INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 VOLUME 5, NUMBER 1 October 2009 F RONT MATTER ARTICLES 4 Gender and Reconciliation in Post-Conflict Societies: the Dilemmas of responding to Large-Scale Sexual Violence M. Melandri ESSAYS/ NOTES 28 The Institutional Conditions for a UN Foreign Policy Frederico Bartels Ferreira 41 Why Straussianism? John Hickman 55 Public Ethics Case Study: The Corporate Social Responsibility of Goldman Sachs Jacob Kloeveroed Griffiths INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 THE IPPR BOOK REVIEW 69 Editorial note to The IPPR Book Review: Exploring (New) Avenues of Information 71 Clashing on the Faultlines Alex Braithwaite Samuel P. Huntington, The Clash of Civilizaions 75 Richard Ned Lebow, A Cultural Theory of International Relations Harry Bauer 79 Foregoing Irredentism: The Power of Argument and the Rise of the Status Quo Norm Harald Heubaum Markus Kornprobst, Irredentism and European Politics: Argumentation, Compromise and Norms 85 Stephan Keukeleire and Jennifer MacNaughtan, The Foreign Policy of the European Union Christine Reh 90 Two Bailout Plans for Planet Earth Wasiq N. Khan Jeffrey Sachs, Common Wealth: Economics for a Crowded Planet Thomas Friedman, Hot, Flat, and Crowded: Why The World Needs a Green Revolution and How it Can Renew Our Global Future INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW Editorial Staff, Volume 5 (2008 – 2009) General Editors Aleyha Ahmed, MSc International Public Policy, Sub Editor Paul Aufiero, MSc International Public Policy, Academic Review Board Liason Amanda Caldeira, MA Human Rights, Coordinator Dilara Demir, MA Human Rights, Academic Review Board Liaison Daisy Ellis, MSc International Public Policy, Copy/Styles Editor Freddy Fallon, MSc International Public Policy Internet and Technology Coordinator Ankita Gandhi, MSc International Public Policy, Coordinator George Kakouris, MSc International Public Policy Submissions Editor Ari Magnusson, MSc International Public Policy, Marketing/Promotion Cole Martin, MSc International Public Policy, Copy/Styles Editor Philippa McMahon, MA Human Rights, Secretary Richard Rowland, MA Legal and Political Theory, Copy/Styles Editor Christophe G. Singh, MSc European Public Policy, Book Review Editor Filip Tanay, MSc European Public Policy External Communications Una Vandra, MSc International Public Policy External Communications Academic Review Panel Dr. Alex Braithwaite Dr. David Hudson Editorial Board Aleyha Ahmed, MSc International Public Policy Paul Aufiero, MSc International Public Policy Amanda Caldeira, MA Human Rights Dilara Demir, MA Human Rights Daisy Ellis, MSc International Public Policy Freddy Fallon, MSc International Public Policy Ankita Gandhi, MSc International Public Policy George Kakouris, MSc International Public Policy Ari Magnusson, MSc International Public Policy Cole Martin, MSc International Public Policy Philippa McMahon, MA Human Rights Nina Musgrave, MSc Global Governance and Ethics Richard Rowland, MA Legal and Political Theory Christophe G. Singh, MSc European Public Policy Filip Tanay, MSc European Public Policy Natalie Tomlinson, MA Human Rights Una Vandra, MSc International Public Policy The INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW (ISSN: 1748-5207) is a peer-reviewed, student-edited, and faculty- supervised academic journal published semi-annually by the University College London‘s School of Public Policy, London, United Kingdom. IPPR welcomes submissions from faculty and postgraduate students of any educational institution, of Articles (original empirical investigations, between 8,000 and 15,000 words), Essays/Notes (empirical or scholarly commentary pieces, between 2,000 and 4,000 words) and Book Reviews (brief assessment pieces, between 1,000 and 2,000 words). All submissions are reviewed anonymously. The Academic Review Panel and the plenary session of the Editorial Board must also approve pieces selected for publication by anonymous referees. Manuscripts may be submitted electronically to ippr@ucl.ac.uk or sent in hard copy to the address below. (For nonelectronic submissions, two copies must be provided, and manuscripts will not be returned.) All submissions must include the Submission Form and conform to the style and formatting guidelines provided at: http://www.ucl.ac.uk/ippr/manuscript-submission To request article reprints, to submit non-electronic manuscripts, as well as for comments or other queries, please contact: Editorial Board, INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW, School of Public Policy, University College London, 29/30 Tavistock Square, London, WC1H 9QU, United Kingdom. For the most recent issue and article archives, please visit IPPR online at: http://www.ucl.ac.uk/ippr/ INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW, Volume 5, Number 1 (October 2009). [ISSN 1748-5207] © 2009 by The School of Public Policy, University College London, London, United Kingdom. All rights reserved. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 4 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 GENDER AND RECONCILIATION IN POST-CONFLICT SOCIETIES: THE DILEMMAS OF RESPONDING TO LARGE-SCALE SEXUAL VIOLENCE M. Melandri ABSTRACT This paper discusses how a better understanding of women's wartime experiences of sexual violence can influence the theory and practice of transitional justice. Attention is first given to identifying the causes behind the widespread use of large-scale sexual violence in contemporary conflicts. Second, an overview is offered of the positive achievements of introducing a gender perspective in planning and implementing judicial and non-judicial transitional justice mechanisms. Third, it is argued that a truly gendersensitive analysis of wartime sexual violence against women has the potential to expand the concept and the scope of post-conflict reconciliation programmes. Keywords: rape, post-conflict reconciliation, sexual violence, transitional justice, war INTRODUCTION War, women, and sexual violence against women in wartime have always existed, but it was not until the 1990s that this issue reached the agenda of the international community. The mass rape of women in Rwanda and Bosnia finally lifted the taboo of wartime sexual violence, and the phenomenon started to attract worldwide attention. Recent research has shed light on the epidemic proportion of sexual violence taking place during contemporary conflicts. Statistics suggest that as many as 275,000 women and 5 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 girls may have been violated during the war in Sierra Leone1, approximately 500,000 during the 1994 genocide in Rwanda2, and between 20,000 and 60,000 in BosniaHerzegovina.3 This essay will discuss how a better understanding of women‘s wartime experiences of sexual violence can influence the theory and practice of transitional justice. Research on this topic is needed because it has been recognized that both the legal standards and the processes which transitional justice mechanisms draw on, have tended to either exclude women or to operate with a gender bias.4 In many respects, the way transitional justice programmes are designed and implemented determines how survivors of wartime sexual violence are treated in the aftermath of conflict and the type of support they receive from the community. It is thus imperative that the needs of women survivors of sexual violence are properly understood, if appropriate responses are to be given. The term ‗transitional justice‘ has been attributed a wide range of meanings, but it should be understood here as ‗the set of practices, mechanisms and concerns that arise following a period of conflict, civil strife or repression, and that are aimed directly at confronting and dealing with past violations of human rights and humanitarian law‘.5 The term encompasses both judicial mechanisms aimed at bringing perpetrators to account (criminal proceedings) and non-judicial mechanisms (truth commissions, vetting, reparation programmes and security sector reforms) aimed at providing justice for victims and promoting peace and reconciliation. The paper argues that a broader approach to transitional justice should be adopted to encompass women‘s experiences of conflict and duly address the specific 1 Report of the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Witness to Truth (Freetown, 2004), pp. 86. 2 R. Baksh et al, eds., Gender Mainstreaming in Conflict Transformation (London, Commonwealth Secretariat, 2005), pp. 22. 3 R. Seifert, ―The Second Front: The Logic of Sexual Violence in Wars‖, Women’s Studies International Forum vol. 19, no. 1/2 (1996): pp. 35; R. Seifert, ―War and Rape: A Preliminary Analysis‖, in Mass Rape: The War against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina, ed. A. Stiglmayer (Lincoln: University of Nebraska, 2001), pp. 55. 4 See C. Bell, C. Campbell and F. Nì Aolàin, ―Justice Discourses in Transition‖, Social and Legal Studies vol. 13, no. 3 (2004): pp. 318-19; C. Bell and C. O‘Rourke, ―Does Feminism Need a Theory of Transitional Justice? An Introductory Essay‖, The International Journal of Transitional Justice vol. 1, no. 1 (2007): pp. 24-25; N. Reilly, ―Seeking Gender Justice in Post-Conflict Transitions: Towards a Transformative Women‘s Human Rights Approach‖, International Journal of Law in Context vol. 3, no. 2 (2007): pp. 159. 5 N. Roth-Arriaza and J. Mazzacurrena, Transitional Justice in the Twenty-First Century: Beyond Truth versus Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University, 2006), pp. 2. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 6 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 consequences of wartime sexual violence perpetrated against women. In so doing, the discussion will focus particularly on the issue of reconciliation. This issue indeed remains largely unexplored in contemporary transitional justice discourses. To date, reconciliation discourses have substantially failed to address ‗gender reconciliation‘.6 Some steps have been taken for reconciliation efforts to include an understanding of how conflicts affect different social groups, including women. Nevertheless, I will argue that this current understanding of how reconciliation should address gender-specific violence, although an important achievement, has yet to include fully women's concerns. Drawing on women‘s experiences of sexual violence in wartime, I suggest that the concept and processes of reconciliation should be re-interpreted and expanded to meet women‘s needs better. The topic is one of relevance to the realms of both law and public policy, since the two are closely interlinked in the area of transitional justice. However, this paper should not be interpreted as advocating a strong approach to the 'legalisation' of transitional justice, or to reconciliation strategies in particular. In recent decades the law has already made very important steps in shaping justice programmes to protect better women seeking justice after war. What needs to be broadened now is the scope and meaning of justice itself, so as to reflect better women's experiences of conflict. Hence, the essay is best read as a call for a reinterpretation of the boundaries of international public policies on transitional justice; for policy in this area to proceed alongside the achievements of the law. It is argued here that only such a combined and interdisciplinary interpretation of justice can fully respond to the needs of women who have experienced wartime sexual violence. The paper is divided in three sections. Part 1 considers why sexual violence against women, and rape in particular, is perpetrated in times of war, so as to gain a clearer view of the social consequences of such violence, and to understand the extent to which these consequences are not incidental but intentional. Part 2 briefly sketches out the positive achievements of introducing a gender perspective into planning and 6 Some have acknowledged this gap, see Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (IDEA), Reconciliation after Conflict (Stockholm: IDEA, 2003), pp. 13-14; D. Pankhurst, ed., Gendered Peace: Women’s Struggle for Post-War Justice and Reconciliation (Geneva: Routledge & UNRISD, 2007), pp. 11; United Nations Research Institute for Social Development (UNRISD), Gender Equality: Striving for Justice in an Unequal World (Geneva: UNRISD, 2005), pp. 233. 7 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 implementing transitional justice projects, including international tribunals, truth commissions and formal reparations programmes. It highlights the conceptual exclusion of women‘s experiences in formulating the ideas of justice and reconciliation, and explains how a truly gender-sensitive analysis of wartime sexual violence can address these shortcomings. The final section offers concluding remarks on the inescapable link between fully including women‘s experiences of conflict and the need to enlarge the scope of transitional justice, and considers future trends in post-conflict reconciliation. It must be emphasised that while the discussion will focus on the experiences of women, its aim is to develop a gender analysis of the implications of large-scale sexual violence committed in wartime. More specifically, the focus will be on the use of sexual violence as a gender crime, hence perpetrated against women with a specific aim in mind: to destroy community relations by targeting women because of their gender. It is considered methodologically sound to limit this research to violence perpetrated against women because of the different values and restrictions attributed by society to male and female sexuality. For these reasons, sexual violence perpetrated against men will not come under consideration here.7 1. CAUSES AND CONSEQUENCES OF WARTIME SEXUAL VIOLENCE This section considers the causes and consequences of sexual violence (particularly of rape) perpetrated during armed conflicts. It endeavours to unravel the underlying motives behind wartime rape and what differentiates it from peacetime rape. The closer focus on rape, among other forms of sexual violence, is explained by the existence of a more extensive body of literature specifically on this issue. However, it should be borne in mind that in fact there is a wide array of other abhorrent practices such as forced impregnation, forced abortion, enforced prostitution, sexual slavery, abduction, and forced marriage, which are widespread and often perpetrated systematically against 7 For an in-depth discussion of this issue see S. Sivakumaran, ―Sexual Violence Against Men in Armed Conflict‖, European Journal of International Law vol. 18, no. 2 (2007). 8 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 women during conflict.8 Why, then, is rape used in wartime, and what strategic purposes are served by sexual violence against women during armed conflicts? 1.1 THE MOTIVATIONS FOR WARTIME RAPE AND SEXUAL VIOLENCE A survey of the literature reveals that rape and sexual violence arise from different specific motivations in various wars, which are not necessarily linked to sexual desire.9 The reasons advanced to explain wartime rape are manifold and approach the issue from different levels. At the individual level, Goldstein argues that wartime rape essentially occurs because war presents different opportunities from peacetime. He notes that rape was used as revenge by Russian soldiers in Berlin in 1945; it stemmed from soldiers‘ frustration in Vietnam, or it may result from the weakening of social norms and the awakening of aggressiveness.10 Other writers have attributed soldiers‘ aggressive sexual conduct to the ‗craziness of war‘, lack of discipline, frustration, suffering and drug use.11 Critics have strongly opposed such theories which try to explain wartime rape through an individual approach, arguing that they fail to account for the fact that many men do not rape during war.12 From a sociological perspective, it was indeed argued that wartime sexual attacks on women are historical and social processes carried out 8 E. Rehn and E. J. Sirleaf, Women, War and Peace: The Independent Expert’s Assessment on the Impact of Armed Conflict on Women and Women’s Role in Peacebuilding (New York: United Nations Development Fund for Women, 2002), pp. 3. 9 See M. Alison, ―Wartime Sexual Violence: Women‘s Human Rights and Questions of Masculinity‖, Review of International Studies vol. 33 (2007); M. Eriksson-Baaz and M. Stern, ―Making Sense of Violence: Voices of Soldiers in the Congo (DRC)‖, Journal of Modern African Studies vol. 46, no. 1 (2008); J. S. Goldstein, War and Gender: How Gender Shapes the War System and Vice Versa (Cambridge: Cambridge University, 2001). Interestingly, Seifert (1996) argues that the ‗sexual urge‘ argument does not stand up to scientific scrutiny, because wartime rape has nothing to do with the availability of willing women or prostitutes. 10 Goldstein, pp. 362-65. 11 Eriksson-Baaz and Stern, pp. 75-76. From interviews conducted with soldiers from the Democratic Republic of Congo Eriksson-Baaz and Stern found that the major reasons behind the violence were factors such as hunger, suffering and frustration related to poverty and neglect (pp. 78). The authors also noticed how the soldiers differentiate between ‗evil‘ or 'bad' rapes – where the violence is intended to humiliate the victim and often involves mutilations or is committed against children – and 'normal rapes', where the violence is intended to satisfy sexual desire (pp. 83). 12 See C. Snyder et al, ―On the Battleground of Women‘s Bodies: Mass Rape in Bosnia-Herzegovina‖, Affilia: Journal of Women and Social Work vol. 21, no. 2 (2006): pp. 185-6. 9 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 collectively, which must therefore have a collective meaning.13 Looking from the rapist‘s perspective, some authors have put forward the idea that rape, and especially gang rape (which represents a high proportion of wartime sexual violence), serves primarily as an act of loyalty between men, a bonding ritual which promotes group cohesion.14 On the other hand, from the victim‘s standpoint, social interpretations of sexual violence argue that women in war are not raped simply because they are women, but because of the interplay of their gender and other attributes which inevitably make certain women more vulnerable than others to sexual violence. For instance, Skjelsbaek notes that, during ethnic conflicts, it is the particular combination of their gender and ethnic identity which makes women ‗eligible‘ for rape15. Indeed in many cases it is the intersection of gender and other factors, such as ethnicity, that permits warring parties to differentiate women as theirs and others’. Women thus become targets because they belong to a specific group, and their violation and humiliation becomes a way to humiliate the men, religion, ethnic group, nation-state and culture they are identified with.16 In the last two decades, increasing attention has been paid to a conceptualisation of wartime rape as a ‗weapon of war‘. In this sense, rape may be used against targeted segments of the female population as part of a military strategy and to advance military aims, for instance, with genocidal intent. Forced impregnation is the most blatant example of rape as genocide. The explanation for how forced pregnancy could constitute genocide lies with cultural attitudes to ethnicity, according to which a woman is only a ‗biological box‘, since the children will bear the father-rapist‘s ethnicity.17 In other words, through systematic rape the perpetrators aim to create more babies belonging to their ethnic group, and through this to alter and erase the ethnic, religious and national 13 Seifert (1996), pp. 36. The authors highlight that this is an important factor in highly militarized societies. See Alison, pp. 77; L. Price, ―Finding the Man in the Soldier-Rapist: Some Reflections on Comprehension and Accountability‖, Women’s Studies International Forum vol. 24, no. 2 (2001): pp. 216. 15 See Alison, pp. 79-80; I. Skjelsbaek, ―Victim and Survivor: Narrated Social Identities of Women Who Experienced Rape During the War in Bosnia-Herzegovina‖, Feminism & Psychology vol. 16, no. 4 (2006): pp. 388. 16 Snyder et al, pp.193. Rejali argues that, where ethnic identities are blurred, rape can also serve as an ‗ethnomarker‘, which redefines racial and ethnic conventions. See D. Rejali, ―After Feminist Analyses of Bosnian Violence‖, Peace Review vol. 8 (1996). 17 B. Allen quoted in Alison, pp. 86. 14 10 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 identities of the raped women.18 In this case, rape (and subsequent pregnancy) thus serves to transform the victim ethnically, culturally or religiously. In other cases, studies have revealed that rape as a weapon of war has been used a means of terrorising not only the victims, but also their families and the larger population, into leaving their homes – hence functioning as a strategy of ethnic cleansing.19 Finally, there is evidence of rape and sexual violence being used as a weapon of war with the specific intent of destroying the social and cultural stability of the collective enemy, its very social fabric.20 Even more than in peacetime, in times of war women hold families and communities together while the men are called to arms. Women‘s physical and emotional destruction, therefore, strongly affects the group‘s social and cultural cohesion. Hence, in some cases, sexually-violent acts carry the defined intent to destroy the enemy by violating its social and gender-structured arrangements. This is confirmed by the fact that sexual violence is indeed largely perpetrated in contexts where cultures of honour and shame are deeply rooted, and where a high value is placed on female sexuality, chastity and marital virtue. In such contexts, it is rape victims themselves who bear the main burden of shame and stigma, rather than the rapists. The violence has therefore long-lasting effects, not only on the victims themselves, but also on gender relationships within the affected community.21 As we will see, this gives rise to a number of specific consequences in the aftermath of attacks. 2.1 CONSEQUENCES OF WARTIME RAPE AND SEXUAL VIOLENCE Donna Pankhurst notes that sexual violence, especially public rape, is used particularly successfully in strongly patriarchal societies to undermine the enemy22. The presence of an honour/shame culture, and the emphasis many cultures place on women‘s sexual virtue, indeed, enables the rapist to humiliate and demoralize not only the women 18 Skjelsbaek (2006), pp. 375. Price, pp. 223, Snyder at al, pp. 190. 20 J. Phillips quoted in Rejali, pp. 367; Seifert (1996), pp. 39; Alison, pp. 18. 21 International Alert, Addressing Gender-Based Violence in Sierra Leone (London: International Alert, 2007), pp. 12; Seifert (1996), pp. 41. 22 Pankhurst, pp. 46. See also I. Skjelsbaek, ―Sexual Violence and War: Mapping Out a Complex Relationship‖, European Journal of International Relations vol. 7, no. 2 (2001): pp. 228. 19 11 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 themselves, but also the whole community and the men who have failed to protect ‗their‘ women.23 Speaking of the conflict in the Balkans, and in relation to the existence of an honour/shame culture, Olijic writes: Men suffer the shame of their failure to protect their property that includes women, family, bloodlines, and soil. Women suffer through their duty to endure the private stigma of shame. Their suffering is protection of men‘s public shame. Public admission of sexual victimization means public defeat of the honour of the men: the loss of their public, status-focused face; the public admission of the loss of their bloodline; and the loss of their soil/nation.24 The shaming intent behind the use of rape and sexual violence in war gives rise to a number of important social consequences for the violated women. Non-governmental organizations working in conflict-affected countries have consistently reported alarming cases of women whom, because of the violence they suffered, have been stigmatised, systematically ostracised by their communities, or even abandoned by their husbands. A husband may indeed simply refuse to have further contact with his wife after such violence and may abandon or ostracise her, or he may allow her to remain in the household but humiliate her, or even take a second wife.25 Many men abandon the woman claiming that she may have been infected by HIV/AIDS, and fearing that they in turn will contract the virus. Although data are difficult to obtain (because sexual crimes go largely unreported), a 2003 survey conducted by International Alert in the area of Kivu, Eastern DRC, reports that in a sample of 492 women and girls who experienced rape, 26% of married victims had been abandoned by their husbands.26 In addition, the 23 Skjelsbaek (2006), pp. 388. M. Olijic quoted in Snyder et al, pp. 190. 25 Human Rights Watch, The War Within the War: Sexual Violence against Women and Girls in Eastern Congo (New York: Human Rights Watch, 2002), pp. 64-66; Medicins Sans Frontieres, ‘I Have No Joy, No Peace of Mind: Medical, Psychosocial, and Socio-Economic Consequences of Sexual Violence in Eastern DRC (Amsterdam: Medicins Sans Frontieres, 2004). 26 International Alert, International Alert, Women’s Bodies as a Battleground: Sexual Violence against Women and Girls During the War in the Democratic Republic of Congo, South Kivu (1996- 2003) (London: International Alert, 2005), pp. 42-43. 24 12 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 divorce rate among couples where the rape resulted in pregnancy was reported to be at 36%.27 In general, the research reports that of the husbands told about such violence, about half reacted very badly, becoming suspicious of their wives, while only a third showed compassion and supported their wives.28 These data are alarming and paint a tragic picture of the situation of women who have survived wartime sexual violence. Despite this, some researchers have warned against the risk of stereotyping rape victims as being isolated, hopeless individuals. Skjelsbaek argues that, in fact, the impact of wartime rapes in patriarchal families can be quite different from what one might expect, and that rejection, stigmatisation and ostracism are only one part of the picture.29 Interesting examples of the real complexities through which social stigma operates can be found in ethnographic studies conducted on rape survivors. Mookherjee, in her study of rape survivors and their husbands in a rural Bengali village, describes quite effectively the complex interplay of factors affecting these families at community level.30 In the Bangladesh war of 1971, it is estimated that as many as 200,000 women were raped. After the war, the government of Bangladesh publicly referred to the raped women as birangonas (‗war heroines‘), in an attempt to discourage social ostracisation.31 Despite these efforts, after the violence many of these women were still rejected by their husbands and ended up living in camps appositely set up by the government.32 At the same time, Mookherjee found that the women who, instead, had been ‗accepted‘ by their husbands after rape, and even actively supported in their struggle for accountability, had witnessed their husbands, in their turn, becoming extremely vulnerable to stigma and verbal violence in their communities, as well as economically in their daily negotiations.33 Essentially, this suggests that the discrimination faced by sexual violence 27 Ibid. Ibid. 29 Skjelsbaek (2006), pp. 385-97. 30 N. Mookherjee, ―May man (honour) is Lost but I Still Have my iman (principle): Sexual Violence and Articulations of Masculinity‖, in South Asian Masculinities: Context of Change, Sites of Continuity, ed R. Chopra, C. Osella & F. Osella (Delhi: Unlimited, 2004). 31 See N. Mookherjee, ―"Remembering to Forget": Public Secrecy and Memory of Sexual Violence in the Bangladesh War of 1971‖, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute vol. 12 (2006), pp. 440-41. 32 Price, pp. 37. 33 Mookherjee (2004). 28 13 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 survivors is a complex phenomenon, and one which is articulated at many different levels. Summing up, the underlying rationales explaining wartime rape are many and cannot be reduced to a single, oversimplified notion of ‗rape as a weapon of war‘. Nevertheless, it must be acknowledged that a large proportion of violence is indeed perpetrated as part of military strategy, which thus needs to be addressed and understood as such. We have seen that rape as a weapon of war is, to some extent, perpetrated with the intention of altering social and cultural stability, or destroingy the social fabric, by destabilising gender and family relations. This kind of violence is what this paper primarily addresses, as a specific typology of war rape. To conclude, if rape and sexual violence are used as a weapon of war, they constitute an intrinsic part of the parties‘ military strategies. Hence sexual violence is a component of the conflict itself, and is chosen because it is the most efficient means of reaching certain specific and strategic aims. In other words, large-scale sexual violence may be used during conflict with the specific aim of destroying a society by destroying its gender relations. It is an effective strategy as it is often successful in destabilising social patterns, indeed, it creates situations where women may be ostracised, abandoned by their husbands, or where families who support the woman can themselves be ostracised by the community. This paper argues that this is an important point, and one which needs to be taken into consideration in designing remedial and preventive measures for the violence. Thus, how should the international community respond to the needs of victims of wartime rape and, more generally, of sexual violence? 2. GENDER, JUSTICE AND RECONCILIATION Transitional justice has become a key pillar of the international community‘s postconflict reconstruction framework. Its processes and mechanisms are designed with the twin aims of providing justice for the victims and making the perpetrators accountable. In doing this, transitional justice should also encompass what Mckay defines as ‗gender justice‘: ‗legal processes which are equitable, not privileged by and for men, and which INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 14 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 distinguish the nefarious forms of injustice women experience during and after armed conflict‘.34 With few exceptions, women today are denied justice. The majority of perpetrators of wartime sexual violence still go unpunished – due in part to the massive numbers of perpetrators with which no national system can cope, and so women themselves often do not receive redress. In the last two decades, significant steps have been taken at international level to including women‘s experiences of conflict in justice programmes, yet some argue that their invisibility in transitional justice processes has still not been adequately addressed.35 The following discussion centres on the present shortcomings of transitional justice projects, and proposes a new model of reconciliation to address fully women‘s experiences of sexual violence during armed conflicts. 2.1 GENDER AND JUSTICE International law has led the way in including women in its efforts to respond to massive human rights violations, and it first did so by conceptualising sexual violence as a weapon of war. The International Criminal Tribunals for the Former Yugoslavia and Rwanda have indeed made notable progress in recognizing sexual and gender-based violence as a violation of the laws of war, not least by including rape as a crime against humanity in their statutes.36 Although the judgements they delivered represent but a tiny fraction of the real number of abuses, they have set important historical precedents. As a result of their pioneering practices, the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (ICC) today lists a number of provisions with respect to the prosecution of genderspecific crimes, including forced pregnancy, enforced prostitution, enforced sterilisation and sexual slavery.37 34 S. Mckay, ―Gender Justice and Reconciliation‖, Women’s Studies International Forum vol. 23, no. 5 (2000), pp. 561. 35 S. N. Anderlini, Women Building Peace: What They Do, Why it Matters (London: Lynne Rienner, 2007), pp. 158. 36 C. Chinkin, ―Gender-Related Crimes: A Feminist Perspective‖, in From Sovereign Impunity to International Accountability: The Search for Justice in a World of States, eds R. Thakur and P. Malcontent (Tokyo, United Nations University, 2005), pp. 117. 37 Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, in A/Conf.138/9 (reprinted in 37 ILM (1998), 999. 15 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 The practice of the tribunals thus marks an important contribution to the advancement of accountability for gender crimes. Their practices have nonetheless been beset by problems and inconsistencies. International justice has for instance been accused of being too slow, of having inadequately supported victims and witnesses, of having conducted inappropriate investigations and with inadequate staff training - all of which are regarded in some quarters as having amounted to further victimisation.38 Acknowledging these shortcomings, the ICC rules of procedure have been designed to include witness protection programmes, trained staff with expertise in trauma related to sexual crimes, and have introduced a requirement for judges to have specific expertise on the issue.39 In additon, under the complementarity principle, in future the ICC may have a role in influencing the adoption of domestic laws and judicial remedies for women living in conflict-affected countries. These recent developments have marked the beginning of a new era of international justice and accountability for women. However, a broader critique was made that justice for women survivors of sexual violence should not be understood simply in terms of criminal accountability. Indeed, while some women proactively seek accountability, the majority prefer not to be exposed to public knowledge – often fearing social stigma and ostracisation, as already discussed. Also, women survivors of sexual violence are often in desperate need of healthcare and social rehabilitation programmes. Widows, or women rejected by their husbands, are especially likely to be unable to provide for themselves and their children, and to many, prostitution may seem the only viable option.40 For these reasons, if gender justice requires the introduction of gender perspectives in all dimensions of justice, it also requires a redefinition of the boundaries of justice itself to accommodate women‘s requirements. Noleen Heyzer, former Executive Director of the United Nations Development Fund for Women (UNIFEM), argues that in many countries a focusing on restorative justice is needed, to help women 38 See Anderlini (2007), pp. 160-174; B. Noworojee, ――Your Justice is Too Slow‖: Will the ICTR Fail Rwanda‘s Rape Victims?‖ (Geneva: UNRISD, 2005); E. Rehn and E. J. Sirleaf, pp. 93-96. 39 Reilly, pp. 161-62. 40 J. Ward and M. Marsh, ―Sexual Violence against Women and Girls in War and Its Aftermath: Realities, Responses and Required Resources‖, paper presented to the Symposium on Sexual Violence in Conflict and Beyond, 21-23 June 2006, Brussels, Belgium. 16 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 move beyond their trauma and begin to reconstruct their lives. 41 The concept of restorative justice moves beyond discourses of criminal punishment to focus on repairing relationships.42 In post-conflict transitions, this model of justice proposes mechanisms such as Truth and Reconciliation Commissions (TRCs) and formal reparation programmes, which, it is argued, are capable of delivering a broad range of possible objectives, including national and personal reconciliation. 2.2 GENDER AND RECONCILIATION The word ‗reconciliation‘ has many meanings and remains a highly-contested concept. A basic definition entails the search for a shared truth, some form of justice, and an element of forgiveness and healing43; but while some focus on the individual level, some consider groups, while others consider society as a whole.44 Post-conflict reconciliation can typically occur in a situation where war has ended, a settlement has been reached, and a new regime is struggling to reconstruct society. In this context, reconciliation is a process through which a society moves from a divided past to a shared future, deeply concerned with re-building relationships between former enemies.45 Of particular concern here are the issues raised when a gender perspective is included in reconciliation efforts, particularly as to how this could affect the idea of whom needs to be reconciled. One of the most commonly employed reconciliation processes is to establish a national TRC. TRCs provide a public forum where victims can express their grievances, recount their memories of violence and, by so doing, seek reconciliation. Prior to 2000, the only commissions to take gender crimes into account were those in Guatemala, Haiti and South Africa. Since 2001, gender crimes are expressly on the agenda of TRCs – including those in Sierra Leone, East Timor and Peru. This emerging practice has had the 41 N. Heyzer, ―Gender Justice‖, Statement to the Security Council on Women, Peace and Security by Noleen Heyzer, Executive Director, UNIFEM, 28 October 2004. 42 Bell and O‘Rourke, pp. 40-41. 43 S. N. Anderlini, C. P. Conaway and L. Kays, ―Transitional Justice and Reconciliation‖, in Inclusive Security, Sustainable Peace: A Toolkit for Advocacy and Action, eds Women Waging Peace (Cambridge, MA: Women Waging Peace, 2005), pp. 3; IDEA, pp. 12. 44 Pankhurst, pp. 11. 45 IDEA, pp. 12. 17 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 important effect of broadening the scope and methods of investigation.46 Significant developments have indeed resulted in ensuring that the process takes into account the needs of women traumatised by sexual violence, both at the substantial level and at the procedural level. For example, the South Africa TRC created Special Hearings on Women and formed an all-women panel to encourage women to speak freely about their experiences of violence.47 In Sierra Leone, guidelines were developed on how to take statements, and included the presence of female statement-takers, the absence of fathers and husbands (unless explicitly requested by the victim), and training for personnel dealing with traumatised women.48 Some relative success was achieved by TRCs in addressing women‘s experiences of human rights violations and in acknowledging the ways in which women have experienced conflict. According to Lederach, acknowledgement is decisive in the reconciliation dynamic. While knowledge is important, acknowledgement is a different social phenomenon, and a necessary one for reconciliation, as it is only through acknowledgement that it is possible to start restoring relationships.49 Yet, the validity of this principle in the context of sexual offences is disputed. Feminist critique has warned against the potentially risky assumptions of a vision of reconciliation through public acknowledgement, which may not be universally applicable. While hundreds of sexual violence survivors have courageously come forward to recount their experiences in public forums, in most cases women hesitate to testify because it would be considered shameful and, typically, result in stigmatisation and even severe punishment.50 Seeking justice in an environment where women are traditionally encouraged to ‗forgive and forget‘ may indeed prove more complicated than providing fair processes for witnesses, mainly because of the complexity inherent in the social dynamics of shame 46 See K. Askin, ―The Quest for Post-Conflict Justice‖, Columbia Journal of Transnational Law vol. 41 (2003), pp. 513; V. Nesiah, Gender and Truth Commissions Mandates (New York: International Center for Transitional Justice, 2005); World Bank, Gender and Truth and Reconciliation Commissions (Washington, DS: World Bank, 2006). 47 Anderlini, pp. 163. 48 Ibid., pp. 172-73. 49 J. Lederach, Building Peace: Sustainable Reconciliation in Divided Societies (Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace, 1998), pp. 26. 50 See IDEA, pp. 56; N. Valji, Gender Justice and Reconciliation (Berlin: Friederich Ebert Stiftung, 2007), pp. 17. 18 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 and stigmatization. The ethnographic study conducted among rape survivors in Bangladesh specifically illustrates this. Mookherjee found that while the public authorities and the wider community acknowledged the heroism of the women (birangonas) who had endured sexual violence, this was lacking in the community, and in the villages the women who exposed their experiences were considered shameful.51 In the villagers‘ eyes, the proper response to such taboo crimes was to remain silent, hidden and invisible.52 Following their public acknowledgement, the women were seen as sinful, often branded prostitutes, and subjected together with their families to scorn and blame.53 Summing up, the reconciliation process for gender-specific crimes needs to take place without undue assumptions, or it may run the risk of doing harm instead of restoring dignity. McKay stated that, ideally, ‗new meaning can be given to private shame as it is transformed into political dignity when the traumatic story becomes testimony.‘54 The above discussion warns that this may not always be the case. The issue of shame, a paramount concern to women victims of sexual abuse, poses significant questions as to whether including a gender perspective into reconciliation discourses could indeed mean more than just re-adapting the current categories of reconciliation to accommodate women‘s needs, as we shall see. 2.3 HOW GENDER COULD SHAPE THE DISCOURSE ON RECONCILIATION Transitional justice mechanisms have been built on false demarcations between conflict-related (political) violence – to be addressed in justice and reconciliation processes, and post-conflict (incidental) side-effects of such violence – largely neglected by justice and reconciliation programmes. I suggest that the case of wartime sexual violence challenges such assumptions, precisely because of the reasons behind the use of sexual violence as a strategy of war. When rape, sexual violence and other horrible practices alike are chosen as the form of wartime violence which best serves the purpose of destroying the enemy‘s social fabric by destabilizing gender and family relations, I 51 Mookherjee (2006), pp. 440-41. Ibid. 53 Ibid. See also Noworojee, pp. 24. 54 Mckay, pp. 564. 52 19 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 would argue that justice and reconciliation programmes, to be effective, must not ignore the tangible, and intended, long-term social consequences of such violence and must aim to repair damaged gender relations. It has been said that, for women who have experienced sexual abuse, reconciliation means: ‗Offences against them being recognized and punished, illegitimate children being recognized as legitimate with full rights, and resources being allocated to deal with the physical and psychological consequences. For war widows, reconciliation would be expected to include compensation and to address existing inheritance laws and practices that dispossess them or hinder them in fulfilling their new obligations as family providers‘.55 This continues, noting that: ‗Establishing trustful and respectful relations between men and women, and between particularly targeted groups of men and women, is essential for fashioning a democratic society‘.56 Some progress has been made in recent years, partially to address these concerns. The report of the Sierra Leone TRC sets the agenda in this regard, by endorsing important policy recommendations on the adoption of reparation measures, and by calling, for instance, for the government to provide free healthcare for victims of sexual violence, a monthly pension, and skills-training programmes.57 Moreover, there is a move towards the prevention of wife abandonment or stigmatisation with the Commission establishing 55 IDEA, pp. 13. Ibid. 57 J. King, ―Gender and Reparations in Sierra Leone: The Wounds of War Remain Open‖, in What Happened to the Women? Gender and Reparations for Human Rights Violations, eds R. Rubio-Marín (New York: Social Sciences Research Council, 2006), pp. 22-23. The reparations programme, however, does not provide direct government assistance for widows. See generally, Report of the Sierra Leone TRC (2004). 56 20 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 that male spouses should also receive free medical treatment for HIV/AIDS, counselling and psychosocial support.58 Nothing has been done though to establish better relationships between men and women.59 Hence the key purpose of this essay is to suggest that the widespread use of wartime rape and sexual violence calls for urgent action to remedy this situation. For these purposes, Lederach‘s understanding of reconciliation as a locus – a space or location – where the parties to a conflict meet, provides an interesting model. In the specific case of sexual violence as a weapon of war, it can be argued that there are many parties to the conflict which need to meet: the perpetrator, the woman, her husband and family, and the community to which the woman belongs. As discussed earlier, rape and sexual violence are not only used to humiliate the woman, but are deliberately chosen among other forms of violence for their negative social connotations, with the purpose of humiliating and destroying the social relationships of an entire group. Reconciliation should therefore take into consideration all these dynamics and be understood as providing a context for the healing process to take place at many different levels. Indeed, reconciliation needs to take place at the individual level, between the victim and the perpetrator; at the family level, between the victim, the family and husband; and at the community level, between the victim and the local community which has stigmatised her. In other words, a closer analysis of women's experiences of conflict suggests that reconciliation should be understood as the locus where all the parties intended to be affected by the conflict (whether directly or indirectly) meet, and where all the dimensions of the conflict are addressed. In so doing, it is suggested that reconciliation efforts should leave space for, and engage with, community practices. Such mechanisms are anchored in existing values and relationships, and thus they are likely to receive broader support60 and possibly be more effective in working towards the elimination of the stigma attached to victims of sexual violence. Community leaders can play an 58 Ibid. In the words of Donna Pankhurst, ―there has been virtually no discussion about ‗gender reconciliation‘. Women are often expected to identify themselves with reconciliation and peace-building interventions [...] Some of these interventions could be interpreted as being about reconciliation between women and men‖ (pp. 11). 60 IDEA, pp. 17; R. Shaw, ―Rethinking Truth and Reconciliation Commissions: Lessons from Sierra Leone‖ (Washington, DC: United States Institute for Peace, 2005). 59 21 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 important role in promoting the social reintegration of survivors as, for instance, was done in Burundi where community leaders themselves negotiated with husbands and fathers to allow wives and daughters back into the household.61 It cannot be over-stressed how important it would be for reconciliation programmes to include space for men to participate, through the community, in the process of healing. In so doing, men themselves would have a role in promoting the public acknowledgement of gender violence – an act which is traditionally discouraged for women. This is an essential step to achieve reconciliation for gender crimes, and one which is likely to rebuild more egalitarian gender structures because it should initiate a process of re-negotiation of gender roles in which both genders can participate. Safeguards to prevent abusive traditional practices should also be put in place, to avoid the recurrence of abusive practices – such as reconciliation by means of asking the rapist to marry the raped woman, or the compensatory exchange of women. To sum up, I have argued that reconciliation efforts should include consideration of how to eliminate the shame attached to victims of sexual violence, this might be achieved by integrating a deeper understanding of rape as a form of conflict into the logic of re-building relationships between the parties involved in the conflict. If rape constitutes a form of conflict chosen with the specific intention of affecting not only the woman but, through her, the wider community, then all these parties then must participate in the reconciliation process. Indeed, not only should the process aim to reconcile the rapist with the victim, but also it should aim to restore the relationships pre-existing between the woman and her family and the woman, her family and her community. At present, instead, the woman who decides to participate in national justice and reconciliation programmes must deal with the perpetrators largely unsupported, leaving her vulnerable to stigma and ostracism by her family, husband and community. It is incumbent on the international community to find ways to respond to the needs of women who have endured sexual violence, to offer them a third alternative to the rocky road to public acknowledgement which is often followed by social stigmatisation, and the socially-acceptable coping strategy of self-imposed silence. 61 See N. Zicherman, ―Addressing Sexual Violence in Burundi‖, Forced Migration Review vol. 27 (2007). 22 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 3. CONCLUSIONS: HOW WARTIME SEXUAL VIOLENCE MAY RE-DEFINE THE BOUNDARIES OF TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE The inclusion of sexual violence in the range of offences which are seen as constituting an international crime, and grave breaches of the laws of war, has resulted in significant developments in the substance and practice of international criminal justice. Perpetrators have been held accountable for raping girls and women during conflicts, and tribunals have gradually been adapting to the need to protect and support victims of sexual violence. Although much remains to be done, women‘s experiences of conflict are now on the international agenda and cannot be neglected by accountability mechanisms. The formal commitment on behalf of the international community to eliminate sexual violence in armed conflicts was expressed through Security Council Resolution 1325 (2000), and again through Resolution 1820 (2008). This paper has highlighted that, notwithstanding the noble intents, women‘s perspectives are not yet fully included in the discourse and practice of reconciliation programmes. Social stigma is still the biggest obstacle to achieving gender accountability and reconciliation - but for reconciliation to be effective and inclusive it needs to be eliminated. To this end, reconciliation must be re-defined to include and address the intended negative consequences on women of the use of sexual violence as a weapon of war. Security Council resolutions provide the grounds for such reinterpretation, and thus the international community is not only urged but also mandated to address this issue. A key future challenge for justice and reconciliation programmes, therefore, is to develop a more holistic understanding of how such violence impacts on women‘s lives and on gender relations more broadly, and to promote a multi-dimensional understanding of the harm suffered. At this stage, an analysis is essential of how patriarchal social structures and gender discrimination interact to further victimise women in post-conflict settings. This essay has advocated the need to understand women‘s experiences of conflict, so as to advance an inclusive vision of gender justice and reconciliation in post-conflict societies. I have shown how this could redefine the scope of international public policies on transitional justice and move beyond the initial boundaries created by gender-blind mechanisms. Further, I suggest that, in so doing, future justice and reconciliation efforts 23 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 could be designed with a view to promoting a shift towards gender equality in social and interpersonal relationships. Essentially, it appears that the transformative potential of including gender analysis in transitional justice is still largely under-explored. REFERENCES Alison, M. ―Wartime Sexual Violence: Women's Human Rights and Questions of Masculinity‖, Review of International Studies 33 (2007): pp.75-90. Anderlini, S. Women Building Peace: What They Do, Why It Matters. London: Lynne Rienner, 2007. Anderlini, S., Conaway, C. and Kays, L. ―Transitional Justice and Reconciliation‖ In Inclusive Security, Sustainable Peace: A Toolkit for Advocacy and Action, International Alert and Women Waging Peace, 2005. http://www.huntalternatives.org/ (accessed February 2nd, 2009). Askin, K. ―The Quest for Post-Conflict Gender Justice.‖ Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 41 (2003): pp.509-521. Baksh, R., Etchart, L., Onubougu, E. and Johnson, T. eds. Gender Mainstreaming in Conflict Transformation. London: Commonwealth Secretariat, 2005. Bell, C., Campbell, C., and Nì Aolàin, F. ―Justice Discourses in Transition.‖ Social and Legal Studies 13, no. 3 (2004): pp.305-28. Bell, C. and O'Rourke, C. ―Does Feminism Need a Theory of Transitional Justice? An Introductory Essay.‖ The International Journal of Transitional Justice 1, no. 1 (2007): pp.23-44. Chinkin, C. ―Gender-Related Crimes: A Feminist Perspective.‖In From Sovereign Impunity to International Accountability: The Search for Justice in a World of States, edited by R. C. Thakur and Peter Malcontent, 116-34. Tokyo: United Nations University, 2005. 24 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Eriksson-Baaz, M. & Stern, M. ―Making Sense of Violence: Voices of Soldiers in the Congo (DRC).‖ Journal of Modern African Studies 46, no. 1 (2008): pp.57-86. Goldstein, J. War and Gender: How Gender Shapes the War System and Vice Versa. Cambridge: Cambridge University, 2001. Heyzer, N. ―Gender Justice‖, statement to the Security Council on Women, Peace and Security by Heyzer, N. Executive Director, UNIFEM, October 28, 2004. http://www.peacewomen.org/ (accessed February 2nd, 2009). Human Rights Watch. The War Within the War: Sexual Violence Against Women and Girls in Eastern Congo. New York: Human Rights Watch, 2002. __________ We Will Kill You if You Cry: Sexual Violence in the Sierra Leone Conflict. New York: Human Rights Watch, 2003. Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (IDEA). Reconciliation after Violent Conflict. Stockholm: IDEA, 2003. International Alert. Women's Bodies as a Battleground: Sexual Violence Against Women and Girls During the War in the Democratic Republic of Congo, South Kivu (1996-2005). London: International Alert, 2005. http://www.internationalalert.org/ (accessed February 2nd, 2009). __________ Addressing Gender-Based Violence in Sierra Leone. London: International Alert, 2007. http://www.international-alert.org/ (accessed February 2nd, 2009). King, J. ―Gender and Reparations in Sierra Leone: The Wounds of War Remain Open.‖ In What Happened to the Women? Gender and Reparations for Human Rights Violations, edited by R. Rubio-Marin, pp.247-83 . New York: Social Sciences Research Council, 2006. Lederach, J. Building Peace: Sustainable Reconciliation in Divided Societies. Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace, 1998. Mckay, S. ―Gender Justice and Reconciliation.‖ Women's Studies International Forum 23, no. 5 (2000): pp.561-70. 25 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Medicins Sans Frontieres. 'I Have No Joy, No Peace of Mind': Medical, Psychosocial, and Socio-Economic Consequences of Sexual Violence in Eastern DRC. Amsterdam: Medicins Sans Frontieres, 2004. Mookherjee, N. ―‗My man (honour) is Lost but I Still Have my iman (principle)‘: Sexual Violence and Articulations of Masculinity.‖ In South Asian Masculinities: Context of Change, Sites of Continuity, edited by R. Chopra, C. Osella and Filippo Osella, pp.131-59. Delhi: Women Unlimited, 2004. __________ ‗Remembering to Forget‘: Public Secrecy and Memory of Sexual Violence in the Bangladesh War of 1971.‖ Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 12 (2006): pp.433-50. Nesiah, V. Gender and Truth Commission Mandates. New York: International Center for Transitional Justice, 2005. http://www.ictj.org/ (accessed February 2nd, 2009). Pankhurst, D., ed. Gendered Peace: Women’s Struggles for Post-War Justice and Reconciliation. Geneva: Routledge & UNRISD, 2007. Price, L. ―Finding the Man in the Soldier-Rapist: Some Reflections on Comprehension and Accountability.‖ Women's Studies International Forum, 24, no. 2 (2001): pp.211-27. Rehn, E. and Sirleaf, E. Women, War and Peace: The Independent Expert’s Assessment on the Impact of Armed Conflict on Women and Women’s Role in Peacebuilding. New York: UNIFEM, 2002. Reilly, N. ―Seeking Gender Justice in Post-Conflict Transitions: Towards a Transformative Women's Human Rights Approach.‖ International Journal of Law in Context 3, no. 2 (2007): pp.155-72. Rejali, D. (1996) ―After Feminist Analyses of Bosnian Violence.‖ Pace Review 8 (1996): pp.365-72. Roth-Arriaza, N. and Mazzacurrena, J. Transitional Justice in the Twenty-First Century: Beyond Truth versus Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University, 2006. 26 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Seifert, R. ―The Second Front: The Logic of Sexual Violence in Wars.‖ Women's Studies International Forum 19, no. 1/2 (1996): pp.35-43. __________ ―War and Rape: A Preliminary Analysis.‖ In Mass Rape: The War Against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina, edited by A. Stiglmayer, 54-70. :Lincoln University of Nebraska, 2001. Shaw, R. Rethinking Truth and Reconciliation Commissions: Lessons from Sierra Leone. Washington, DC: United States Institute for Peace, 2005. http://www.usip.org/ (accessed February 2nd, 2009). Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission. Witness to Truth Freetown, 2004. Sivakumaran, S. ―Sexual Violence Against Men in Armed Conflict.‖ European Journal of International Law 18, no. 2 (2007): pp.253-76. Skjelsbaek, I. ―Sexual Violence and War: Mapping Out a Complex Relationship‖ European Journal of International Relations 7, no. 2 (2001): pp.211-37. __________ ―Victim and Survivor: Narrated Social Identities of Women Who Experienced Rape During the War in Bosnia-Herzegovina.‖ Feminism & Psychology 16, no. 4 (2006): pp.373-403. Snyder, C., Gabbard, Wesley., May, Dean. and Zulcic, N. ―On the Battleground of Women's Bodies: Mass Rape in Bosnia-Herzegovina.‖ Affilia: Journal of Women and Social Work 21, no. 2 (2006): pp.184-95. Stiglmayer, A., ed. Mass Rape: The War Against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina. Lincoln: University of Nebraska, 1994. United Nations Research Institute for Social Development (UNRISD). Gender Equality: Striving for Justice in an Unequal World. Geneva: UNRISD, 2005. Valji, N. Gender Justice and Reconciliation. Berlin: Friederich Ebert Stiftung, 2007. Ward, J. & Marsh, M. ―Sexual Violence Against Women and Girls in War and Its Aftermath: Realities, Responses, and Required Resources‖, paper presented to Symposium on Sexual Violence in Conflict and Beyond, Brussels, Belgium, 2123 June 2006. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 27 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 World Bank. Gender, Justice and Truth Commissions. Washington, DC: World Bank, 2006. Zicherman, N. ―Addressing Sexual Violence in Post-Conflict Burundi.‖ Forced Migration Review 27 (2007): pp.48-49. http://www.fmreview.org/ (accessed February 2nd, 2009). 28 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 THE INSTITUTIONAL CONDITIONS FOR A UN FOREIGN POLICY Frederico Bartels Ferreira ABSTRACT This article addresses the institutional capabilities of the United Nations to develop its own foreign policy. Basing the analysis on the works in the field of Foreign Policy Analysis, the article deals with the apparatus necessary for the organisation to craft its own policy. Furthermore the article draws parallels between the national institutions and the institutions of the organisation in order to enlighten the function of the different branches inside the United Nations. The UN Secretariat is dealt as one important instrument for the exercise of an independent foreign policy for the institution. Foreign Policy requires two main elements in its most simplistic definition: i) a foreign element; and ii) a coherent aggregate of actions. In the absence of these two points there can be neither a foreign environment nor a policy, therefore derailing what we understand as foreign policy. During the course of this paper, bear in mind these two initial elements seen that they ought to be clarified in the stance of the United Nations (UN), with the goal of demonstrating the organisation‘s capacity for developing its own foreign policy. In order to achieve this goal this paper will access the implications of adapting the current literature of Foreign Policy Analysis to an International Organisation, followed by an exploration of the institutions that permit the UN to develop his own foreign policy. First, there will be an exploration of the initial concepts in Foreign Policy Analysis, followed by an assessment of the place in which foreign policy develops comparing a country and the UN. Further on, the paper will discuss the institutions of the UN and their implications for the construction of an independent foreign policy. 29 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 DEFINING DEFINITIONS Foreign Policy is usually thought to be related to one country‘s identity and actions in the international scenario, an assumption that is correct even tough it does not suffice the phenomenon of foreign policy. The study of Foreign Policy Analysis (FPA), as represented by Hudson,62 is entrenched between the domestic and the international levels, as one could put forward, between International Relations and Political Science. In that fashion, FPA is designed to access concerns of internal and external nature within a political society. A useful definition is given by Hill as follows, ―[a] brief definition of foreign policy can be given as follows: the sum of official external relations conducted by an independent actor (usually a state) in international relations.‖63 The importance of this definition for the current work is two-folded, firstly, it already opens up the possibility of a non-state actor to be the owner of an independent foreign policy, and it also narrows foreign policy to the official external relations, which can be easily identified. These two elements will be explored further on for the case of the UN. At this point, it is also important to bear in mind the definition of foreign policy of Smith, Hadfield and Dunne as follows, ―For us, foreign policy, although usually linked to the behaviour of a state, can apply to other actors. Thus it is perfectly possible to speak of companies, regional governments, and non-state actors having foreign policy.‖64 This definition encompasses the possibility of expanding the foreign policy concept and, hence, the FPA tools to nonstate actors, which is paramount to this work. FPA started with the work of Snyder, Bruck and Sapin65 which was dedicated to exposing how the decision-making approach, as described, could contribute to the understanding of the International Relations as a whole. It is also important to take notice 62 Hudson, V. M. ―Foreign Policy Analysis: Actor-Specific Theory and the Ground of International Relations‖.Foreign Policy Analysis Vol. 1, no.1 (2005): 1-30. 63 Hill, C. The Changing Politics of Foreign Policy. (New York: Palgrave Macmilliam, 2003) pp.3 64 Smith, S.; Hadfield, A.; Dunne, T. Foreign Policy: Theories, Actors, Cases. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008) pp.2. 65 Snyder, R.C.; Bruck, H.W.; Sapin, B. Foreign Policy Decision-Making. 1962. Revisited by: Hudson, V.M.; Chollet, D.H.; Goldgeier, J.M. (New York: Palgrave Macmilan, 2002). 30 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 that Hudson66 emphasises the role of personality and of bureaucratic organisation for foreign policy. In that fashion, ―[t]he single most important contribution of FPA to IR theory is to identify the point of theoretical intersection between the primary determinants of state behavior: material and ideational factors. The point of intersection is not the state, it is human decision makers‖.67 The centrality of human decision makers, as stated, creates the importance of the institutional arrangements, mainly because humans are constrained by these arrangements in different social scenarios. Regarding bureaucratic organisations, Checkel68 supports the idea that the organisation of the institution is important when considering analysis within the foreign policy approach. Checkel69 puts forward explicitly that thinking in terms of bureaucratic organisation and its development is correctly positioned in the center of FPA, concurring with Halperin‘s70 claim of the proximity between bureaucratic organisation and the development of foreign policy. Hilsman71 also supports the importance of bureaucracy for the understanding of foreign policy, dedicating the bulk of his work to the different interactions within departments of the US government and among those very departments. Hill72 further shows a concern with the role that each bureaucracy assumes in the decision-making process, taking into account elements as the intelligence agencies in the process and imperfect information. This bureaucratic concern is adamant to understand the situation of a UN foreign policy, seen that the UN was a complex organisational charter that ought to be explored. All in all, bureaucratic concerns 66 Hudson, V. M. ―Foreign Policy Analysis: Actor-Specific Theory and the Ground of International Relations‖.Foreign Policy Analysis Vol. 1, no.1 (2005): 1-30. 67 Ibid, p.3. 68 Checkel, J. T. ―Constructivism and foreign policy‖. In Foreign Policy: Theories, Actors, Cases, edited by Smith, S.; Hadfield, A.; Dunne, T., 71-80. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. 69 Ibid. 70 Halperin, M. H. Bureaucratic Politics & Foreign Policy. (Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution, 1974). Hilsman, R. The Politics of Policy Making in Defense and Foreign Affairs: Conceptual Models and Bureaucratic Politics. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc, 1987. 71 Hilsman, R. The Politics of Policy Making in Defense and Foreign Affairs: Conceptual Models and Bureaucratic Politics (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc, 1987). 72 Hill, C. The Changing Politics of Foreign Policy. (New York: Palgrave Macmilliam, 2003) INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 31 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 as deemed strong enough to shape not only the process of decision-making in foreign policy, but also the outcome itself. Hilsman73 is a supporter of this point, considering as well that, the post that one occupies could shape their considerations on a given issue. Hudson74 explores five elements of FPA in her work which encompass the kind of research in the field. These elements are: i) individual decision-makers; ii) group decision-making; iii) culture and identity; iv) domestic politics; and v) the international system. Each of these elements account for a different perspective on the phenomenon and can be regarded to be complementary, mainly when one takes into account the complexities of the reality of a decision-maker. Hudson75 points out that there have been works that focused one any of the five aspects, nevertheless, the author points out the importance of addressing all the elements in order to form a more complete picture. THE LOCUS Foreign Policy is, by no means, an isolated event that can be analysed outside of its social context. That is even more important in the case of the UN, seen that the organisation deals, in principle, with the whole world and ought to consider the planet as a unity. In the case of countries and nation-states, there is little problem separating the foreigner from the domestic, even with the current advances of globalisation, one can easily determine which are the official relations of a given state. Considering that Hill‘s 76 definition of foreign policy only considers the sum of official external relations of an independent actor, the globalisation does not change that countries usually have few sources which conduct their official external relations. In this sense, national frontiers and national bureaucracy still counts a lot towards defining the external and the domestic. Departments of State, Ministries of Foreign Affairs and their similar represent the obvious places to search for the official external relations of a country. FPA also considers different sources for the formation of the official external relations of a given 73 Hilsman, R. The Politics of Policy Making in Defense and Foreign Affairs: Conceptual Models and Bureaucratic Politics (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc, 1987). 74 Hudson, V. M. Foreign Policy Analysis: Classic and Contemporary Theory. (Lanham: Rowan & Littlefield Publishers, Inc, 2007). 75 Ibid. 76 Hill, C. The Changing Politics of Foreign Policy. (New York: Palgrave Macmilliam, 2003) 32 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 country. For instance, Hilsman77 believes that one important role of a president is to be their nation main diplomat, echoing the concept of presidential diplomacy and the growing importance of foreign relations to the domestic scenario and the president. In that sense, even if the characters and the post they occupy have different names, the functions and limitations are the same across state borders. The dispersion of authority on foreign relations, as takes place in the Unites States, in the relationship between the State and Defense Departments and the National Security Council, does not melt away the concentration and location of the official external relations. The complication arises when we take into consideration an international organisation which is open to all ‗peace-loving countries, a requirement that barely serves as a real pre-condition for membership. In the United Nations, each country has the responsibility to have a representative in the organisation; this representative is a part of the official external relations of each individual country. In that regard, as Berger and Luckmann78 would put, there is the formation of specific interaction environment in which diplomats from different countries are in the same social context. Therefore, those diplomats develop a common socialisation pattern which encompasses the behaviour and choices of words that have became characteristic of the United Nations. A great example is the language of the resolutions that emerged in the United Nations Security Council that has specific sentences that are part of the social consensus of the organisation. Another example is the set of rules of procedure of the UN that have spilled out to other organisations, there is also the ocean of acronyms and abbreviations that requires even growing lists. Further on, a former Permanent Representative of the United States, stated that the UN is a place ‗with its own language and time zone, where ‗demand‘ means ‗ask‘, ‗strong‘ means ‗not so strong‘ and ‗severe‘ means ‗not so severe‘ and ‗urges‘ means ‗begs‘‘79. The UN developed, through time and social interaction, a large set of idiosyncrasies which includes the different rituals of the organisation, as the procedure for the opening of the annual session of the General Assembly, or the format of every 77 Hilsman, R. The Politics of Policy Making in Defense and Foreign Affairs: Conceptual Models and Bureaucratic Politics (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc, 1987). 78 Berger, P. L. and Luckmann, T. The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. (New York: Anchor Books, 1966). 79 Holbrooke apud Fasulo, L. An Insider’s Guide to the UN. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004). pp.91. 33 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 resolution of the organisation with the same typology font and spatial organisation. In that fashion, the bearers of official external discourse of each country mould themselves and their discourse to the international patterns represented by the UN, forming a culture on its own. In that sense, Shawn80 explores how the unique culture and sense of belonging of press corps of the United Nations plays a role in not properly investigating the oil for food scandal, pointing out that press corps did not played its role in the democratic societies of seeking accountability from politicians. Further on, Shawn81 explores how economic interests toppled the values in the case of Iraq, demonstrating how the interaction in the organisation created a culture on its own. Gold82 on the other hand explores how the United Nations was capable to undermine the situation of the Israeli representation in the organisation. This example demonstrates how the interaction among the diplomats inside the UN could form a culture that is even capable of undermining one country. Tabor83 in his turn explores how the UN culture is out of touch with national sovereignty and aims at the expansion of its role in the world. Those three examples serve to cement the idea of a unique culture within the United Nations‘ walls. This unique culture allows us to determine what would be foreign to the United Nations community and what would be domestic. In that regard, as put forward by Walker84, there is the discursive formation of a unique inside and a unique outside, defined by the practises of the organisation. In that fashion, this work argues that there is the construction of a domestic scenario for the United Nations in the figure of the diplomats that work there and share the same discursive instruments. Whereas the foreign of the United Nations can be thought to be the world outside the walls of the UN buildings, the world that receives the resolutions of the organisation and where the blue helmets deploy. In that sense, one could put forward that the United Nations has the world adapted to its culture when in the confines of its buildings and in the same sense 80 Walker, R.B.J. Inside/outside: International Relations as Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993). 81 Ibid. 82 Gold, D. Tower of Babble: How the United Nations has Fueled Global Chaos. (New York: Crown Forum, 2004). 83 Tabor, N. The Beast on the East River: The UN Threat to America’s Sovereignty and Security (Nashville: Nelson Current, 2006). 84 Walker, R.B.J. Inside/outside: International Relations as Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993). 34 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 the whole world is foreign to the organisation. This understanding is reinforced by the common sense that portraits the organisation as an independent actor in many of the news around the globe. Further on, one has to consider the role of a diplomat that works in the UN inside their own government. This diplomat does represent a specific political view inside a Ministry of Foreign Affairs, the views of the United Nations and her bureaucracy, just as the Ambassador to Sri Lanka represents the demands that this country has towards his or her own country. In this sense, the domestic of the United Nations can be said to reach the domestic level of every member-state. Nevertheless, the contact between the UN domestic and a given country‘s domestic scenario is limited to the participants of that countries mission to the UN and even the other diplomats of the country are already in the foreign sphere of the organisation. Therefore, there is a limit of reach in the organisation in the composition of its domestic and foreign spheres and both spheres are in direct contact with its member-states. INSTITUTIONALISING THE FOREIGN The United Nations organisational chart represents the easiest form to have glimpse at the bureaucratic complexity that is the world body.85 The important element of the organisational chart is that each and every body that composes the United Nations System has individual capacity to construct foreign policy. Further more, each of them represent a part in the sum of official external relations of which Hill86 considers. One can consider that the capacity of a UN body to affect the sum of official external relations of the organisation as whole is equivalent to the capacity of any given ministry, with the exception of a Ministry of Foreign Affairs. In this fashion, every organisation within the United Nations was the capacity of issuing documents that can be considered to be part of the official external relations of the UN. Nevertheless, due to the very characteristics of the United Nations, mainly regarding voting procedures within its bodies, there can be divergent voices inside the official external relations of the organisation. For instance it is possible that a specialised body such as the Human Rights Council, emits a resolution 85 86 United Nations Organization. The United Nations System: Principal Organs. (New York: UN,2007), Hill, C. The Changing Politics of Foreign Policy. (New York: Palgrave Macmilliam, 2003) 35 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 that is contradictory or even disregard the considerations from the United Nations Security Council or from the Secretary-General himself. Those contradictions, as one might call it, are not problematic to the analysis and should be treated as part of a healthy democratic debate. Furthermore, those contradictions do exist in every country in the form of debates among the advisors that help shaped parts of the foreign policy. It is as common as for undersecretaries in the Department of State of the United States of America to have disagreements amongst themselves as it is among countries. There is no dividing difference between the debate that takes place in the General Assembly and in the confines of a national government. One might argue that the organisation is different, as are the procedures, but this does not disqualify the debate in the international forum as one that seeks to build a policy for the body. The organisation of a debate does not disqualify the process, the very process could take place in a non-democratic country and it would still be a policy-making process. Nonetheless, the duty of harmonising the internal voices of the United Nations, as it takes place in the government, relies in the executive, in the case, the Office of the Secretary General and the figure of the Secretary General, which will be addressed in due moment. The UN Charter divides the organisation into six main bodies, namely as defined in article 7, the General Assembly, the Security Council, the Economic and Social Council, the Trusteeship Council, the International Court of Justice and the Secretariat.87 From those bodies, with the exceptions of the Trusteeship Council and the International Court of Justice, emerge countless organisations which are related to one or more of the four bodies. One good example of this in the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change which reports to the United Nations Environment Programme, a program under the General Assembly, and the World Meteorological Organisation, a specialised agency under the umbrella of the Economic and Social Council. In a way, all the organisations under the United Nations reports to one or more of the four main bodies that compose the constellation of the organisation. The organisational chart in itself does not account to all the bodies that exist under the brand of the UN, nonetheless it gives a good overview of the size and complexity of the organisation‘s bureaucracy. Even with 87 United Nations Organization. Charter of the United Nations and Statute of the International Court of Justice. New York: UNDPI, 2003. 36 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 the size and complexity, all of these bodies ought to be responsive the UN purposes and values as stated by the UN Charter and the different directives issued by the Secretary General since ―An Agenda for Peace‖.88 All things considered, the task of maintaining a coherent foreign policy line for the organisation falls to the Office of the Secretary General and the Secretary General himself. SECRETARY OF THE GENERAL Whether he considers himself as such or not, the Secretary General, similar to the figure of a President, is the face of the organisation for the world and the general public. Therefore, the role of granting coherence and unity to the foreign policy falls, in a large part, on him and the people that work directly for him. The Secretary General has at least 15 organisations, among departments and organs, which are directly connected to his Office, a number that is comparable to the number of ministries of a country. In that regard, the head of the UN has at his disposal a number of tools, including a Department of Public Information that publishes a number of documents, to guarantee that his message will be the one to be considered the official from the organisation. Furthermore, one can draw analogies between the organisation of the Office of the Secretary General and the bureaucratic organisation of a country that can be helpful to elucidating how the foreign policy apparatus would work in the UN. Three institutions demand special attention in the organisation of the Office of the Secretary General, which are the Department of Peacekeeping Operations (DPKO), the Department of Political Affairs (DPA) and the Chiefs Executives Board for Cooperation (CEB). The Department of Peacekeeping Operations is analogous to a Ministry of Defense in the sense that it is department with the duty of overseeing the military engagements of the organisation and determining parameters for those, such as the rules of engagement. Duties close to the one of a Ministry of Defense in the national bureaucratic scheme. This is not a perfect analogy, but suffices in the arrangement of the UN due to the construction of a chain of command and the preparation for military 88 United Nations An Agenda for Peace: Preventive Diplomacy, Peacemaking and Peace-keeping. (UN, 1992) 37 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 action. The lack of proper military force is not enough to dismiss the bureaucratic functions that the DPKO shares with a national Ministry of Defense, seen that the bureaucratic part of the process that gives the civilian oversight required. Furthermore, the DPKO represents in practical terms the main idea of keeping peace and international security in the world, as stated in the UN Charter, therefore upholding the main goal of the organisation. In this regard, the organisation puts forward that the ‗(…) UN peacekeeping goals were primarily limited to maintaining ceasefires and stabilising situations on the ground, so that efforts could be made at the political level to resolve the conflict by peaceful means‘89. The Department of Political Affairs, on the other hand, is analogous to the Department of State of the United States of America. The DPA does not have the same authoritative capabilities of a Ministry of Foreign Affairs, which normally tends to concentrate most of the foreign policy related initiatives at large within a government, but rather the analogous capacity of conducting and guiding diplomacy across the United Nations system, as takes place in the United States with the Department of State. The Department itself describes its function as: The Department of Political Affairs plays a central role in these [preventing deadly conflicts] efforts: monitoring and assessing global political developments; advising the U.N. Secretary-General on actions that could advance the cause of peace; providing support and guidance to U.N. peace envoys and political missions in the field; and serving Member States directly through electoral assistance and through the support of DPA staff to the work of the Security Council and other U.N. bodies.90 The most interesting portion is the advisory capability of the DPA, which means that they have access to the Secretary General, which as Hilsman (1987) would argue, is necessary for having influence over policy. 89 90 United Nations United Nations Peacekeeping (UN, 2008) United Nations The Department of Political Affairs. (UN, 2009a), INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 38 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 The Chief Executives Board is the UN proxy of a presidential cabinet or a national security council, despite being excluded from the organisational chart. 91 As its function, The Chief Executives Board (CEB) furthers coordination and cooperation on a whole range of substantive and management issues facing United Nations system organisations. CEB brings together on a regular basis the executive heads of the organisations of the United Nations system, under the chairmanship of the Secretary General of the United Nations.92 Therefore, the goal of the CEB is to achieve system-wide coherence, which can be understood as the unity in the official external relations, guaranteeing a form of control for the Secretary General to issue the message he deems appropriate for the organisation. CONCLUSION Looking beneath the forum-like structure of the United Nations reveals a dense bureaucratic web capable of, not only, organising meetings, but also of producing foreign policy on its own capacity. Furthermore, one has to take into consideration that the Secretary General‘s power of agenda setting, as granted by the UN Charter, is important for shaping the political process in the organisation. Regardless of the outcome of the political debate, within any of the three debate-oriented bodies of the UN (General Assembly, Security Council and Economical and Social Council), the Secretariat has the capacity of determining goals for the organisation and by publicising them, as in the case of ―An Agenda for Peace‖. To that extent one can say, with property, that the organisation has the instruments to forge its own foreign policy. Whether those capabilities are used, or if they are used properly in accordance with the UN Charter is not in the goal of this work, the point is to highlight the institutional capabilities for constructing an independent foreign policy. Capacities that are present strongly in the 91 92 United Nations The United Nations System: Principal Organs. (UN, 2007), United Nations The Chief Executives Board (CEB). (UN, 2009b), INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 39 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Office of the Secretary General and ought to be observed. Furthermore, one important aspect of the UN that differentiates it from the regular foreign policy construction of the State-nation is the characterisation of what would be foreign and what would be domestic. Through this work, it was exposed that the composition of the domestic scenario on the organisation is largely confined to the walls of the organisation‘s buildings, whereas the whole world is foreign to the organisation. The extent of the foreign aspect for the organisation is crucial due to the fact that it allows them to navigate in any issue they judge to be important. All in all the United Nations is not only capable of producing its own foreign policy, considering the institutions in place, but is also able to access a large scope of subjects, having an agenda that can encompass basically any aspect of human life in society. Additionally, the foreign policy of the United Nations can bring the international attention to situations that were not of concern before or catapult those situations to the international media, as it has done with global warming, for instance.93 REFERENCES Berger, P. L.; and Luckmann, Thomas. The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Anchor Books, 1966. Checkel, J. T. ―Constructivism and foreign policy‖. In Foreign Policy: Theories, Actors, Cases, edited by Smith, S.; Hadfield, A.; Dunne, T., 71-80. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. Fasulo, L. An Insider’s Guide to the UN. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004. Gold, D. Tower of Babble: How the United Nations has Fueled Global Chaos. New York: Crown Forum, 2004. Halperin, M. H. Bureaucratic Politics & Foreign Policy. Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution, 1974. 93 Tabor, N. The Beast on the East River: The UN Threat to America’s Sovereignty and Security. Nashville: Nelson Current, 2006. 40 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Hill, C. The Changing Politics of Foreign Policy. New York: Palgrave Macmilliam, 2003. Hilsman, R. The Politics of Policy Making in Defense and Foreign Affairs: Conceptual Models and Bureaucratic Politics. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc, 1987. Hudson, V. M. ―Foreign Policy Analysis: Actor-Specific Theory and the Ground of International Relations‖. Foreign Policy Analysis Vol.1, no.1 (2005): 1-30. Hudson, V. M. Foreign Policy Analysis: Classic and Contemporary Theory. Lanham: Rowan & Littlefield Publishers, Inc, 2007. Shawn, E. The U.N. Exposed: How the United Nations Sabotages America’s Security and Fails the World. New York: Sentinel, 2006. Smith, S., Hadfield, A., Dunne, T. Foreign Policy: Theories, Actors, Cases. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. Snyder, R.C., Bruck, H.W., Sapin, B. Foreign Policy Decision-Making. 1962. Revisited by: Hudson, V.M., Chollet, D.H., Goldgeier, J.M. New York: Palgrave Macmilan, 2002. Tabor, N. The Beast on the East River: The UN Threat to America’s Sovereignty and Security. Nashville: Nelson Current, 2006. United Nations An Agenda for Peace: Preventive Diplomacy, Peacemaking and Peacekeeping. New York: United Nations, 1992, http://www.un.org/Docs/SG/agpeace.html (accessed 15 March 2009). United Nations Charter of the United Nations and Statute of the International Court of Justice. New York: UNDPI, 2003. United Nations The United Nations System: Principal Organs. New York: United Nations, 2007, http://www.un.org/aboutun/chart_en.pdf, (accessed 11 March 2009) United Nations United Nations Peacekeeping New York: United Nations, 2008. http://www.un.org/Depts/dpko/dpko/index.asp (accessed 15 March 2009). United Nations The Department of Political Affairs New York: United Nations, 2009a, http://www.un.org/Depts/dpa/intro.html (accessed 15 March 2009). United Nations The Chief Executives Board (CEB) New York: United Nations, 2009b, http://www.unsystemceb.org/reference/ceb (accessed 15 March 2009). INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 41 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Walker, R.B.J. Inside/outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. WHY STRAUSSIANISM? John Hickman ABSTRACT This article explores the explanations for Straussianism, the ‘ideology for elites’ articulated by arch-conservative political philosopher Leo Strauss. Why would ambitious American elites ever embrace an ideology whose founder is tainted by his affiliation with figures foreign and authoritarian? Although American academia is relatively tolerant of heterodox ideas, American politics is not. Yet many Straussians have been appointed to political offices responsible for public policy making. In addition to the pleasures of textual interpretation, satisfaction in belonging to an intellectual elite, and membership in an academic-bureaucratic mutual aid network, being a Straussian offers the individual intellectual license to exercise the loyalty option: fervent demonstrations of loyalty to current organisational leadership. Unlike the voice or exit options, the loyalty option offers Straussians the opportunity to rise in the leaderships of well established but declining organisations. The ability of avoid or deflect responsibility for poor performance is at a premium in such organisations. Straussianism as political philosophy has been explained. There may be little agreement about the value of the intellectual contributions made by University of Chicago political philosopher Leo Strauss, but their content presents no more mystery for scholars than they do interest for the general public. The ‗solution‘ to the problems of modernity 42 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 offered by Strauss and epigones like Allan Bloom and Walter Berns was for intellectual elites in the United States to reclaim the heritage of an essentialised West which they conceived as being embodied in the classical Western canon and then work to prevent the less responsible vulgar masses from succumbing to modernity‘s various isms: communism, anti-Semitism, secularism and scientism. For the next generation of Straussians the list of offensively modern ideological challenges to established institutions grew to include, but is not limited to, multiculturalism, feminism, and ‗radical‘ environmentalism. What has not been explained is the attraction of Straussianism for the extensive and influential network of intellectuals identifiable as the Straussians. That attraction is puzzling because there are other 20th century conservative political philosophers to choose from, Michael Oakeshott for example, who are less alien to the Anglo-American political tradition and untainted by any association with the ideas of the Nazi jurist and political philosopher Carl Schmitt.94 Like Struass, Oakeshott offers a political philosophy critical of empirical science, which would make him attractive to math-phobic students of the humanities.95 This is all the more puzzling because today the most prominent Straussians serve neither as teachers of political philosophy nor in any other capacity in academia. Instead, many hold appointive positions in government, work as journalists or occupy places in the peculiar liminal world of the Washington think tank.96 While the American academy is relatively tolerant of heterodox beliefs, the world beyond its walls is often less forgiving of commitments to ideas deemed foreign and authoritarian. Three partial solutions to the puzzle are facially plausible. The first solution is that the intricacies of textual interpretation – Straussianism is first and foremost a method of reading texts – provide scholars with pleasure in the same way that some laymen are fascinated by the intricacies of baseball statistics or bird watching. Irving Kristol, editor of influential neo-conservative organ The Weekly Standard, describes encountering the ideas of Leo Strauss as a conversion experience in which the student is privileged to 94 N. Xenos, Cloaked in Virtue. (New York: Routledge, 2008). P. Franco, The Political Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990) 96 G. Dorren, Imperial Designs: Neoconservatism and the New Pax Americana (New York: Routledge, 2004); S. M. Hersh, Chain of Command: The Road from 9/11 to Abu Ghraib (New York: Harper Collins, 2004); J. Mann, The Rise of the Vulcans: The History of Bush’s War Cabinet (New York: Viking, 2004). 95 43 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 perceive the modern as the ‗ancients‘ would. Along with imagining that they are capable of channeling the intellectual world of the ancient eastern Mediterranean, the student also imbibes a heavy dose of anti-empiricism.97 Textual interpretation and disdain for rigorous empirical analysis that shades into contempt are also features of Straussianism‘s largely unacknowledged sibling intellectual movement: post-modernism. The flaw in this first solution is that there are no networks of amateur baseball statisticians, bird watchers and even post-modern deconstructionists linking government, journalism and academia. The second solution is that some intellectuals are attracted to Straussianism because they enjoy its self-conscious and self-defined elitism, in the same way that Victorian British elites might take satisfaction in belonging to exclusive London gentlemen‘s clubs like the Traveller‘s Club or East India Club, or in the same way that cliques of ‗sneaker-heads‘ with collections of expensive limited edition tennis shoes might take pride in their collections. Part of the satisfaction of being recognised as a Straussian by fellow Starussians is that the vulgar masses, who ought not to be exposed to philosophy in any event, cannot gain admission to the magic circle of the like minded. Like the post-modernists dominant in the English departments of American universities and colleges, the Straussians disdain communicating the core ideas of their political philosophy to the masses, not the least because the masses would find it irrelevant, annoying or distasteful. That natural science and universal education are primarily responsible for modern problems is a claim no more acceptable to the majority of Americans than the post-modern moral relativism that everything is text. Unlike the post-modernists, however, the Straussians are interested in what the masses think, or more importantly, might be persuaded to think. Philosophical understanding should not be disclosed to the masses lest it undermine the political order that makes the life of the philosopher and philosophic inquiry possible. Instead, it could and perhaps should be used to shape political events, if at a safe remove. The conviction that the masses must not be instructed in the philosophic insights is of course a rather silly conceit. Even when Strauss first began communicating his ‗dangerous truths‘ to his students, there were already far too many competing philosophies, ideologies and theologies for any one of them to undermine the political order by enlightening the masses. That Straussianism 97 I. Kristol, Neoconservatism: The Autobiography of an Idea. (New York: The Free Press, 1995). 44 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 was capable of doing serious damage to public trust in government as an ‗ideology of elites‘ is both evident from the disastrous record of the second Bush administration and something Leo Strauss failed to caution against. The third solution is that the Straussians are members of a mutual-aid network. Halper and Clarke note that the network of political associations emanating from the University of Chicago in the 1970s present a framework of interrelated biographies for many of those considered to be among the rank and file of today‘s neo-conservatives.‘98 That Straussians club together is no secret. However they do more than merely socialise. In university philosophy and political science departments, the Straussians propagate themselves and their creed by directing the resources of the departments they enter, particularly when making hiring decisions, and encouraging a focus on the personalities, methods and issues that other Straussians deem important. Such attention is good for Straussian academic careers, especially the careers of figures who would otherwise find the competitive work of getting published in peer reviewed journals too daunting. Straussians appointed to high public office use their own powers of appointment and recommendation to help the careers of fellow Straussians rise in political prominence. Straussians working as journalists in news sources or biding their time in think tanks engage in similar behaviors. In many respects, the Straussian network operates in much the same manner as an ethnic niche. Opportunities for advancement are effectively hoarded for members of the network. That so many of the leading lights among the Straussians are identifiable as members of American white ethnic groups—Eastern European Jews and Irish or Italian Roman Catholics—reinforces the impression that their universalistic moralising conceals a rather ordinary parochialism and individual ambition. The impression left is of individuals whose immigrant parents or grandparents suffered social discrimination in pre-war America and now feel compelled to thunder their gratitude at having been allowed into the once prohibited halls of power and privilege by denouncing members of other, non-white ethnic minority groups who are still outside and demanding admission without having ‗paid their dues‘. Heilbrunn, for example, notes 98 S. Halper and J. Clarke, America Alone: The Neo-Conservatives and the Global Order (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004) pp. 67. 45 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 that Cornell became an academic hotbed of Struassianism because of what some white faculty perceived as the thuggish politics of the Afro-American Society.99 That gratitude may be tinged with a measure of guilt. Some neoconservatives are former Trotskyists or their offspring who marched had ideologically from anti-Stalinism to liberal anti-communism and then onward to neo-conservatism.100 As many Cold War defectors learned, confessing one‘s guilt and asking for forgiveness offers political opportunity. Repudiation of their former leftist political identities is an unending process for some neoconservatives, because it serves as a vehicle to claim special authority on the subject of political tyranny. A fourth and more complete answer is that Straussianism is attractive to its adherents less as a philosophy for the reflective individual than as an ideology suited to the operation of a network of ambitious elites, whose members seek to rise within the leaderships of well established institutions. Straussians occur more frequently in organisations that have reached at their zenith or that have begun to decline, rather than in organisations are still being constructed. Their textual analysis skills make them better suited to the climb up the hierarchies of venerable organisations than younger organisations where innovation is more in demand. There is more to this fourth argument but before elaborating it two challenges merit response. The argument that Straussianism is an ‗ideology for elites‘ rather than a philosophy may be challenged because it is not addressed to the masses, a characteristic common to modern ideologies. The problem with that challenge is that the alternative conclusion that it is a philosophy is even weaker. Ideologies are widely understood to offer an analysis of present conditions, a vision of better future conditions, and a plan for achieving such future conditions. During the 20th century, notes Richard Ashcraft, political philosophy became identified with abstract discussions of ‗timeless truths‘ and ‗perennial questions‘ in opposition to its deployment as political ideology, ‗as a weapon or guide to practical action in the hands of a political group, party or class‘.101 Strauss 99 J. Heilbrunn ―The Neoconservative Journey,‖ in P. Berkowitz, ed., Varieties of Conservatism in America. (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2004), p. 119 100 H. Wolford The Mighty Wurlitzer: How the CIA Played America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2008) 101 Richard Ashcraft, ―Political Theory and the Problem of Ideology.‖ The Journal of Politics. Vol. 42 no. 3. (1980), pp. 687-705, 602. 46 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 was among those leading the condemnation of the use of political philosophy as ideology. Yet that condemnation may be understood as an exercise in taqiya, or dissimulation in the presence of threatening power. In fact, Straussianism is simple rather than profound and encourages action rather than inaction, both of which are conventionally understood as characteristics of an ideology. Familiar conservative criticisms of the Enlightenment philosophy and of the negative social effects of modernity based on analyses of the Western classics and the American founding texts that comprise the parochial Straussian canon fail to make it profound. That Straussians covertly instruct one another in the art of advancing their careers by whispering advice in the ears of more powerful elites is hardly the withdrawal into contemplation that marks the traditional philosopher. For Leo Strauss the public duty of the philosopher was to speak in a manner likely to, ‗move the city according to a standard existing outside the city, known to the philosopher and unknown to its citizens, but to do so in a way that seems in accord with the conventions of the city‘102. In effect, the responsibility of the philosopher is to act in much the same manner as a bureaucratic political appointee seeking to make public policy or a foreign intelligence officer seeking to influence elite or mass opinion in a target country. Straussianism thus offers elites in well established organisations the sanction they need to act together in a covert and undemocratic manner to achieve their political goals. Another likely challenge to the argument that Straussianism is an ideology for elites is that when Straussians choose to descend from the realm of philosophy to the realm of the political they simply become neo-conservatives. In effect, Straussianism is a philosophy while neo-conservatism is an ideology. That counter-argument would be stronger if prominent neo-conservatives did not reject the characterisation of neoconservatism as an ideology. Neo-conservatism, from their perspective, emerged because like minded thinkers shared similar opinions about major public policy issues. According to Irving Kristol, neo-conservatism is not a political movement but instead merely a political ‗persuasion‘ recognised only post hoc.103 Just as Strauss insisted on his distinction between philosophy and ideology, Kristol insists on his distinction because the word ‗movement‘ suggests the sort of modernity that neo-conservatives are in the 102 N. Xenos, Cloaked in Virtue. (New York: Routledge, 2008), pp. 27. I. Kristol. ―The Neoconservative Persuasion: What it was and what it is.‖ The Weekly Standard. Vol. 1008 no. 47 (August 25th, 2003). 103 47 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 business of bemoaning. The self-described ‗godfather‘ of the ‗persuasion‘ begins his attempt at a definition by describing its distinctly American temperament. Americans are cheerful and optimistic, he explains, and so too is neo-conservatism. This is contrasted with the dourness and pessimism of the Europeans and other varieties of conservatism. Kristol thus acts as a proper Straussian ought by appealing to the citizens, ‗in accord with the conventions of the city‘. One of those conventions is that Americans think of themselves as an optimistic people imbued with a ‗can-do‘ spirit. Beyond the absurdity of such essentialist reductions of American and European character, it is worth noting that Kristol makes comparison only to Europe. Straussians are dyed in the wool Eurocentrists and as a consequence typically make comparisons only to ideas and events across the Atlantic. Kristol goes on to admit in his essay that neo-conservative domestic policy preferences are essentially those of other American conservatives. They oppose government social welfare spending, support tax cuts, endorse government censorship of pornography, and are suspicious of the separation of church and state. With the eclipse of the paleo-conservatives, the neo-conservative foreign policy preferences identified by Kristol are now effectively identical to the conservative movement. Massive military spending, uninhibited military patriotism and uncritical Zionism are all basic elements.104 This is simply a collection of policy preferences and little different from that held by other conservatives, it is reasonable to see neo-conservatism not as an ideology but as the public mask worn by the underlying ideology: Straussianism. Why would Straussianism appeal to elites? The ideas of another, more pragmatic political philosopher who embraced rather than rejected modernity, Albert O. Hirschman, suggest an answer. In his 1970 essay Exit, Voice and Loyalty, Hirschman laid out the possible options of those involved with large organisations that were encountering challenges and failing to meet expectations, which is to say, nearly all large organisations.105 Faced with poor performance, the employees and customers of firms, the members of interest groups or political parties, and the citizens of nation-states can 104 R. Swansborough. Test by Fire: The War Presidency of George W. Bush (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008). 105 A. O. Hirschman. Exit, Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1970). 48 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 choose to leave the organisation for an alternative, give voice to their unhappiness about the organisation, or express more fervent loyalty to the organisation. The loyalty option is more likely to be selected, according to Hirschman, where the entry barriers to an organisation such as initiation rites are high.106 Penalties for exercising the voice or exit options tend to be high. Political appointees and public intellectuals have typically paid high prices to achieve their statuses. They must survive the rigors of competition for places in their formal organisations and, if they are Straussians, also serve in the informal coteries of more senior Straussians. To exercise the voice option by protesting in place or resigning in protest would be too costly. Membership in a Straussian network results in dependence on the network of employment and access to platforms from which to speak if formal positions in government are lost due to alternation in the party in power, that moment when a new administration brings with it a different cadre of political officials. Exercising the loyalty option is also likely because it serves the ambitious in large organisations that are performing poorly, which is a good general description of the second Bush administration. Consider the career of John P. Walters, a political appointee described as an ‗admirer‘ of Leo Strauss by the Economist.107 Although not trained as a physician, biomedical researcher or law enforcement officer, Walters was appointed as the second Bush administration‘s Director of National Drug Control Policy or ‗Drug Czar‘. His qualifications for that position included having been appointed as chief of drug interdiction under first Bush administration drug czar William Bennett, and of earning a reputation for ‗talking tough‘ about crime while outside government during the Clinton administration. Before his stint as drug tsar, Walters was best known for having coauthored a book with William Bennett and John J. Dilulio, Body Count: Moral Poverty and How to Win America’s War Against Crime and Drugs, that predicted the rise of young urban ‗superpredators‘ destined to terrorise America.108 The authors did not need to state that these menaces to society were African-American or Hispanic because that was implicit in the message. Decoding the charged imagery was not difficult. The 106 Ibid. pp. 92-98 ―Philosophers and Kings.‖ The Economist. Vol. 367, no. 8329. (June 21st, 2003): p. 29. 108 W. Bennett, J. J. Dilulio and J. P. Walters. Body Count: Moral Poverty and How to Win America’s War Against Crime and Drugs (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1996) pp. 26-34. 107 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 49 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 book‘s central policy recommendation was that the United States must overcome the ‗moral poverty‘ that they claimed was the cause of crime by ‗restoring‘ religion in American life. For the authors to have noted that Americans already presented markedly higher rates of religiosity, as measured by claimed church attendance in cross national surveys, than the citizens of most of the other advanced industrial societies, would have detracted from a rhetorical point pleasing to social conservatives. The anticipated waves of superpredators failed to materialise but did not prevent Walters from being appointed drug tsar. As Drug Czar, Walters was unwavering in his assertion that the government was winning the drug war. Rather than answer the criticism that the legal prohibition has caused much of the social harm associated with drug use, he was content to insist that drugs such as marijuana were harmful to users and that prohibition was necessary to authorise the state to act on their behalf.109 Walters also exaggerated specific drug threats in an effort to elicit public support for prohibition. In 2008 his office issued press releases warning of a ‗dangerous new drug threat coming from Canada‘ that Walters tagged as ‗Extreme Ecstasy‘.110 Rather than being a new drug, the substance actually combined the chemically similar methamphetemine and Ecstasy. Although the press reported the announcement, it did not spark much public concern. Walters‘ moral panic may have failed to launch because the source of the drug was insufficiently threatening. Successful moral panics about drugs in American history have been fueled by anxiety about exotic racial or ethnic minorities perceived as outside the moral community.111 Canadians do not fit that description even when laboring in drug labs. Although its anti-empiricism operates as an intellectual prophylactic to understanding the economic, scientific and technical bases for entire realms of public policy making, the textual interpretation skills taught by the Straussians are useful for adherents because the management of powerful organisations in decline is one of manipulating meaning to minimise responsibility for decisions incompetently made and 109 J. P. Walters ―No Surrender.‖ National Review. Vol. 56, no. 18 (September 27th, 2004) pp. 41-42. Office of National Drug Control Policy Press Release ―Canadian-Made, Meth-Laced Ecstasy Being Dumped into U.S. Illegal Drug Markets.‖ January 3rd, 2008. 111 Nachman Ben-Yehuda. ―The Sociology of Moral Panics: Toward a New Synthesis.‖ The Sociological Quarterly Vol. 27, no. 4 (1986) pp. 495-513; D. Streatfield. Cocaine: An Unauthorized Biography. (New York: Picador, 2001) pp. 138-173. 110 50 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 executed. There is a premium on organisational leadership that successfully avoids or shifts blame for poor performance rather than innovating when large organisations begin to fail. Consider the work of Douglas Feith, who was appointed the Director of Policy Planning in the Department of Defense under Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld. To explain why his office had proposed rebranding the ‗Global War on Terrorism‘ or GWOT as the ‗Global Struggle against Violent Extremism‘ or GSAVE in early 2005, he stated that ‗terminology is what drives people what people think about this subject…If its called the war on terrorism, they think differently about it then if it‘s called a struggle against violent extremism‘.112 After leaving office he defended his role in planning the disastrous post-war occupation of Iraq during an April 8, 2008 interview on National Public Radio.113 Asked about the criticisms of his role in the planning process levelled in other reports, Feith countered by dismissing them as narratives, ‗that came out of the top levels of the State Department‘. For those trained in textual interpretation, one narrative interpretation is no better than another. When pressed to name who was responsible for the Iraq occupation debacle, Feith attempted to escape by spreading responsibility to the entire U.S. government: ‗I mean, I can give you a captain-of-the-ship type answer, where you say, well, the president is in charge or the secretary of defense is in charge or the national security advisor is in charge. I mean, ultimately, when you're talking about political responsibility in the government, the top people are in charge. That's - but I don't think that was what your question was. I thought your question was where did the decision making process actually break down? And as I said, I only saw my window‘114 Note that the Straussians begin to emerge in their neo-conservative guise as important decision-makers only after the Cold War battles of the 1960s and 1960s had already been waged and become dominant only after the defeat of the Soviet Union. 112 B. Graham. By His Own Rules: The Ambitions, Successes, and Ultimate Failures of Donald Rumsfeld. (New York: Public Affairs, 2009): pp. 547-548. 113 S. Inskeep. ―Feith Regrets Not Pushing ‗Law and Order‘ in Iraq.‖ National Public Radio, Morning Edition. http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=89429658 (April 8th, 2008). 114 Ibid. 51 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 During the 1950s and 1960s, American foreign policy was in the hands of Cold War liberal Democrats or moderate Republicans. The Straussians crop up in positions of power during the Nixon and Ford administrations and re-appear in even larger numbers during the Reagan administration, a moment when international communism Soviet style had lost its appeal as a model. Nor were their other chosen ideological enemies strong when they began to expand their influence in the 1970s. Anti-Semitism was just an ugly memory everywhere but the Middle East and a few pockets of atavistic nationalism in Eastern Europe. Support for Israel has been rock solid in the United States since the Johnson administration. With these enemies vanquished, the Straussians went hunting for domestic monsters to slay and joined the assault of the religious Right on multiculturalism, feminism, secularism and scientism. However it was the events of September 11th, 2001 that reinvigorated the Straussians by giving them a worthy international ideological enemy: Islamism. Here the comparison between Straussianism and Islamism is useful. Peter Demant describes Islamism as, ‗a reaction against modernity produced by modernity, during modern times, using modern means, and irreversibly partaking of modernity‘.115 That description also fits Straussianism. Like the Islamists, Straussians see themselves not as establishing a new order but as restoring an older and better order. If they seek a less radical transformation of the existing order, they do so from within the engine of modernity rather than outside it. The Straussian mission is to give conservative purpose to the immense power over nature created by modernity. Here the analogy between the Straussians and the Islamists crumbles. Where the Straussians seek to exercise power over mass publics who know they benefit, and benefit handsomely, from modernity, the Islamists seek to exercise power over mass publics who do not know they benefit, and have not benefited handsomely, from modernity. The obvious historical analogy to the Straussians is to the education in the Classics among Victorian era British elites, which sought inspiration for the brutal business of maintaining an empire from the Roman example.116 Classical education has 115 P. R. Demant Islam vs. Islamism: The Dilemma of the Muslim World (Westport, CT: Praeger, 2006), pp. 181. 116 F. Campbell ―Latin and the Elite Tradition in Education.‖ The British Journal of Sociology. Vol. 19, no. 3 (1968) pp. 311-313. 52 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 long been a salient feature of the amateur tradition among senior civil servants in Britain. Latin provided not only a means for distinguishing elites from masses but some of the Classics provided philosophic justification for government decisions recognisable as morally repugnant to the uninitiated. This is reinforced by what Norton has described as the distorted, positive image of British imperialism common among neo-conservatives.117 Barnett condemns the Arnoldian emphasis on the Classics and the certainties of Evangelical Christianity in the British elite education for undermining the pragmatism that had made Britain the greatest power of its time. The result was an elite incapable of adapting to international challenge in the Twentieth century. ‗In an epoch that required in men the itch to develop, create and exploit, school had fostered (especially in its prefects) a habit of routine administration-cautious ‗responsibility‘ rather than the taking of risk. Where continued British success and survival depended on innovation and open-mindedness, school admired conservatism and conformism—loyalty to what existed‘.118 Perhaps the best historical analogy is to the Neo-Confucian literati of late Qing dynasty China.119 Like contemporary Straussians, the humanist intellectuals who ruled the 19th century Chinese Empire were masters of textual analysis, albeit of a different Classical canon. Chinese intellectuals were granted authority as Mandarins by demonstrating their mastery of the Confucian canon in competitive examinations requiring interpretation. They too inherited rather than constructed a powerful state— from the once dynamic Jurchen cum Manchus who established the Qing dynasty—and made it their business to preserve the empire by protecting what they perceived as the best in its cultural traditions and social institutions. The Neo-Confucian literati failed China, though not their own careers however, by their inability to sponsor lasting 117 A. Norton Leo Strauss and the Politics of American Empire. (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2004 ) pp. 129-130. 118 C. Barnett, The Collapse of British Power. (Atlantic, NJ: Humanities Press, 1986) pp. 37. 119 M. Clabaugh Wright, The Last Stand of Chinese Conservatism: The T’ung-Chih Restoration, 18621874 ( Stanford CA: Stanford University Press, 1957) pp. 69-70. 53 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 technological industrial innovation. Like contemporary Straussians, they held empirical science and engineering in contempt as lesser forms of intellectual endeavor unworthy of gentlemen. Very large, very powerful organisations sometimes take a very long time to collapse and ambitious elites may achieve professional success by climbing to the top of decaying organisations. The Qing dynasty would survive the rebellions of the 19 th century before finally collapsing in 1911 due to the incompetence and corruption of its rulers and aggression by more modern foreign powers. Until the regime‘s collapse, the loyalty option remained the most rational choice for the ambitious Chinese elites. Straussianism has attracted ambitious American elites for precisely the same reasons. REFERENCES Ashcraft, R. ―Political Theory and the Problem of Ideology.‖ The Journal of Politics. Vol. 42, no. 3. (1980): pp. 687-705. Barnett, C. The Collapse of British Power. Atlantic, NJ: Humanities Press, 1986. Ben-Yehuda, N. ―The Sociology of Moral Panics: Toward a New Synthesis‖ The Sociological Quarterly. Vol. 27, no. 4 (1986): pp. 495-513. Bennett, W., Dilulio, J.J. and Walters, J.P. Body Count: Moral Poverty and How to Win America’s War Against Crime and Drugs. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1996. Campbell, F. ―Latin and the Elite Tradition in Education.‖ The British Journal of Sociology. Vol. 19, no. 3 (1968): pp. 308-325. Clabaugh Wright, M. The Last Stand of Chinese Conservatism: The T’ung-Chih Restoration, 1862-1874. Stanford CA: Stanford University Press, 1957. Demant, P. R., Islam vs. Islamism: The Dilemma of the Muslim World. Westport, CT: Praeger, 2006. Doren, G. Imperial Designs: Neoconservatism and the New Pax Americana. New York: Routledge, 2004. Economist, The ―Philosophers and Kings.‖ The Economist. vol. 367, no. 8329 (June 21st, 2003): pp. 29. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 54 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Franco, P. The Political Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990. Graham, B. By His Own Rules: The Ambitions, Successes, and Ultimate Failures of Donald Rumsfeld. New York: Public Affairs, 2009: pp. 547-548. Halper, S. and Clarke, J.. America Alone: The Neo-Conservatives and the Global Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Heilbrunn, J. ―The Neoconservative Journey,‖ In Varieties of Conservatism in America, edited by P. Berkowitz, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2004, pp. 105128. Hersh, S. M., Chain of Command: The Road from 9/11 to Abu Ghraib. New York: Harper Collins, 2004. Hirschman, A. O., Exit, Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1970. Inskeep, S. ―Feith Regrets Not Pushing ‗Law and Order‘ in Iraq.‖ National Public Radio, Morning Edition. (April 8th, 2008). http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=89429658 Accessed April 9th, 2008. Kristol, I. Neoconservatism: The Autobiography of an Idea. New York: The Free Press, 1995. Kristol, I. ―The Neoconservative Persuasion: What it was and what it is.‖ TheWeekly Standard. vol. 1008, no. 47 (August 25th, 2003). Mann, J. The Rise of the Vulcans: The History of Bush’s War Cabinet. New York: Viking, 2004. Norton, A. Leo Strauss and the Politics of American Empire. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2004. Office of National Drug Control Policy Press Release: ―Canadian-Made, Meth-Laced Ecstasy Being Dumped into U.S. Illegal Drug Markets‖ January 3 rd, 2008. www.whitehousedrugpolicy.gov/news/press08/010308.htnm Accessed July 30th, 2009. Streatfield, D. Cocaine: An Unauthorized Biography. New York: Picador, 2001. 55 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Swansborough, R. Test by Fire: The War Presidency of George W. Bush. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008. Walters, J. P., ―No Surrender.‖ National Review. Vol. 56, no. 18 (September 27th, 2004): pp. 41-42. Xenos, N. Cloaked in Virtue. New York: Routledge, 2008. PUBLIC ETHICS CASE STUDY: THE CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY OF GOLDMAN SACHS Jacob Kloeveroed Griffiths INTRODUCTION In 2008 Goldman Sachs received $10bn of US taxpayer‘s money, and at the same time the bank admitted that it had a bonus pot of $2.6bn for its executives.120 Though the concern in this case study is not pay equity, it is important to establish whether the employees at Goldman Sachs can legitimately claim their excessive remuneration in these circumstances. The main purpose of this paper is to examine whether the bank has a moral responsibility to other stakeholders, especially in the light of the burdens which the recession is putting on the rest of society. The theoretical starting point is Friedman‘s notion that the only responsibility of business is profit maximisation.121 This idea has formed the basis for a free market regulation paradigm in neoclassical economics and has indeed formed the basis of the politics that has governed globalisation since the 1980s. This system appears to have failed in the financial sector. 120 J. Robinson, J. Treanor, ―Anger over £6.4bn bonus bonanza at four City banks‖, The Observer, November 1st, 2009, 121 M. Friedman ―The Social Responsibility of Business to increase its Profits‖, in T.L. Beauchamp and N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001). 56 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 The essay will argue that the scope of Friedman‘s business ethics is too narrow. As the impact of banks on society is so significant, the range of concerns they need to address is wider than Friedman assumes. Firstly, it will be shown that both theoretically and practically Friedman and the stockholder thesis does not hold, as it does not adequately incorporate externalities and wrongly assumes perfect competition as well as conflicting with virtue ethics. Secondly, the stakeholder thesis will be discussed. While taking a broader approach, this alternative theory could potentially damage private property rights and will be found to be unclear. Thirdly, an attempt will be made to incorporate both private property rights with a wider notion of ethics. The syntheses will be made using Kantian ethics. This will also demonstrate the limitations in Friedman‘s work, but allow his concerns for profits to be preserved. However, before the main argument can be advanced, Friedman‘s concequentialist position will be outlined with an argument legitimising high remuneration based on freedom. The essay is philosophically committed to disputing Friedman‘s position, but also examines practical economic arrangement in society. It is an investigation into Goldman Sachs's moral responsibility, though it must be viewed in the context of a critique of neoclassical economics in the finance crisis of 2008 and public ethics and Corporate Social Responsibility (CSR) generally. AN OUTLINE OF FRIEDMAN’S ARGUMENT REGARDING TO REMUNERATION Friedman‘s main argument is that business ethics is solely a relationship between managers and owners. However, popular interpretations of Friedman suggest that his theory is devoid of ethical considerations. These readings reflect a misconception of what Friedman actually says.122 Although he argues the only moral obligation of managers is profit maximisation for owners, he does not condone all behaviour that increases financial returns. Quite explicitly, he places four restrictions on profit seeking: business people must obey the law, follow ethical customs, commit no deception or fraud, and engage in open and free competition.123 For Friedman, social responsibility means 122 J. Harvey, ―Smith, Friedman, and Self-Interest in Ethical Society‖, Business Ethics Quarterly, Vol. 10, no. 3. (2000) 123 Ibid. 57 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 pursuing one's interests without interfering with the legally protected freedom of others. In Baron‘s framework of a three way approach to ethics: concequentialist, virtue and Kantian, Friedman should be considered a concequentialist because he believes that by limiting the responsibility of companies the consequence will be a free society124. Though the different natures of the approaches mean they cannot automatically be contrasted, from a virtue ethics position Friedman undermines the inner characteristic of human morality and also from a Kantian perspective it is problematic to justify a policy on the basis that it is morally obligatory because it produces the best outcomes, it is principles that count.125 Paradoxically though, Friedman advocates a free society as the highest principle, whereas in Kantian ethics there could be potential conflicting principles, for instance if the maintaining of a free society required the killing of an opponent of it. The principles of a free society and principle of everyone‘s freedom to live would contradict, so Kantian ethics could be criticised because it prescribes no concrete action to get a free society. However, the point of Kantian ethics is that it is concerned with obligatory ends, not obligatory actions.126 On the contrary, Friedman strongly adheres to act-consequentialism; the act of not enforcing more regulation will result in a free society. This sentiment forms the basis for his views on business ethics and ultimately remuneration. His belief in freedom and the responsibility of business being to increase its profits closely resembles, though slightly incorrectly, the interpretation of Smith‘s notion of the invisible hand. This maintains that market participants, in pursuit of their self-interests, unknowingly benefit society. Thus the market is a mechanism which regulates itself to produce the best outcome. Businesses should freely do whatever improves their financial position, even though others could be harmed.127 Thereby limited regulation of remuneration is automatically controlled by the market. If enough customers at Goldman Sachs object to high bonuses, an alternative would be provided and they could choose 124 M. Baron, P. Pettit, M. Slote, Three Methods if Ethics. (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2007) Ibid. 126 Ibid. 127 J. Harvey, ―Smith, Friedman, and Self-Interest in Ethical Society‖, Business Ethics Quarterly, Vol. 10, no. 3. (2000) 125 58 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 another bank. Friedman is advancing that the public good is optimised through individuals pursuing self-interest in a free market. This raises two questions. Firstly, whether the free market does benefit everyone? Friedman‘s answer would be utilitarian, claiming that most people will benefit. 128 The second contestation is whether self-interest is an adequate basis for morality? For Smith and Friedman profit maximising behaviour is not inconsistent with normal ethical values.129 The invisible hand justifies this position. However, for Bowie, concern for one's self-interest is the very heart of behaviour that conflicts with public ethics.130 When self-interest is narrowly interpreted to mean selfishness that is the case. Though, Friedman does not use the concept of self-interest in this narrow sense. For Smith the overriding principle governing his interpretation of self-interest is justice, while for Friedman the principle is freedom. For both writers, self-interest embodies anotherregarding aspect that requires individuals to moderate their actions when others are adversely affected.131 It is this concept of self-interest that Friedman advocates. As the basis for Friedman‘s morality is freedom, it allows individuals to pursue their selfinterest. He believes that a free market is the best system to effectively coordinate people without denying them this freedom. The basic problem of social organisation, explains Friedman, is how to coordinate the economic activities of large numbers of people. 132 He advocates market mechanisms characterised by voluntary exchanges between individuals. Central planning necessarily involves some degree of coercion by the state. For Friedman regulation is inefficient and immoral, it means everyone loses as there would be less profit in society. MacPherson rejects the argument that political freedom requires capitalism133. However, this misses the main point i.e. the state is to be feared 128 N. Barry, The morality of Business Enterprise. (Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press, 1991) Ibid. 130 T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 131 J. Harvey, ―Smith, Friedman, and Self-Interest in Ethical Society‖, Business Ethics Quarterly, Vol. 10, no. 3. (2000) 132 M. Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1962) 133 C. MacPherson, ―Elegant Tombstones: A Note on Friedman's Freedom‖, Canadian Journal of Political Science / Revue canadienne de science politique, Vol. 1, no. 1. (1968) 129 59 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 because it represents a concentration of power to which there is no alternative134. The only positive duty of the bank is to act in the best interests of shareholders. At the same time this duty is constrained by negative duties not to cheat, injure, or lie to all stakeholders. In this way the optimal social coordination can be achieved. From the forgoing analysis of Friedman's view of freedom, his position on CSR can be derived. Since actions that impose involuntary harm on others are unacceptable, the bank‘s actions must be examined in the context of whether they are voluntary and compatible with the freedom of those affected by their decisions. Friedman says that a social responsibility other than to generate as much profit as possible for business owners is a highly ―subversive doctrine‖.135 Bankers have a direct responsibility to conduct business in accordance with their desires, which will be to make as much money as possible while conforming to the basic rules of the society. Furthermore, they have no moral obligation to indulge in any philanthropic activity to help other victims of the credit crisis. They lack the expertise to find the best way to help others. So, Friedman has both teleological and deontological reasons for advancing the thesis that bank executives should pursue only profit, and stay away from actions that purport to promote society's interests.136 On teleological grounds, he argues that it may not be possible for bankers to know what constitutes society's interests. On deontological grounds, Friedman believes that the bank‘s actions, justified as socially responsible, violate specific duties of those pursuing the actions. For example, unless Goldman Sachs obtains the consent of those affected, they violate the duty not to coerce others. If bank executives do not act in the interest of their employer, then they are coercing them into financing a project that the owners might not want. The executive would be spending someone else's money for a general social interest. Business people who claim they have an obligation to desirable social ends are unwittingly puppets of intellectual forces that have been undermining the 134 R. Crowley, ―A Comment on Professor Macpherson's Interpretation of Friedman's ‗Capitalism and Freedom‘‖, Canadian Journal of Political Science / Revue canadienne de science politique, Vol. 2, no. 2. (1969) 135 M. Friedman, ―The Social Responsibility of Business to increase its Profits‖, in T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business. (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001), pp. 401 136 J. Harvey, ―Smith, Friedman, and Self-Interest in Ethical Society‖, Business Ethics Quarterly, Vol. 10, no. 3. (2000) 60 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 basis for a free society.137 Thus, the setting of wages is a decision for shareholders, and any other‘s involvement is a violation of their property rights. Friedman‘s free market view of CSR legitimates high wages if they are the result of a free exchange. The owners of the bank have a right to decide the amount of remuneration. The reason for this is that in a free society an executive is an employee of the owners of the business. Distorting this relationship is damaging and immoral, because it results in lower profits. The price setting mechanism of the free market determines the price someone gets for their labour. Walzer argues that there are problems with allowing markets to dictate wages because of the inequity of power within the market138. However, arguably even from a Friedmanite position the bonuses at Goldman Sachs are not justified. As its market value has been halved, employees appear not to have maximised profits.139 Though, ultimately this is a decision for bank investors to evaluate. Walzer identifies the marketplace as a sphere of justice. Within a certain sphere of justice certain rules apply140. Similarly, Marx claimed that it was nonsensical to criticise capitalism for being unjust because justice was itself a capitalist term.141 The mode of production creates its own moral rules. Thus, an actor in the market knows the mechanism and is entitled to what he gets, but that does not necessarily correspond to any other evaluation of how significant the job is, as demonstrated by Nozick‘s Chamberlain argument. So, in a market system, our remuneration or the price of our labour is our desert. Walzer argues this is to misunderstand the concept of desert, indeed timing and luck are decisive, and business is a chancy business. 142 The remuneration of bank managers can therefore be justified by its free market context. The bonuses are gained in a free market. As Locke argued, labour itself creates the foundation for property rights143. So when accepting the premises of a capitalist economy, as Friedman does, bank managers can legitimately claim their remuneration. 137 M. Friedman, ―The Social Responsibility of Business to increase its Profits‖, in T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business. (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 138 M. Walzer, Spheres of Justice. (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1983) 139 S. Duke, ―Goldman Sachs ready to hand out £7bn salary and bonus package‖, The Daily Mail, 30th October, 2008. 140 M. Walzer, Spheres of Justice. (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1983) 141 K. Marx, Capital. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999) 142 M. Walzer, Spheres of Justice. (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1983) 143 J. Locke, Second Treatise of Government. (Indianapolis: Hacket, 1980) 61 1. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 CRITIQUE OF THE STOCKHOLDER THESIS Friedman is defining a very limited circumstance for applying morality to business decisions. His business ethics state that the shareholder‘s interests are superior to other considerations. There appears to be problems with this neoclassical view. Neither the bank‘s managers nor owners have any obligation to take responsibility for anything other than running a profitable bank. However, banks rely on investors which are technically everyone who holds an account with them, though some investors are more significant than others. Goldman Sachs has also been bailed out with taxpayer funds due to their important role. This raises problems with Friedman‘s argument. Using tax payers‘ money seems to imply a collective ownership, though technically the state is not an owner. Nonetheless, the system Friedman has advocated seems to have failed. There appears to be wider accountability for firm‘s actions than just to stockholders. Friedman does not only assume the opposite, but maintains that accountability is sustained through selfregulation in the market.144 His theory is strongly grounded in a neoclassical framework of economic belief. Central to this are the concepts of externalities, perfect completion and an overarching assumption of market self-regulation and, finally, arrangements relating to the role of management. The aforementioned concepts will now be discussed. Firstly, Friedman dismisses other parties that do not fit into his framework as externalities. An externality says Friedman, is the effect of a transaction on a third party who has not consented to or played any role in the carrying out of that transaction.145 Accordingly, he acknowledges that some restrictions on our freedom are necessary to avoid other, still worse, restrictions.146 However, control of wages would not count as such a condition. So when taxpayer‘s money is used to pay for bonuses instead of, for instance cheaper loans, it is justified by the fact that the democratic US government technically does not own Goldman Sachs and the bank is best suited to running itself. Friedman distinguishes between harm caused by external effects, which he opposes, and the personal consequences of decisions individuals make when they freely enter into 144 T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) J. Bakan, The Corporation (London: Constable, 2004) 146 M. Friedman, ―The Social Responsibility of Business to increase its Profits‖, in T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 145 62 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 risky transactions, such as the remuneration at Goldman Sachs, which he accepts as necessary in a free society. According to Friedman, the former reduces individual freedoms while the latter does not.147 However, the bank seems to have pursued its selfinterest so ruthlessly that its damaging effects cannot simply be disregarded as externalities, or ―other people‘s problems‖ as Bakan puts it148. It seems that most members of society within Friedman‘s framework cannot be considered outside his limits of people who have a right to decide and moral worth. This becomes especially apparent due to the asymmetry of power between individuals and large corporations. It is difficult for them to be compensated. Today there are grounds to claim that big business is oligopolistic. Taxpayers and others stakeholder have no real power over banks. Therefore it seems like the neoclassical axiom of perfect competition, is incorrect. The absence of perfect competition is a problem with regards to Friedman‘s theory because of the banks‘ power relation to external parties seems unbalanced. Secondly, aspects relating to a corporation's legal arrangements can create problems. Friedman makes it clear that his argument applies only to companies in which the decision managers are not the owners of the company149, as is the case in Goldman Sachs. Bank executives may feel they have personal obligations to, for instance their families, consciences, religion, et cetera150. However, in these respects they are acting as principles, not as agents. The banker is using his own money, time or energy, not that which he is contracted to by his employers. If there are social responsibilities they concern individuals not business. Corporations, even though claimed to be an artificial legal person, cannot have responsibility, according to Friedman151. However, dichotomising a person into a moral agent and an amoral professional can seem strange, especially with regards to virtue ethics. Also, it can be contended that executives have a conscience and it is their morality that should be applied to business. As Thompson152 147 J. Harvey, ―Smith, Friedman, and Self-Interest in Ethical Society‖, Business Ethics Quarterly, Vol. 10, no. 3. (2000) 148 J. Bakan, The Corporation (London: Constable, 2004) 149 J. Harvey, ―Interest in Ethical Society‖, Business Ethics Quarterly, Vol. 10, no. 3. (2000) 150 M. Friedman, ―The Social Responsibility of Business to increase its Profits‖, in T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 151 Ibid. 152 D. Thompson, Restoring Responsibility: Ethics in Government, Business and Healthcare (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) 63 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 points out, there is a tendency to make individual ethics the only kind of ethics in public life. It seems individual relations such as within families for instance which is face to face, are different moral principles than institutional ethics which governs relations between individuals as members of organisations and as citizens. According to Thomson individual ethics, like the ones Friedman discusses, dominate institutional ethics. He calls this privatisation of business ethics. One way of regenerating institutional ethics is to treat the corporation itself as a moral equivalent of an individual, as is the case legally153. As Friedman feels that a business has no moral conscience, it has no moral obligation and is not a socially responsible institution. Individuals have responsibility. Though, Thompson argues that less emphasis should be on the moral character of the individual manager, but the structure in which he operates. Friedman‘s focus is both too individualistic and does not appreciate the inner characteristics of human morality. 2. CRITIQUE OF THE STAKEHOLDER THESIS For the reasons mentioned above the stockholder thesis does not to hold and appears to be too narrow. The bonuses at Goldman Sachs exemplify this. In the light of the financial crisis of 2008, they are not completely using their government funds to aid society. Alternatively, the stakeholder thesis states that business should take into account all groups affected by a firm‘s decisions. Traditionally six stakeholders have been identified: stockholders, employees, customers, managers, suppliers and the local community.154 These groups are also discussed in Friedman‘s theory, but their moral obligations are something which must be derived from their view of a liberal society. As people who have dignity and rights that must be respected, their status should be emphasised to a greater extent,155 it seems that their interests have been unfairly subordinated. Stakeholder theory also acknowledges the importance of profit maximising, but questions whether the profits should go to the investors and managers instead of other groups. However, in Thompson‘s institutional form of business ethics, he appeals to principles 153 D. Thompson, Restoring Responsibility: Ethics in Government, Business and Healthcare (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) 154 T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 155 J. Dienhart, E. Freeman, Business Institutions and Ethics: a text with cases and readings (London: Oxford University Press, 2000) INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 64 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 that are shared with all fellow citizens, and not just for the pursuit of profit. Thus he proposes, in his view, a more democratic solution so that all interests of society can be taken into account.156 Depersonalising ethics leads in Thompson‘s view to the Friedmanite system where managers only have responsibility to maximise profits. This neglects the nature of public ethics. It seems correct to assume that a democratic outcome would not be such high remuneration for the bankers at Goldman Sachs. As Walzer notes, the free market system is not founded on the one person one vote principle; sectorial interest of a few wealthy parties seems to dictate.157 Thompson wants a balance between profit and morality to be the aim for all business ethics that can claim to be the ethics for all citizens. However, what sort of regulatory system he wants is unclear. Potentially it could limit the property rights Friedman is correct in determining. In a liberal society, taking the returns from investors would be a violation of their property rights. Stakeholder theory is not as developed as stockholder, so it appears vague. The rights and responsibilities of each stakeholder are not distinct. Friedman clearly defines manager‘s obligations. They have legal obligations to the stockholders.158 In the stakeholder thesis it is impossible to discover the balance between profits and responsibility and the relationship between the different stakeholders. So the thesis appears vague and could potentially undermine property rights. 3. BROADENING MORAL APPLICATION TO BUSINESS IN LIGHT OF THE FINANCIAL CRISES The financial crises illustrates that a broader approach to business ethics is required. There appear to be problems with both stockholder and stakeholder notions of CSR. On the one hand Friedman and his followers define a too limited scope of morality, while on the other hand it emerges that stakeholder theory could threaten property rights and 156 D. Thompson, Restoring Responsibility: Ethics in Government, Business and Healthcare (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) 157 Walzer, M. Spheres of Justice. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing 1983 158 M. Friedman, ―The Social Responsibility of Business to increase its Profits‖, in T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 65 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 actor‘s responsibility seems difficult to define. As already established, Friedman is correct in his analysis of property rights, but at the same time he has a limited scope of morality, but it will now be shown how Kantian ethics can present a philosophical solution to this problem. Kant is able to include elements with regards to, firstly, externalities and, secondly, the problems concerning the manager‘s legal and moral obligations that Friedman and neoclassical economics neglect. Kantian ethics are not only broader, but transcend the problems in Friedman‘s work. For Kant, CSR would not be seen as a positive externality that results from the modern corporation‘s pursuit of profit, but a factor which carries moral worth in itself. CSR should be undertaken for genuine and altruistic reasons, rather than merely a cynical gussied up bid for good favour. However, many stockholder theorists put shareholders and their returns at the centre of business decisions, yet hold CSR as important for the modern corporation. They would have no moral problem, for example, with the idea that ethics is good business.159 To pay managers lower wages than other companies might make it look like the company is taking responsibility. However, if it is done purely for the sake of increased profits it would not adhere to a higher moral principle in Kantian ethics and Thompson would call this personalising ethics. If the aim is to strengthen the bank‘s position in the market, the outcome is still good but would not adhere to Kantian ethics. At the same time, it is important to clarify that Kant‘s categorical imperative has often been misinterpreted to mean simply not to treat others as a means to an end. He actually states one should not exclusively treat others as means to ends.160 Therefore it seems possible to include Friedman‘s narrow business ethics into Kant‘s wide moral philosophy. Firstly, with regard to Friedman treating stakeholders as externalities, it is possible for managers to do the right thing motivated by both profits and virtuous moral principles. For instance, to show restraint in order to generate profit, and to do so for the reason that it is a right course of action in the finance crises, are both acceptable in Kant‘s theory. Friedman would call the latter motive ―window dressing‖, bordering on fraud,161 and Kant would reject the idea of action purely on profit maximising grounds. At the same 159 D. Thompson, Restoring Responsibility: Ethics in Government, Business and Healthcare (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) 160 T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 161 M. Friedman, ―The Social Responsibility of Business to increase its Profits‖, in T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 66 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 time he would allow a profit-seeking mentality, as long as it was not the sole factor. Although the motive for the action is different, there seems no contradiction in assuming that doing the right thing, cutting bonuses, could be the same as doing the profitable thing. Since Friedman wrote Capitalism and Freedom in 1962 there have been many changes. The maintenance of a good corporate image is important to profitability; therefore acts of CSR must be firmly on the agenda. It is plausible that it would be good business for the bank to decrease bonuses and instead provide cheaper loans that would benefit everyone. Property rights would be intact and if this was done for the sake of helping society, it would adhere to Kantian ethics. Thus, Goldman Sachs can afford, if their morality is so inclined, to incorporate society‘s interest into business decisions. Secondly, regarding the dichotomy of the individual agent in Friedman‘s thesis, this can be overcome by clarifying a common misunderstanding in Kant‘s thesis. Some think that Kant emphasised universal obligations over particular ones. An obligation such as keeping a promise is universal, whereas the obligation to grade students fairly is one that falls only on teachers.162 Similarly, the managerial obligation to use the funds of an investor to create profit is an obligation that falls only on the manager, whereas the manager‘s obligations to for instance his local community or family are universalistic. Thereby the bank managers theoretically should, assuming it is not contradictory, increase profits specifically at work, but aid society generally. Though principles may conflict in Kantian ethics, it does none the less seem possible to unite Friedman‘s main concerns with a broader thesis in ethics. Friedman‘s goals of a free society would still remain intact. CONCLUSION As the outlining argument explains, banker‘s high remuneration alone is not in itself a problem within Friedman‘s theory because they are justified by market forces. Though, the bankers at Goldman Sachs cannot legitimate their bonuses as their job of profit maximisation has arguably been poor. It appears free market mechanisms have not succeeded in the finance sector. Markets seem not to be self-regulating; therefore Friedman‘s neoclassical assumptions emerge as incorrect. The main question can now be 162 T.L. Beauchamp, N.E. Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001) 67 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 answered with a fair degree of certainty. Goldman Sachs has a wider social responsibility than Friedman postulates. Firstly, Friedman‘s stockholder thesis and neoclassical economics fails to incorporate externalities, wrongly axiomates perfect competition and dichotomises executives‘ personalities. Secondly, the stakeholder theory does take into account a wider range of concerns, but it was found to be vague and potentially neglects property rights of shareholders. Thirdly, it has been demonstrated that Friedman need not limit his scope of morality, even though his main concern is preserving shareholders rights over their profits. This is because virtuous business has become more profitable business since Friedman wrote his theory. Firstly, concerning externalities, Goldman Sachs‘ wish to generate profits can be combined with moral regard for other stakeholders. Nearly all corporate philanthropy seems to be motivated by publicity163. That would not necessarily be a problem for Kant, as long as there are other ethical motives. Secondly, with regards to the dichotomy of the moral agent in Friedman‘s theory, this can be overcome by Kant‘s distinction between special and universal moral principles. The bank could accept the intrinsic moral worth of other factors and maximise profits. Thereby Friedman‘s limited view of CSR as purely an issue between mangers and owner can be broadened. REFERENCES Baron, M., Pettit, P., Slote, M. Three Methods if Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2007. Bakan, J. The Corporation. London: Constable, 2004. Barry, N. The Morality of Business Enterprise. Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press, 1991. Beauchamp, T.L., Bowie, N.E. Ethical Theory and Business. New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001. 163 Ibid. 68 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Crowley, R. ―A Comment on Professor Macpherson's Interpretation of Friedman's ‗Capitalism and Freedom‘‖, Canadian Journal of Political Science / Revue canadienne de science politique, Vol. 2, no. 2 (1969). Dienhart J., Freeman, E. Business Institutions and Ethics: a text with cases and readings. London: Oxford University Press, 2000. Duke, S. ―Goldman Sachs ready to hand out £7bn salary and bonus package‖, The Daily Mail, 3rd October, 2008, URL: http://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/worldnews/article-1081624/Goldman-Sachsready-hand-7BILLION-salary-bonus-package--6bn-bail-out.html Accessed 11th January, 2009. Friedman, M. ―The Social Responsibility of Business to increase its Profits‖, in Beauchamp, T.L., Bowie, N.E., Ethical Theory and Business. New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2001. Friedman, M. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1962. Harvey, J. ―Smith, Friedman, and Self-Interest in Ethical Society‖, Business Ethics Quarterly, Vol. 10, no. 3. (2000). Locke, J. Second Treatise of Government. Indianapolis: Hacket, 1980. MacPherson, C. Elegant Tombstones: A Note on Friedman's Freedom. Canadian Journal of Political Science / Revue canadienne de science politique, Vol. 1, No. 1. 1968 Marx, K. Capital. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Thompson, D. Restoring Responsibility: Ethics in Government, Business and Healthcare Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005. Robinson, J. Treanor, J. ―Anger over £6.4bn bonus bonanza at four City banks‖, The Observer, 21st December, http://www.guardian.co.uk/business/2008/dec/21/ 2009, URL: executive-salaries-bonuses- city-finance Accessed 11th January, 2009. Walzer, M. Spheres of Justice. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1983. 69 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 EDITORIAL NOTE TO THE IPPR BOOK REVIEW * EXPLORING (NEW) AVENUES OF INFORMATION Welcome to the International Public Policy Review Book Review section. The IPPR Book Review is a new addition to the IPPR, starting with IPPR Volume Five, Issue One. The Editorial Board for Volume Five established the IPPR Book Review last year to provide an additional forum within the journal to bring practitioners (and scholars) up to speed with contemporary developments within the field of International Public Policy (IPP). The book reviews aim to be brief and sharp assessments, or prognostications, of topical issues within the field of IPP and should provide the reader with concise ‗take away‘ snapshots. The reviews may also include re-appraisals of seminal texts within the field of IPP and more broadly that of Political Science. This first edition of the IPPR Book Review section brings together five scholars to review six works dealing with multiple subfields of IPP, namely those of European Public Policy, International Political Economy, International Security and (more broadly) Theories of International Relations. As a special tribute to the late Samuel P. Huntington164, Dr. Alex Braithwaite —Lecturer in International Relations in the Department of Political Science at the School of Public Policy, University College London (UCL) — revisits Huntington‘s seminal work The Clash of Civilizations and demonstrates its enduring relevance to the field of International Security in the post 9/11 era. Dr. Harry Bauer—SIAS Fellow—discusses Richard Ned Lebow‘s recent work A Cultural Theory of International Relations in which Lebow lays the groundwork for a novel holistic constructivist account of world politics. In ―Foregoing Irredentism,‖ Harald L. Heubaum—PhD candidate in International Relations in the Department of Political Science at the School of Public Policy, UCL—assesses Irredentism in European Politics * I would like to thank all the reviewers in this novel section for their kind contribution. In particular, I would like to express my sincere gratitude to Harry Bauer for kindly providing me with instrumental advice for generating this section for the journal. 164 Dr. Samuel P. Huntington was an eminent political scientist, who passed away on December 24, 2008. His famous works include, amongst many others, The Soldier and the State (1957), Political Order in Changing Societies (1968) and American Politics: The Promise of Disharmony (1983). 70 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 —a recent publication by Markus Kornprobst, which focuses on why western European states have given up their irredentist claims in favour of cooperation. Dr. Christine Reh— Lecturer in European Politics in the Department of Political Science at the School of Public Policy, UCL—examines Stephan Keukeleire and Jennifer MacNaughtan‘s The Foreign Policy of the European Union and demonstrates its timely contribution to the recently burgeoning research topic of EU External Relations — a subarea of European Public Policy. Finally, in ―Two Bailouts for Planet Earth‖, Dr. Wasiq N. Khan—Assistant Professor of Economics in the Economics and Finance Department at the Faculty of Natural and Social Sciences, Franklin College Switzerland—compares and contrasts Jeffrey Sachs‘s Common Wealth and Thomas Friedman‘s Hot, Flat and Crowded critically evaluating two competing approaches in the realm of International Political Economy for dealing with climate change videlicet, (a) internationally financed economic development programmes as a means, over the long haul, to reduce extreme poverty by eliminating runaway population growth and thus limit our aggregate carbon footprint versus (b) a radical paradigm shift from fossil fuels to carbon neutral-based economies165. The Book Review Editor would like to thank the Editorial Board for Volume Five for entrusting him with the challenging task of setting up this novel section for the journal and eagerly looks forward to it becoming a lasting presence in future editions. The Book Review Editor, Volume Five Christophe G. Singh‡ 165 For additional discussions of Common Wealth and Hot, Flat and Crowded by the respective authors, please see the following two audio lectures: Jeffrey D Sachs, ―Common Wealth: economics for a crowded planet‖, Introduced by Professor David Held. London School of Economics.MP3.The Old Theatre, Old Building, May 2, 2008. http://www.lse.ac.uk/resources/podcasts/publicLecturesAndEvents.htm; Thomas L Friedman, ―Hot, Flat and Crowded‖ Introduced by Professor Eric Neumayer. London School of Economics.MP3.The Old Theatre, Old Building, October 14, 2008. http://www.lse.ac.uk/resources/podcasts/publicLecturesAndEvents.htm. ‡ MSc candidate in European Public Policy (Expected: November 2010) in the Department of Political Science at the School of Public Policy, University College London. For questions or comments, please contact: c.singh@ucl.ac.uk. 71 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 CLASHING ON THE FAULT LINES BOOK REVIEW The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order. By Samuel P. Huntington. London: The Free Press, Simon & Schuster, 2002. Pp. 367. £9.99 (paper); ISBN-10: 074323149x. It is closing in on two decades since Samuel P. Huntington first published his civilization-based theory of post-Cold War conflict. He then expanded upon this in his 1996 book. So why is it that we are now reviewing this text a further 13 years on? Huntington passed away on Christmas Eve of 2008. At that time, many suggested that his Clash of Civilizations hypothesis might pass, too. Very recently, Nobel Laureate Amartya Sen identified Huntington‘s hypothesis as an example of the kind of inadequate theories of violence that have gained widespread support and run the danger of having us continually oversimplify our understanding of violence in society. 166 He argued that we should choose, instead, to engage in a global debate about the multitude of complex causes of the various forms of violence that plague our societies. Yet, just two days after Sen‘s speech, President Barack Obama laid out an important aspect of his foreign policy strategy in his Address to the Muslim World.167 This speech would appear, on the face of it, to vindicate Huntington‘s simple characterization of the post-Cold War world; in essence, Obama was acknowledging that the West is in some kind of stand off with its Muslim counterparts. This review is designed, therefore, to offer a brief assessment of the potential value of Huntington‘s model of post-Cold War politics as a guide to the post-9/11 environment. At the heart of his thesis, Huntington noted that the vacuum of post-Cold War politics would be short-lived; that the ideological battle that had defined divisions between humankind in the years since the rise of communism and fascism in the wake of the Great War were already being replaced by divisions along the lines that separate 166 A. Sen, ―Violence in Society‖, (University College London. Lecture, 2009 Global Citizenship Lecture Series. June 2, 2009). 167 B. Obama, ―Address to the Muslim World‖, (University of Cairo, Egypt. Lecture, June 4, 2009). 72 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 civilizations. In detailing the implications of this bold assertion, Huntington stated very clearly that the most significant fault line, runs along what are now the boundaries between Finland and Russia and between the Baltic states and Russia, cuts through Belarus and Ukraine…, swings westward separating Transylvania from the rest of Romania, and then goes through Yugoslavia almost exactly along the line now separating Croatia and Slovenia from the rest of Yugoslavia…The peoples to the north and west of this line are Protestant and Catholic…; they are generally economically better off than the peoples to the east…The peoples to the east and south of this line are Orthodox or Muslim…; they are generally less advanced economically; they seem much less likely to develop stable democratic political systems. 168 Writing in the early-to-mid 1990s, it was not exactly prescient to highlight the potential for conflict in the Balkans. However, in the years since, tensions have been heightened there and elsewhere along this and other fault lines between civilizations. Hostilities over territorial control of Kashmir have been recurrent; Russia has engaged militarily with Chechen and Georgian populations in the Trans-Caucus region and feuded with Ukraine (and indirectly, much of the rest of Europe) over energy supplies. IsraeliPalestinian violence has, rather unsurprisingly, continued to erupt but also been accompanied by increased Western involvement in the Middle East and Central Asia. Notably, many of the transnational conflicts that appear to be defining our twentyfirst Century experience have occurred on or very close to the fault lines between civilizations. Yet, surprisingly little empirical research has focused upon this inherent geography underlying the Huntingtonian hypothesis. Initial tests of the hypothesis, focusing upon whether or not warring countries were both neighbouring and of different civilizations tended to return no statistically significant findings.169 Such studies were typically undermined, however, by their minimal conceptualisation of geography. They 168 S. Huntington, ―The Clash of Civilizations?‖ Foreign Affairs Vol. 72, no. 3 (1993): 30-31. See, e.g., B. Russett, J. Oneal, and M. Cox, ―Clash of Civilizations or Realism and Liberalism Déjà vu?‖ Journal of Peace Research Vol. 37, no. 5 (2000). 169 73 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 would simply tend to include an interaction term of two dummy variables—one measuring similarity or difference in civilization, a second indicating whether or not the two parties in conflict share a land border. At no point did these studies seek to identify where conflict had broken out. With the recent collection and publication of data on the precise locations of conflicts170 as well as the distribution of populations of ethnic groups, 171 now may be the ideal time to more robustly test the validity of Huntington‘s inherently geographic fault line hypothesis. Pending the publication of any such results, it may be difficult to offer any credible, categorical assessment of Huntington‘s claims. It does seem, however, as if there is reason to suspect that those that were quick to dismiss Huntington may wish to reconsider their judgement. Alex Braithwaite‡ REFERENCES Braithwaite, A. ―Location, Location, Location…Identifying Conflict Hot Spots.‖ International Interactions Vol. 31, no. 4 (2005): 251-272. Buhaug, H., and Gates, S.. ―The Geography of Civil War.‖ Journal of Peace Research Vol. 39, no. 4 (2007): 417-433. Cederman, L.-E., and Girardin, L.. ―Beyond Fractionalization: Mapping Ethnicity onto Nationalist Insurgencies.‖ American Political Science Review Vol. 101, no. 1 (2007): 173-185. 170 H. Buhaug and S. Gates, ―Beyond Fractionalization: Mapping Ethnicity onto Nationalist Insurgencies,‖ American Political Science Review Vol. 101, no. 1 (2007); A. Braithwaite, ―Location, Location, Location…Identifying Conflict Hot Spots,‖ International Interactions Vol. 31, no. 4 (2005). 171 L-E. Cederman and L. Giradin, ―Beyond Fractionalization: Mapping Ethnicity onto Nationalist Insurgencies,‖ American Political Science Review Vol. 101, no. 1 (2007). ‡ Lecturer in International Relations in the Department of Political Science at the School of Public Policy, University College London. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 74 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Henderson, E., and Tucker, R. ―Clear and Present Strangers: The Clash of Civilizations and International Conflict.‖ International Studies Quarterly Vol. 45, no. 2 (2001): 317-338. Huntington, S. P. ―The Clash of Civilizations?‖ Foreign Affairs Vol. 72, no. 3 (1993): 2249. _______. The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order. London: The Free Press, Simon & Schuster, 2002. Obama, B. ―Address to the Muslim World‖, University of Cairo, Egypt. Lecture. June 4, 2009. Russett, B., Oneal, J. & Cox, M. ―Clash of Civilizations or Realism and Liberalism Deja Vu?‖ Journal of Peace Research Vol. 37, no. 5 (2000): 583-608. Sen, A. ――Violence in Society‖, University College London. Lecture. 2009 Global Citizenship Lecture Series. June 2, 2009. 75 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 BOOK REVIEW A Cultural Theory of International Relations. By Richard Ned Lebow. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008. Pp. xi+762. £21.99 (paper); ISBN-13: 9780521691888; £60.00 (hard); ISBN-13: 9780521871365. All books, including those in our disciplines, can be understood as invitations. Sometimes they are warm and welcoming, sometimes they are reluctant even awkward. In any case, books turn their readers into guests of rather special occasions. Sometimes we witness more or less dry lectures in badly lit and badly aired lecture halls, sometimes we find ourselves in neatly organised, slightly freakish laboratories, and sometimes— perhaps in the best of cases—we enter into a conversation. Reading Ned Lebow's A Cultural Theory of International Relations might still evoke another scene, somewhat reminiscent of Giorgio Varsari's Lives and apposite to Lebow, one of the very few true Renaissance men in International Relations (IR) these days: here we find ourselves in the workshop of an Italian master painter in the 15th century and follow him from dusk to dawn, while he outlines the draft sketch of a painting on a massive canvas. Lebow's book is, in many respects, a highly ambitious and demanding enterprise. In fact, the volume itself is part of a Herculean project, which began with Lebow's The Tragic Vision of Politics in 2003 and is meant to find its provisional conclusion with a third study to be published in the years to come. The overall aim of this grand endeavour exceeds the narrow confines of IR by far; it attempts nothing less than to offer ―a new ontology for social science‖172 and to ―'develop[ing] a new paradigm of politics and theories nested within it.‖173 In this regard, the volume's focus on IR is just seen as a special (intricate) case of the more genuine issue of political order, its genesis, various forms and trajectories. The book therefore develops a framework for the study of politics and ―derives from it a theory of international relations.‖174 172 Lebow, R.N. A Cultural Theory of International Relations Quentin Skinner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), ix. 173 Ibid., p.28. 174 Ibid., p.505. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 76 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 While The Tragic Vision of Politics reconstructed the concepts used implicitly or explicitly by von Clausewitz, Morgenthau and Thucydides, in order to engage with their attempts to come to a universally valid understanding of the underlying dynamics that govern particular social processes, A Cultural Theory applies the reverse strategy. It transports concepts stemming from Greek antiquity (and especially from Plato, Aristotle, and Thucydides, as well as their reception in modern Western thought) to the course of (Western) history—from Homer to George W. Bush—on the grounds that ―these concepts capture universal attributes of human nature that find expression in all cultures all times, with the very important caveat that they are manifested and described in a wide variety of ways.‖175 This approach is deliberately multidisciplinary; it draws on Lebow's interest into antique political thinking, his expertise in social theory, political psychology and international history. The keystone of Lebow's framework for the analysis of politics and therefore his theory of international relations is, with some understatement, ―a simple set of assumptions about human motives.‖176 Drawing on his Greek sources, he identifies universal ―human needs‖—spirit, appetite, reason and fear—all linked ―with distinct objects or ends.‖177 These drives in turn induce distinct patterns of behaviour, like cooperation, conflict or risk-taking, which have different implications for the way social and political orders unfold. Moreover, the different drives translate into distinct forms of hierarchy grounded in different concepts of justice. By applying this concept of order to the different levels of social association—individual, state, regional and international— Lebow links individual behaviour and different forms of social aggregation, human drives and the normative equipment of political organisations. But even more, an element of change is also introduced, as the hierarchies in which orders rest are vulnerable. They can become weak and break down, when mismatches between (elite) behaviour and principles of justice become all too big. In this way, order is conceived as a constant achievement, change as a constant occurrence, while disorder at one level can easily spread to other levels. With this core conception, Lebow formulates his ontology as an implicit response to a number of seminal issues IR has grappled with in recent decades: 175 Ibid., p.41. Ibid., p.26. 177 Ibid. 176 77 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 the structure and agency problématique, the issue of methodological individualism, the problem of change and the locus of norms as well as emotions in IR. Lebow is very much aware that the human drives he identifies blend in social reality, which naturally also applies to the associated behaviours, hierarchies and principles of justice. In order to tease out the mechanisms that lead to order and disorder, he describes ideal-type worlds with the respective characteristics of spirit, appetite and reason. The main concern of his argument lies however on 'spirit' as motive for human conduct, as for him this element has been neglected in IR's analysis. Spirit is understood as the universal human drive for self-esteem—for honour, glory, standing—and the 'theory' of IR Lebow develops, by passing through world history, is in essence a historical account of the impact of self-esteem during the ages. What makes Lebow a fascinating read is perhaps most of all his inclination to pursue unusual paths to offer surprising arguments—take the recourse to Greek philosophy as the most obvious one—and to (implicitly) take issue with the current state of IR. Although he positions himself within constructivism, he is not afraid to repeatedly criticise some variants of constructivism178 and other mainstream theories. Despite a growing trend to turn to practices and, hence, also to the micro-level of interaction as object of research, Lebow forcefully argues for grand theorising, in order to provide focus and inspiration for research through ―abstract and normative theories of human nature and conduct.‖179 Certainly, a book of such proportion and complexity must provoke criticism. Let me just highlight a very few points. The argument made is ambitious, perhaps overly ambitious for just one book—somewhat reminiscent of Rosenau's Turbulence in World Politics, whose title became a catchphrase, but whose sophisticated analytical framework found hardly anyone able or willing to apply its approach. To develop a general framework for the analysis of politics would have justified a volume on its own, and would have offered demonstrations of this approach at different levels and areas of politics. Lebow's starting point, his human drives, indicates an inherently foundational perspective, yet it becomes not entirely clear how this is reconciled with the overall 178 Ibid., p.509. Skinner, Q. ―Introduction: the return of Grand Theory,‖ in The Return of Grand Theory in the Human Sciences, ed. Quentin Skinner (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985), p.1. 179 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 78 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 constructivist outlook of the project. This brings me to the 'empirical part' of the volume. It takes on the form of an essentially Western world history. However, it would have been interesting to see how the universal human needs, derived from Western political thought, fare in non-Western cultures. Now what kind of picture could we witness emerging over the 500 odd pages of Lebow's A Cultural Theory of International Relations? It might perhaps be fair to say that there are still essential elements missing to the classical triptych the overall project intends to be. So perhaps it is not really Hans Holbein we are yet confronted with, but rather a collage by Georges Braque with some fine sand trickling down, reminding us to have a look at the next inspirational canvas already in work. Harry Bauer‡ REFERENCES Lebow, R. N. A Cultural Theory of International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008. _______. The Tragic Vision of Politics: Ethics, Interests and Orders. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Rosenau, J. N. Turbulence in World Politics: A Theory of Change and Continuity. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990. Skinner, Q. ―Introduction: the return of Grand Theory.‖ In The Return of Grand Theory in the Human Sciences, edited by Quentin Skinner, pp.1-20. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985. ‡ SIAS Fellow 2009/2010. Harry Bauer recently co-edited Pragmatism in International Relations. 79 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 FOREGOING IRREDENTISM: THE POWER OF ARGUMENT AND THE RISE OF THE TERRITORIAL STATUS QUO NORM BOOK REVIEW Irredentism and European Politics: Argumentation, Compromise and Norms. By Markus Kornprobst. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008. Pp. xvi+301. £50.00 (hard); ISBN-13: 9780521895583. Quarrels over territory have long been a staple of relations between sovereign states. Several of the most prominent of these so-called irredentist disputes, including India‘s and Pakistan‘s mutual claim to Kashmir, China‘s claim to Taiwan, and Syria‘s and Israel‘s clashes over the Golan Heights, have for many decades threatened regional and world security. Yet irredentist conflicts are neither predestined to eventually end in bloodshed or the exchange of territory nor are they bound to last forever. Many irredentist conflicts may in fact be settled by the claimants foregoing their demands and accepting existing border arrangements. In Irredentism and European Politics, Markus Kornprobst convincingly explains how irredentist disputes between European states have been resolved peacefully since the end of the Second World War by casting more light on the role of argumentation and compromise in bringing about both policy change and a deeper-lying, more fundamental normative change. He does so by applying a novel three-stage norm selection mechanism to two case studies: the Federal Republic of Germany (FRG) and the Republic of Ireland. The West German case spans the better part of three decades – the 1950s, 60s and early 70s – between the partition of the Third Reich at the end of the war and the wide acceptance of the territorial status quo under the chancellorship of Willy Brandt. The Irish pendant covers a substantially longer period, from the 1921 Anglo-Irish Treaty that divided the island into its northern and southern part to eventual dispute settlement in the late 1990s. Both country cases are analysed with great attention to detail and the author draws on an impressive range of sources, including parliamentary debates, newspaper editorials, opinion polls, as well as (auto-) biographies of the relevant German 80 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Chancellors and Irish Prime Ministers. The picture is rounded out by interviews with key decision-makers and advocates involved in each country‘s debates on the issue. The main question posed by Kornprobst is why European states have given up their irredentist claims. A comprehensive survey covering irredentist disputes throughout the world from 1946 to 2000 (from 1848 in Europe) provides a convincing puzzle from which the question is drawn: in a divergence from its own past and the situation in other world regions, European states have largely solved their disagreements through peaceful recognition of the territorial status quo since the end of the Second World War. What explains this variation in outcomes? Expanding on more traditional understandings of irredentism that focus largely on the retrieval of ethnic kin and the land they inhabit from other states180, the author starts by defining the phenomenon as ―a territorial claim by a sovereign state against another sovereign state, aimed at reaching congruence between the boundaries of the nation and the borders of the state‖181. While traditional definitions may suit cases such as the claims made by Serbia in the 1990s, the FRG‘s claims to lands incorporated into Poland and Russia after 1945 and the Republic of Ireland‘s continued claim to Northern Ireland, they are unsuited to explain the FRG‘s claims to the GDR – this having been a claim to the whole country and its inhabitants. Irredentist disputes and their settlement cannot be properly understood, Kornprobst alerts the reader, without taking into account three tightly intertwined ideational factors – the episteme, identity and norms – which together form the repertoire of commonplaces that structures public discourse. As the collection of taken-for-granted beliefs upon which people construct the world around them, the episteme ―delineates what is imaginable for actors.‖182 The identity narrative defines what the nation is and how actors see it in relation to others. Later chapters provide empirical evidence that dispute settlement in both the FRG and the Republic of Ireland was driven by advocates who primarily drew on their respective countries‘ identity as part of the European Union, employing the norms of peaceful resolution of conflicts and the territorial status quo. 180 See Ambrioso, T. Irredentism: Ethnic Conflict and International Politics (Westport: Praeger, 2001); Saideman, S. M. and William Ayres, R. For Kin or Country: Xenophobia, Nationalism, and War. (New York: Columbia University Press, 2008). 181 Kornprobst, M. Irredentism and European Politics: Argumentation, Compromise and Norms, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), pp. 9. 182 Ibid., pp. 22. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 81 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Championed by constructivist scholars, norms have come to play an increasingly important role within International Relations. Analysing norm selection in two country cases by drawing on a great variety of domestic sources spanning several decades, this book contributes to an academic discipline that, despite a few notable exceptions, has not yet devoted enough attention to the often-decisive influence of levels below the international. Despite its title then, this book is not so much a study just of irredentism as the development and testing of an innovative three-stage norm selection mechanism. According to Kornprobst, various actors involved in the West German and Irish irredentist debates came to select the territorial status quo norm through a process of innovative argumentation (1st stage), persuasive argumentation (2nd stage) and compromise (3rd stage). During the first stage, advocates of change, including prominent intellectuals, made first attempts at reasoning in favour of the territorial status quo. Although their efforts were at first met with staunch opposition in most quarters, these early attempts laid the foundation for a more refined mode of argumentation, crucially supported by revolutionary events – the building of the Berlin Wall in 1961 and the collapse of the Sunningdale Agreement in 1974 – which ―made advocates feel compelled to seek a new beginning.‖183 The new situation clearly required new arguments. Over time, drawing on historical experience, the Idea of Europe and the norm of peaceful resolution of disputes, the advocacy coalition broadened to include major parties, churches, interest groups and the most influential national newspapers. This no doubt made the difference in persuading the wider public of the necessity of giving up irredentist claims – public opinion in the FRG and the Republic of Ireland turned in favour of this view in the late 1960s an early 1990s, respectively. In both countries, the shift in public opinion put pressure on influential elites either unconvinced of or opposed to foregoing irredentist claims. Wishing to get rid of the costs that come with opposing a majority view, those actors that shared the repertoire of commonplaces settled for a compromise resembling ―the original position of the advocates much more closely than the recalcitrant actors‘ original stance.‖184 In West Germany, the Christian Democrats largely abandoned their former opposition to Chancellor Brandt‘s Ostpolitik and 183 Ibid., p. 135. Ibid., p. 223. 184 82 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 continued to support the territorial status quo norm upon their return to power in the 1980s. In Ireland, Fianna Fáil compromised in support of the 1998 Good Friday Agreement, recognising Northern Ireland as rightfully part of the United Kingdom. The development of a mechanism that accounts for both genuine persuasion of the appropriateness of an advocated idea and compromise at the bargaining table in fear of the consequences of non-compliance is a significant advancement over existing accounts of norm selection. Kornprobst‘s study of reasoning and argumentation is, therefore, an important further step towards bridging the constructivist-rationalist divide. It is not lost on the author that the small number of cases examined may lend itself to criticism and it is useful here to compare Irredentism and European Politics to another major work tackling irredentism published in 2008, Saideman and Ayres‘ For Kin and Country: Xenophobia, Nationalism and War. Saideman and Ayres, both prolific academics in the field of ethnic conflict and foreign policy, base their work on two sets of irredentist disputes between states in Eastern Europe: one involving ―pit bulls‖ that sought forceful resolutions to their territorial claims, as was on evidence in the violent conflicts engulfing Serbia and Croatia in the early 1990s, and the other involving socalled ―silent dogs‖ that did not bark, such as Hungary and Romania.185 Although an integral part of his overall research puzzle, Kornprobst alludes to these cases only in passing, focussing his attention instead on two successful Western European examples. While this may limit the applicability of the findings to other cases, the author does not strive to ―resolve the research puzzle of European irredentism once and for all.‖ 186 He instead presents the reader with two in-depth case studies testing his theoretical approach to argumentation and norm selection. In effect, Kornprobst devotes considerably more space to each of his cases than comparable works, resulting in a cornucopia of insights that should appeal to social scientists as well as historians. Furthermore, Irredentism and European Politics identifies the emergence of a worldview heavily influenced by the Idea of Europe as an important factor steering domestic debates on the territorial status quo while For Kin and Country emphasises the power of xenophobia in driving the dynamics of territorial disputes between states. Each makes valid points and it seems clear that a 185 Ibid., pp. 12. Ibid., pp. 52. 186 83 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 comparability of cases encompassing both Eastern and Western Europe has its limits. Yet acknowledging that certain outcomes are contingent on a variety of factors allows for each of these works to be seen as offering complementary rather than rival explanations, each filling existing gaps in the literature. Finally, more attention could have been devoted to economic development and trade in shaping the repertoire of commonplaces and helping to build the basis for a peaceful resolution of territorial disputes. In recent years, the historical literature has begun to shed more light on the crucial role played by trade between the two German states in laying the foundation for the cautious policy of détente (Entspannungspolitik) pursued by the FRG in the early 1960s, which in turn fed into Chancellor Brandt‘s new Ostpolitik and, ultimately, the acceptance of the territorial status quo. 187 West German industry engaged in an economic diplomacy that sought to open trade relations with the Eastern bloc and ease political restrictions, all of which contributed to Bonn‘s rapprochement and a greater normalisation of German-German relations188 (Rudolph, 2004). Furthermore, the West German economic miracle (Wirtschaftswunder) of the 1950s and 60s and the resulting increased economic and political importance of the FRG are likely to have played a role in this outcome. Overall, Kornprobst succeeds in exploring a much denser web of reasoning than has been identified in the literature to date. This well-researched, lucidly written book sheds more light on the puzzle of European irredentism while making an important contribution to theory development in International Relations. In addition, it serves as a rich historical account of public opinion and elite debate on matters of national identity in both Western Germany and the Republic of Ireland. For all these reasons it should be widely read and discussed. Harald Heubaum‡ 187 Fäßler, P.E. Durch den “Eisernen Vorhang“: Die deutsch-deutschen Wirtschaftsbeziehungen 19491969 (Köln: Böhlau, 2006). 188 Rudolph, K. Wirtschaftsdiplomatie im Kalten Krieg: Die Ostpolitik der westdeutschen Großindustrie 1945-1991, (Frankfurt am Main: Campus Verlag, 2004). ‡ PhD candidate in International Relations in the Department of Political Science at the School of Public Policy, University College London. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 84 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 REFERENCES Ambrosio, T. Irredentism: Ethnic Conflict and International Politics. Westport: Praeger, 2001. Fäßler, P. E. Durch den “Eisernen Vorhang“: Die deutsch-deutschen Wirtschaftsbeziehungen 1949-1969. Köln: Böhlau, 2006. Kornprobst, M. Irredentism and European Politics: Argumentation, Compromise and Norms, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008. Rudolph, K. Wirtschaftsdiplomatie im Kalten Krieg: Die Ostpolitik der westdeutschen Großindustrie 1945-1991. Frankfurt am Main: Campus Verlag, 2004. Saideman, S. M. and William Ayres, R. For Kin and Country: Xenophobia, Nationalism, and War. New York: Columbia University Press, 2008. 85 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 BOOK REVIEW The Foreign Policy of the European Union. By Stephan Keukeleire and Jennifer MacNaughtan. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008. Pp. xvii+392. £ 22.99 (paper); £65.00 (hard); ISBN-10: 1403947228 (paper); ISBN-10: 140394721X (hard). The external relations of the European Union (EU) have become a burgeoning topic of research and a popular subject of teaching: few European or international studies conferences do without a roundtable or panel on Europe‘s global role; numerous research projects and academic networks generate a steady stream of publications on the topic; and courses on foreign policy are in high demand on European politics programmes, undergraduate and postgraduate alike. This academic interest stands in some contrast to the EU‘s actual global actorness—unchallenged and acknowledged in world trade; active but less consistent when it comes to ―mixed competences‖ such as environmental policy; criticised and contested with regard to crisis management and conflict resolution. Stephan Keukeleire and Jennifer MacNaughtan‘s The Foreign Policy of the European Union was published in the European Union Series at Palgrave in 2008— almost a decade after the Amsterdam Treaty entered into force and with it a number of far-reaching institutional changes to Europe‘s Common Foreign and Security Policy (CFSP). The year 2008 also saw much activity in EU external relations—the launch of a military bridging operation in Tschad; the preparation of a rule of law mission in Kosovo; the breakdown of the Geneva ministerial meeting under the Doha trade round; agreement on a climate and energy package that not only committed the Union to cut its greenhouse gas emissions to at least 20% below 1990 levels by 2020, but pledged to increase the cut to 30% should other industrialised countries agree to do the same. In their book, Keukeleire and MacNaughtan cover the entire breadth of these activities: it is their declared aim to look at EU foreign policy beyond the narrow confines of CFSP and defence, and to assess how such policy can ―shape and influence structures and long-term processes‖ worldwide.189 189 Keukeleire, S. and MacNaughtan, J. The Foreign Policy of the European Union (Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008) p. 4. 86 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 On a market already rich in textbooks, research monographs and edited volumes on the subject, The Foreign Policy of the European Union fills a niche in between theorydriven research monographs, such as Michael E. Smith‘s institutionalist account of foreign policy cooperation in Europe190 and more basic introductions to the topic, such as Karen Smith‘s European Union Foreign Policy in a Changing World 191 ; it covers wider substantive ground than Simon Nuttall‘s excellent and comprehensive historical overview European Foreign Policy192 or Jolyon Howorth‘s single-issue study Security and Defence Policy in the European Union 193 ; and it offers a welcome break from the dominant analytical focus on Europe‘s identity as a global actor—be it ―civilian‖, ―military‖ or ―normative‖—as developed prominently in Charlotte Bretherton and John Vogler‘s The European Union as a Global Actor.194 In their volume Keukeleire and MacNaughtan pursue two objectives: first, ―to provide an overview and analysis of EU foreign policy‖, and, second, ―to reappraise the nature of EU foreign policy and foreign policy more generally‖ 195. The latter objective builds on their distinction between conventional foreign policy with its (alleged) focus on ―states, military security, crises and conflicts‖, and structural foreign policy, which ―conducted over the long-term seeks to influence or shape sustainable political, legal, socio-economic, security and mental structures.‖196 The authors develop their approach against the backdrop of a post-Cold War and globalising international context (chapter 1), as well as the historic development of EU foreign policy cooperation from the Marshall Plan to the Lisbon Treaty (chapter 2). They subsequently introduce Europe‘s ―foreign policy apparatus‖197 in a systematic, detailed and accessible way: chapter 3 discusses the complex network of intergovernmental, supranational and bureaucratic actors behind EU foreign policy-making; chapter 4 turns from actors to processes, covering both de jure competences and decision-procedures and de facto policy-practices; while chapter 5 190 Smith, M.E. Europe’s Foreign and Security Policy: The Institutionalization of Cooperation Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004). 191 Smith, K.E. European Union Foreign Policy in a Changing World (Cambridge: Polity, 2008). 192 Nuttall, S. European Foreign Policy, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000). 193 Howorth, J. Security and Defence Policy in the European Union. (Houndmills: Palgrave, 2007). 194 Bretherton, C. and Vogler, J. The European Union as a Global Actor (Abingdon: Routledge, 2006). 195 Keukeleire, S. and MacNaughtan, J. The Foreign Policy of the European Union (Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), p.3. 196 Ibid., p. 25. 197 Ibid., p. 329. 87 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 looks at the interplay between European and national foreign policies in both a bottom-up and a top-down perspective—a commendable exercise, given the much-discussed problem of vertical ―consistency‖ or ―coherence‖ in CFSP. The six remaining substantive chapters can be divided into two parts: chapters 6 to 9 are devoted to policies; chapters 10 and 11 cover issues of international cooperation. The first set covers ―traditional ground‖—CFSP (chapter 6) and European Security and Defence Policy (chapter 7); yet, true to the book‘s aim of broadening our understanding of foreign policy they also introduce external policies located in the first pillar, including trade, development and the promotion of human rights (chapter 8) as well as internal policies with an external dimension, such as justice and home affairs or environmental policy (chapter 9). Following the discussion of three types of inter-regional cooperation—with potential member states; with neighbourhood countries; with Africa—in chapter 10, the penultimate chapter discusses cooperation with other ―global ‗structural powers‘‖ 198 such as the US, China and Russia as well as the EU‘s embeddedness in multilateral institutions. Chapter 12 concludes the book; unfortunately, it chooses to link the argument back to theories of European integration and International Relations more generally instead of focusing on the author‘s potential contribution to foreign policy analysis. Throughout, the volume covers traditional textbook material in a systematic and accessible way; it also discusses less well-known aspects of EU foreign policy, such as the Council of Ministers‘ substructure and the European Commission‘s diverse Directorate-Generates199; the systematic cooperation between member states200; the external dimension of health and demography policies201; or the EU‘s approach to international financial institutions202 and its relationship to ―Islamism‖.203 Hence, Keukeleire and MacNaughtan certainly reach their first goal—their volume offers a comprehensive well-structured overview and analysis of EU foreign policy. The unusually broad approach taken, the wealth of information provided, the topical examples 198 Ibid., p. 298. Ibid., p. 73. 200 Ibid., p.159. 201 Ibid., p. 249. 202 Ibid., p. 307. 203 Ibid., p. 322. 199 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 88 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 and up-to-date facts given in the text and additional tables as well as the further readings and sources suggested on the companion website make the book an accessible and readable resource for anyone researching, teaching and studying EU external relations. More scepticism is, however, in order when it comes to the authors‘ second goal—to reappraise the nature of EU foreign policy beyond conventional wisdom. Indeed, the book‘s twofold ―conceptual backbone‖ 204 —the distinction between conventional foreign policy and structural foreign policy,205and the definition of EU foreign policy as ―multipillar and multilevel, operating within a complex multilocational web of interlocking actors and processes‖ 206 —appeals for two reasons: it allows us to study foreign policy as an instance of multilevel governance, and it facilitates a potentially more fine-grained assessment of the EU‘s performance than its usual broadbrushed condemnation (or praise) as (in)coherent or (in)effective. Yet, the framework suffers from a combination of overload and under-specification. First, the framework is overloaded because the authors identify no less than six research themes: the tensions between Atlanticists and Europeanists, between civilian and military power, between intergovernmentalism and supranationalism, and between external and internal objectives; the EU‘s ambition to shape regional, national and global structures; and the EU‘s struggle with power.207 These themes have not only been somewhat exhausted in the existing literature; their amalgamation also leaves the reader puzzling over what it is that the authors, ultimately, want to explain: the nature and trajectory of EU foreign policy? The way foreign policy decisions are reached? The distinction between the EU‘s short-term and long-term policy-goals and the reasons for reaching these goals? The Union‘s structural influence? The book touches upon all of these questions, yet it answers none of them in systematic depth. Second, the framework is underspecified, because the authors fail to translate their definition of structural foreign policy into an analytical framework, and because they do not engage with the established literature on foreign policy analysis—conventional or not. According to Keukeleire and MacNaughtan foreign policy differs from external relations; the latter is about ―maintaining relations with 204 Ibid., p. 34. Ibid., p. 25. 206 Ibid., p. 34. 207 Ibid., p. 8. 205 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 89 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 external actors‖, the former ―is directed at the external environment with the objective of influencing that environment and the behaviour of other actors within it, in order to pursue interests, values and goals.‖208 If this is, indeed, the case then the reader would have expected a set of analytical tools that help her a) to identify such interests, values and goals; b) to assess whether the external environment and actors within it have changed; and c) to identify the scope conditions under which such change is likely. Chapter 10, which contrasts the use of conventional foreign policy and structural foreign policy in inter-regional cooperation, is a step in this direction. Overall, however, Stephan Keukeleire and Jennifer MacNaughtan neither equip us with sufficient analytical tools, nor do they give us a systematic empirical account of how the EU identifies its objectives of structural influence, how its policies correspond to these objectives, and how structures world-wide have (or have not) changed in response to Europe‘s policy intervention. As it stands, The Foreign Policy of the European Union convinces as a rich, informative and in-depth account of EU foreign policy across its thematic board; yet it will disappoint those readers who do, indeed, expect a systematic reappraisal of this foreign policy as ―structural.‖ Christine Reh‡ REFERENCES Bretherton, C. and Vogler, J. The European Union as a Global Actor. Abingdon: Routledge, 2006. Howorth, J. Security and Defence Policy in the European Union. Houndmills: Palgrave, 2007. Keukeleire, S. and MacNaughtan, J. The Foreign Policy of the European Union. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008. Nuttall, S. European Foreign Policy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. 208 Ibid., p. 19. ‡ Lecturer in European Politics in the Department of Political Science at the School of Public Policy, University College London. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 90 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Smith, K.E. European Union Foreign Policy in a Changing World. Cambridge: Polity, 2008. Smith, M. E. Europe’s Foreign and Security Policy: The Institutionalization of Cooperation Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. TWO BAILOUT PLANS FOR PLANET EARTH BOOK REVIEW Common Wealth: Economics for a Crowded Planet. By Jeffrey Sachs. London: Penguin, 2008. Pp. xi+386. £9.99 (paper); ISBN-978: 0141026152. Hot, Flat, and Crowded: Why The World Needs a Green Revolution and How it Can Renew Our Global Future. By Thomas Friedman. London: Allen Lane, Penguin Group, 2008. Pp. 444. £20 (hard); ISBN-978:1846141294. Jeffrey Sachs, the Director of the Earth Institute at Columbia University, is the world‘s most active fire-fighting economist. Having, over the last twenty years, taken on the liberalization of planned economies in the former Soviet bloc as well as the stubborn problem of hyper-inflation in Latin America, Sachs has more recently, in The End of Poverty: Economic Possibilities for Our Time209, set his sights on designing multi-year, multinational, and multibillion dollar projects to eradicate extreme poverty, control malaria, and stimulate a four-fold increase agricultural productivity in Africa. His current work, Common Wealth: Economics for a Crowded Planet210, aims no lower; Sachs now has a plan and budget to simultaneously mitigate global climate change, control population growth, protect biodiversity, reduce extreme poverty, and forestall serious world water shortages. For someone who was once best known for advocating market 209 210 Sachs, J. The End of Poverty: Economic Possibilities for Our Time (New York: Penguin, 2005). Sachs, J. Common Wealth: Economics for a Crowded Planet (London: Penguin, 2008). 91 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 based solutions to government failures in centrally planned economies and is still associated with the term ‗shock therapy,‘ Sachs‘ recent work may represent a shift in thinking emblematic of the times we live in; large portions of his recent books, The End of Poverty and Common Wealth, are devoted to explaining why free markets have failed to safeguard common resources, are inadequate at providing public goods, and will not kick start development in regions caught in poverty ‗traps.‘ Sachs‘ proposals to head off a five-way-gathering global catastrophe are persuasive and his plan is methodical, but all require a massive shift in government spending priorities, a large increase foreign aid, and the creation of several new international organizations that would expedite critical initiatives. Using a broad range of quantitative data from geography, demography, economics, and ecology, Sachs clearly describes what threatens the world and what it will cost to mitigate and, in many instances, eliminate these threats. Those expecting a pessimistic rumination on inevitable catastrophe will instead find a hopeful book that carefully tallies the costs of positive interventions and compares these to the costs of inaction. Sachs argues that once the prevalence of extreme poverty is reduced, runaway population growth will cease which will, in turn, mitigate biodiversity loss, reduce fresh water scarcity, limit carbon emissions, and ease global warming. Much will depend, however, on the willingness of rich nations to spend at least 0.7 per cent of their gross domestic products on foreign aid as well as on the research and development of new technologies to generate clean energy from renewable sources, produce food in environmentally sustainable systems, and preserve fresh water supplies.211 In short, solutions are available, but only if humankind were to fully absorb the urgency of the crisis, be willing to cooperate, and to give generously. Sachs believes strongly in setting concrete goals in international development endeavors and using these goals to monitor progress. Well known for supporting the United Nation‘s Millennium Development Goals, Sachs, in Common Wealth, lays out a detailed budget for seven specific priorities. To fund climate change mitigation, so that increases in the global average temperature do not exceed two degrees centigrade by 2050, Sachs proposes that rich donor nations spend 1 per cent of their combined GDP or 211 Ibid., pp. 245, 310. 92 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 approximately $350 billion per year while poor countries spend approximately $125 billion per year for an indefinite period into the future on efforts to reduce greenhouse gas emissions.212 To help poor countries better adapt to the negative side effects of a warming globe, Sachs estimates that $70 billion per year from rich countries will be needed for the foreseeable future. The bill for the conservation of biodiversity would come to $35 billion per year. Interventions to combat desertification would also cost rich nations $35 billion per year – again for an indefinite period. The same price tag of $35 billion is the annual outlay needed to support efforts at stabilizing global population growth so that total world population peaks in 2050 at 7.8 billion and the world population growth rate falls to zero by 2050. The costs of research and development needed to create a new generation of sustainable technologies for energy generation will require an annual outlay of $70 billion, again for an indefinite period of time. Assistance for poor countries to ensure the achievement of the Millennium Development goals by 2015 and the eradication of extreme poverty by 2050 will require an annual outlay of $245 billion for the next five to forty years. In total, the costs of keeping the world from being destroyed would be about $840 billion per year for an indefinite period into the future. Sachs believes that much of this can be met by redirecting available funds from military budgets, bilateral aid programs, and a broad array of other expendable revenue sinks. The United States, for example, currently spends approximately $1.6 billion per day or $572 billion per year on defense (more than the rest of the world combined and twenty times the world average per capita military expenditure).213 Sachs argues that military budgets, agricultural subsidies, and various other programs in rich nations could be pared down or eliminated and the revenue easily redirected to areas where the social rate of return is much higher. He notes that one crucial intervention proven to drastically reduce malaria, the provision of anti-malarial bed net protection to every sleeping site in Africa, would cost as little as a one-time outlay of $1.5 billion while yearly Africa suffers from at least $12 billion in lost economic output directly due to malaria – in short, for every dollar spent on bed-nets, approximately $8 could be recouped in the form of increased labour productivity, reduced 212 Ibid., p. 310. Ibid., p. 274. 213 93 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 spending on health care, and this could easily be achieved through a reduction in the bloated spending on sectors such as defense and agriculture in rich nations. Sachs has been criticized for his faith in the ability of aid from rich to poor countries to solve such a wide range of deeply entrenched social problems. William Easterly, among others, has claimed that trillions of dollars have been spent since the Second World War on aid from rich to poor countries and he notes that the level of aid per capita is negatively correlated with economic growth and social development. Easterly and others have also argued that foreign aid fosters dependency in poor countries and this undermines precisely those social institutions that might enable poor countries to do more to help themselves.214 Sachs pre-empts these criticisms by describing several past triumphs of foreign assistance programs including India‘s Green Revolution, the eradication of small pox, polio, and the success of the Global Fund for Tuberculosis, Malaria, and HIV/AIDS. A weakness in Sachs‘s proposals is that no specific timeline is proposed. While it may be possible to convince rich nations to donate 2.4 percent of their yearly output to fund critical initiatives aimed at saving all terrestrial life, a plan such as Sachs‘s becomes a much tougher sell when the anticipated funding would be needed for an indefinite period of time. The problem of donor-fatigue needs to be considered in light of the fact that development grants to poor countries were once described as sunset programs that would expire once specific targets for economic growth and social development had been achieved. Instead development programs and many development bureaucracies have grown in size over time and, in the worst instances, fostered long-term dependency. Sachs‘s proposals would be more convincing if he were to explain how his plan would avoid repeating the mistakes of past foreign aid initiatives. Thomas Friedman, the three time Pulitzer Prize winner and foreign affairs columnist for the New York Times, is best known for writing popular books on American foreign policy, the Middle East, globalization, and environmental affairs. To his fans, he is distinguished by an uncanny ability to present complex political-economic ideas in an 214 Doubts regarding the efficacy of foreign aid programs can be found in Easterly, W. The Elusive Quest for Growth (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 2002), Weaver, C. Hypocrisy Trap: The World Bank and the Poverty of Reform (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008), and Svensson, J. ―Foreign Aid and Rent-Seeking,‖ Journal of International Economics Vol. 51 (August 2000): pp. 381-40. 94 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 engaging, accessible, and conversational way. Though he was an early and fervent proponent of invading Iraq and has been described, by critics, as an apologist for the worst excesses of globalization and free markets, he is a hugely influential maker of American public opinion. In his most recent book, Hot, Flat, and Crowded: Why The World Needs a Green Revolution and How it Can Renew Our Global Future215, Friedman passionately argues for immediate action to prevent a global climatic apocalypse. Friedman‘s intended audience is American and to them he argues that the United States‘ world leadership position, badly eroded in the post 9/11 era, could be recovered if Americans were to spearhead a ‗green revolution‘ to convert their fossil fueled based economy into one that relied on renewable sources of energy which would in turn reduce carbon emissions, mitigate climate change, protect biodiversity, and bolster American economic competitiveness – all the while restoring the United States‘ moral prestige and spearheading a global movement dedicated to sustainable and ecologically sound development. Friedman‘s proposals for change have a very different slant from Sachs‘s and, at times, appear to be diametrically opposed to Sachs‘s emphasis on top-down forms of international cooperation. Friedman is extremely skeptical of the capacity of massive governmental or intergovernmental spending programs to generate the necessary changes and innovations to bring about sustainable forms of economic growth.216 A revolution in how energy is generated and used would require very context-specific adjustments such as taxes on carbon intensive production or consumption, price floors on fossil fuels, and careful attention, at all points, to local political alignments to ensure that what was proposed would work in tandem with local interests.217 Friedman does not discuss water scarcity or extreme poverty. He is almost entirely focused on the threat of climate change. Unlike Sachs, he makes no attempt to link extreme poverty, runaway population growth, and water scarcity with global warming. Instead, Friedman argues that the primary cause of global warming is the fossilfuel-intensive economic growth paradigm.218 Hot, Flat, and Crowded goes a lot further than Sachs‘ Common Wealth in actually describing the manner in which a sustainable215 Friedman, T.L. Hot, Flat, and Crowded: Why the World Needs a Green Revolution and How It Can Renew Our Global Future. London: Allen Lane, Penguin Group, 2008. 216 Ibid., pp. 244, 246. 217 Ibid., p. 336. 218 Ibid., p. 32. 95 INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 carbon neutral economy would function, where the savings and efficiencies would be greatest, and what types of new technologies and public policies would be needed to convert our current economic system into one that was cleaner and greener. Friedman, like Sachs, does not think free markets can do much to protect common resources or provide public goods, but rather than correcting this by creating new United Nations agencies with massive budgets, Friedman favours country specific corrections that involve some spending and a lot of market tweaking – a carbon tax, subsides and tax credits directed to producers of solar, geo thermal, and wind based power equipment and some strategy to counteract the lobbying of interest groups ranging from oil companies to coal and auto producers.219 In comparison to Sachs, Friedman is more sceptical and worried about the prospects for mitigating global climate change and, to his credit, he provides more detail describing the technological and political obstacles that would have to be overcome before mitigation were achieved; the result is a portrait of a difficult and complex challenge that will require great sacrifice and global perseverance to overcome. Sachs‘ tone is much more hopeful -- he does not dwell on the obstacles to affecting positive change, but focuses on the affordability of the solution; implicit in this point of view is the idea that if goals are clear and budgetary commitments are met, then what remains is not necessarily a painful and costly adjustment, but a steady advance to a better world based on the self-evident merits of the cause. Wasiq N. Khan‡ REFERENCES Easterly, W. The Elusive Quest for Growth: Economists’ Adventures and Misadventures in the Tropics. Cambridge: The MIT Press, 2002. 219 Ibid., pp. 17, 245. ‡ Assistant Professor of Economics and Finance in the Economics and Finance Department at the Faculty of Natural and Social Sciences, Franklin College Switzerland. INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC POLICY REVIEW 96 - VOL. 5, NO. 1 - OCTOBER 2009 Friedman, T. Hot, Flat, and Crowded: Why The World Needs a Green Revolution and How it Can Renew Our Global Future.. London: Allen Lane, Penguin Group, 2008. Sachs, J. Common Wealth: Economics for a Crowded Planet. London: Penguin, 2008. Svensson, J. ―Foreign Aid and Rent-Seeking,‖ Journal of International Economics 51 (August 2000): 381-402. Weaver, C. Hypocrisy Trap: The World Bank and the Poverty of Reform. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008.