© 2011 The Ethics of Disasters Policy and Practice Sarah Clark and Albert Weale Author contact: Sarah Clark Department of Political Science School of Public Policy University College London 29/30 Tavistock Square London WC1H 9QU This material was written as part of a programme of work for an ESRC research project entitled ‘Social Contract, Deliberative Democracy and Public Policy’ (RES-051-27-0264). This support is warmly acknowledged. Workshop on ‘The Ethics of Disasters Policy and Practice’ Thursday, 26 January 2012; 9.30-14.30 Venue: Mary Ward House, 5/7 Tavistock Place London WC1H 9SN Organisers: Albert Weale and Sarah Clark, UCL School of Public Policy Contact: Sarah Clark Email s.l.clark@ucl.ac.uk; Tel. 07981130302 Pre-Workshop Pack Contents 1. Aims of the workshop 2. Outline programme 3. Ethical dilemmas: issues, examples and questions A. Issues of priority setting: dilemmas of equal treatment B. Issues of quality I: dilemmas of compromising standards in emergency situations C. Issues of quality II: dilemmas of standards and cultural difference D. Issues of responsibility: dilemmas of action and non-action 4. Delegate list 2 1. Aims of the workshop The ethical issues around disasters are numerous: this is a very large and varied field with challenging ethical problems occurring at many different levels and in multiple types of scenarios. The primary purpose of this workshop is to provide an opportunity to hear participants’ views and experiences of the issues and to promote discussion, with the aim of better understanding the relevant ethical dilemmas from the perspective of practitioners. As you will no doubt be aware, there are a number of sets of ethical guidelines which apply to this area, for example the Sphere Standards. However, the approach we would like to take is bottom-up. We think that progress is likely to be made by reflections on the experience that people have had in facing hard ethical questions. We do not aim to resolve the issues! However, we hope that by building up a ‘casebook’ of interesting and important problems, and bringing ethical analysis to bear on them, we can improve understanding of the problems, and feed that understanding in to improving ethics and governance around disasters work. Our idea is that good governance in this area should be substantially informed by practice and genuinely responsive to the issues faced by practitioners. We hope that learning from the workshop can be instrumental in this, and we would greatly value suggestions as to practical ways in which the work might be carried forward, in particular by creating a research resource that would help improve practice. 3 2. Outline Programme 09.30 Arrivals and coffee 10.00 - 10.30 Start Introductions, background and aims for the workshop 10.30 - 11.15 Discussion of ethical dilemmas: Issues of priority-setting 11.15 - 11.30 Coffee 11.30 - 12.45 Discussion of ethical dilemmas: Issues of quality and responsibility 12.45 - 13.15 Lunch 13.15 - 13.45 Discussion of ethical dilemmas: Issues of responsibility (continued) 13.45 - 14.30 Round up of themes and discussion of ways forward 14.30 Tea 4 3. Ethical dilemmas: issues, examples and questions The following material is largely drawn from thoughts and comments kindly contributed by participants at the workshop, and based on their experiences of issues of policy and practice in the context of disasters. It is by no means exhaustive, and does not seek to set a specific agenda, but rather just to stimulate thought and to provide a starting point for discussion. Material has been edited with every attempt to remain faithful to contributors’ meanings, but naturally we take responsibility for any mistakes or misinterpretations. A) Issues of priority-setting: dilemmas of ‘equal treatment’ In the context of providing help to people in disaster situations, humanitarian principles suggest that all people in need are equal and that assistance must be provided according to need without discrimination on grounds of, for example, race, religion, politics or age. By implication, priorities should be set strictly by need alone and, in doing this, they should take into account particular vulnerabilities which contribute to need. However, in practice, personnel in extreme conditions face acutely challenging decisions about who receives what kind of help, and the following situations can arise: i) Strictly equal treatment sometimes does not lead to equal benefit - that is, to needs being met equally. For example, in a context where the disaster area is also one of conflict, one contributor asked ‘do you "run with the devil"?’: if the UN has an agreement that humanitarian aid will be distributed equally between warring factions, but one side has significantly greater needs than the other, do you comply with the UN requirement for equal treatment, given the possibility that not doing so may exacerbate conflict? The contributor commented ‘When I didn't (comply) and tried to take it all (the aid) to the most needy, the other side took the lot at gunpoint’. ii) The young are often prioritized over the elderly. It is a common implicit assumption in disaster (and non-disaster) situations that priority should be given to children. Some suggest this is on grounds that they have simply had fewer years of life than older people and therefore fairness indicates that they should take priority in order that they can have similar opportunities to people who have already enjoyed long lives. However, one contributor commented, ‘older people are rarely, if ever, given specific consideration… we see this as discrimination and contrary to humanitarian principles, but the instinctive feeling that children are more important is deeply ingrained in humanitarians (and people in general) so how can we square this with our other principles that everyone has a right to life and humanitarian assistance?’ 5 iii) Some people may be not only difficult and time-consuming to treat, but also less likely to survive than others. If the aim is to maximize the benefits that can be provided to all of those affected, spending a great deal of time and resources on a small number of people may seem ill-advised. However, if all needs are to be met equally, then needs which demand intensive effort and resource must be given equal priority with needs which can be more easily met, even if that means fewer needs are met overall. For example, issues have been raised about the discriminatory nature of some disaster triage systems in relation to people with disabilities: the US Sequential Organ Failure Assessment (SOFA) protocol evaluates patient health status and suggests that patients below a certain SOFA score are not eligible for ventilator support in times of scarcity, and that the duration of the period of care on a ventilator must be limited in order to meet the needs of as many people as possible. This arguably discriminates against those with disabilities involving breathing difficulties - some have commented that ‘natural disasters are realized disproportionately as human disasters for disabled people’ (Wolf and Hensel, 2011). But if ventilators are in short supply, how should their use be allocated? iv) To what extent should people on the ground obey rules set down by, for example, the UN, if those rules seem to rule out meeting legitimate need appropriately? For example, one contributor commented about being involved in medical evacuation but having concerns about the UN approach of deciding which conditions qualified for evacuation and which did not, rather than setting priorities but allowing for flexibility on the ground. 6 B. Issues of quality I: dilemmas of compromising standards in emergency situations Achieving the standards of quality and excellence to which professionals work in nondisaster circumstances may be very difficult in extreme conditions. The reality may be that delivering services or care that is clinically excellent by ‘normal’ standards means that very few people would be assisted in the context of a disaster. There are practical issues of professional competence, of variability of practice across foreign teams and of accountability here. However, some particularly difficult ethical issues arise around the following: i) How far it is acceptable to compromise quality standards in an emergency response situation, if we are to reach as many people as possible? If there has to be a compromise in standards, how do we decide what is acceptable or justifiable practice and what is not? Is practice that would be considered substandard in ‘normal’ circumstances acceptable in the context of disasters, given the exceptional challenges? For example: ii) • There has been a debate in emergency nutrition between those who say that clinical excellence is best achieved by taking mothers and infants into therapeutic feeding centres where high quality care can be provided, and those who advocate a community therapeutic care approach based on home-feeding, where the quality of nutrition is lower but where many more people are reached. • Rehabilitation for amputees would be routinely provided in the UK, but there may not be capacity to do it when all resources are focused on emergencies: providing rehabilitation may dramatically improve amputees’ quality of life, but it may reduce capacity for meeting short term need. • Similarly, in ‘ordinary’ circumstances, patient follow up is considered to be a vital part of care, but in emergency situations, doing this means less time for seeing patients who have not yet been treated. Is it ever acceptable for rehabilitation work or patient follow-up not to be carried out in a disaster scenario? • Is it acceptable for medical personnel to work beyond their abilities - for example, performing procedures of which they have no experience and for which they are not qualified - if they are the only people available? How should the balance be struck between values of quality and efficiency on the one hand, and capacity building and/or sustainability on the other? For example, should speed and efficiency dictate that locally sourced medicines be used even if they may be of lower quality? Should agencies always use local building materials (better from the perspective of capacity building) even if it is 7 slower and less efficient to obtain them in an emergency situation, and if they are of lower quality and therefore less sustainable in the long term? Conversely, should high-tech, highly effective equipment be installed to provide short-term benefits, even if there are negative effects in the long term? For example, air conditioning units have been shown to provide a strong protective effect during extreme heatwaves, but their use is environmentally unsustainable and creates a negative feedback loop: they raise carbon emissions and potentially add to global warming, thereby increasing the risk of future extreme heat events. iii) Is it acceptable to opt for the short-term easiest option if it will help more people, more quickly, even if it leaves problems in the long term? As one contributor put it, is it acceptable to ‘do what you can do (and do it now), rather than wait and do what you should do?’ For example in Haiti, cities of temporary shelters were built with little planning and in some cases on disaster-prone land. Possible reasons for this are that NGO agencies had the skills and donor funding to build temporary shelters rather than permanent structures, and because it was a way around inadequate land tenure documents and avoided the risk of conflict with local authorities. Is it ethical to take this kind of quick and easy option in the short term, when in the medium and long term it may be worse than doing nothing for as long as it takes to work out how to achieve a more sustainable and development-orientated intervention? iv) How justifiable is it in disaster situations to spend time and resources on activities related to data gathering and research which may improve the quality of future practice and outcomes but impinge on the ability to relieve suffering in the present? For example, many think it essential that the experiences, lessons and successes of disaster preparedness and response are written up and published so that future policies and practices can be improved. Documenting these experiences accurately may mean gathering data in the immediate aftermath of a disaster. There have been conflicts between medical practitioners in the field about this: some believe that all efforts should be put into responding in the aftermath of a disaster, and that research activities are not a priority. In another example, photographs and film footage are very valuable for record keeping. However, in certain situations the relationship between patients and health workers could be made more difficult by taking photos, since some authorities regard photography as a way of publicising their failings. This can negatively impact on the relationship between humanitarian responders and the host country and therefore ultimately on patients. Furthermore, it can be difficult to obtain the kind of consent for taking photographs of patients that would be required in the UK: 8 is the potential harm of showing disrespect to patients and ignoring confidentiality a price worth paying if it leads to better documentation from which learning can be taken and future practice improved? 9 3. Issues of quality II: dilemmas of standards and cultural difference Standards of practice in many areas relevant to disasters, for example medicine and construction, may vary widely across different countries. Some local cultural practices may also conflict with ‘liberal’ approaches to fairness and equality. To what extent should interventions be adapted to fit local circumstances and preferences? For example: i) How far should foreign medical personnel adapt their practice to local practice? For example, in the UK sedation and pain relief would always be given to children for painful procedures including dressing changes, but in other countries this is not always common practice. The use of opiates in particular, and pain relief in general does not always cross cultural boundaries and patients may be expected to suffer a level of pain that would be considered unacceptable in the UK. What should be done in a situation where a foreign team is managing local medical staff who do not work to the standards of the foreign team, but rather to the standards of local practice? Should the local medical staff be required to work to, for example, UK standards in their own country? ii) How far should foreign development agencies impose their standards for following official protocols in disaster zones, against the practices and preferences of local populations? For example, following official government processes in seeking planning permission in creating disaster-resilient infrastructures, may not only significantly slow the process of development, but also go against the practice and preferences of local people who do not follow official processes, perhaps regarding the relevant authorities as corrupt, discriminatory or autonomy-limiting. On one hand it could be thought important from the perspective of government capacity building for agencies to engage in official processes. However, on the other hand, it could earn distrust from local people, and even empower politicians complicit in making their populations vulnerable to the effects of disasters. iii) Should liberal standards of fairness and equality be imposed in order to meet all needs equally, even if that runs against (reasonable) local cultural practices? Some have noted a disconnect between external and local definitions of vulnerability and therefore disparities about who - if anyone - is thought to deserve targeted assistance. This can lead, for example, to widespread sharing of targeted food or medical assistance such that everyone gets something even if that means no-one gets very much, or so that men receive most of the aid because they are seen as central to the survival of families (Jaspars and Maxwell, 2008). To what extent should these community/communitarian practices be accepted and/or facilitated by the policies and practices of ‘western liberal’ organizations? 10 4. Issues of responsibility: dilemmas of action and non-action Whilst it seems obvious that we need to act in response to disasters, there are nonetheless very important questions around issues of responsibility for action and non-action. Within this, there are commonly thought to be a range of ‘duties’ which recommend or limit action, for example duties to assist those in need, duties to ‘do no harm’, and duties to protect the vulnerable. However, the need to determine who is responsible for what precedes any action or performance of a ‘duty’. Some questions that arise in connection with issues of responsibility are as follows: i) Who is responsible and where is the locus of responsibility for different types of action? How wide do the limits of responsibility stretch? How do we assign obligations to act, given the vastly different and complex levels and areas of responsibility, and the number of actors - local, regional, global involved in disasters planning, policy and practice? One recent report uses the phrase ‘common but differentiated responsibility’ referring to the need for shared overall responsibility but where specific actions are clearly assigned to different agents (Cox and Max, 2011). In terms of the limits of responsibility, for example, there are issues about UK medical staff being released from the NHS for short term deployments in disaster zones. Currently, staff must take annual leave to do this. Should the NHS as an institution be willing to release some of its staff to assist in disasters on a nonannual leave basis? That is, what responsibility do relevant UK institutions have, and is it such that they should bear some cost in performing those responsibilities? ii) When is it justifiable to assign culpability to people who performed their responsibilities, but did so ineffectively or with bad consequences? For example, the geophysicists who failed to predict the L’Aquila earthquake in Italy were prosecuted as a result. Japanese geophysicists seriously underestimated the magnitude of the Tohoku earthquake and tsunami in their hazard assessments, which meant that people were evacuated to areas which were devastated by the tsunami. Should the Japanese geophysicists be prosecuted too? In a different context, should development agencies who build structures from poor quality local materials be held responsible if those structures fail to hold up well in another disaster, even though, from another perspective, buying local materials could be seen as acting ethically by supporting local markets? iii) When is it right not to act? In some professional codes of conduct the first principle is ‘do no harm’. This implicitly recognizes that benefits and harms are not of the same value, hence it is always better to avoid a harm than to gain a benefit of the same value (Cox and 11 Max, 2011). The precautionary principle in some ways ‘backs up’ the injunction to do no harm, but where decisions have to be made quickly and in highly nonideal circumstances with inadequate information, weighing up the severity and likelihood of risk (the two elements of the precautionary principle) may be very challenging. Our choice may be between two apparent harms, rather than a clear harm and a benefit: how should we judge the lesser harm, especially in circumstances of uncertainty? For example: • If foreign agencies intervene with food aid to ameliorate malnutrition in a post-disaster area where the government has the capacity but is failing to act, does the agency effectively alleviate the government from its rightful responsibilities, therefore fostering a ‘harm’ in the shape of ineffective government whilst working to avoid the harm of malnutrition amongst its population? • Similarly, in conflict situations, one contributor asks ‘do external ‘neutral’ forces effectively relieve warring factions of the responsibility to deal with the consequences of their actions, and so prolong the war?’ • Another contributor offers the following example: ‘I was running an emergency field hospital for an IDP camp housing 350,000 people in a post conflict situation. The monsoon rains created regular flooding and we had limited access to patients due to strict military control. We had a Memorandum of Understanding with the Government that stipulated we could not contact international press about what was happening: if we breached these rules we would be asked to leave the country. We were one of only a handful of organisations that had permission to work in this camp. We faced a difficult decision about the risks of communicating what was happening to the international community on the one hand, and maintaining a presence, continuing health care and not jeopardising the safety, health and security of both our staff and patients on the other.’ 12 4. Delegate List Name Organisation Role Ayesha Ahmad Tutor Mark Bulpitt University College London Medical School World Vision Katie Carmichael Health Protection Agency Kate Crawford Sarah Clark Carolyn Johnston University College London Kings College London Justine Lowe Imperial College Hospital Niddhi Mittal Save the Children Virginia Murray Linda O’Halloran Marcus Oxley Christopher Potter Anthony Redmond Health Protection Agency Thinking Development (UCL) Medicins Sans Frontier Disaster Bioethics project at Dublin City University School of Nursing and Human Sciences Disasters Network NHS Wales University of Manchester Mark Salter Health Protection Agency Peter Sammonds Emily Speers-Mears UCL Institute for Risk and Disaster Reduction Save the Children Frances Stevenson Jo Wells Dan Walden HelpAge International HelpAge International Save the Children Albert Weale University College London Simon Heuberger Dónal O’Mathúna Head of humanitarian emergency affairs Environmental Public Health Scientist Independent Consultant Research Associate Advisor in Medical Law and Ethics Consultant Anaesthetist and RCOA College Tutor Climate Change Adaptation Advisor Head of Extreme Events Founder of ‘Thinking Development’ MSF Association Co-ordinator Head of Disaster Bioethics Project Director Director of Public Health Professor of International Emergency Medicine; Deputy Director Humanitarian and Conflict Response Institute Consultant in Communicable Disease Control Director Senior Conflict and Fragile States Advisor Head of Emergencies Humanitarian Policy Manager Disaster Risk Reduction Policy Advisor Professor of Political Theory 13