ways to model fundamental processes that we do not have adequate metaphors to use as a basis for modeling.6 In regards to the reification of Science – Science as the new Religion - I believe that it is the job of philosophers of science to delineate exactly which questions do and do not fall under the purview of science. That is, some questions do not seem to be capable of being understood sufficiently through the scientific method, a notable example is aesthetics. If we can understand which elements of Nature and culture are appropriately understood through the scientific method and which are not, we can avoid the mistake of reifying Science, which will be seen as one among many significant paths towards knowledge. This will require that humanities scholars accept scientific findings and appropriately delineate how the cultural sphere while depending on material phenomenon is primarily constituted by emergent entities best understood through the discursive method. It will also require scientists give due weight and space to other levels of reality whose explanations and explorations are incommensurate with the scientific method. These steps are only possible through respect, experience across fields of study, and a 5 There are four sets of reasons for adopting naturalism. One is historical: it is the success of the hypothetico-deductive model and the rise of science (through thinkers such as Francis Bacon and Giordano Bruno), which led to a corresponding loss of faith in supernatural explanation. Another argument for naturalism is pragmatic, Galileo claimed that of Aristotle’s four causes (material, formal, efficient, and final), only the material and formal causes could be tested, this is similar to Newton’s reasoning such that we should proceed upon the assumption of materialism because we are able to gain traction on problems through the empirical naturalist method. Epistemologically, Hume, and Kant to some extent, argued that naturalism leads to better knowledge than supernaturalism. Ontologically, more radical claims were made for naturalism by La Mettrie, with his notion that man is a machine, and Feuerbach with his espousal of dialectical materialism. 6 For example, models that require multiple dimensions of space and time, etc, 3 Presented April 2009 Dr. Rami Gabriel great dose of humility in the face of the incredible world, this incredible society, and the incredible mind. As to the reification of rationality, once we understand the limitations of our cognitive processes, we must trust them within those bounds. Even if rationality proves to be fundamentally incapable of representing the world, we are nevertheless tied to it, and a life lived in distrust of the basic capacities of the human mind is bound to be a life of nihilism and moral decay. Furthermore, the conclusions we inevitably draw will apply to reason and the human mind regardless of the veridicality of those conclusions, so whether or not the mind can represent reality in itself, reason is all we have to interface with the world, so it will have to do, if not on the deep ontological level - which may remain a transcendent and ephemeral absolute - then on a pragmatic day-to-day level. One more issue needs to be raised concerning the downfall of past human nature projects, namely that the individuals and groups who put forth the definition of human nature must not be from solely one sector of society. Due to the injustices carried out in the name of human nature, most recently in the early twentieth century with social Darwinism, human nature projects have been, in an unspoken manner, off limits. The way to surmount this worry is that in the case of the neural theory of human nature, the empirical evidence must be beyond differences of opinion, it must be a solid actuality that cannot be mistaken or manipulated in itself, the way this can be achieved is through empirical replication and a broadening of the pool of scientists. To explain or not to explain? My final point is that although some view the debate on human nature as the old human sciences debate of can we explain ourselves, I believe the real question at this point is, do we want an explanation of ourselves? This is a question of responsibility and meaning, an ethical question. At some level, we each answer it according to what we want the truth to be. We can answer it with our hearts, with our minds, or with our loins, that is, with what we feel is right, with what seems to be logically correct, or with what we wish were true. Some deny explanation because it treads on the mystery of life, while some embrace our present historical moment. For modern psychologists, human nature will be a description of neural, chemical, and electrical circuitry. The magic that is humanity will not be explained away – just like the fresh taste of water did not change after it was revealed to be two Hydrogen atoms and one Oxygen atom. Nor will the wide range of possibilities that humans can manifest be limited by this knowledge. The explanation of human nature as a set of neural processes will simply provide us with the mechanical backdrop that under girds the value-ridden extra-biological forces we each bring to this ever so short cosmic waltz. 4