High Datives in Polish* Natalia Cichosz Abstract In this paper I will propose an analysis of dative nominals that occur in the highest sentence-initial position in a number of structures in Polish. Contrary to proposals inspired by Pylkkänen’s (2008) applicative model, I will argue that high datives in Polish should be analysed as adjuncts that select the structure that they combine with on the basis of its eventive semantics. In order to account for syntactic and semantic properties of the dative DP, I will propose that the dative should be interpreted as a participant in the event it is associated with but not in control of. This out-of-control semantics will be expressed either when the dative is identified with the subject argument of the event it is associated with or when it is affected by that event. The choice of the appropriate interpretation for a given structure will be regulated by a context sensitive rule responsible for co-indexation of the dative with the subject argument available in the structure that it combines with. In the absence of an appropriate argument in the structure, it will be proposed that the dative receives a default affectedness interpretation that allows it to be interpreted as a participant in the event. The adjunct status of the dative will be confirmed by evidence coming from binding and secondary predication data. It will be demonstrated that the analysis proposed in this paper is able to correctly predict the semantic and syntactic properties of dative nominals and structures in which they occur. Keywords: dative, Polish, out-of-control, affectedness, reflexive 1 Introduction The distinction between arguments and adjuncts has commonly been considered one of the key issues forming part of most current formal linguistic theories. Even though it is difficult to provide a definition of these notions, there are certain semantic and syntactic criteria that help to determine whether a given category should be classified as an argument or an adjunct. For instance, arguments, but not adjuncts, are expected to receive an interpretation that belongs to a limited list of semantic functions such as agents, experiencers, goals, etc. Syntactic criteria draw a distinction between arguments and adjuncts on the basis of, for example, their obligatory or optional presence in the structure, movement and extraction possibilities. As arguments are also subcategorised for by the verb and directly related to its meaning, their omission often renders the sentence ungrammatical. Adjuncts, on the other hand, are never obligatory, since they are not implied by the semantics of the predicate. As they are always optional elements of the sentence, when removed they do not create any sense of semantic incompleteness or ungrammaticality. In the present paper I will focus on a number of Polish structures particularly significant from the point of view of the above argument – adjunct distinction. I will demonstrate that the common assumption that a case-marked DP referring to an individual associated with an event should be assigned the argument status can be challenged when confronted with data coming from less widely investigated languages. 1.1 Preliminary data * I am especially grateful to Ad Neeleman for all his advice and support. Special thanks are also due to Klaus Abels for many valuable comments and discussions. UCLWPL 2012 123 The structures that provide crucial evidence in support of the above claim are illustrated below. (1) a Jankowi dobrze się tańczyło. John.Dat. well refl danced.3sg.n. ‘John danced and he experienced that as pleasurable.’ (2) b Jankowi się kichnęło. John.Dat. refl sneezed.3sg.n. ‘John (accidentally) sneezed.’ Jankowi zepsuł się samochód Pawła. John.Dat. broke down.3sg.m. refl car.Nom. Paul.Gen. ‘Paul’s car broke down and John was affected by that.’ (3) (4) a Jankowi Ania zepsuła samochód Pawła. John.Dat. Ann.Nom. broke.3sg.f. car.Acc. Paul.Gen. ‘Ann broke Paul’s car and John was affected by that.’ b Jankowi Ania wyjechała z kraju. John.Dat. Ann.Nom. left.3sg.f. from country ‘Ann left the country and John was affected by that.’ a Jankowi te teksty łatwo się tłumaczą. John.Dat. these texts.Nom. easily refl translate.3pl. ‘To John, these texts translate easily.’ b Jankowi napisały się dwie litery. John.Dat. wrote.3pl. refl two letters.Nom. ‘John accidentally wrote two letters (of the alphabet).’ In what follows, contrary to the assumptions of traditional argument structure theories that would ascribe the argument status to the dative DPs in the above sentences, I will demonstrate that even though they seem to share certain properties with arguments, dative nominals in (1) – (4) should in fact be analysed as adjuncts. In section 2, I will propose a semantic specification for the dative and discuss the interpretations that the dative can receive in various contexts as well as the mechanisms by which those interpretations can be assigned. It will be demonstrated that the proposal put forward in this paper correctly predicts the syntactic and semantic properties of dative-nominal sentences. Section 3 will discuss the syntax of dative-nominal structures and provide further arguments in favour of the adjunct status of the dative. Finally, I will refer to possible alternative analyses of non-argumental datives and demonstrate that they cannot account for the properties of the dative in Polish. In all the structures provided in (1) – (4) above, the dative requires that the sentence it combines with express an event it is associated with but not in control of. In some of these structures, the dative is identified with the performer of the action and in cases in which it is not associated with the subject argument, it is interpreted as an individual affected by a given event. There are no particular requirements with regards to the morphology of structures that can combine with the dative. However, as will be demonstrated further in the paper, the UCLWPL 2012 124 availability of the actor argument interpretation of the dative depends on the presence of the reflexive morpheme się1 in sentences that the dative precedes. In (1a) and (1b) the dative DP co-occurs with an impersonal sentence that is obligatorily composed of the neuter 3ps sg form of the verb and the morpheme się. I will refer to the dative sentences exemplified in (1) as the dative impersonal się construction. The sentence in (1a) also contains an obligatory experiencer adverb that refers to the manner in which the agent perceives the action that he is performing and not to the quality of the action itself. In both (1a) and (1b) the impersonal structure that the dative attaches to, illustrated by (5a) and (5b) below, expresses an action that is performed by an arbitrary [+human] subject.2 The adverb in (5a), similarly to its interpretation in (1a), normally refers to the manner in which the arbitrary subject perceives the action that he is performing.3 (5) a Dobrze się tańczyło. well refl danced.3sg.n. ‘One danced and they experienced their dancing as good.’ b Kichnęło się. sneezed.3sg.n. refl ‘One (accidentally) sneezed.’ This interpretation of the adverb is not possible in nominative-subject sentences. In those cases, the adverb can only refer to the quality of the action: (6) Janek dobrze tańczył. John.Nom. well danced.3sg.m. Not: ‘John danced and he experienced his dancing as good.’ As indicated earlier, the difference between the two dative impersonal się sentences in (1) lies in the obligatory presence of an experiencer adverb in one of them. In both cases, however, the dative is not in control of the event in which it participates. The nominative-subject 1 ‘Reflexive’ is the term traditionally used to refer to the morpheme się. I will use this term throughout the paper even though się has many usages some of which are not related to the notion of reflexivity. 2 Depending on the referent(s) available in the context in which the sentence is uttered, the covert arbitrary subject of the impersonal się construction may be specified for any person, number or gender (the following example has been adopted from Kibort (2004: 288)): (i) Pracowało się jako nauczyciel/ nauczycielka/ worked.3sg.n. refl as teacher.m. teacher.f. ‘One worked as a teacher.’/’People worked as teachers.’ nauczyciele/ teachers.vir. nauczycielki. teachers.non.vir. As will be illustrated further in the paper, the presence of such an arbitrary subject in the structure will be necessary for the dative in sentences such as (1a) and (1b) to receive an (involuntary) agent/experiencer interpretation. 3 Alternatively, in certain cases an experiencer adverb can express the speaker’s attitude towards the event in which he is not interpreted as (one of) the actor(s): (i) W tej firmie przyjemnie zaczyna się pracę o 10.00. in this company pleasurably start.3sg.n. refl work at 10.00 1. ‘In this company one starts work at 10.00 and I consider this pleasurable.’ 2. ‘In this company one starts work at 10.00 and they experience that as pleasurable.’ UCLWPL 2012 125 version of (1), illustrated by (7) below, is underspecified with regards to whether or not the subject is in control of the action – it is compatible with a scenario according to which John performs the action on purpose and with the one in which he does it accidentally. (7) Janek kichnął. John.Nom. sneezed.3sg.m. ‘John sneezed.’ For this reason, it seems that the use of the dative case in sentences such as (1b) is justified only if the event expressed by the predicate can in theory be controlled by the actor argument. This initial observation is confirmed by the ungrammaticality of sentences in which the dative precedes a subject experiencer verb that describes a state that cannot be controlled4: (8) * Jankowi lubi się Anię. John.Dat. likes.3sg.n. refl Ann.Acc. Intended reading: ‘John likes Ann.’ If the dative cannot be identified with the subject argument of the event described by the sentence it combines with, it has to be interpreted as affected by that event. As illustrated by (2) and (3) above, the affectedness dative can precede sentences that belong to various syntactic types. In (2) the dative attaches to the anticausative structure and in (3a) – (3b) it precedes a transitive and unergative sentence, respectively.5 The obligatory affectedness interpretation of the dative occurring in the above-mentioned sentences is due to the fact that they all contain independent grammatical subjects with which the dative cannot be identified. The availability of the affectedness interpretation for the dative will be discussed in the relevant sections of this paper. 4 There is no similar restriction on the formation of impersonal się sentences that contain subject experiencer verbs: (i) Lubi się Anię. likes.3sg.n. refl Ann.Acc. ‘One likes Ania.’ Reasons for why this restriction should hold in the case of dative sentences such as (7) will be provided further in this section. 5 An affectedness dative can combine with any type of structure illustrated in (3) which has an independent grammatical subject. In the sentence below it precedes the impersonal –no/ -to construction that contains a covert subject which has to have a human referent. However, there are reasons to believe that there are certain restrictions on possible subjects of impersonal –no/ -to sentences that do not apply in the impersonal się construction (but see Kibort (2004) for discussion). As a result, in the sentence below the dative cannot receive the involuntary agent/experiencer interpretation that was available for it in sentences in which it preceded the impersonal się construction. (i) Jankowi zepsuto samochód Pawła. John.Dat. broke.impers. car.Acc. Paul.Gen. ‘People broke Paul's car and John was affected by that.’ UCLWPL 2012 126 In the middle sentence in (4a), the dative DP is normally interpreted as the performer of the action. Similarly to the sentence in (1a), it is not in control of the manner in which it experiences that action. However, in some cases in the middle and in the impersonal się construction the dative can also be interpreted as affected by the action performed by an arbitrary human subject. I will refer to some of those contexts in section 2. The structure in (4b) is similar to (1b) in that the action happens spontaneously. However, it turns out that for a number of reasons (4b) patterns with the middle rather than with the impersonal się construction. For example, it does not contain a syntactically active agent6 and due to obligatory agreement between the verb and the logical object, it can only be used with transitive verbs. As shown by the examples in (1) – (4), the structures so far introduced in this paper are restricted to sentences that contain high datives. These dative DPs should be distinguished from other kinds of datives that are also widely used in Polish. The relevant examples include datives functioning as sole or indirect objects, beneficiary and ethical datives. They are illustrated by the sentences in (9) – (11) below, respectively: (9) Janek nie ufał swojemu John.Nom. neg trusted.3sg.m his.refl. ‘John didn’t trust his doctor.’ lekarzowi. doctor.Dat. (10) Upiekłam Jankowi ciasto. baked.1sg. John.Dat. cake.Acc. ‘I baked a cake for John.’ or ‘I baked a cake so that John does not have to do that.’ (11) Nie bądź mi znowu niemiły dla Janka! neg be.imp. I.Dat. again unkind for John ‘Don’t be unkind to John again’ + ethical dative ‘me’ Dative DPs occur also in the structure illustrated by (12) below. Even though it is not clear at the moment how they should be analysed, it is still possible to point to some of their properties that seem to demarcate them from dative nominals occurring in (1) – (4). As 6 The following sentences illustrate the contrast between the middle and the impersonal się construction with respect to the availability of a syntactically active subject in their structures. The impersonal się construction can be followed by a purpose clause (i) and modified by the adverb celowo ‘deliberately’ in (ii). This is not possible in the case of middle sentences in (iii) and (iv): (i) Tańczyło się żeby zadowolić danced.3sg.n. refl in order to please.Inf. ‘One danced in order to please the audience.’ (ii) Pracowało się powoli worked.3sg.n refl slowly ‘One worked slowly on purpose.’ publikę. audience.Acc. celowo. deliberately (iii) *Te teksty szybko się tłumaczą żeby zadowolić wydawcę. these texts.Nom. fast refl translate.3.pl in order to please.Inf. publisher *‘These texts translate fast in order to please the publisher.’ (iv) *Te bułki szybko kroją these rolls.Nom. fast cut.3pl. *‘These rolls cut fast deliberately.’ się refl celowo. deliberately UCLWPL 2012 127 shown below, the structure in (12) should be distinguished from those in (1) – (4) on the basis of its special morphological form. To be more precise, the predicate of (12) is formed of an adverb7 but it is also possible to have nouns and certain non-personal verb-like elements in this function.8 None of these featured in this role in the dative sentences in (1) – (4). (12) Jankowi było przyjemnie/ zimno/ John.Dat. was.3sg.n. pleasurably cold.adv. ‘John felt nice/ cold/ comfortable/ sad.’ wygodnie/ comfortably smutno. sadly Similarly to the above structure, also beneficiary and ethical datives demonstrate properties that differentiate them from dative DPs in (1) – (4). The distinct behaviour of ethical datives can be observed on the basis of their semantic contribution to the meaning of the structure in which they occur and some distributional properties that are clearly different from those demonstrated by the highest datives in (1) – (4). Beneficiary datives and those that function as sole/indirect objects are normally assumed to originate within the VP and the difference between them and high dative DPs is related to their distribution in focus and in the correction context. In addition, the same distinction between high and low datives can be illustrated on the basis of their interpretation in sentences modified by the adverb ponownie ‘again’ and some reconstruction for binding data. For reason of space, I will limit my discussion of evidence that differentiates between high and low datives to the data provided by the ‘again’ and the reconstruction for binding test. 1.2 High and low datives – distinction In sentences in which the dative receives the performer of the action interpretation, there is no need to assume that it does not surface in its base-generated position. As it is claimed that the dative originates so high in the structure, the constituent it combines with is expected to occupy the position either to the left or to the right of the dative. Since in Polish the performer of the action typically occupies the initial position in nominative-subject sentences, when the dative is identified with the subject argument and therefore receives the performer of the action interpretation, it will also be expected to occur sentence-initially rather than to follow the rest of the clause. This prediction has already been confirmed by the examples in (1a) and (1b). However, the question of high or low attachment is particularly relevant for affectedness datives that similarly to the lower dative in (10) are not identified with the subject argument of the event. First of all, if beneficiary datives originate in the low position, as opposed to high datives in (1) – (4), they should only be able to occupy the sentence-initial position in sentences such as (13) below as a result of movement: 7 There is some evidence that adverbs occurring in structures such as (12) should in fact be analysed as non-agreeing predicative adjectives. See, for example, Kibort (2004) and references thereof. 8 This can be illustrated by the following sentences: (i) Jankowi było John.Dat. was.3sg.n. John felt ashamed.’ wstyd. shame.m.Nom. (ii) Jankowi nie wolno John.Dat. neg be-allowed.non-personal. ‘John is not allowed to work.’ pracować. work.Inf. UCLWPL 2012 (13) 128 Marysii Janek upiekł ti Mary.Dat. John.Nom. baked.3sg.m. ‘John baked a cake for Mary.’ ciasto. cake.Acc. The test that confirms the contrast between beneficiary and affectedness datives with regards to the position in which they are generated in the structure involves modification of dative-nominal sentences by the adverb ponownie ‘again’. As the adverb can take scope over different constituents attaching in various positions, structures in which it occurs below the dative but above the subject position can provide evidence for different attachment sites of high and low datives. If the dative in (13) originates in the low position, in sentences such as (14) below it should be interpreted internally to the constituent containing the adverb. This is confirmed by the data: (14) Jankowi ponownie Ania John.Dat. again Ann.Nom. ‘Ania baked a cake for John again.’ upiekła baked.3sg.f. ciasto. cake.Acc. Namely, (14) is true only when the dative has already been interpreted before as the beneficiary of the action described by this sentence. Therefore, it cannot refer to the situation in which John would have the cake baked for him for the first time. On the contrary, the affectedness dative in the sentence below can be interpreted outside the scope of the adverb, which confirms that it can be generated in the highest position: (15) Jankowi ponownie Ania potłukła wazon jego John.Dat. again Ann.Nom. broke.3sg.f. vase.Acc. his ‘Ania broke John’s mum’s vase again and John was affected by that.’ mamy. mum.Gen. Unlike the beneficiary dative in (14), the dative DP in the above sentence can be interpreted externally to the constituent containing the adverb. For this reason, (15) can be used also when Ania broke the vase again but John was affected by that for the first time. For example, John did not know that it was Ania who originally broke the vase but as he was involved in gluing the vase together, he was affected by Ania breaking it again. The above data confirm the difference between beneficiary and affectedness datives with respect to the position in which they are generated in the structure. The same contrast should also be demonstrated by the reconstruction for binding data that involve structures in which the dative DP occurring sentence-initially contains a subject-oriented reflexive possessor swój. As beneficiary datives are assumed to originate low in the structure, in sentences in which they appear sentence-initially, they should be able to reconstruct and allow binding of the reflexive possessor by the subject. This prediction is confirmed by the grammaticality of (16): (16) [Swojej siostrze] Janek [his.refl. sister]Dat. John.Nom. ‘John baked a cake for his sister.’ upiekł baked.3sg.m. ciasto. cake.Acc UCLWPL 2012 129 On the contrary, high datives should not allow modification by the reflexive possessor. The lack of a reconstruction site for the dative combining with the middle structure is confirmed by the ungrammaticality of the following example: (17) *Swoim autorom te teksty najlepiej się [their.refl. authors]Dat. these texts.Nom. best refl Intended meaning: ‘These texts translate best to their authors.’ tłumaczą. translate.3pl As expected, the reflexive possessor in the above sentence cannot be bound by the dative.9 In this example the dative is interpreted as the subject performing the action but the same result is expected for affectedness datives. However, this is not what is demonstrated by the data. In the sentence below, the dative is affected by the actions of an independent subject but the reflexive possessor is nonetheless allowed within the dative constituent: (18) [Swojej nauczycielce] Tomek nie zdał egzaminu. [his.refl. teacher]Dat. Tom.Nom. neg passed.3sg.m. exam.Gen. ‘Tom failed his exam and his teacher was affected by that.’ The data introduced so far confirm that affectedness datives can be generated both in a high and in a low position in the structure. Such availability of two attachment sites for the dative is allowed provided that the dative does not simultaneously receive the interpretations available in those two distinct positions. The required evidence is provided by the combination of the reconstruction for binding test and the interpretation of ‘again’. Namely, the dative constituent that contains the reflexive possessor and therefore must have been generated below the subject position should not be allowed to be interpreted outside the scope of ‘again’ in sentences in which it occurs sentence-initially, such as (19) below: (19) [Swojej nauczycielce] ponownie Tomek nie zdał [his.refl. teacher]Dat. again Tom.Nom. neg passed.3sg.m. ‘Tom failed his exam again and his teacher was affected by that.’ egzaminu. exam That this prediction is right is confirmed by the choice of scenarios compatible with the above sentence. Namely, (19) can receive the interpretation paraphrased as Again, Tom failing the exam affected his teacher but it cannot refer to a scenario The teacher was affected (for the first time) by Tom again failing the exam. The unavailability of this interpretation is expected as in order to bind the reflexive, the dative has to be interpreted in the scope of the 9 (i) The same is true for the dative impersonal się construction: *Swoim dzieciom przyjemnie się tańczyło. pleasurably refl [their.refl. children]Dat. danced.3sg.n. Intended meaning:’*One=one’s children danced and they experienced that as pleasurable.’ However, in this example, even if the dative’s reconstruction to a lower position was possible, the agent argument introduced by się would have to be identified with the dative in this case referring to the agent’s children, which would create incomprehensible semantics for this structure. UCLWPL 2012 130 adverb. However, the latter interpretation is available for the dative in structures in which it is not modified by the reflexive possessor: (20) Marysi ponownie Tomek nie zdał egzaminu. Mary.Dat. again Tom.Nom. neg passed.3sg.m. exam.Gen. ‘Tom failed his exam again and Mary was affected by that.’ That means that the dative must be generated above the subject, providing evidence, just like the sentence in (15), for the high attachment site of the affectedness dative. The data provided in this section confirm that dative nominals associated with the agent subject can only be generated in the highest position in the structure (cf. 17). However, both high and low attachment sites are available for affectedness datives. There exists substantial evidence that high dative DPs should not be analysed on a par with lower datives occurring in sentences such as (10). However, due to space limitations in the present paper, I have only been able to provide arguments for the above claim based on the reconstruction for binding and the ‘again’ test. 2 Basic analysis As shown by (1) – (4), dative DPs attaching in the highest position in the structure may combine with a number of constructions that otherwise occur in the language as independent, well formed structures. The relation between the dative nominal and the sentence that it cooccurs with can in principle be expressed by the three representations provided below. 2.1 Semantic selection by the dative The representations in (21) and (22) assume monoclausal structures in which the dative either selects (21) or is selected by its sister constituent (22): (21) TP Dat TP (e) (Adv) ... się ... V The above configuration assumes that the dative directly selects its sister constituent, which is a property associated with the adjunct status. In (22), the selection process proceeds in the other direction: the dative is selected by the TP: (22) TP Dat TP (e) (Adv) ... się ... V UCLWPL 2012 131 Another possible configuration representing the relation between the dative and the cooccurring sentence can be considered a special instance of (22). Namely, in the biclausal structure in (23), the dative is also the selected element however, unlike in (22), it is not introduced directly by its sister but by an additional syntactic head that establishes the relation between the two constituents. The analysis of the dative as an element introduced by such a head makes (23) a type of applicative construction parallel to Pylkkänen’s ‘High Applicative’ in which the dative occupies the specifier position of a High Applicative Phrase (XP) and an applicative head X is responsible for the semantics assigned to it.10 (23) XP Dat X TP (e) (Adv) ... się ... V In this representation a separate projection headed by X dominates the whole structure. The head introduces a human dative DP in its specifier and includes a Tense Phrase (TP) argument as an embedded clause.11 The Tense Phrase, depending on its structure, consists of an impersonal się construction, a middle sentence, the anticausative or any other kind of predicate. In the following sections, I will present a number of arguments to support the claim that the correct relation between the dative and the constituent it precedes is represented by the structure in (21) in which the dative functions as a modifier. The argument supporting semantic selection by the dative of the clause it attaches to is based on the observation that regardless of the structure it occurs in, the dative requires that the sentence it combines with expresses an event that the dative is associated with, but not in control of. This implies that the semantics of the dative has the form in (24): (24) [[Dat]] = λxλe [PARTICIPANT (x,e) & OUT OF CONTROL (x,e)] 10 An account along these lines has been proposed by Bosse, Bruening and Yamada (2011) for structures occurring in a number of unrelated languages that allow a DP to be added to a clause with the interpretation that that DP is psychologically affected by the event described by the verb phrase. Their proposal assumes that in what they call the affected experiencer construction, the dative experiencer is introduced by a syntactic head Aff(ect) that is also responsible for its affectedness semantics. However, Bosse et al. do not discuss any structures in which the dative would be identified with the performer of the action. 11 An analysis based on the applicative model has also been proposed by Rivero, Arregui and Frąckowiak (2010) and Rivero and Arregui (2012), among others. In their proposal, the structure of Polish sentences such as (1a) consists of an applicative phrase that is headed by a silent circumstantial modal. The ApplP takes the dative as its specifier and the Tense Phrase and the adverb, both analysed as embedded clauses, are the arguments of the modal. Whilst the analysis based on the presence of the modal head is supposed to account for the syntactic and semantic properties of (1), due to the fixed position of the arguments of the modal with respect to one another, the representation proposed by Rivero et al. faces certain difficulties with respect to, for instance, the availability of interpretations that it predicts to be possible for sentences such as (1) that occur in structures involving further modification. For example, when the structure in (1) interacts with negation, it can be demonstrated that the interpretations that it receives differ from those predicted by Rivero et al.’s proposal. UCLWPL 2012 132 The above lack of control interpretation that characterises the dative occurring in (1) – (4) makes certain predictions with regards to the semantics that the dative can receive. In what follows, I will assume that depending on the structure it occurs in, the dative’s lack of control over the event can be expressed either when the dative is identified with the subject argument of that event or when it is affected by that event. In order to be interpreted as the performer of the action, the dative has to be co-indexed with the referent of the arbitrary subject argument available in the structure that it precedes. As participants in a given event must be specified, the requirement in (24) that the dative be interpreted as a participant in the event it is associated with is satisfied when, as a result of co-indexation with the arbitrary subject argument, the dative is linked to the subject thematic role. On the other hand, if no such specification is provided, I will propose that through the application of the rule in (25), participants are assigned a default affectedness interpretation.12 I will assume that this notion of affectedness is interpreted as a presupposition. (25) PARTICIPANT (x) à AFFECTED (x) Structures in which the dative cannot be identified with the external argument or an implicit semantic subject include sentences in which the reflexive marker is present but it does not mark the presence of the subject (e.g. the anticausative structure) and those that have a separate logical subject performing or involved in the action (cf. 3). In those cases, the dative receives the affectedness interpretation. Crucially, the dative can receive the affectedness interpretation also when the reflexive marker identifies the presence of the external argument or a semantic subject but they are not necessarily co-referent with the dative, as can happen in the impersonal and in the middle structure. As provided by (24), the inherent meaning of the dative is defined as ‘out-of-control’. I will claim that the requirement that the category selected by the dative must be an event and, consequently, the ungrammaticality of sentences such as (8), repeated as (26) below, in which the dative combines with states, follows from this semantic description of the dative. (26) *Jankowi lubi się Anię. John.Dat. likes.3sg.n. refl Ann.Acc. Intended reading: ‘John likes Ann.’ As out-of-control is part of the meaning assigned to subjects of subject experiencer verbs such as lubić ‘like’, I will assume that the ungrammaticality of (26) in which the subject experiencer verb is preceded by a DP also specified for the lack of control is caused by economy conditions that block the derivation of this structure. In line with proposals according to which a more costly derivation is permitted only when it produces a new interpretation13, (26) is disallowed as its interpretation is the same as that of the nominativesubject sentence in (27): both the dative and the nominative DP have no control over the state expressed by the predicate. (27) Janek lubi John.Nom. like.3sg.m ‘John likes Ann.’ 12 Anię. Ann.Acc. There are other rules of this nature that assign default interpretations to categories, which remain unspecified. See, for example, Harley and Ritter's (2002) discussion of person features. 13 See Reinhart (1995) for a discussion of phenomena affected by economy considerations. UCLWPL 2012 133 In the case of agentive predicates, on the other hand, the use of dative DPs is motivated. As the dative has no control over the action, in sentences in which it is identified with the subject, it is interpreted as an involuntary agent/experiencer. As was already demonstrated by (7), repeated as (28) below, the involuntary agent interpretation is also available for the nominative-subject equivalent of the sentence in (1b): (28) Janek kichnął. John.Nom. sneezed.3sg.m. 1.‘John sneezed (on purpose).’ 2.‘John sneezed (accidentally).’ The availability of the involuntary agent interpretation for the nominative subject of the above sentence is unexpected. Namely, as provided by the elsewhere principle, if the dative case is available to encode that a given action was performed involuntarily, the fact that the nominative DP is chosen over the dative should indicate that the agent was in control of that action. However, as shown above, this is not the case in (28) as its subject could act either on purpose or accidentally. The fact that there is no elsewhere effect in this case and that the involuntary agent interpretation is available for (28) suggests therefore that (28) and (1) are not in competition. This should not be considered surprising in the light of the proposal introduced in this paper as sentences such as (1) are assumed to have a very different structure to those represented by (28). 2.2 The arb rewriting rule As was proposed earlier, depending on the structure that the dative combines with, its out-ofcontrol interpretation can be expressed either when it is identified with the subject participant in an event or when it is affected by that event. However, both the performer of the action and the affectedness interpretation are available for the dative that co-occurs with the middle or the impersonal structure. In order to explain how these interpretations can be assigned to the dative, I will follow Williams’s (1980) proposal concerning the possibility of co-indexing PRO subjects of infinitives marked as arb with DPs occurring in the sentence. Namely, I will assume that in the impersonal się construction and in the middle structure the morpheme się is assigned an arbitrary interpretation arb and that in both structures the subject agent marked by the presence of sięarb, whether syntactically active or only implicit in the semantics, receives a generic interpretation. However, according to Williams, there are cases when it is not possible to interpret arb generically. For example, the subject of the infinitive in the following sentence has to be interpreted as John: (29) It is important to John PROarb to leave. The sentence above differs from the example in (30) below in which PRO can be controlled either by John, Mary, or by neither of them: (30) John told Mary that it would be important PROarb to leave early. In the above examples arbs have to, as in (29), or may, as in (30), be subject to a nongeneric interpretation. Williams proposes that they are rewritten as co-indexed with nominal phrases UCLWPL 2012 134 in line with two rewriting rules14 which govern the assignment of antecedents to them. According to these rules, any arb which is not rewritten is interpreted as generic or free in reference. Also, as demonstrated by (29), arb rewriting rules are not subject to c-command. In this example, the antecedent is within the PP but it is still able to provide a referent for the pronoun. Applying the above proposal to dative structures illustrated by (1) – (4), I will assume that the dative and the morpheme się in the impersonal się construction and in the middle structure will have the same referent as a result of the application of a rule rewriting sięarb as co-indexed with the dative. The rule is formulated as follows15: arb à i / DPDATi się_ (31) Subject As the arb rewriting rule is not obligatory, the reflexive morpheme will still be interpreted as referring to a generic subject16 in sentences such as (32c) or (33c) below in which it is not coindexed with the dative. Therefore, in those cases it will receive the same interpretation as in the impersonal structure in (32a) and in the middle construction in (33a) which are not preceded by the dative: (32) a Kicha sneezes.3sg.n. ‘One sneezes.’ sięarb. refl b Jankowii sięi kicha. John.Dat. refl sneezes.3sg.n. ‘John (accidentally) sneezes.’ c Jankowi sięarb kicha. 14 See Williams (1980:216-17) for details. For convenience, I will indicate that the rule identifies the dative with the morpheme się. In fact, the rule co-indexes the dative with the implicit subject available in the structure that the dative precedes whose presence is marked by się. 16 There are various factors that determine whether the dative becomes identified with the performer of the action or whether it receives the affectedness interpretation. For example, in particular in the case of verbs which describe actions typically controlled by the subject, the involuntary agent interpretation is more accessible to the dative when the verb appears in the perfective rather than in the imperfective aspect: 15 (i) Jankowii sięi zatańczyło. John.Dat. refl danced.3sg.n.perf. ‘John (accidentally) danced (once).’ (ii) ??Jankowii sięi tańczyło. John.Dat. refl danced.3sg.n.imperf. ‘John (accidentally) danced (repeatedly).’ The above contrast is expected as the sentence in (ii) indicates that the dative performed the action more than once which, in the absence of any additional information in the context, may seem pragmatically odd. On the other hand, if the dative is to be interpreted as an affectee, this interpretation seems to be more accessible if the action that affects the dative is performed repeatedly. Therefore, the affectedness interpretation in the context of (i) and (ii) would be more compatible with the imperfective aspect of the verb. UCLWPL 2012 135 John.Dat. refl sneezes.3sg.n. ‘One sneezes and John is affected by that.’ (33) a Te bułki sięarb these rolls.Nom. refl ‘These rolls cut well.’ dobrze well kroją. cut.3pl. b Jankowii te bułki John.Dat. these rolls.Nom. ‘To John, these rolls cut well.’ c Jankowi te bułki sięarb dobrze kroją. John.Dat. these rolls.Nom. refl well cut.3pl. ‘These rolls cut well (to someone else) and John is affected by that.’ sięi dobrze refl well kroją. cut.3pl. The fact that the above rule affects both the impersonal and the middle structure suggests that it applies either in the syntax – semantics interface or only in the semantics. Namely, as in the middle structure there is no syntactically active subject, in this case it is the implicit semantic agent that is provided with a specific referent by the dative. As demonstrated above, the arb rewriting rule is in operation in the context of the middle and the impersonal się construction in which it determines the interpretation assigned to the dative. However, there are also certain contexts where this rule does not apply. For example, in the impersonal passive structure the dative can only receive the affectedness interpretation which suggests that the arb rewriting rule which would identify the dative with the referent of się is not in operation and, consequently, the pronoun receives a generic interpretation: (34) a *Jankowii bywa sięi naśladowanym. John.Dat. is.3sg.n.habitual refl impersonated Intended meaning: ‘John is (regularly) impersonated.’ b Jankowi bywa sięarb naśladowanym. John.Dat. is.3sg.n.habitual refl impersonated ‘One is (regularly) impersonated and John is affected by that.’ In the grammatical examples in (32), the interpretation of się as referring to the same individual as the dative DP is licensed by its co-indexation with the dative which is the most local element in the structure by which the pronoun can be provided reference. As in the impersonal passive sentence in (34a) co-indexation is not allowed, there must be a reason why the arb rewriting rule does not apply even though the locality condition mentioned above seems to be satisfied. In line with what was said above about the arb rewriting rule assigning reference to arbitrary subjects, I will assume that co-indexation of the arb pronoun and the dative is disallowed in impersonal passive sentences because the pronoun is interpreted as linked not to the external argument but to the logical object of the passive verb. The difference between the two interpretations of się in active and passive impersonal sentences can be illustrated by the two examples below: (35) a Pobiło beat-up.3sg.n. się refl Janka John.Acc. (*przez by Tomka). Tom.Acc. UCLWPL 2012 136 Intended reading: ‘One beat John up (*by Tom).’ b Było się pobitym was.3sg.n. refl beaten-up ‘One was beaten up by Tom.’ przez Tomka. by Tom.Acc. As impersonal sentences such as (35a) contain a syntactically active subject, they cannot be followed by the by-phrase. However, the by-phrase can be used in the passive impersonal structure in (35b), which proves that się in this example is not linked to the presence of the external argument but it indicates the arbitrary reference of the logical object of the passive verb. Therefore, it is expected that in cases in which the referent of the object DP is a specific individual, się will not be available in the structure. This is confirmed by the data: (36) Janek był pobity John.Nom. was.3sg.m. beaten-up ‘John was beaten up by Tom.’ przez Tomka. by Tom As in (34) the referent of się is interpreted as the arbitrary logical object, it will not be coindexed with the dative given that the arb rewriting rule provides reference only for subject arguments of structures that combine with the dative. If this is the case, there is no need to refer to any locality conditions with regards to the DP that becomes co-indexed with the arb pronoun. The choice of one of the two interpretations available for the dative DP depends on whether or not the dative is co-referent with the performer of the action. The fact that in the passive structure only one interpretation is possible is an independent argument that supports the existence of the arb rewriting rule operating in the context of dative sentences. In addition, the difference in the acceptability of (34a) and (34b) confirms the claim put forward in this paper that the affectedness and the actor interpretation of the dative are two separate readings. If there was no real linguistic difference between those two readings, it would not be possible for one interpretation to be available in the circumstances when the other was not accepted. 2.3 Affectedness as a presupposition According to the rule in (24), when the dative receives the actor interpretation, it is not in control of the event in which it is a participant. In the affectedness scenario, the action is not performed by the dative but there is a presupposition that the dative is psychologically affected by that event. I will demonstrate that this claim is true on the basis of the Hey wait a minute test applied to one of the affectedness dative structures.17 According to the test, in response to the speaker’s utterance of Y, the hearer can reply Hey wait a minute I didn’t know X if and only if Y presupposes X. Therefore, in the context of (37a), when the hearer is informed about Paul’s actions, they can object along the lines of (37b): (37) a 17 Jankowi Paweł biega po swoim ogrodzie! The same observation is also confirmed by the results of other tests typically used to identify presuppositions. For example, the presupposition that John is affected by the event expressed by sentences such as (37a) survives when this sentence is embedded under negation but is blocked in the reported speech context. UCLWPL 2012 137 John.Dat. b Paul.Nom. runs.3sg.m. around his.refl. garden Hej, zaraz, nie wiedziałem, że Janek tym Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that John.Nom. this.Instr. Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that John was affected by that!’ się przejmuje! worries.3sg.m. On the other hand, the results of the Hey wait a minute test applied to datives which are identified with actor arguments of their events confirm that there is no need to assume that those datives are also affected: (38) a Jankowi się zakaszlało! John.Dat. refl coughed.3sg.n. ‘John (accidentally) coughed.’ b Hej, zaraz, nie wiedziałem, że #Janek tym Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that John.Nom. this.Instr. Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that #John was affected by that!’ się przejmuje! worries.3sg.m. The same results are obtained in the case of structures in which the dative is identified with the subject and experiences the action in a particular manner: (39) a Jankowi przyjemnie się tańczyło. John.Dat. pleasurably refl danced.3sg.n. ‘John danced and he experienced that as pleasurable.’ b Hej, zaraz, nie wiedziałem, że #Janek tym Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that John.Nom. this.Instr. Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that #John was affected by that!’ się przejmuje! worries.3sg.m. In that respect, the examples in (40) and (41) resemble nominative-subject sentences whose agent subjects are not presupposed to be affected by the action that they perform: (40) a Janek zakaszlał. John.Nom. coughed.3sg.m. ‘John coughed.’ b Hej, zaraz, nie wiedziałem, że #Janek tym Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that John.Nom. this.Instr. Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that #John was affected by that!’ się przejmuje! UCLWPL 2012 138 worries.3sg.m. (41) a Janek tańczył z John.Nom. danced.3sg.m. with ‘John danced with pleasure.’ przyjemnością. pleasure b Hej, zaraz, nie wiedziałem, że #Janek tym Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that John.Nom. this.Instr. Hey, wait a minute, I didn’t know that #John was affected by that!’ się przejmuje! worries.3sg.m. The above data confirm that dative performers of the action receive the out-of-control semantics but are not necessarily interpreted as affectees. Therefore, in this aspect they pattern with nominative agents that are not expected to encode affectedness as part of their semantics. The proposal described above assumes that the affectedness interpretation for the dative is only available when the dative is a participant in an event but in the structure it combines with there is no argument to which it could be linked to receive the performer of the action interpretation. It does not mean that an experiencer/involuntary agent dative cannot at the same time be affected by the event that he performs. In fact, one would be expected to be affected by a state that they experience or an action that they knowingly perform. In this case, this additional affectedness interpretation would not be necessary for the individual in question to become a participant in the event. However, if the dative is not the performer of the action, as in the examples above, it can only be linked to that action via the notion of affectedness. 2.4 Truth-conditional and non-truth-conditional meanings of dative constructions As opposed to the out-of-control semantics that is part of the inherent meaning of the dative, the affectedness interpretation is not linguistically encoded by the rule in (24). This may be one of the reasons why affectedness datives contribute both truth-conditional and non-truthconditional meaning to the interpretation of the structure in which they occur. The existence of the truth-conditional component of their meaning is confirmed by the fact that they can be questioned and negated just like any other elements of the sentence carrying a lexical meaning. For negation, this is demonstrated by the following data: (42) a Nie jest tak, że Jankowi zepsuli samochód Tomka. neg is so that John.Dat. broke.3pl. car.Acc. Tom.Gen. ‘It is not the case that John was affected by them breaking Tom’s car.’ b Pawłowi zepsuli samochód Tomka. Paul.Dat. broke.3pl car.Acc. Tom.Gen. ‘Paul was affected by them breaking Tom’s car.’ c Jankowi porysowali samochód Tomka. John.Dat. scratched.3pl. car.Acc. Tom.Gen. ‘John was affected by them scratching Tom’s car.’ UCLWPL 2012 139 As shown above, all constituents in the above examples can be negated. However, what survives negation in these sentences is the notion of affectedness itself. For example, (42a) above cannot mean that someone broke Tom’s car but that did not affect John. Similarly, even if the answer to the question below is negative, it cannot refer to the lack of affectedness on John’s part. (43) Jankowi zepsuł się samochód John.Dat. broke down.3sg.m. refl car.Nom. ‘Was John affected by Paul’s car breaking down?’ Pawła? Paul.Gen. The above examples prove that the dative’s state of being affected by the event does not affect the truth conditions of sentences in which the dative occurs. However, according to the rule in (24), the inherent meaning of the dative is ‘out-of-control’. As this meaning component is encoded in the syntax of the dative nominal, it should allow questioning and negation. The examples in (44) and (45) confirm that this is indeed the case. In (44), the answer contains a nominative instead of a dative DP which changes the involuntary action into an intentional one. The correction context in (45) also involves replacing the dative with the nominative DP to mark the agent’s control over the dancing: (44) (45) a Jankowi się zatańczyło? John.Dat. refl danced.3sg.n. ‘Did John accidentally dance?’ b Nie, Janek zatańczył. neg John.Nom. danced.3sg.m. ‘No, John danced (intentionally).’ Nie jest tak, że Jankowi się zatańczyło; neg is so that John.Dat. refl danced.3sg.n. ‘It is not the case that John danced by accident; Janek zatańczył. John.Nom danced.3sg.m. John intentionally danced.’ The data presented above provide evidence for the semantic specification of the dative proposed in (24) which requires that the dative be a participant in the event. This requirement is trivially satisfied if the dative controls się that is linked to an argument position. If this is not the case, as a result of the application of the default rule in (25), the dative can be interpreted as a participant even though it is not linked to a thematically marked argument. 3 Syntax of highest datives The analysis proposed in this paper relies on the proposal that the relation between highest datives and their sister constituents is represented by the structure in (46) in which the dative nominal functions as an adjunct which c-commands and directly selects a constituent with a particular semantic specification: UCLWPL 2012 (46) 140 TP DPDAT Adjunct TP (e) (Adv) ... się ... V The requirement that the clause selected by the dative DP describe an event as well as the dependencies within the dative itself were defined by (24), repeated as (47) below, specifying the inherent meaning of the dative: (47) [[Dat]] = λxλe [PARTICIPANT (x,e) & OUT OF CONTROL (x,e)] According to above rule, an individual (with an appropriate [+sentient] semantics) is selected by the dative marker and it receives the out-of-control interpretation, as illustrated by (48). I will assume that the dative is a functional category which does not prevent the argumental properties of the DP that it selects from percolating to the higher node. As a result, the dative DP combines both adjunct and argument properties. (48) TP DP Adjunct DP Argument TP(e) DAT The above representation makes certain predictions with regards to the status of the dative DP. The initial evidence in favour of the adjunct status of dative DPs in (1) – (4) is based on their three important properties. Namely, in all of the examples above, the dative nominal is an optional element of the structure, it makes a constant semantic contribution to the meaning of the constituent that it modifies and it seems to select its sister constituent on the basis of its semantic specification. Additional arguments in favour of (48) are provided by binding and secondary predication data.18 18 There is some evidence to suggest that mixed adjunct and argument properties of the dative are also illustrated by their weak islands extraction patterns. However, in order to claim that this is the case, it is necessary to collect more data illustrating weak islands extraction properties of dative DPs that can be interpreted both as involuntary agents/ experiencers and as affectees. UCLWPL 2012 141 3.1 Optionality and semantic selection by the dative As far as the optionality argument is concerned, the semantic or syntactic well-formedness of the above sentences does not depend on the dative DP. Therefore, in the absence of a dative nominal, in line with the semantics of the middle structure, by whoever utters the sentence in (4a), the translation task described by that sentence will be considered easy. Similarly, (1a) used without the dative will also remain grammatical. It will become an impersonal sentence referring to the action of dancing performed by an arbitrary subject who will perceive that action as pleasurable. Another difference between adjuncts and arguments concerns the fact that adjuncts are systematically optional whilst arguments can be left out from the structure only under certain conditions. As was indicated earlier, the dative is never an obligatory constituent of the structures illustrated by (1) – (4). This is a property characteristic of adjuncts. Arguments, on the other hand, can only be left over in some specific cases. For example, objects of some transitive verbs can only be omitted if the interpretation of the verb – object unit is specified in the lexicon and, as a result, its reading remains the same even when the object has been left over. This happens in the case of verbs such as smoke or drink that typically refer to smoking tobacco and drinking alcohol also when their objects are not explicitly present. Expression of a direct object is sometimes optional also in the case of some other transitive verbs, e.g. read, win, bake, etc. However, alongside such verbs there are those that never allow their objects to be omitted. In that respect, the distribution of the dative is much more regular than that of direct objects. Namely, the dative in sentences illustrated in 1 - 4 is never an obligatory element of the structure and as such it can be freely omitted without having to satisfy any semantic or syntactic requirements. Also, the examples provided in (5a) and (5b) cannot be treated as instances of (1a) and (1b) in which the dative would have been left out according to the same principles that allow the omission of pragmatically inferable argument pronouns in a number of pro-drop languages. As demonstrated by the two examples below, only (49b) is an acceptable continuation of (49a). The unacceptability of (49c) in this context confirms that this sentence is an impersonal structure referring to an action carried out by an arbitrary subject and as such it does not contain a phonologically null dative pronoun: (49) a Czego chciałeś się dowiedzieć o Janku? ‘What did you want to find out about Janek?’ b Że właśnie wyszedł? that just left.3sg.m. ‘That he has just left?’ c #Że przyjemnie się wczoraj tańczyło? that pleasurably refl. yesterday danced.3.sg.n. Intended meaning: ‘That yesterday he danced with pleasure?’ The above data confirm that datives pattern with adjuncts rather than with arguments. Just like adjuncts, they are always optional. Even though in some circumstances arguments can also be considered optional, there exist certain conditions specifying when they can be left out from the structure. There are no similar restrictions in the case of the dative. UCLWPL 2012 142 Arguments and adjuncts differ also in terms of the way in which they semantically contribute to the meaning of the sentence they occur in. Whilst arguments demonstrate a lot of variation in terms of their semantic interpretation, it has typically been assumed that adjuncts make a constant semantic contribution to the meaning of the constituent that they modify.19 Therefore, even though adjuncts belong to different groups distinguished on the basis of their meanings, a particular adjunct will always contribute to the meaning of a sentence in the same way. For example, adverbs of time will always specify the temporal frame of the modified event regardless of the other properties of the structure in which they occur. Arguments, on the other hand, will receive a different interpretation depending on the kind of syntactic head they are selected by.20 As a result, even the interpretation assigned to arguments that constantly occur in the subject or the object position in a clause will vary among agents, experiencers, themes, etc. For instance, the DPs in run a mile, knit a sweater or worry John will be interpreted in a different way even though they occupy the same position within their verbal phrases. The fact that unselected datives always receive the same interpretation regardless of the structure that they are followed by demonstrates that in this respect they also pattern with adjuncts. 3.2 Binding One of the assumptions of the traditional binding theory is that binding is only possible from an argument position. However, this claim cannot be true for pronominal binding as a pronoun can be bound by a quantificational expression occupying an A-bar position in sentences such as (50) below21: (50) Every dayi John thinks iti is the best day of his life. (50) can be accounted for if it is assumed that pronominal binding from an adjunct position should be allowed as long as it does not create weak cross-over effects. If this is the correct proposal, subject to locality conditions on binding, the dative should be able to bind pronominal elements occurring in the clause it combines with. On the other hand, anaphoric 19 A proposal trying to undermine this claim could potentially rely on the observation that the adverb ‘cleverly’ in the following examples can either describe the way in which the car was repaired (i) or it can refer to the fact that the car was repaired at all (ii), which would suggest that the meaning of the adverb changes depending on the position in which it attaches: (i) John has repaired the car cleverly. (ii) John cleverly has repaired the car. However, the above data can also be explained in the following way. One possibility is that there are two types of ‘cleverly’ and each of these has unique semantic contribution. According to the other solution, there is only one ‘cleverly’ that has the same semantic contribution but its interpretation depends on what element it combines with. Crucially, regardless of which of the two options is chosen, the adverb still makes single semantic contribution to the meaning of the constituent that it modifies and the claim that its interpretation depends on its attachment site can no longer be maintained. 20 Proposals that would like to relate those different interpretations to different syntactic structures could rely on data showing that cross-linguistically certain types of objects could occupy a different position from other objects with respect to the head that they are selected by. However, there has been no evidence available as yet to confirm that such data actually exist. 21 Example adopted from Adolfo Ausín’s abstract on Pronoun binding and the A/A-bar distinction. The 26th University of Pennsylvania Linguistics Colloquium. 2003. UCLWPL 2012 143 binding by the dative is expected to be impossible.22 These predictions are confirmed by the data. The sentences in (51) and (52) below are ungrammatical due to principle B violation but, as expected, long distance binding by the dative of a pronominal subject (53) and object (54) is possible: (51) *Każdemu chłopcui proi uderzył Pawła. [every boy]Dat. pro hit.3sg.m. Paul.Acc. Intended meaning: ‘Every boy hit Paul and they were affected by that.’ (52) *Każdemu chłopcui Paweł goi uderzył. [every boy]Dat. Paul.Nom. he.Acc. hit.3sg.m. Intended meaning: ‘Paul hit every boy and they were affected by that.’ (53) Każdej nauczycielcei Paweł oblał egzamin bo proi [every teacher]Dat. Paul.Nom. failed.3sg.m. exam.Acc. because pro ‘Every teacher was affected by Paul failing the exam because they had badly go niedobrze przygotowała. he.Acc. badly prepared.3sg.f. prepared him for it. (54) Każdej nauczycielcei Paweł oblał egzamin bo jeji [every teacher]Dat. Paul.Nom. failed.3sg.m. exam.Acc. because she.Gen. ‘Every teacher was affected by Pawel failing the exam because he didn’t listen to nie słuchał. neg listened.3sg.m. them.’ The above sentences demonstrate that even though the dative is an adjunct, it is allowed to bind pronominal elements occurring in the clause it precedes. As illustrated by (55) and (56) below, that includes binding pronominal possessors contained within the subject or the object constituent23 of the clause: 22 There are no available data to suggest that anaphoric binding from an adjunct position is allowed. The sentence in (i) that contains a reflexive pronoun is clearly ungrammatical: (i) *Every dayi John admires itselfi. 23 The grammaticality of (55) and (56) indicates that pronominal possessors in Polish are exempt from principle B effects and allow local binding. If this is the case, the fact that the pronoun cannot be locally bound by the subject in sentences such as (i) below should not be considered the result of principle B violation. Instead, as there is a subject-oriented anaphor in Polish, it is preferred over the pronoun: (i) Pawełi podał Jankowij swojąi,*j/ jego*i,j książkę. Paul.Nom. passed.3sg.m. John.Dat. his.refl. his.pron. book.Acc. ‘Paul passed his (Paul’s) book to John.’ UCLWPL 2012 (55) 144 Każdemu piekarzowii jegoi [every baker]Dat. his.pron. ‘To every baker his bread cuts well.’ (56) chleb bread.Nom. się refl dobrze kroi. well cuts.3sg.m. Każdemu piekarzowii klienci chwalą jegoi [every baker] customers.Nom. praise.3pl. his.pron. ‘Every bakerDat. is affected by customers praising his bread.’ chleb. bread.Acc. On the other hand, as anaphoric binding is only possible from an argument position, it should not be possible for reflexive anaphors or reciprocals to be bound by the dative. However, due to their subject-orientation24, reflexive anaphors cannot be used to argue that anaphoric binding by the dative is disallowed. Reciprocals, on the contrary, can be bound by nonsubject constituents and therefore they can provide evidence in favour of the argument or the adjunct status of the dative. As demonstrated by (57) below, the reciprocal expression sobie nawzajem ‘self reciprocally’ can be bound by the subject and by the object constituent but, crucially, not by the dative: (57) Obydwu nauczycielomi [Paweł i Tomek]j przedstawili [both teachers]Dat. [Paul and Tom]Nom. introduced.3pl.vir. ‘Both teachers were affected by Paul and Tom introducing the girls to dziewczynyk girls.Acc. each other.’ sobie*i,j,k nawzajem. self.Dat. reciprocally As was demonstrated above by sentences such as (51) and (52) that give rise to principle B effects, the dative must belong to the binding domain of the clause that it precedes. If this is the case, the fact that binding of the reciprocal expression by the dative in (57) above is not available can only be accounted for if it is assumed that the dative occupies an A-bar position from which anaphoric binding is not allowed. The above structures confirm that the dative can bind pronominal but not anaphoric elements occurring in the clause that it combines with. This observation is also true in cases when the dative precedes the impersonal structure represented by (58) below in which x stands for an anaphoric or pronominal object or possessor: 24 (i) The two sentences below demonstrate that the reflexive sobie ‘self’ can only be bound by the subject: Janeki kazał Tomkowij kupić sobiei,j samochód. John.Nom. told.3sg.m. Tom.Dat. buy.Inf. self.Dat. car.Acc. ‘John told Tom to buy a car for himself.’ (ii) Janeki obiecał Tomkowij kupić sobiei*j samochód. John.Nom. promised.3sg.m. Tom.Dat. buy.Inf. self.Dat. car.Acc. ‘John promised Tom to buy a car for himself.’ In (i), the reflexive can be bound by the local or by the matrix subject. Crucially, as in (ii) the object cannot act as a binder, binding of reflexive anaphors cannot be used as a diagnostic to determine the status of the dative. UCLWPL 2012 145 (58) DAT się x As was proposed before, the choice of one of the two interpretations available for the dative DP depends on whether or not the dative is the performer of the action. According to the arb rewriting rule introduced in the previous section, the dative is associated with the subject argument when it provides reference for the arbitrary pronoun. When the rule does not apply, się is interpreted as an arbitrary subject different from the dative. Therefore, when it comes to anaphoric/ pronominal binding, sentences with sięarb functioning as the subject do not differ from cases such as (52) or (56) where the subject is a specific individual different from the dative and the dative receives the affectedness interpretation: (59) Każdemu chłopcu i uderzało sięarbj siebie*i,j/ go*i,* j,k. [every boy]Dat. hit.3sg.n.imperf. refl self/ he.Acc. Intended meaning: ‘Every boy was affected by one/people hitting themselves.’ As in the sentence in (52), principle B prevents the dative in (59) from binding the pronominal object go ‘him’. The pronoun cannot be bound by the reflexive subject either as the subject locally can only bind reflexive anaphors. Similar patterns can be observed for pronominal and anaphoric possessors. As in the above sentence, the reflexive anaphor in (60) can only be bound by the subject. In (61), the pronominal possessor cannot be locally bound by the subject and as it does not give rise to principle B effects, it can be bound by the dative: (60) Każdemu chłopcui biegało sięArbj po swoim*i,j ogrodzie. [every boy].Dat. ran.3sg.n.imperf. refl around his.refl. garden Intended meaning: ‘Every boy was affected by one/people running in their (one’s) garden.’ (61) Każdemu chłopcui biegało sięArbj po jegoi,*j,k ogrodzie. [every boy].Dat. ran.3sg.n.imperf. refl around his.refl. garden Intended meaning: ‘Every boy was affected by one/people running in their (every boy’s) garden.’ The above predictions with regards to the possibility of anaphoric/ pronominal binding by the dative are also confirmed when as a result of the application of the arb rewriting rule the dative is associated with the impersonal subject and interpreted as the performer of the action, as in the sentence in (62): (62) Jankowii przyjemnie sięi John.Dat. pleasurably refl ‘John ran and he considered that pleasurable.’ biegało. ran.3sg.n.imperf. If the impersonal clause selected by the dative contains a possessor pronoun referring to the dative, it is expected that the possessor will have to be expressed by the reflexive swój. This is confirmed by the data: (63) Jankowii John.Dat. przyjemnie pleasurably sięi refl biegało w ran.3sg.n.imperf. in swoimi his.refl. ogrodzie. garden UCLWPL 2012 146 ‘John ran in his garden and he considered that pleasurable.’ As subjects cannot locally bind pronominal elements in Polish, it is expected that the above sentence should not remain grammatical when swój is replaced by the pronominal possessor jego. However, such data can be accounted for if it is assumed that the pronominal is interpreted as co-referent with and not bound by the dative.25 As demonstrated above, the data provided so far support the configuration in (48). Further evidence to confirm that this proposal correctly represents the relation between the dative and the constituent that it selects comes from structures that illustrate the effects of binding principle C. Namely, as predicted by (48), the sentence below in which the dative pronoun is co-indexed with the R-expression contained in the clause that it precedes is ungrammatical: (64) *Jemui Marysia uderzyła Pawłai. he[strong]Dat. Mary.Nom. hit.3sg.f. Paul.Acc. Intended meaning: ‘Mary hit Paul and he was affected by that.’ If the above example is excluded by principle C, it should be possible to construct sentences in which a possessor contained within the dative constituent could be co-indexed with an Rexpression. The following data demonstrate that such sentences are indeed grammatical. As the pronominal possessor in (65) does not c-command the R-expression, this sentence does not give rise to principle C effects. (65) Jego mamiei Marysia uderzyła Pawłai. [his mum]Dat. Mary.Nom. hit.3sg.f. Paul.Acc. ‘Intended meaning: ‘Mary hit Paul and his mum was affected by that.’ The sentences in (64) – (65) demonstrate that condition C effects in dative structures are consistent with the proposal in (48). Even though a detailed study of how principle C operates in Polish would be necessary to draw further conclusions with regards to the data, on the basis of the above examples it seems that the analysis proposed in this paper is likely to make the right predictions in this respect. Summing up, the totality of the binding data presented above are easily accounted for if it is assumed that the dative in (1) – (4) should be analysed as an adjunct that is generated in the highest position in the structure from which it c-commands the clause that it combines with. 25 This can be checked with the use of the data that illustrate the availability of a bound reading for sentences involving the operator tylko ‘only’ that contain the reflexive or the pronominal possessor: (i) Tylko Jankowi dobrze spało się w swoim/ jego łóżku. only John.Dat. well slept.3sg.n. refl in his.refl/ pron. bed ‘Only John slept well in his bed.’ In order to express the meaning Only Janek is an x such that x slept well in x’s bed, speakers of Polish prefer to use the version of (i) that contains the reflexive possessor. On the other hand, in order to say Only Janek is an x such that x slept well in Janek’s bed, the pronominal possessor is chosen over the reflexive one. This suggests that the relation between the dative and the pronominal possessor is co-reference and not binding. UCLWPL 2012 147 3.3 Secondary predication As secondary predicate licensing conditions include the requirements that a secondary predicate has to be c-commanded by its subject and that the subject has to occupy an Aposition, secondary predication data can provide a further argument to support the configuration in (48). The role of the c-command restriction on predication is demonstrated by the following examples: (66) a b John ate the dish warm. * John ate from the dish warm. In both cases the subject of the secondary predicate occupies an argument position. However, in the ungrammatical (66b), the dish does not c-command the adjective that it is supposed to be modified by because it is contained inside a PP which does not contain warm; in (66a) there is c-command from the DP to the modifying adjective. On the contrary, in the case of the structure in (67), the c-command restriction on secondary predication is the only requirement that is satisfied. Due to its adjunct status, the dative DP cannot be modified by a secondary predicate26: (67) * Jankowi Paweł biega po ogrodzie nago. John.Dat. Paul.Nom. runs.3sg.m. around garden naked Intended meaning: ‘Paul runs in the garden when John is naked and John is affected by that.’ As expected, the above sentence becomes acceptable when the secondary predicate refers to the nominative subject of the clause preceded by the dative: (68) Jankowi Paweł biega po ogrodzie nago. John.Dat. Paul.Nom. runs.3sg.m. around garden naked Intended meaning: ‘Paul runs naked in the garden and John is affected by that.’ Similarly, the fact that the dative does not occupy an A-position accounts for the ungrammaticality of the middle (69) and the anticausative (70) structure below: (69) * Jankowi te teksty najlepiej się tłumaczą nago. 26 The fact that the dative can be the subject of the secondary predicate in sentences such as (i) below is due to the fact that it is identified with the subject of the impersonal sentence that occupies an A-position and ccommands the secondary predicate that it is modified by: (i) Jankowii najlepiej czyta sięi tę książkę nago. John.Dat. best read.3sg.n. refl this book naked ‘John reads this book and he enjoys the reading most when he reads it naked.’ UCLWPL 2012 148 John.Dat. these texts.Nom. best refl translate.3pl. naked Intended meaning: ‘To John these texts translate best when John is naked.’ (70) * Jankowi kawa wylała się nago. John.Dat. coffee.Nom. spilt.3sg.f. refl naked Intended meaning: ‘The coffee spilt and John was affected by that when he was naked.’ 3.4 The status of the dative – summary The data provided in this section confirm that the relation between the dative DP and the constituent that it selects in structures illustrated by (1) – (4) is correctly represented by (48). According to the rule in (24), the dative DP has the adjunct status with regards to the clause it combines with but within the adjunct constituent, the dative marker selects a noun phrase and provides it with the required semantics. These properties have been illustrated by numerous binding and secondary predication data. Further arguments in favour of (48) can possibly be provided by weak island extraction patterns but more research needs to be carried out to collect the relevant data. 4 Summary and alternative proposals The data presented in the previous sections illustrate a number of syntactic structures that can be preceded by a dative DP. They include the impersonal się construction, the middle and the anticausative structure and various types of other intransitive and transitive sentences. The variety of structures that can combine with the dative can also be argued to provide further evidence for the representation in (21) and the proposal that the dative selects the structure that it co-occurs with and, consequently, against the structure in (22) in which the selection process happens the other way round. Namely, the proposal in (22) is undermined by the fact that there are no semantic or syntactic properties that the above mentioned constructions could have in common to form a uniform category that would select and thetamark the dative argument. On the contrary, as according to (21), if the dative does not have the syntactic status of an argument, it can attach to a category in which all thematic roles have already been satisfied. This is characteristic of a process involving adjunct modification. Also, additional evidence against the representation in (22) concerns the fact that the presence of the dative in (1) – (4) is optional. As according to (22) the dative is selected by the clause that it precedes, in order for this proposal to be correct, the dative would have to be an obligatory element of the structure. The main alternative to the proposal put forward in this paper has already been illustrated by the representation in (23), repeated as (71) below. It involves a structure in which the dative is a constituent introduced by an additional syntactic head that establishes a relation between the dative and the event expressed by the verb: (71) XP Dat X (Adv) ... się ... V TP (e) UCLWPL 2012 149 Regardless of the semantics of X, the above structure cannot correctly predict the meaning of the dative, its properties and the properties of structures in which the dative occurs. If X was a functional head in the extended projection of the verb, it would be difficult to find phonological evidence confirming its presence due to the fact that X would not be phonologically realised. Also, because of the word order in dative-nominal sentences in which the VP normally follows the dative, there is no clear syntactic evidence for the existence of such a functional projection. In addition, in the absence of arguments supporting the presence of a functional head X, there is some evidence arguing against its existence. Namely, if X was a functional head in the extended projection of the verb, it would be expected to constitute an obligatory element of the structure. However, that this cannot be the case is demonstrated by the fact that the presence of the dative, the constituent supposed to be introduced by X, is optional in all structures discussed in this paper. Alternatively, if X was a lexical head, it would have its own event structure. An analysis of structures in (1) – (4) involving the dative being introduced by a head with this semantics would be inspired by Pylkkänen’s analysis of applicative arguments in which the highest dative would be introduced by a high applicative head denoting a relation between the applied argument and the event expressed by the sentence it combines with. It could be possible to find evidence for the presence of a lexical head introducing the dative by looking at adverbial modification of dative-nominal sentences. Namely, if the dative’s state of affectedness could be modified by a different temporal adverb than the event that caused that state, that would constitute evidence for the presence of an additional lexical head introducing the dative and assigning the affectedness semantics to it. However, as demonstrated below, sentences containing a highest dative DP do not accept modification by time adverbials referring to different time frames: (72) * Jankowi we wtorek zepsuł się samochód Tomka. John.Dat. in Tuesday broke down.3sg.m. refl car.Nom. Tom.Gen. Intended meaning: ‘John was affected on Tuesday by Tom’s car breaking down at w weekend. in weekend the weekend.’ The above sentence containing an affectedness dative is ungrammatical even though it is not uncommon to experience the effects of an event some time after the event occurred. Therefore, (72) cannot be used to provide motivation for the existence of an additional projection responsible for the affectedness semantics. The same conclusion can be drawn on the basis of dative-nominal sentences that contain adverbials sensitive to aspectual properties of the modified VP. For example, a durative adverbial can only occur in a sentence containing an atelic event predicate. In the two sentences below, the verb can be interpreted as atelic only in (74) as its imperfective aspect allows a multiple-event reading: (73) Jankowi (*przez tydzień) zepsuł się samochód John.Dat. for week broke down.3sg.perf. refl car.Nom. ‘*John was affected by Tom’s car breaking down once for a week.’ (74) Jankowi przez tydzień psuł się samochód Tomka Tom.Gen Tomka UCLWPL 2012 150 John.Dat. for week broke down.3sg.imperf. refl car.Nom. ‘John was affected by Tom’s car breaking down repeatedly for a week.’ Tom.Gen If ‘for a week’ could be introduced into the sentence in (73), that would confirm that this structure contained a separate verbal projection encoding the affectedness semantics of the dative just like the stative expression odczuwać skutki czegoś ‘be affected by the effects of sth’: (75) Janek przez tydzień odczuwał skutki John.Nom. for week felt.3sg.m.imperf. effects ‘John was affected for a week by Tom’s car breaking down.’ zepsuł broke down.3.sg.perf. się samochód refl car.Nom. tego, this.Gen. że that Tomka. Tom.Gen. As described above, in order to confirm the presence of an applicative head in the relevant structures, it would be necessary for sentences such as (72) and (73) to be grammatical. Therefore, the fact that they cannot be modified by two independent time adverbials means that there is no positive evidence to confirm the existence of an additional projection introducing the notion of affectedness into the relevant dative structures. 5 Conclusion In this paper I have proposed that highest dative DPs in (1) – (4) should be analysed as adjuncts with the inherent ‘out-of-control’ semantics defined by (24) and an internal syntactic structure represented by (48). This analysis correctly predicts the meaning of structures in which the dative occurs and it accounts for the two interpretations that can be assigned to the dative in relevant contexts. This cannot be achieved by proposals based on the applicative model that have been assumed to account for the properties of at least some non-argumental dative structures in other languages. References Ausín, A. (2003). Pronoun binding and the A/A-bar distinction. Abstract for The 26th University of Pennsylvania Linguistics Colloquium. Bosse, S., Bruening, B., & Yamada, M. (2012). Affected experiencers. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 30, 1185–1230. Harley, H., & Ritter, E. (2002). Person and Number in Pronouns: A Feature-Geometric Analysis. Language, 78, 482–526. Kibort, A. (2004). Passive and passive-like constructions in English and Polish. Ms., Cambridge: University of Cambridge. Pylkkänen, L. (2008). Introducing arguments. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Reinhart, T. (1995). Interface strategies. OTS Working Papers in Linguistics, Utrecht University. Rivero, M., Arregui, A., & Frąckowiak E. (2010). Variation in circumstantial modality: Polish vs. St’át’imcets. Linguistic Inquiry, 41, 704-714. Rivero, M., Arregui, A., & Frąckowiak E. (2012). Building Involuntary States in Slavic. In V. Demonte & L. McNally (Eds.), Telicity, change, and state: A cross-categorial view of event structure (pp 300-332). Oxford University Press, New York. Williams, E. (1980). Predication. Linguistic Inquiry, 11, 203-38.