The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic behaviour Roman V. Belavkin Middlesex University April 16, 2010 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 1 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Paradoxes of Expected Utility Optimisation of Information Utility Results Example: SPB Lottery References106 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 2 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Paradoxes of Expected Utility Optimisation of Information Utility Results Example: SPB Lottery References106 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 3 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Learning Systems Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 4 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Learning Systems Performance O v t r p t n m k / Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 4 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Learning Systems Performance O v t r p t n m Information O k / k m o q t s u w / Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 4 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Learning Systems Performance O v t r p t n m Information O k / k m o q t s u w / Performance and information have orders, and the relation between them is monotonic. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 4 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Learning Systems Performance O v t r p t n m Information O k / k m o q t s u w / Performance and information have orders, and the relation between them is monotonic. Complete partial orders, domain theory. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 4 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Learning Systems Performance O v t r p t n m Information O k / k m o q t s u w / Performance and information have orders, and the relation between them is monotonic. Complete partial orders, domain theory. Utility theory, information theory Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 4 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Learning Systems Performance O v t r p n m Information O k / t k m o q t s u w / Performance and information have orders, and the relation between them is monotonic. Complete partial orders, domain theory. Utility theory, information theory Allows for treating both deterministic and non-deterministic case: x = f (ω) , x = f (ω) + rand() Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 4 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Expected Utility Theory f : Ω → R a utility function. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 5 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Expected Utility Theory f : Ω → R a utility function. p : R → [0, 1] a probability measure on (Ω, R). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 5 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Expected Utility Theory f : Ω → R a utility function. p : R → [0, 1] a probability measure on (Ω, R). The expected utility Ep {x} := X x(ω)p(ω) ω∈Ω Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 5 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Expected Utility Theory f : Ω → R a utility function. p : R → [0, 1] a probability measure on (Ω, R). The expected utility Z Ep {x} := x(ω) dp(ω) Ω Choice under uncertainty q.p ⇐⇒ Eq {f } ≤ Ep {f } Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 5 / 33 Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Expected Utility Theory f : Ω → R a utility function. p : R → [0, 1] a probability measure on (Ω, R). The expected utility Z Ep {x} := x(ω) dp(ω) Ω Choice under uncertainty q.p ⇐⇒ Eq {f } ≤ Ep {f } Question (Why expected utility?) 1 Ey {f } = f (ω) if y(Ω0 ) = δω (Ω0 ). 2 x.y ⇐⇒ λx . λy, ∀ λ > 0 3 x.y ⇐⇒ x + z . y + z, ∀ z ∈ Y . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 5 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Paradoxes of Expected Utility Optimisation of Information Utility Results Example: SPB Lottery References106 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 6 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility St. Petersburg lottery Due to Nicolas Bernoulli (1713) The lottery is played by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 7 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility St. Petersburg lottery Due to Nicolas Bernoulli (1713) The lottery is played by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. If the head appeared on nth toss, then you win £2n . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 7 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility St. Petersburg lottery Due to Nicolas Bernoulli (1713) The lottery is played by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. If the head appeared on nth toss, then you win £2n . For example n=3 £23 = £8 n=4 £24 = £16 ··· n = 20 £220 = £1, 048, 576 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 7 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility St. Petersburg lottery Due to Nicolas Bernoulli (1713) The lottery is played by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. If the head appeared on nth toss, then you win £2n . For example n=3 £23 = £8 n=4 £24 = £16 ··· n = 20 £220 = £1, 048, 576 To enter the lottery, you must pay a fee of £X Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 7 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility St. Petersburg lottery Due to Nicolas Bernoulli (1713) The lottery is played by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. If the head appeared on nth toss, then you win £2n . For example n=3 £23 = £8 n=4 £24 = £16 ··· n = 20 £220 = £1, 048, 576 To enter the lottery, you must pay a fee of £X How much is £X? Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 7 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Why is it a paradox? We don’t want to pay more than expect to win: X ≤ E{win} Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 8 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Why is it a paradox? We don’t want to pay more than expect to win: X ≤ E{win} How large is Ep {win}? Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 8 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Why is it a paradox? We don’t want to pay more than expect to win: X ≤ E{win} How large is Ep {win}? Let p(n) be the probability of n ∈ N head 1 2 3 4 ··· win £2 £4 £8 £16 · · · 1 1 1 p(n) 12 ··· 4 8 16 n ··· 2n · · · 1 2n · · · Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 8 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Why is it a paradox? We don’t want to pay more than expect to win: X ≤ E{win} How large is Ep {win}? Let p(n) be the probability of n ∈ N head 1 2 3 4 ··· win £2 £4 £8 £16 · · · 1 1 1 p(n) 12 ··· 4 8 16 n ··· 2n · · · 1 2n · · · It is easy to see that ∞ Ep {win} = 2 · X 2n 1 1 1 1 + 4 · + 8 · + 16 · + ··· = =∞ 2 4 8 16 2n n=1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 8 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Why is it a paradox? We don’t want to pay more than expect to win: X ≤ E{win} How large is Ep {win}? Let p(n) be the probability of n ∈ N head 1 2 3 4 ··· win £2 £4 £8 £16 · · · 1 1 1 p(n) 12 ··· 4 8 16 n ··· 2n · · · 1 2n · · · It is easy to see that ∞ Ep {win} = 2 · X 2n 1 1 1 1 + 4 · + 8 · + 16 · + ··· = =∞ 2 4 8 16 2n n=1 One cannot buy what is not for sale. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 8 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Classical solutions Daniel Bernoulli (1738) proposed f (n) = log2 2n = n. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 9 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Classical solutions Daniel Bernoulli (1738) proposed f (n) = log2 2n = n. Note that for any f (n) we can introduce a lottery p(n) ∝ f −1 (n): Ep {f } ∝ ∞ X f (n) n=1 f (n) =∞ Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 9 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Classical solutions Daniel Bernoulli (1738) proposed f (n) = log2 2n = n. Note that for any f (n) we can introduce a lottery p(n) ∝ f −1 (n): Ep {f } ∝ ∞ X f (n) n=1 f (n) =∞ Some suggest to use only f such that kf k∞ := sup |f (ω)| < ∞ Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and economic April 16, behaviour 2010 9 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Northern Rock lottery Due to unknown author (2008) You can borrow a mortgage of any amount £X Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour10 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Northern Rock lottery Due to unknown author (2008) You can borrow a mortgage of any amount £X The amount you repay is decided by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour10 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Northern Rock lottery Due to unknown author (2008) You can borrow a mortgage of any amount £X The amount you repay is decided by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. If the head appeared on nth toss, then you repay £2n . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour10 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Northern Rock lottery Due to unknown author (2008) You can borrow a mortgage of any amount £X The amount you repay is decided by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. If the head appeared on nth toss, then you repay £2n . For example n=3 £23 = £8 n=4 £24 = £16 ··· n = 20 £220 = £1, 048, 576 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour10 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Northern Rock lottery Due to unknown author (2008) You can borrow a mortgage of any amount £X The amount you repay is decided by tossing a fair coin repeatedly until the first head appears. If the head appeared on nth toss, then you repay £2n . For example n=3 £23 = £8 n=4 £24 = £16 ··· n = 20 £220 = £1, 048, 576 How much would you borrow? (£X =?) Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour10 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Allais (1953) paradox Consider two lotteries: A : p(£300) = 1 3 (and p(£0) = 23 ) B : p(£100) = 1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour11 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Allais (1953) paradox Consider two lotteries: A : p(£300) = 1 3 (and p(£0) = 23 ) B : p(£100) = 1 Most of the people seem to prefer A . B Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour11 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Allais (1953) paradox Consider two lotteries: A : p(£300) = 1 3 (and p(£0) = 23 ) B : p(£100) = 1 Most of the people seem to prefer A . B Note that 1 2 + 100 · 0 + 0 · = 100 3 3 EB {x} = 300 · 0 + 100 · 1 + 0 · 0 = 100 EA {x} = 300 · Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour11 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Allais (1953) paradox Consider two lotteries: A : p(£300) = 1 3 (and p(£0) = 23 ) B : p(£100) = 1 Most of the people seem to prefer A . B Note that 1 2 + 100 · 0 + 0 · = 100 3 3 EB {x} = 300 · 0 + 100 · 1 + 0 · 0 = 100 EA {x} = 300 · Remark Safety is preferred (i.e. risk averse). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour11 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Allais (1953) paradox (2) Consider two lotteries: C : p(−£300) = 1 3 (and p(£0) = 32 ) D : p(−£100) = 1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour12 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Allais (1953) paradox (2) Consider two lotteries: C : p(−£300) = 1 3 (and p(£0) = 32 ) D : p(−£100) = 1 Most of the people seem to prefer C & D Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour12 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Allais (1953) paradox (2) Consider two lotteries: C : p(−£300) = 1 3 (and p(£0) = 32 ) D : p(−£100) = 1 Most of the people seem to prefer C & D Note that 1 2 − 100 · 0 − 0 · = −100 3 3 ED {x} = −300 · 0 − 100 · 1 − 0 · 0 = −100 EC {x} = −300 · Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour12 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Allais (1953) paradox (2) Consider two lotteries: C : p(−£300) = 1 3 (and p(£0) = 32 ) D : p(−£100) = 1 Most of the people seem to prefer C & D Note that 1 2 − 100 · 0 − 0 · = −100 3 3 ED {x} = −300 · 0 − 100 · 1 − 0 · 0 = −100 EC {x} = −300 · Remark Risk is preferred (i.e. risk taking). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour12 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Why is it a paradox? 1 U = {0, 1, 2} E{u} = P i Pi Ui = const Increasing utility P3 E{u} = 21 0 P1 1 Remark Any linear functional (e.g. Ep {x}) has parallel level sets. If people use expected utility to make choices, then they are either risk-averse or risk-taking, but not both. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour13 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Prospect theory Due to Tversky and Kahneman (1981) It was proposed that the utility is convex, when the choice is among gains, and concave when the choice is among losses. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour14 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Prospect theory Due to Tversky and Kahneman (1981) It was proposed that the utility is convex, when the choice is among gains, and concave when the choice is among losses. This would make the choice risk averse for gains and risk taking for losses. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour14 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility Prospect theory Due to Tversky and Kahneman (1981) It was proposed that the utility is convex, when the choice is among gains, and concave when the choice is among losses. This would make the choice risk averse for gains and risk taking for losses. Remark This theory is not normative (i.e. it is not derived using rational approach). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour14 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Ellsberg (1961) paradox Consider two lotteries: A : p(£100) = 1 2 (and p(£0) = 12 ) B : p(£100) = unknown Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour15 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Ellsberg (1961) paradox Consider two lotteries: A : p(£100) = 1 2 (and p(£0) = 12 ) B : p(£100) = unknown Most of the people seem to prefer A & B Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour15 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Ellsberg (1961) paradox Consider two lotteries: A : p(£100) = 1 2 (and p(£0) = 12 ) B : p(£100) = unknown Most of the people seem to prefer A & B Note that 1 1 EA {x} = 100 · + 0 · = 50 2 2 Z 1 EB {x} = (100 · p + 0 · (1 − p)) dp = 50 0 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour15 / 33 Paradoxes of Expected Utility The Ellsberg (1961) paradox Consider two lotteries: A : p(£100) = 1 2 (and p(£0) = 12 ) B : p(£100) = unknown Most of the people seem to prefer A & B Note that 1 1 EA {x} = 100 · + 0 · = 50 2 2 Z 1 EB {x} = (100 · p + 0 · (1 − p)) dp = 50 0 Remark More information is preferred. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour15 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Paradoxes of Expected Utility Optimisation of Information Utility Results Example: SPB Lottery References106 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour16 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Extreme Value Problems Unconditional extremum Maximise f (y): sup f (y) Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour17 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Extreme Value Problems Unconditional extremum Maximise f (y): sup f (y) Necessary condition ∂f (ȳ) 3 0. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour17 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Extreme Value Problems Unconditional extremum Maximise f (y): sup f (y) Necessary condition ∂f (ȳ) 3 0. Sufficient, if f is concave. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour17 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Extreme Value Problems Unconditional extremum Maximise f (y): sup f (y) Necessary condition ∂f (ȳ) 3 0. Sufficient, if f is concave. Conditional extremum Maximise f (y) subject to g(y) ≤ λ: f (λ) := sup{f (y) : g(y) ≤ λ} . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour17 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Extreme Value Problems Unconditional extremum Maximise f (y): sup f (y) Necessary condition ∂f (ȳ) 3 0. Sufficient, if f is concave. Conditional extremum Maximise f (y) subject to g(y) ≤ λ: f (λ) := sup{f (y) : g(y) ≤ λ} . Necessary condition ∂f (ȳ) − α∂g(y) 3 0. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour17 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Extreme Value Problems Unconditional extremum Maximise f (y): sup f (y) Necessary condition ∂f (ȳ) 3 0. Sufficient, if f is concave. Conditional extremum Maximise f (y) subject to g(y) ≤ λ: f (λ) := sup{f (y) : g(y) ≤ λ} . Necessary condition ∂f (ȳ) − α∂g(y) 3 0. Sufficient if K(y, α) := f (y) + α[λ − g(y)] is concave. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour17 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Representation in Paired Spaces x ∈ X, y ∈ Y , h·, ·i : X × Y → R Z hx, yi := x(ω) dy(ω) Ω Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour18 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Representation in Paired Spaces x ∈ X, y ∈ Y , h·, ·i : X × Y → R Z hx, yi := x(ω) dy(ω) Ω Separation: hx, yi = 0 , ∀ x ∈ X ⇒ y = 0 ∈ Y hx, yi = 0 , ∀ y ∈ Y ⇒ x=0∈X Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour18 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Representation in Paired Spaces x ∈ X, y ∈ Y , h·, ·i : X × Y → R Z hx, yi := x(ω) dy(ω) Ω Separation: hx, yi = 0 , ∀ x ∈ X ⇒ y = 0 ∈ Y hx, yi = 0 , ∀ y ∈ Y ⇒ x=0∈X Can equip X and Y with kxk∞ and kyk1 . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour18 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Representation in Paired Spaces x ∈ X, y ∈ Y , h·, ·i : X × Y → R Z hx, yi := x(ω) dy(ω) Ω Separation: hx, yi = 0 , ∀ x ∈ X ⇒ y = 0 ∈ Y hx, yi = 0 , ∀ y ∈ Y ⇒ x=0∈X Can equip X and Y with kxk∞ and kyk1 . Statistical manifold: M := {y ∈ Y : y ≥ 0 , kyk1 = 1} Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour18 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Representation in Paired Spaces x ∈ X, y ∈ Y , h·, ·i : X × Y → R Z hx, yi := x(ω) dy(ω) Ω Separation: hx, yi = 0 , ∀ x ∈ X ⇒ y = 0 ∈ Y hx, yi = 0 , ∀ y ∈ Y ⇒ x=0∈X Can equip X and Y with kxk∞ and kyk1 . Statistical manifold: M := {y ∈ Y : y ≥ 0 , kyk1 = 1} Expected value Ep {x} = hx, yi|M Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour18 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Information Definition (Information resource) a closed functional F : Y → R ∪ {∞} with inf F = F (z). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour19 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Information Definition (Information resource) a closed functional F : Y → R ∪ {∞} with inf F = F (z). Example (Relative Information (Belavkin, 2010b)) For z > 0, let E D y ln z , y − h1, y − zi , if y > 0 F (y) := h1, zi , if y = 0 ∞, if y < 0 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour19 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Information Definition (Information resource) a closed functional F : Y → R ∪ {∞} with inf F = F (z). Example (Relative Information (Belavkin, 2010b)) For z > 0, let E D y ln z , y − h1, y − zi , if y > 0 F (y) := h1, zi , if y = 0 ∞, if y < 0 ∂F (y) = ln yz = x ⇐⇒ y = ex z = ∂F ∗ (x) Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour19 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Information Definition (Information resource) a closed functional F : Y → R ∪ {∞} with inf F = F (z). Example (Relative Information (Belavkin, 2010b)) For z > 0, let E D y ln z , y − h1, y − zi , if y > 0 F (y) := h1, zi , if y = 0 ∞, if y < 0 ∂F (y) = ln yz = x ⇐⇒ y = ex z = ∂F ∗ (x) The dual F ∗ : X → R ∪ {∞} is F ∗ (x) := h1, ex zi Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour19 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Utility of Information If x ∈ X is utility, then the value of event y relative to z is hx, y − zi = Ey {x} − Ez {x} Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour20 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Utility of Information If x ∈ X is utility, then the value of event y relative to z is hx, y − zi = Ey {x} − Ez {x} Definition (Utility of information) Ux (I) := sup{hx, yi : F (y) ≤ I} Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour20 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Utility of Information If x ∈ X is utility, then the value of event y relative to z is hx, y − zi = Ey {x} − Ez {x} Definition (Utility of information) Ux (I) := sup{hx, yi : F (y) ≤ I} Stratonovich (1965) defined Ux (I) for Shannon information. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour20 / 33 Optimisation of Information Utility Utility of Information If x ∈ X is utility, then the value of event y relative to z is hx, y − zi = Ey {x} − Ez {x} Definition (Utility of information) Ux (I) := sup{hx, yi : F (y) ≤ I} Stratonovich (1965) defined Ux (I) for Shannon information. Related functions −U−x (I) := inf{hx, yi : F (y) ≤ I} Ix (U ) := inf{F (y) : U0 ≤ U ≤ hx, yi} Ix (U ) := inf{F (y) : hx, yi ≤ U < U0 } Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour20 / 33 Results Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Paradoxes of Expected Utility Optimisation of Information Utility Results Example: SPB Lottery References106 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour21 / 33 Results Information Bounded Utility Definition (Information Bounded Utility) A function f : Ω → R that admits a solution to the utility of information problem Uf (I) for I ∈ (inf F, sup F ) Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour22 / 33 Results Information Bounded Utility Definition (Information Bounded Utility) A function f : Ω → R that admits a solution to the utility of information problem Uf (I) for I ∈ (inf F, sup F ) Theorem A solution to Uf (I) and If (U ) exists if and only if set {x : Fq∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } absorbs function f : ∃ β −1 > 0 : Fq∗ (βf ) < ∞ Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour22 / 33 Results Information Bounded Utility Definition (Information Bounded Utility) A function f : Ω → R that admits a solution to the utility of information problem Uf (I) for I ∈ (inf F, sup F ) Theorem A solution to Uf (I) and If (U ) exists if and only if set {x : Fq∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } absorbs function f : ∃ β −1 > 0 : Fq∗ (βf ) < ∞ Remark (Separation of information) For all I ∈ (inf F, sup F ) there exist β1−1 , β2−1 > 0: Fq (∂Fq∗ (β1 f )) < I < Fq (∂F ∗ (β2 f )) Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour22 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: inf F = F (y0 ) P3 F : L → R∪{∞} , y0 0 1 P1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 0 1 P1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : yn C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Information Topology (Belavkin, 2010a) 1 The topology is defined using an information resource: F : L → R∪{∞} , inf F = F (y0 ) P3 Neighbourhoods of y0 : yn C := {y : F (y) ≤ I} y0 The topology of information bounded functions: 0 1 C ◦ := {x : F ∗ (x) ≤ I ∗ } P1 Generally, f ∈ C ◦ does not imply −f ∈ C ◦ . Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour23 / 33 Results Parametrisation by the Expected Utility hx, ŷi = U (β) 1 0 Binary set Uncountable set −4 −3 −2 −1 0 1 2 3 4 −1 β Let F (y) be negative entropy (i.e. F (y) is minimised at y0 (ω) = const) x : Ω → {c − d, c + d} U (β) = Ψ0 (β) = c + d tanh(β d) x : Ω → [c − d, c + d] U (β) = Ψ0 (β) = c + d coth(β d) − β −1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour24 / 33 Results Parametrisation by Information F (ŷ) = I(β) 2 Binary set Uncountable set 1 −4 −3 −2 −1 0 1 2 3 4 0 β I = Φ0 (β −1 ) , I = β Ψ0 (β) − Ψ(β) Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour25 / 33 Results F (ȳ) = I Parametric Dependency Binary set Uncountable set 1 −1 −0.5 0 0.5 1 0 hx, ȳi = U Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour26 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Paradoxes of Expected Utility Optimisation of Information Utility Results Example: SPB Lottery References106 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour27 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox f : N → R is information bounded iff for some β −1 > 0: ∗ F (βf ) = ∞ X q(n)eβf (n) < ∞ n=1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour28 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox f : N → R is information bounded iff for some β −1 > 0: ∗ F (βf ) = ∞ X q(n)eβf (n) < ∞ n=1 Using P∞ n=1 rn <∞ ∃ β −1 > 0 : βf (n) < − ln z(n) , ∀n ∈ N Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour28 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox f : N → R is information bounded iff for some β −1 > 0: ∗ F (βf ) = ∞ X q(n)eβf (n) < ∞ n=1 Using P∞ n=1 rn <∞ ∃ β −1 > 0 : P where z(n) = q(n) q(n). βf (n) < − ln z(n) , ∀n ∈ N Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour28 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox f : N → R is information bounded iff for some β −1 > 0: ∗ F (βf ) = ∞ X q(n)eβf (n) < ∞ n=1 Using P∞ n=1 rn <∞ ∃ β −1 > 0 : P where z(n) = q(n) q(n). βf (n) < − ln z(n) , ∀n ∈ N Let q(n) = (e − 1)e−n (i.e. 2−n ). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour28 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox f : N → R is information bounded iff for some β −1 > 0: ∗ F (βf ) = (e − 1) ∞ X eβf (n)−n < ∞ n=1 Using P∞ n=1 rn <∞ ∃ β −1 > 0 : P where z(n) = q(n) q(n). βf (n) < − ln z(n) , ∀n ∈ N Let q(n) = (e − 1)e−n (i.e. 2−n ). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour28 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox f : N → R is information bounded iff for some β −1 > 0: ∗ F (βf ) = (e − 1) ∞ X eβf (n)−n < ∞ n=1 Using P∞ n=1 rn <∞ ∃ β −1 > 0 : P where z(n) = q(n) q(n). βf (n) < n , ∀n ∈ N Let q(n) = (e − 1)e−n (i.e. 2−n ). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour28 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox f : N → R is information bounded iff for some β −1 > 0: ∗ F (βf ) = (e − 1) ∞ X eβf (n)−n < ∞ n=1 Using P∞ n=1 rn <∞ ∃ β −1 > 0 : P where z(n) = q(n) q(n). βf (n) < n , ∀n ∈ N Let q(n) = (e − 1)e−n (i.e. 2−n ). For f (n) = n, we have β < 1. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour28 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox Using U = Ψ0f (β) obtain U= 1 , 1 − eβ−1 U0 = 1 1 − e−1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour29 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox Using U = Ψ0f (β) obtain 1 1 , U0 = 1 − e−1 1 − eβ−1 The inverse of function U (β) is β = 1 + ln(1 − U −1 ). U= Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour29 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox Using U = Ψ0f (β) obtain 1 1 , U0 = 1 − e−1 1 − eβ−1 The inverse of function U (β) is β = 1 + ln(1 − U −1 ). U= Using I = β(ln Ψ(β))0 − ln Ψ(β): If (U ) = (1 + ln(1 − U −1 ))U − ln(e − 1) − ln(U − 1) Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour29 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox Using U = Ψ0f (β) obtain 1 1 , U0 = 1 − e−1 1 − eβ−1 The inverse of function U (β) is β = 1 + ln(1 − U −1 ). U= Using I = β(ln Ψ(β))0 − ln Ψ(β): If (U ) = (1 + ln(1 − U −1 ))U − ln(e − 1) − ln(U − 1) Change e to 2 (ln to log2 ). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour29 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox Using U = Ψ0f (β) obtain 1 , U0 = 2 1 − 2β−1 The inverse of function U (β) is β = 1 + ln(1 − U −1 ). U= Using I = β(ln Ψ(β))0 − ln Ψ(β): If (U ) = (1 + log2 (1 − U −1 ))U − log2 (U − 1) Change e to 2 (ln to log2 ). Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour29 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery A Solution of the SPB Paradox Using U = Ψ0f (β) obtain 1 , U0 = 2 1 − 2β−1 The inverse of function U (β) is β = 1 + ln(1 − U −1 ). U= Using I = β(ln Ψ(β))0 − ln Ψ(β): If (U ) = (1 + log2 (1 − U −1 ))U − log2 (U − 1) Change e to 2 (ln to log2 ). For the information amount of 0 bits, the optimal entrance fee is c ≤ U0 = 2. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour29 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery Expected utility, U = hf, p̄i, (n) SPB Lottery −5 2 1 −4 −3 −2 −1 0 1 Parameter, β Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour30 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery SPB Lottery Information, I = Fq (p̄), (bits) 2 −5 1 −4 −3 −2 Parameter, β −1 0 1 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour31 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery Information, I = Fq (p̄) (bits) SPB Lottery 1 1 2 3 4 Expected utility, U = hf, p̄i, (n) 5 6 0 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour32 / 33 References Introduction: Choice under Uncertainty Paradoxes of Expected Utility Optimisation of Information Utility Results Example: SPB Lottery References106 Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour33 / 33 Example: SPB Lottery Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de l’École americaine. Econometrica, 21, 503–546. Belavkin, R. V. (2010a). Information trajectory of optimal learning. In M. J. Hirsch, P. M. Pardalos, & R. Murphey (Eds.), Dynamics of information systems: Theory and applications (Vol. 40). Springer. Belavkin, R. V. (2010b). Utility and value of information in cognitive science, biology and quantum theory. In L. Accardi, W. Freudenberg, & M. Ohya (Eds.), Quantum Bio-Informatics III (Vol. 26). World Scientific. Ellsberg, D. (1961, November). Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75(4), 643–669. Stratonovich, R. L. (1965). On value of information. Izvestiya of USSR Academy of Sciences, Technical Cybernetics, 5, 3–12. (In Russian) Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453–458. Roman V. Belavkin (Middlesex University) The effect of information constraints on decision-making and April economic 16, 2010 behaviour33 / 33