A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS OF PROTECTION AFFORDED TO FREE EXERCISE OF RELIGION BY THE FREE EXERCISE AMD FREE SPEECH CLAUSES OF THE FIRST AMENDMENT Gerrit M. Pronske Independent Research Professor Rodrick Schoen Texas Tech University School of Law Sepember 23, 19 83 ooim INTRODUCTION The free exercise clause of the first amendment"'" affords three basic protections of individual liberty: First, the clause protects those who engage in religious 2 activity; second, the clause protects those who wish to forego compulsory involvement in activities because of religious conscience ; and third, the clause protects freedom of belief. 4 may In be the forced first to two yield areas, freedoms sought be protected to the a compelling state to interest, 5 but in the third, the protection is absolute. 6 In this paper it will be shown that the free exercise clause of the first amendment runs concurrently to the free speech clause almost to the point of complete inclusion of free exercise rights into the free speech area. 7 sphere of religious activity/religious speech, In the where those attempting to invoke first amendment protection have prevailed, the Court has decided a vast majority of the cases g on free speech grounds, and in the cases where free exercise claims were unaided by free speech claims the challenges 9 were left without vxndication. In those cases where exemp- tion from a compulsorylaw was sought based on religious conscience, the Court has granted such exemption based on both the free speech and free exercise clauses. 0 6 1 B 4 In these "exemption" cases, the courts have often looked to the nature of the activity sought to be exempted to determine how central or essential to the religious belief the practice is.^ Although this centrality principle has not been precisely defined or isolated by the Supreme Court as such, it is applied only in free exercise analysis and therefore shows a possible basis for different results between the two clauses in. exemption cases. In cases where an exemption is sought fro® compulsory laws for an activity that is neither labeled "speech" nor integrally related to speech, the free exercise clause is without counterpart in the free speech clause. The free speech clause does not protect 12 that which is acivity unrelated to speech. The free ex- ercise clause, however, has never been held to protect only activities which possess a speech related component. That several cases have been decided applying free exercise an13 alysis where non-speech activity was at issue shows a major distinction in theory between free speech and free exercise clause analysis. In freedom of belief cases, the results m u s t necessarily be the same bacause both the clauses have been held to provide absolute protection. 14 The establishment clause of the first amendment has likewise not proven to create any intelligible between the free speech and free exercise clauses. distinctions In rel- igious speech cases, if the Court finds the presence of a 15 "public forum no discrimination or differentiation will be allowed on the content of the speech. ^ excludes establishment clause janalysis. g m This virtually In cases where an exemption from compulsory laws is sought, the C o u r t has resigned itself to the tension w h i c h it is inherent between the establishment and free Supreme feels exercise c l a u s e s and h a s allowed the free exercise claims as "nothing m o r e t h a n the governmental obligation of neutrality in the face o f religious differences. . . . R E L I G I O U S W O R S H I P A S SPEECH UNDER WIDMAR V. VINCENT. 1 8 19 In Widmar, the question was whether a state s i t y , w h i c h m a d e its facilities generally available a c t i v i t i e s of registered for student groups, could close f a c i l i t i e s to a student group desiring to use the for religious w o r s h i p and discussion. m e e t i n g s of registered organizations. its facilities The University of M i s s o u r i a t K a n s a s City routinely provided 20 facilities for Cornerstone, a registered religious organization, had held meetings u n i v e r s t i y facilities for four years which included h y m n s , B i b l e commentary, and discussion of religious 21 iences. univer- in prayer, exper- In 1977, the university informed Cornerstone could no longer m e e t in u n i v e r s i t y facilities. This it decision w a s based on a regulation w h i c h prohibited the use of university b u i l d i n g s for 22 purposes of religious worship or religious teaching. Eleven m e m b e r s of Cornerstone suit to challenge the regulation on the grounds that fdr.fw brought their rights of free exercise, equal protection, and free speech were being denied.^ The Supreme Court said that a campus of a public university "possesses many of the characteristics of a 24 public forum. " In a university public forxim, students enjoy first amendment rights of speech and Citing Heffron Sciousness, v. 25 International Inc., and discussion Society association. For Krishna Con- the Court held that religious worship are forms of speech and association pro- tected by the first amendment,and so the case was 2 decided 6 on free speech grounds, not free exercise grounds. In a dissenting opinion, Justice White took issue with the majority's generic classification of speech, arguing that the religious nature of speech is cognizable and, in this case, its presence should have allowed the University of Missouri at Kansas City to exclude Cornerstone from its facilities 27 because of the establishment clause. In a footnote, Justice White raised the point that the majority was, in effect, creating new law on the categorization of religious speech. White said that Heffron did not stand for the proposition that religious worship was speech. the religious group in Heffron zation, i.e., talking about worshipping. religious Rather, was engaging in proselyti- religion, rather than actually White rejected the majority's inclusion of worship into the category of speech, concluding that "talk about religion and religious beliefs. . . is 28 not the same as religious services of worship."*' Also in a f o o t n o t e , 2 9 the majority found three difficulties in the soundness of White's distinction between religious services of worship and talk about religion and talk about religion and religious beliefs. First, argued the major- ity, the dissent failed to establish that an intelligible distinction between the two could be made. indication when "There is no 'singing hymns, reading scripture, and teaching biblical principles. . .' cease to be 'singing, teaching, and reading,' - all apparently forms of 'speech,' despite their religious subject matter - and become unprotected 'worship. 1 Second, even if it were possible to draw such a distinction, it would be highly doubtful that to do such would be in the realm of judicial competence. In practice, this would require the university, and ultimately the courts, to inquire into the significance of words and phrases to different faiths. This type of in- quiry would tend to entangle the state with religion in violation of the third prong of the establishment announced by the Supreme Court in Walz v. Tax test 31 Comm'n. Finally, the dissent failed to establish the relevance of such a distinction. The majority said there was no sub- stantial reason why the establishment clause would require different treatment for religious speech designed to win religious converts than for religious worship by persons 0 0 1 fifl already converted. The Court, in equating religious worship to speech, and deciding that the University of Missouri had discriminated against the student group in not allowing their religious worship, then proceeded with the balancing test to determine whether there existed a compelling state to justify the infringement. interest The university claimed that its compelling state interest derived from the establishment clause. The Court held that an "equal access" policy 32 would not be violative of the establishment clause. Central to the Court's establishment analysis is that by creating a forum with equal access the university does not endorse or promote any of the particular ideas aired there. Despite the fact that the religious group would enjoy benefits from access to university facilities, such benefits would be merely "incidental," and therefore not violative of the prohibition against "primary advancement" of religion. There are two reasons for classifying such benefits as "^incidental": first, an open forum in a public univer- sity does not confer imprimatur of state approval on religious sects or practices. This seems a very important statement in the sanction it gives to religious organizations to use public forums clear of establishment problems. clause It seems unlikely that many instances could be conceived of in which the imprimatur of state approval 6 would be conferred by allowing such access to public for33 urns. Second, the forum is available to a broad class of non-religious as well as religious speakers, so that the "primary effect" of the forum is not the advancement of religion. The Court in Widmar stressed the notion that the denial of general benefits to religious groups would cause such results as a church not being afforded police and fire protection. Obviously, the purpose of the establish- ment clause does not require such harsh results. The effect of the pronouncement of Widmar and far reaching. seems direct Religious worship is now speech protected by the first amendment, and virtually impregnable to establishment clause molestation, at least in cases where non-religious speech would be protected. Despite the ostensible breadth of the Court's pronouncement in Widmar, two questions have apparently been left unanswered: 1. If a plaintiff argues that his right to religious free speech has been denied, but couches his argument only in free exercise language, what result; i.e., does the free exercise clause actually afford less deference to "religious speech" than the free speech clause? If a case were argued under free exercise alone, the free speech requirement of content neutrality would obviously not be present. It would seem that the Court would have to weigh the rights of the free exercise claimant against J)§1?0 the requirements of the establishment clause. The Widrnar C o u r t w a s apparently trying to obviate the necessity of doing this, perhaps attempting to relieve some of the tension w h i c h presently exists between the free exercise and establishment c l a u s e s . If this type of establishment an- alysis w e r e required, the Court would go through the traditional three-pronged test: "First, the governmental pol- icy m u s t have a secular legislative purpose; second, its p r i n c i p l e or primary effect must be one that neither ad- v a n c e s nor inhibits religion. must n o t foster . .; finally, the policy 'an excessive government entanglement with 34 religion,*" 2. The second question is whether the free exercise c l a u s e c o u l d be held to actually afford more p r o t e c t i o n to religious free speech than the free speech clause. It seems p o s s i b l e that if there were no establish- ment c l a u s e p r o b l e m s to countermand a given religious speech r i g h t , t h a t analysis under the free exercise clause could subject this right to greater protection than would analy- sis u n d e r the free speech clause. There is no hint of an answer t o this q u e s t i o n in Widmar; indeed, no case t o have dealt w i t h this p o t e n t i a l fact situation. seems However, it could at least be argued that to completely subsume igious free exercise rights into the free speech rel- clause w h e r e religious speech was in question would empty the free exercise clause of its independent meaning and pur- pose. EXEMPTIONS FROM OTHERWISE COMPULSORY LAWS BASED ON REL- GIODS CONSCIENCE In cases where an exemption from an otherwise compulsory law is sought, courts have found both the free clause and the free exercise clause applicable. speech The basic test to be applied in free exercise cases was announced by the Supreme Court in Sherbert challenged under the Sherbert two-part analysis: v. Verner.^^ Regulations test are scrutinized under a First, it must be found that the law or regulation actually burdens the religious er's free exercise of religion. practition- Second, if such burden is found, the state, in order to justify such burden, must be advancing a compelling state interest using the least 36 restrictive means available. The Sherbert test was ad- opted almost verbatim 37 from the free speech test in MMMCP V. Button. articulated On the surface, it would seem that the use of identical tests would preclude different results to be reached between the free exercise and free speech clauses when analyzing a given statute, i.e., if an interest is deemed compelling with respect to a speech challenge it would similarly be compelling with respect to a free exercise challenge. 00172 Two possible exceptions to the above analysis appear to exist. The first exception deals with cases where the law sought to be exempted from infringes on a particular religious activity (speech related or non-speech related) which the court finds to be of central importance to the religion involved. In such limited situations, the Court has added additional weight to the religious practitioner's 38 side of the Sherbert balancing equation. The second exception deals with cases where the activity sought to be exempted is neither "speech" nor integrally incidental to speech. related or Here, there is a marked theoretical difference between the free exercise and free speech clauses. 39 In United States v. O'Brien, the Supreme Court refused to apply the compelling state interest test to an activity which it found to be lacking in a speech related component. Since the free exercise clause theoretically protects against any potential burden on religious practice, speech related or not, the free exercise clause inherently protects a class of rights which the free speech clause does not: non-speech religious activities. The first exception shows a possible difference in the Court's analysis within the Sherbert balancing test between the free exercise and free speech clauses when "centrality" is shown to be present. shows a difference in whether The second the Sherbert test will be applied, based on the assumption that non-speech -mm exception religious activities w i l l not require a compelling state interest p a s s m u s t e r under the free speech A. THE "CENTRALITY" to clause. PRINCIPLE T h e centrality principle, 40 although never presicely d e f i n e d or isolated by the Supreme Court, began to emerge 41 w i t h the C o u r t ' s decision in Sherbert Sherbert, v. Verner. In t h e appellant, a m e m b e r of the Seventh Day A d - v e n t i s t C h u r c h , was discharged by her e m p l o y e r because she could not w o r k on Saturday, the day of her 42 Sabbath. W h e n she applied for unemployment compensation she was d e n i e d benefits because, contrary to a South Carolina u t o r y requirement, stat- she had failed, without good cause, to a c c e p t available suitable work when offerred by the e m p l o y 43 s e n t o f f i c e or employer. A p p e l l a n t calaimed that the South Caroina statute h a d abridged her right to the free exercise of her b y d e n y i n g her unemployment compensation benefits religion because of her religious based conscientious objection to work on Saturdays. 44 The Court, in announcing its two-part balancing 45 test, first held that it was apparent that the inability to receive benefits derived solely from the practice of her religion and that the pressure upon her to forego mn}n that practice, even though economic by nature, was present. unmistakably The notion that Saturday worship was "a cardinal 46 principle of her religious faith" seems to have helped swing the balance in favor of the appellant against the state's avowed compelling interest in preventing dilution of the unemployment compensation fund through the filing of fraudulent claims. Whether the Court consciously con- templated centrality as a distinctive doctrine or principle is uncertain. A year later, the California Supreme Court the language in Sherbert siezed and raised the notion to a 47spec- ifically enunciated principle. In People v. Woody, a group of Navajos met in an Indian hogan in the desert near Needles, California, to perform a religious ceremony which 48 included the use of peyote. Defendants were arrested and 49 convicted for the unauthorized possession of peyote. Defendants pleaded not guilty of the crime of illegal possession of narcotics, contending that their possession of peyote was incident to the observance of their faith and that the state could not constitutionally invoke the statute against them without abridging their right to the free exercise of their religion.^ The California Supreme Court began its analysis 51 by citing the Sherbert balancing test. Key to the court's holding that the free exercise of the defendants had been violated was the notion that the use of peyote played a "central role in the ceremony and practice of the Native 52 American Church. ..." "Although peyote serves as a sacramental symbol similar to bread and wine in certain Christian churches, it is more than a sacrament. Peyote constitutes in itself an object of worship; prayers are directed to it much as prayers are directed to the Holy Ghost. On the other hand, to use peyote for nonreligious 53 purposes is sacreligious." In Woody, the People prin54 cipally relied on Reynolds v. United States, wherein it was held that the prohibition of polygamy did not unconstitutionally violate the religious freedoms of the members of the Mormon religion. The court distinguished Reynolds on the ground that although polygamy was a basic tenent of Mormanism, it was not essential to the practice of the religion. "On the other hand, peyote is the sine qua non of the defendant's faith; the sole means by which defendants are able to experience their religion. In Leary v. United States, the defendant and his eighteen year old daughter were jointly indicted on three 57 counts for offenses pertaining to marihuana. Dr. Leary w a s a m e m b e r of a Hindu sect of India which used marihuana for religious illumination and meditation. 58 According to the Hindu religion, there are thousands of such roads to 59 illumination to god within a person. Leary testified that if he could not use marihuana it would not affect his religious beliefs but he would consider it a violation of h i s reigious beliefs and practices, as well as a violation 60 of m o r a l and p o l i t i c a l rights. His conviction was ap- p e a l e d on these grounds. The Fifth Circuit Court of A p p e a l s said that the f i r s t amendment e m b r a c e s two concepts: f r e e d o m to b e l i e v e . freedom to act and Freedom to believe is absolute but the freedom to act is conditional and relative and may times b e subordinated to the interests of the public fare and the protection of at wel- society. In holding that L e a r y ' s free exercise rights had been violated the court rejected Leary's attempted not dem- o n s t r a t i o n that the experience he found through the use o f m a r i h u a n a was the essence of his religion. There is no evidence in this case that the u s e of m a r i h u a n a is a formal requisite of the p r a c tice of Hinduism, the religion which Dr. Leary professes. At most, the evidence shows that it is considered by some as being an aid to attain conciousness expansion by w h i c h an individual can m o r e easily mediate or c o m m u n i c a t e with his god. Even as such an aid, it is not used by Hindus universally.61 T h e Leary court dealt w i t h the Woody tinguishing it on the basis of case by dis- centrality. W e note an essential difference between Woody and the instant m a t t e r in that peyote in the Woody case played a "central role in the ceremony and practice of the Native A m e r i c a n C h u r c h , a religious organization of the Indians," and that the "ceremony, marked by the sacramental use of peyote, composes the cornerstone of the p e y o t e religion."62 Other non-0.S. Supreme Court cases have held against the individual seeking exemption from governmental regula- tions and have felt the need to distinguish Woody basis of on the centrality.^ 64 In Wisconsin v. Yoder, the Supreme Court again used centrality in its free exercise analysis. In Yoder, respondents were members of the Old Order 65 Amish religion and the Conservative Mennonite Church. Wisconsin's com- pulsory school attendance law required them to send their children to school until they reached the age of sixteen, b u t respondents refused6 6to send their children to school past the eighth grade. Respondents were tried and con- victed of violating the compulsory attendance law and fined 67 the sum of five dollars each. At the trial, respondents defended on the ground that the attendance law violated right to the free exercise of religion. their They showed at trial that their children's attendance at high school was contrary to the Amish religion and way of life. It is a fundamental belief of the Old Order Amish reigion that salvation requires life in a church community separate and apart from the world and worldly influence. 68 This con- cept is "central to their faith." The Court reiterated the Sherbert test, that only those interests of the highest order can overbalance itimate claims to the free exercise of religion. leg- In dis- cussing the qualities of respondent's claims, the Court (jft: 7 8 determined that the Amish were being compelled by statute to perform acts undeniably at odds with fundamental ten69 ents of their religious belief. If this fundamental be- lief had been secularly grounded the exemption would not have been allowed. The Court said that a Thoreau-like personal or philosophical choice would have not been enough to warrant exemption in this setting. Because personal philosophical beliefs are squarely within the protection of the liberties guaranteed by the free speech clause and 70 the court-created freedom of association, it seems the Court does not elevate the compelling state interest requirement in those 71 cases which rely on freedom of speech and association. exacting standard Therefore, it appears that the more that the centrality principle requires shows a difference in application of the free speech and free exercise tests. B. NON-SPEECH RELATED ACTIVITIES 72 In United States v. O'Brien, the defendant and three companions burned their Selective Service registration certificates on the steps of the South Boston Courthouse in violation of an amendment to the Universal Military 73 Training and Service Act of 1948. O'Brien was indicted, tried, convicted, and sentenced in the United States Dis- "fifflTP trict Court for the District of Massachusetts. 74 In the trial, O'Brien argued that prohibiting the knowing destruc- tion or mutilation of certificates was unconstitutional because it was enacted to abridge free speech and because it 75 served n o legitimate legislative purpose. On appeal has argument prevailed; the First Circuit Court of Appeals held the amendment unconstitutional as a law abridging 76 freedom of speech. The Supreme Court reversed the First Circuit Court of Appeals, holding that the burning of the registration certificate did not constitute an act protected by the free speech clause. Analysis under the compelling state interest standard was thereby obviated. The Court said We note at the outset that the 1965 Amendment plainly does not abridge free speech on its face. . . . The Amendment on its face deals with conduct having no connection with speech. It prohibits the knowing destruction of certificates issued by the Selective Service System, and there is nothing necessarily expressive about such conduct. The Amendment does not distinguish between public and private destruction and it does not punish only destruction engaged in for the purpose of expressing views.77 The importance of the O'Brien decision is that the Court refused to apply the compelling state interest test associated with the free speech clause because of their determination that burning the registration certificate was not of the variety of conduct labeled "speech." is apparent from this case that activities classified It which are not "speech," or not integrally related to speech, are not protected by the free speech clause. - W M m 78 As opposed to the O'Brien analysis, religious act- ivities will be protected by the compelling state interest test of the free exercise clause if found to be burdened by a government law or regulation. This shows a difference in treatment between the two clauses, at least in this limited area. An example of this proposition is Thomas v. 79 Review Board. In Thomas, petitioner, a member of the Jehovah's Witnesses, was denied state unemployment compensation benefits after he terminated his employment because his religious beliefs forbade participation in the production of armaments. 8 0 Thomas had been working in a roll foundry 81 for the Blaw-Knox Foundry and Machinery Co. When the roll foundry closed Thomas was transferred to a department 82 that fabricated turrets for military tanks. After dis- covering that all remaining jobs available with the company were weapons related,Thomas quit, asserting that he could not work on weapons without violating the principles of his religion. 83 Upon leaving the company, Thomas applied for unemployment compensation benefits under the Indiana Em84 ployment Security Act. A hearing was held which concluded that although Thomas' religious beliefs specifically pre- cluded him from producing or directly aiding in the manufacture of items used in warfare and that Thomas had ated his employment because of those religious termin- convictions, Thomas' termination was not based upon good cause arising -18- in connection with his work, as required by the Indiana 85 unemployment compensation statute. On appeal, Thomas made the claim of free exercise violation, which sent the Court into the two part balancing Og test. That free exercise was burdened could be taken as true from the Review Board's own determinations, despite the fact that Thomas had difficulty enunciating precise scriptural foundations in support of his view, and that there was another Jehovah's Witness working in the tank turret operation who had no difficulty with religious conscience based upon the military related work. The state interests presented were two-fold: 1) to avoid widespread unemployment and the consequent burden on the fund resulting if people were permitted to leave jobs for personal reasons; and 2) to avoid a detailed8 7probing by employers into job applicants' religious beliefs. Although the Court thought these to be "by no means unim88 portant considerations," the balance was held to fall in favor of Thomas' free exercise claim. First, there was no evidence that an exemption for religious beliefs would encompass enough people to create a possibility of widespread unemployment and the accompanying drain on the unemployment compensation fund. Second, there was no evidence that the exemption would cause employers to make detailed inquiry into applicants' religious beliefs. Thomas shows that religious activities will be pro- tected by the free exercise clause where there is no speech related component. Furthermore, to explain Thomas on cent- 88 rality grounds would seem to be tenuous. that comes from the reading of Thomas The proposition and O'Brien together is that the free exercise clause subjects state laws which infringe pure activity to the compelling state interest test, where free speech does not protect that which is pure activity (i.e., not related to speech). CONCLUSION That the free speech clause protects an assortment of rights which almost completely subsumes the protections of the free exercise clause seems to be neither a logical non sequitur nor a proposition without practical The free speech clause protects from government justification. intrusion the expression of ideas and beliefs which are generic by definition. mar, To include, as the Supreme Court did in Wid- religious ideas and beliefs into the general category of "speech" seems mandated by the free speech requirement of content neutrality. With respect to practical justifi- cation, to allow religious speech to be treated as "speech" obviates the necessity of further complicating the relation- -20- rnr* ship between the free exercise and establishment clauses. Such inclusion also alleviates the necessity of judges and government administrators in making decisions as to what is religious or non-religious in subject matter. The practical significance of Widmar is the wide range of religious activities which can be protected as having a speech related component. In the limited cases where religious activity has no relation to speech the free exercise clause is still available for vindication of the rights of the religious practioner. The free ex- ercise clause is therefore not emptied of independent pur- pose but instead can work in conjunction with the free speech clause to guarantee first amendment liberties. FOOTNOTES 1. "Congress shall make no law. . . prohibiting the free exercise (of religion]." U.S.CONST, amend. I. 2. See, e.g., Heffron v. International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., 452 U.S. 640 (1981)(right to proselytize) . 3. See, e.g., Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205 (1972)(right to forego compulsory school attendance laws); People v. Woody, 61 Cal.2d 716, 394 P.2d 813, 40 Cal.Rptr. 69 (1964)(right to exemption from law prohibiting possession of peyote); see also, Bob Jones University v. IRS, 103 S.Ct. 2017 (1983). 4. See Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145 5. See the balancing test adopted in Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.S. 398 (1963). If, therefore, the decision of the South Carolina Supreme Court is to withstand appellant's constitutional challenge, it must either be because her disqualification as a beneficiary represents no infringement by the State of her constitutional rights of free exercise, or because any incidental burden on the free exercise of appellant's religion may be justified by a "compelling state interest in the regulation of a subject within the State's constitutional power to regulate. . ." Id. at 403, citing NAACP v. Button, 371 U.S. 415, 438 (1963) (a free speech case). 6. See, e.g., McDaniel v. Paty, 435 U.S. 618 (1978); see also Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145 (1878). 7. The term "religious speech" was used by the Court in 1978 in McDaniel v. Paty, 435 U.S. 616 (1978). At least four circuit courts have made use of the term since 1979. See Brandon v. Board of Education of the Guilderland Central School District, 635 F.2d 971 (2d Cir. 1980), cert, denied 102 S.Ct. 970 (1981); O'Hair v. Andrus, 613 F.2d 924 (D.C.Cir. 1980); Gilfillan v. City of Philadelphia, 637 F.2d 924 (3d Cir. 1980); Collins v. Chandler United School District, 644 F.2d 759 (9th Cir.), cert denied 102 S.Ct. 1716 (1981); Jaffe v. Alexis, 659 F.2d 1018 (9th Cir. 1981). (1878). 8. See, e.g., Lovell v. City of Griffin, 303 U.S. 444 (1938); Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263 (1981). 9. See Pfeffer, The Supremacy L.REV. 1115, 1130 (1973). of Free Exercise, 61 GEO. 10. See L.TRIBE, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 814-11, at 862 (1978); see also, e.g., Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205 (1975); People v. Woody, 61 Cal.2d 716, 394 P.2d 813, 40 Cal.Rptr. 69 (1964). 11. Indeed, it has been argued that the centrality principle is the only possible exception to the general proposition that analysis under the free speech clause and the free exercise clause is identical. Marshall, Village of Schaumberg v. Citizens For a Better Environment and Religious Solicitation: Freedom of Speech and Freedom of Religion Converge, LOY. OF L.A.L.REV. 953, 977 (1980). However, this is probably not accurate in that the free speech clause does not protect nonspeech activity, whereas the free exercise clause does. See text accompanying n.12, infra. 12. See United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.S. 367 13. See Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.S. 398 (1963); Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205 (1972); Thomas v. Review Board, 450 U.S. 7 (1981). 14. "Congress shall make no laws respecting an establishment of religion. . . . " U.S.CONST, amend. I. 15. L.TRIBE, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 688-89 16. See Heffron v. International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., 452 U.S. 640 (1981); Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263 (1981). 17. See Thomas v. Review Board, 450 U.S. 705, 721 quoting Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.S. 398, 409 18. 454 U.S. 263, 102 S.Ct. 269 19. Id. 20. Id., 21. Id., 102 S.Ct., at 272, n.2. 22. The regulation provided as follows: (1981). 102 S.Ct., at 272. (1968). (1978). (1981), (1963). 4.D134.0107 No university buildings or grounds (except chapels as herein provided) may be used for purposes of religious worship or religious teaching by either students or nonstudent groups. . . . The general prohibition against use of University buildings and grounds for religious worship or religious teaching is a policy required, in the opinion of the Board of Curators, by the Constitution and laws of the State and is not open to any other construction. Id., 102 S • Ctl • r clt 272, n.3. 23. Id., 102 S.Ct., at 272. 24. Id., 102 S.Ct., at 273, n.5. 25. 452 U.S. 640 26. Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263, 102 S.Ct. 269, 274 (1981). 27. Id., 28. Id. 29. Id., 30. Id. 31. 397 U.S. 664, 668 32. Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263, 102 S.Ct. 269, 275 (1981). 33. Such an instance has been held to exist in the prayer in public school situation. Dicta in Brandon v. Board of Education of the Guilderland Central School Dist., 635 F.2d 971 (2d Cir. 1980), cert, denied-102 S.Ct. 970 (1981) , said that even if the free exercise rights of the student group desiring to pray during school hours had been violated by the denial of permission to pray, the establishment clause would have provided a compelling state interest to defeat their claim. The rationale for applying the establishment clause in this case was the symbolic inference that could be drawn by an impressionable student that the state has placed its imprimatur on a particular religious creed. It was said that although in a "public forum" the rights of poltical speech are the same as those of religious speech, a secondary school is not such a "public for- (1981) . 102 S.Ct., at 281-82, n.2 (White, J., dissenting). 102 S.Ct., at 274, n.6. (1970). -24- mim um." Even though students have first amendment rights to political speech in public schools, such a right does not exist to engage in religious speech because of the establishment clause. "When the explicit Establish ment Clause proscription against prayer in the public schools is considered, the protections of political and religious speech are inapposite." Id., 635 F.2d, at 980. 34. Lemon v. Kurtzman, 403 U.S. 602, 612-13 (1971). 35. 374 U.S. 398 36. Id., at 403. 37. 371 U.S. 415, 438 38. See Marshall, supra 39. 391 U.S. 367 40. Centrality has been defined central or essential to the affected by the prohibition AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 41. 374 U.S. 398 42. Id. at 399. 43. Id. at 401. 44. Id. 45. See note 5 and accompanying 46. Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.S. 398, 406 47. 61 Cal.2d 716, 394 P.2d 813, 40 Cal.Rptr. 69 48. Id., 40 Cal.Rptr., at 70. 49. Id., at 70-1. 50. Id., at 71. 51. Id. 52. Id., at 73. 53. Id. (1963). (1963). note 11, at 977. (1968). as "the element of how religion is the the practice or requirement." L.TRIBE, §14-11, at 862 (1978). (1963). text. 001M -25- (1963). (1964). 54. 98 U.S. 145 (1878). 55. People v. Woddy, 40 Cal.Rptr., at 76. 56. 383 P.2d 851 (5th Cir. 1967), rev'd on other grounds 395 U.S. 6 (1969). Although neither of these cases is of the United States Supreme Court, read together, Leary and Woody show the isolation of a cognizable concept. 57. Id., 58. Id., at 853. 59. Id., 60. Id. 61. Id., at 860. 62. Id., at 861, quoting People v. Woody, 61 Cal.2d 40 Cal.Rptr. 69, 394 P.2d 813 (1964). 63. See, e.g., People v. Crawford, 69 Misc.2d 500, 508, 328 N.Y.S.2d 747, 755 (1972), aff'd 72 Misc.2d 1021, 340 N.Y.S.2d 848 (1973) (LSD and marijuana not central to the church of Missionaries of the New Truth); People v. Collins, 273 Cal.App.2d 486, 487, 78 Cal.Rptr. 151, 152 (1969)(marijuana not essential to religion). 64. 406 U.S. 205 65. Id., at 208. 66. Id. 67. Id., at 209. 68. Id., at 211. 69. Id., at 219. 70. See Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U.S. 705 71. See Marshall, supra 72. 391 U.S. 367 73. Id., at 369-70. 74. Id., at 369. 383 F.2d, at 852. at 857. (1972). (1968). note 11, at 977. (1977). 716, 75. Id. , at 370. 76. Id. , at 371. 77. Id. , at 375. 78. See, e. g., j Stromberg 79. 450 U.S . 707 80. Icy. , at 710. 81. Id. 82. Id. 83. Id. , at 711. 84. Id. 85. Id. , at 711-12. 86. Id. , at 719. 87. Id. , at 719-20. 88. Id. , at 720. California, 283 U.S. 359 (1981). m 1-90 (1931).