BOOK REVIEW: BIOETHICS BEYOND THE HEADLINES: WHO LIVES? WHO DIES? WHO DECIDES? Authored by: Dr. Albert R. Jonsen * Bioethics Beyond the Headlines. Who Lives? Who Dies? Who Decides? is a book about the growing interest in bioethics and the study of the ethical questions involved in medical science and practice. It is written for the general reader who sees daily media stories about complex topics such as stem cell research, euthanasia, organ transplantation, genetic diagnosis and therapy and other "medical miracles" that offer great benefits but equally perplexing problems. The author, one of the pioneers in the field of bioethics, attempts to explain in plain language what the ethical problems are and how bioethicists attempt to deal with them. LESS BULL, BETTER BIOETHICS Reviewed by: Dr. Jerry Menikojfu . Over the several weeks this was being written, headlines raced across the globe, heralding unsavory doings in the laboratory of the leading Korean stem cell researcher. The story was initially broken by the Washington Post on November 12 with the headline: "U.S. Scientist Leaves Joint Stem Cell Project; Alleged Ethical Breaches By South Korean Cited.,,1 The article went on to note how stem cell pioneer Hwang Woo Suk had obtained some of the human eggs used in his work from junior researchers in his laboratory. It noted that if this was true, his actions would be "in violation of widely held ethics principles that preclude people in positions of authority from accepting egg donations from underlings.,,2 • Albert R. Jonsen, Professor Emeritus of Ethics in Medicine, University of Washington School of Medicine, and Co-director, Program in Medicine and Human Values, California Pacific Medical Center, San Francisco •• Associate Professor of Law, Ethics & Medicine, University of Kansas School of Medicine, and Associate Professor of Law, University of Kansas School of Law. I Rick Weiss, u.s. Scientist Leaves Joint Stem Cell Project; Alleged Ethical Breaches By South Korean Cited, WASHINGTON POST, Nov. 12, 2005, at A2. 2 I d. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1133 2005-2006 1134 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1133 The Washington Post article also noted that Dr. Hwang might have paid the women for providing the eggs, an action that also was described as highly problematic. A researcher at Harvard's Stem Cell Institute was quoted as saying that such payments were in violation of guidelines adopted by the National Academy of Sciences: "There is a right way and a wrong way, and we must be sure to perform this vitally important medical research the right way.,,3 Within two weeks of the revelations, Dr. Hwang admitted that two junior researchers had indeed supplied e§gs and that about 20 of the women who supplied eggs had been paid. He subsequently stepped down as director of the Korean stem cell center. Leading U.S. bioethicist Arthur Caplan co-authored an op-ed claiming that these events demonstrated the need for the U.S. to be playing a prominent role in stem cell research, since otherwise "ethics can get forgotten" as other nations race to be leaders in this field. 5 Hold on a minute. Was everything quite as black-and-white as some of these headlines suggested? Yes, Dr. Hwang had indeed breached commitments to not use his subordinates as sources for eggs and to not pay for the eggs. But to what extent were these two practices violations of "widely held ethical principles"? It is interesting to note that in the United States, which has an extensive and long-standing set of regulations designed to protect human subjects, there is no general prohibition against enrolling a subordinate in a research study. The official Institutional Review Board Guidebook notes that the "issues with respect to employees as research subjects are essentially identical to those involving students as research subjects: coercion and undue influence, and confidentiality.,,6 While it notes that special attention needs to be given to make sure that such subjects are not enrolling as a result of coercion or undue influence, it does not recommend an 3 !d. 4 James Brooke, Korean Leaves Cloning Center in Ethics Furor, N. Y. TIMES, Nov. 25,2005 at AI. The discussion in the text is limited to the ethical issues relating to the recruitment and payment of egg donors. Dr. Hwang was subsequently accused of having fabricated substantial portions of a major paper. See, e.g., Nicholas Wade, . Korean Scientist Said to Admit Fabrication in a Cloning Study, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 16, 2005, at A I. Those accusations, if true, would indeed constitute major violations of "widely held ethical principles." 5 Arthur Caplan & Glenn McGee, Must Support, Regulate Stem Cell Research, TIMES UNION, Nov. 20, 2005 at E I. 6 ROBIN LEVIN PENSLAR, PROTECTING HUMAN RESEARCH SUBJECTS: INSTITUTIONAL REVIEW BOARD GUIDEBOOK, at 6-55 (2d ed. 1993). u.s. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1134 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1135 outright ban on the use of this category of subjects. 7 As for Dr. Hwang's subordinates, there have been few, if any, details regarding the conditions under which he obtained eggs from them. Thus, at best we can say that we don't really have enough information to know whether their participation was truly voluntary. Indeed, the New York Times, writing about Dr. Hwang's resignation less than two weeks after the Washington Post expose, concluded that at the time the egg donations took place, they ''were not considered a legal or ethical vio lation.,,8 And what about the second issue raised with regard to Dr. Hwang's conduct: the fact that he paid these women to supply eggs? As the Harvard stem cell researcher noted, this was the "wrong way" according to the National Academy of Sciences ("NAS") guidelines. The NAS guidelines, however, represent solely the views of that body, which merely acts as an advisor to the federal government. The federal government has not even adopted the guidelines. Thus, they have no binding legal authority. Indeed, these guidelines were developed under unusual circumstances, since the federal government had not even asked for any advice from the NAS, as would be the usual case before the NAS gives its advice. The NAS produced the guidelines in furtherance of an explicit goal, to promote stem cell research, faulting the federal government for its inaction in this area. 9 Moreover, anyone who reads the actual guidelines, at least with regards to paying subjects, will discover that this aspect of them actually does not have that much to do with ethics. The guidelines themselves note that "paying research subjects is 'a common and longstanding practice in the United States.",10 The reason for that practice See id at 6-52 - 6-55. 8 Brooke, supra note 4, at AI. 9 See Nicholas Wade, Scientists Draft Rules for Ethics on Stem Cells, N.Y. TIMES, 7 Apr. 27, 2005, AI. It is interesting to note that the NAS guidelines say very little about many ofthe most controversial aspects of stem cell research, such as whether it is ethical to create new embryos as a source of stem cells. The guidelines deal with such issues by proposing the creation of special ethics committees to review each research study involving stem cells. However, the standards that the committees would use to approve or disapprove such studies are not made clear. 10 NATIONAL RESEARCH COUNCIL AND INSTITUTE OF MEDICINE OF THE NATIONAL ACADEMIES, GUIDELINES FOR HUMAN EMBRYONIC STEM CELL RESEARCH 85 (2005) [hereinafter NRCIM]. The Guidelines also would likely not have permitted Dr. Hwang's collection of eggs from his subordinates. !d. at 85 quoting N. Dickert et al., Paying research subjects: an Analysis of Current Policies. 136 ANNALS INTERNAL MED. 368 (2002); and l.A. Anderson & C. Weijer, The Research Subject as Wage Earner, 23 THEORETICAL MED. AND BIOETHICS 359 (2002). HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1135 2005-2006 1136 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1133 appears to be that "moral principles of fairness and gratitude support providing payment to those who bear the burdens of research on behalf of society.,,11 The guidelines, nonetheless, went on to recommend that, although there is not a consensus on the ethics relating to payment, egg (or sperm) donors should not receive any payments in excess of reimbursement for their direct expenses for donation. 12 In making that recommendation, however, the guidelines state that it was in part because such payments "raise concerns that might undermine public confidence" in stem cell research. 13 Indeed, they go on to specifically note the "strengths of all the arguments surrounding this issue," which include the argument that substantial payments to egg donors (who bear substantial risks and inconveniences) are not only permissible, but should be required as a matter of good ethics. 14 Thus, the NAS itself is acknowledging that its anti-payment position has more to do with good public relations-avoiding any policies that might cause public controversy over stem cell research-than with ethics. A New Primer on Bioethics Lest anyone have thought that the events in early 2005 surrounding the withdrawal of artificial hydration and nutrition from Terri Schiavo were a fluke, this more recent story provides additional support for concluding that bioethics discussions in the media can leave a person less than fully informed about what is really going on. And when people fmd themselves in the situation of wanting a better understanding of such events, they might consider reaching for a cOPls" of Albert Jonsen's new book, Bioethics Beyond the Headlines. 5 Jonsen, Emeritus Professor of Ethics in Medicine at the University of Washington, has played a founding role in the field ofbioethics. He has been influential in a number of ways,16 not least by being a prolific writer. Among other things, he is lead author of one of the most NRCIM, supra note 10, at 85. 12 See id at 85 - 87. 13 Id. at 87. 14Id. 11 ALBERT R. JONSEN, BIOETHICS BEYOND THE HEADLINES: WHO LIVES? WHO DIES? WHO DECIDES? (2005). 15 16 He has served as a member of several prominent bioethics commissions, including the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, and the President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1136 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1137 influential clinical ethics handbooks (now in its fifth edition),17 and is author or co-author of three scholarly works on the history of bioethics. 18 Bioethies Beyond the Headlines is a change from his usual writings, in that it is directed at the general public. Recognizing that complex bioethical issues are often presented by the media "in superficial and inaccurate terms,,,19 Jonsen attempts to provide a more substantive explanation of the most common bioethical issues. The book, a relatively concise 208 pages, is divided into three sections. The first section deals with the core topics of clinical bioethics, including the important role of patient autonomy and its significance in informed consent and in decisions to forgo life support. This section also covers the defmition of death, euthanasia, organ transplantation, assisted reproduction and abortion. The second section is devoted to ethical issues that arise not as part of the clinical encounter between a patient and a doctor, but instead out of our efforts to advance our knowledge. Thus, in this section, Jonsen addresses the rules to protect people who participate as subjects in research studies. He also covers the major hotbutton topics in medical research, including genetics, neuroscience, cloning and stem cell research. The fmal section is directed at topics that he describes as being "beyond the usual borders" ofbioethics. Here he addresses a topic that is of growing prominence: the ethical issues relating to access to health care (including the inability of many people to afford such care). Another major topic dealt with here is that of "ethical relativism": how should we deal with differences in cultural beliefs (such as it being common among certain Asians to not tell a person with terminal cancer that he has a fatal illness) while still being true to the ethical principles that we generally apply in this country? The fmal two chapters in this section address animal ethics and environmental ethics. 20 Obviously, a book of this size cannot provide a comprehensive treatment of such a wide range of topics, nor does Jonsen intend it to do so. He describes the book as a primer, one that will serve as a curious 17 ALBERT R. JONSEN, MARK SIEGLER, & WILLIAM 1. WINSLADE, CLINICAL ETHICS th (5 ed. 2002). 18 ALBERT R. JONSEN, THE BIRTH OF BIOETHICS (1998); ALBERT. R. JONSEN, A SHORT HISTORY OF MEDICAL ETHICS (1999); ALBERT R. JONSEN & STEPHEN TOULMIN, THE ABUSE OF CASUISTRY: A HISTORY OF MORAL REASONING (1988). 19 JONSEN, supra note 15, back cover. The book also has three appendices, providing a "Precis of Moral Philosophy," a "Precis of the History of Medical Ethics," and discussing the "Frankenstein Analogy." 20 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1137 2005-2006 1138 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1133 reader's introduction to this area. 21 Thus, people who already have a fairly extensive background in bioethics should probably go elsewhere for their next bioethics book. But with regard to his chosen audience, Jonsen succeeds admirably in his goals. The book is written in a clear and engaging style, and nicely blends a description of current issues with quite a bit of the historical background, which has been one of Jonsen's lifetime interests. Consistent with the title, most of the chapters are constructed around what appear to be actual newspaper headlines, thus allowing Jonsen to demonstrate how a deeper analysis of a topic will enrich the understanding one might otherwise get from merely a headline or sound bite. He generally avoids the common fault of quickly deciding that one or another view is the "correct" one (a practice that of course does not make for exciting news headlines), noting that in bioethics there often is not a consensus regarding the right answer. 22 There is relatively little jargon or technical terminology; people who are looking for extensive discussions of Kant or deontology will not find it here. What the reader does get, happily, is the wisdom of one of the leading bioethicists, distilled into a very palatable form. A person could do far worse in selecting their first bioethics book. And, hopefully Jonsen will also succeed in his second goal: he hopes this book will not only provide readers with a background in bioethics, but also encourage them to read further. He wants this primer to "prime" a reader's interest for such further explorations. And there is an excellent chance that the book will do just that. Law and Bioethics Since this review is appearing in a health law journal, it seems more than appropriate to say something about the relationship between law JONSEN, supra note IS, at 3. 22 In a book that covers most of bioethics, there will of course be the occasional misstep. In his discussion of withdrawing care from patients in a persistent vegetative state, Jonsen's comments might lead a reader to wrongly conclude that there is a wide consensus in bioethics that keeping such persons alive falls within the category of "futile" care. See id. at 37. He also occasionally misstates some legal points: He comments that the legal standard for informed consent in the United States involves determining what a reasonable person would want to be told (whereas in many states, the standard still looks to what information a physician would generally provide). See id. at 43. He states that in the Baby M case, In re Baby M, 537 A.2d 1227 (N.J. 1988), the Supreme Court of New Jersey enforced a surrogacy contract, when it in fact did just the opposite. Id. at 72. But these are very minor faults in a generally excellent book. 21 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1138 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1139 and bioethics. Time and again, legal issues pop up in Jonsen's book. Within this book are mentions (generally brief) of: the Uniform Determination of Death Act; the legal decisions regarding Karen Ann Quinlan, Nancy Cruzan, Elizabeth Bouvia, and Terri Schiavo; the Schloendorff v. The Society of the New York Hospital23 opinion; the laws regarding refusals of care by Jehovah's Witnesses; the Supreme Court decisions on physician-assisted suicide; the Uniform Anatomical Gift Act and the role of the United Network for Organ Sharing in distributing organs; the Baby M case; Roe v. Wade24 and the federal ban on partial birth abortions; and the federal regulations regarding research with human subjects. Given the frequency with which Jonsen brings up legal issues, it is interesting to note his own viewpoint about the connection between law and bioethics. He addresses this topic in the fmal paragraph of his fIrst chapter: Inevitably, the questions of bioethics mingle with the questions of the law. From the beginning of bioethics, legal scholars have joined the discussion. Many cases involving bioethical questions have come to the courts. Legislatures have passed laws that reflect various bioethical positions. So, it is impossible to describe the field of bioethics without reference to "biolaw," and the reader will fmd many references in the following pages. Despite the prominence of law, a bioethics that seeks to alleviate the human predicament must be, in essence, a philosophical and theological enterprise. 25 It seems, then, that he is somewhat apologetic about the amount of law that shows up in the book, viewing it perhaps as a necessary but not always welcome distraction from the philosophical and theological analyses that form the core ofbioethics. Jonsen might be somewhat overstating the case in suggesting that legal reasoning is a largely distinct endeavor from that ofbioethical analysis. The two might have more in common, particularly in areas of the law where there is little statutory or similar guidance. Indeed, one of Jonsen's own landmark works-The Abuse of Casuistry: A History 23 24 25 105 N.E. 92,211 N.Y. 125 (1914). 410 U.S. 113,93 S.Ct. 705 (1973). JONSEN, supra note 15, at 21. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1139 2005-2006 1140 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VOL.9.2:1133 ofMoral Reasonini 6-describes how modem bioethical thinking owes much to the religious case-based reasoning known as casuistry that was popular hundreds of years ago. Any fIrst-year law student would no doubt recognize the similarity between casuistry and the type of reasoning that courts undertake in answering questions relating to common law. One of this nation's leading legal scholars, Cass R. Sunstein,27 devoted part of his 1994 Tanner Lectures to reaffIrming the importance of casuistry in modem legal decision-making. 28 He noted that case-based analysis (making legal decisions in a framework that does not involve interpreting a specifIc "rule" such as a statute) plays a vital role in our legal system, and that we should consider expanding that role. 29 Even assuming that legal reasoning and bioethical reasoning sometimes follow similar procedures for coming to decisions, it might nonetheless still be the case that these two disciplines apply those procedures to wholly different types of substantive rules. But perhaps even these substantive differences are not always as great as one might suspect. One of the more fascinating academic legal debates in recent years involved Judge Richard Posner's presentation in 1997 of the Oliver Wendell Holmes Lectures at Harvard Law School, which he titled The Problematics ofMoral and Legal Theory.3D Posner argued in these lectures that (1) the work of academic philosophers who specialize in moral issues is of little practical help in making decisions about such issues,3l and (2) more particularly, moral theory should play no role in making legal decisions. 32 The Harvard Law Review subsequently published Posner's lectures with accompanying critical responses 33 from a "Who's Who" of legal luminaries: Ronald JONSEN & TOULMIN, supra note 18. Karl N. Llewellyn Distinguished Service Professor of Jurisprudence, Law School and Department of Political Science, University of Chicago. 28 See generally Problems with Rules, 83 CAL. L. REv. 953 (1995). 29 See id. at 958. 30 Richard A. Posner, The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory, III HARV. L. REv. 1638 (1998). Posner, consistent with his generally prolific nature, subsequently expanded these ideas into a book, RICHARD A. POSNER, THE PROBLEMATICS OF MORAL AND LEGAL THEORY (1999). 31 See Posner, supra note 30, at 1638 - 1692. 32 See id at 1693 - 1709. 33 Ronald Dworkin, Darwin's New Bulldog, 111 HARv. L. REv. 1718 (1998); Charles Fried, Philosophy Matters, 111 HARv. L. REv. 1739 (1998); Anthony T. Kronman, The Value of Moral Philosophy, III HARv. L. REv. 1751 (1998); John T. Noonan, Jr., Posner's Problematics, III HARV. L. REv. 1768 (1998); and Martha C. Nussbaum, Still Worthy ofPraise, III HARv. L. REv. 1776 (1998). 26 27 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1140 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1141 Dworkin/ 4 Charles Fried,35 Anthony Kronman/ 6 John T. Noonan, Jr./ 7 and Martha C. Nussbaum. 38 These are all wonderful articles, discussing an extremely complicated and important issue, and I will not even attempt to present what would no doubt be an overly-simplistic summary here. The only point to be made here is that several of this nation's great legal minds strongly disagree with Posner's conclusions, and believe that moral theory often plays a very significant role in determining what the law is. Justice Fried, for example, states that I am a judge, and I will reaffIrm that my reading, thinking and writing about moral, political and legal philosophy makes a difference to my work. In fact, I regularly test my work as a judge against the arguments that have influenced my thinking about these more academic matters.... [M]aterials of positive law are interpreted in light of morality and in the last analysis are accountable to it. 39 Dean Kronman notes that "Posner badly understates the real, if limited, role that moral reflection can and must play in the decision of cases.... In reality, the role judges occupy is one in which the need for moral reflection is steadier and more insistent than in almost any other position. ,,40 In the clash of viewpoints between Posner and his critics, it is especially noteworthy that the examples that are brought up by both sides often are taken from the field of bioethics. Thus, both abortion and physician-assisted suicide end up being discussed. And, upon reflection, this is not very surprising. Issues in bioethics often constitute so-called "hard cases" where we do not have a clear and explicit statute to reference, which will provide an easy answer to a particular question. In part, this is due to the rapid changes in technology that create new Both Professor of Jurisprudence at Oxford University and Professor of Law and Philosophy at New York University. 35 Former Harvard Law School professor and U.S. solicitor general, and Associate Justice of the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts. 36 Dean of the Yale Law School. 37 Judge on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit. 38 Professor of Law and Ethics in the Law School, Philosophy Department, and the Divinity School of the University of Chicago. 39 Fried, supra note 33, at 1743. 40 Kronman, supra note 33, at 1761-62. 34 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1141 2005-2006 1142 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1133 questions where previously none existed. (We need not have worried about whether having gestated a child or being the genetic mother of a child is a "stronger" sign of motherhood before technology allowed us to have these two aspects residing in two different women). But whatever the cause, it is nonetheless true that to the extent moral reasoning may playa role in legal decision making, it is far more likely to do so in the analysis of bioethics cases than in the more typical case. Thus, the type of analysis that Jonsen provides in his book should be particularly useful to a lawyer (whatever her role) who fmds herself confronting a legal issue that falls within the field ofbioethics. Hopefully Jonsen would not object to the notion that legal decision-makers and commentators are indeed frequently paying attention to the very same moral issues that concern bioethicists. And, in Jonsen's spirit of priming a reader's interest, I will take this opportunity to briefly provide a few appetizers, as it were: food for thought showing how further reading in the legal literature relating to some of the topics Jonsen addresses can contribute to the understanding of the relevant ethical issues: Selective Reduction. In his chapter on abortion, Jonsen concludes with a discussion of how assisted reproductive technology has caused a large increase in multiple gestation pregnancies (a woman who is gestating, for example, four or more fetuses) and the unique dilemma of selective reduction. Such pregnancies, given that the female human body was not designed to carry such a large number of fetuses to term, often result in all of the babies having major health problems. By aborting one or more of the fetuses, an outcome can often be produced where all of the babies have a much greater chance of being healthy. Jonsen notes: Presumably, parents want all of these babies; all fetuses in the multiple gestation are wanted. One or several of the fetuses poses a threat to its siblings. An ethicist opposed to abortion simply would fmd no justification for selective reduction. However, an ethicist opposed to abortion generally but not universally might fmd a selfdefense justification. However, even then, it would not be clear in most cases which fetus is the aggressor and why. The "aggressor" is selected somewhat at random (and is often the smallest fetus). Indeed, can mere HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1142 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1143 coexistence in the same womb count as aggression? ... Selective reduction is truly an ethical paradox. 41 The selective reduction issue naturally leads one to the discussions in the legal literature regarding similar "coexistence" problems. Anyone can benefit from rereading (or better yet, reading for the first time, if they have not yet had the pleasure) Lon Fuller's classic article, The Case of the Speluncean Explorers. 42 Fuller describes a case in the far future (the year 4300), decided by the fictitious Supreme Court of Newgarth. The facts involved a party of amateur cave explorers who end up being trapped underground as a result ofa landslide. 43 They are able to remain in communication with the outside world. 44 Learning that it will take at least 10 days before they can be rescued, they talk with a committee of physicians, which advises them that given their lack of food and water, it is unlikely that they will be able to survive until the rescuers reach them. 45 They then ask if, were they to kill and eat one of themselves, could they could survive long enough to be rescued. 46 That question was "reluctantly" answered in the affrrmative. 47 The explorers all agree to throw dice to determine who is to be eaten, but in the middle of the process of doing that, one of them decides to withdraw from the arrangement. 48 The others force him to participate, and he ends up being the loser; he is killed and eaten. 49 After the successful rescue, the survivors are tried for murder. Fuller's article presents the opinions of the several justices on the fictitious supreme court. 50 He constructed each opinion so that it represents a particular point of view regarding where the law comes from. 51 Fuller's thoughtful analysis of jurisprudence allows the reader to explore how much (or how little) some views of law-making (such as the natural law approach) might overlap with the type of ethical decisions about right and wrong that Jonsen wrestles with in his book. lonsen, supra note 15, at 83. 42 Lon L. Fuller, The Case ofthe Speluncean Explorers, 62 43Id. 44 I d. at 617. 45 Jd. 46 !d. 47 Fuller, supra note 42, at 617. 48 !d. at 618. 49 Jd. 50 See generally id 51 See generally id 41 HARV. L.REv. 616 (1949). HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1143 2005-2006 1144 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VOL.9.2:1133 Fuller's article continues to engage us more than a half-century after it was written, regularly producing new commentary in the legal literature. As recently as 2002, it was employed in analyzing a case involving the separation of conjoined twins, which raises issues very similar to those surrounding multiple gestations. 52 Withdrawal ofArtificial Hydration and Nutrition. In discussing the judicial review of Terri Schiavo's case, Jonsen notes the following: Every [Florida] court recognized that much law existed about similar cases and that, indeed, the U.S. Supreme Court had ruled on a similar case. In 1990, it concluded in the similar case of Nancy Cruzan that "a State may apply a clear and convincing evidence standard in proceedings where a guardian seeks to discontinue nutrition and hydration of a person in persistent vegetative state." 53 Jonsen is of course correct in noting the relevance of the Cruzan 54 decision to the legal analysis of Terri Schiavo's situation. And given that obvious relevance, it is especially interesting to note the paucity of references to that landmark opinion in the otherwise massive amounts of media coverage that led up to Terri Schiavo's death on March 31, 2005. For example, between January I of that year and Schiavo's death, the New York Times 55 and the Washington Post 56 each published only two news articles by its reporters even mentioning the Cruzan case. The minimal attention given to that case during the Schiavo media frenzy is especially surprising, given how much there is to learn from Cruzan. In the Schiavo case, two of the most controversial issues appeared to be (1) the allegedly lax burden of proof standard being 52 See Tom Stacy, Acts, Omissions, and the Necessity ofKilling Innocents, 29 AM. 1. CRIM. L. 481, 486 - 99 (2002) (discussing Fuller's article, the conjoined twins situation, and the nineteenth century real-life lifeboat case, Regina v. Dudley & Stephens, 14 Q.B.D. 273 (1884)). 53 JONSEN, supra note 15, at 39 quoting the Supreme Court's decision in Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Dept. of Health, 497 U.S. 261 (1990). 54 Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Dept. of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 110 S.Ct. 2841 (1990). 55 Denise Grady, The Best Way to Keep Control: Leave Instructions, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 29, 2005, F5; David D. Kirkpatrick & Sheryl Gay Stolberg, How Family's. Cause Reached the Halls ofCongress, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 22,2005, AI. 56 Manuel Roig-Franzia, Catholic Stance on Tube-Feeding Is Evolving; Terri Schiavo Case Reopens International Debate on Ethics and the End of Life, WASHINGTON POST, Mar. 27,2005, A7; Dana Milbank, Legal Experts Say Parents Are Unlikely To Prevail, WASHINGTON POST, Mar. 22, 2005, AI. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1144 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1145 applied by the Florida courts in deciding what Terri Schiavo would have wanted done, and (2) the allegedly barbaric nature of allowing someone to die as a result of withdrawal of artificial hydration and nutrition. Cruzan squarely addressed both of those issues. With regard to the burden of proof issue, the Cruzan decision was actually rather controversial back in 1990. It determined, by only a 5-4 majority, that it was acceptable under the Constitution for a state to require "clear and convincing" evidence of a person's wishes before allowing life-sustaining medical care to be withdrawn. And, tellingly, it was the more conservative block of the Court-including Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justice Scalia-whose views were on that winning side. Justice Rehnquist's opinion for that majority accepted that a state, in effect, could err on the side oflife (where have we heard that concept recently?!) by imposing the more demanding burden of proof The more liberal dissenting four Justices would have not allowed a state to impose such a strict standard; their view was that this type of standard improperly kept people alive too long, unconstitutionally violating their interest in having their wish to die--even if only supported by merely a preponderance of the evidence-respected. And in 2005, what was the relevant law in Florida applicable to Terri Schiavo's case? Florida's statute explicitly required that there be "clear and convincing" evidence of a patient's wishes before lifesustaining care could be withdrawn. In other words, Florida applied the strict standard that was at issue in the Cruzan case, a standard that - but for the swing vote of a single Justice fifteen years earlier - might not have even been constitutionally permissible. How odd, then, that during the Schiavo case much of the media took no notice of the fact that an evidentiary standard that strongly favored the "pro-life" viewpoint, and that barely survived being upheld by the Supreme Court, was suddenly being characterized by many as too generous in allowing people to die. The Cruzan Court had also spoken to another of the most controversial issues regarding Terri Schiavo: the acceptability of allowing someone to die by withdrawing artificial hydration and nutrition. Simply stated, that Court had determined that this issue was not even very controversial back in 1990. Withdrawal of artificial hydration and nutrition was to be treated in the same way as withdrawal of any other form of medical care. Eight of the nine Justices accepted this conclusion. Indeed, even Chief Justice Rehnquist-rare1y considered a wild-eyed liberal-writing for the majority, appeared to acknowledge that the Constitution probably protected a person's right to have artificial hydration and nutrition withdrawn. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1145 2005-2006 1146 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1133 Again, how odd that relatively little attention was paid to these facts by much of the media. Surely it was relevant that a practice that fifteen years earlier was considered non-controversial, even constitutionally protected, by some of the most conservative members of the Supreme Court, was now being recharacterized as some type of cruel invention for killing people off The Cruzan decision-each and everyone of the various opinions-remains a source of much wisdom, no matter what one's political leanings might be. That fact makes it even worse that there has been so little serious discussion of it in the major media, even as there are calls for "tightening up" the burden of proof for allowing care to be withdrawn from future patients. The issues addressed in that case, regarding the appropriate burden of proof, were difficult ones back in 1990, and still remain difficult ones, even today. How to "properly" make a decision for someone when we are not sure what she really wants done remains a vexing problem, whether we treat it as one oflaw or ethics. Whatever we decide, we will be doing a wrong to some people by doing something to them that they would not have wanted done. 57 Determining When a Person is Dead. One of the few issues that was relatively non-controversial in the recent debate over Terri Schiavo was the fact that she was not dead. This is the first substantive topic that Jonsen addresses in his book. 58 And even though many of those who advocated withdrawing artificial nutrition and hydration from Schiavo might have felt that she should be considered dead (she was perhaps "as good as dead"), and thus presumably her wishes would then be irrelevant, such arguments were rarely made. To a significant extent, that is because the debate about where to draw the line between life and death took place decades ago, and is largely settled: a person with a functioning brainstem and a beating heart does not meet the legal defmition of death in any state ofthe u.S. But oddly enough, there is still an ongoing controversy about one aspect of the defmition of death. Jonsen notes the relatively recent practice of obtaining organs for transplantation not only from people who are declared dead under "brain death" criteria (their entire brain has irreversibly ceased functioning, even though their hearts continue to beat), but rather who die as a result of their heart ceasing to beat. These people used to be called non-heart-beating donors, although the See, e.g., JERRY MENIKOFF, LAW AND BIOETHICS: AN INTRODUCTION 322-27 (2001). 58 JONSEN, supra note 15, at 26-27. 57 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1146 2005-2006 BOOK REVIEW 2005] 1147 newest terminology refers to this practice as donation after cardiac death (DCD). In spite of there being specific statutory guidance on this issue-almost all states have adopted a version of the Uniform Determination of Death Act ("UDDA")-there is a significant controversy about whether organs are regularly being removed from DCD donors prior to the time that they meet the legal criteria for being dead. 59 The growing legal literature on this issue addresses many of the same questions that philosophers would ask. Are there fundamental concepts we have in mind-concepts that are embedded in the UDDA-when we decide that someone is dead? The current protocols for removing organs in the DCD context allow a person to be declared dead even though that person could later end up being brought back to life. They allow persons to be declared dead even though they might still have continuing brain function. We are again discovering that core ideas about the nature of our being, long thought settled, can revive themselves to present challenging new issues. Conclusion Over the coming years, issues in bioethics will no doubt continue to attract a great deal of media attention, and playa growing role in 'public policy debates. Jonsen's book is an excellent starting point for beginning an exploration of this field. And hopefully it wi11lead many readers to a further and deeper inquiry-delving into both the philosophical and legal literature, each of which has much to contribute to "alleviat[ing] the human predicament.',(jo 59 See, e.g., ROBERT M. ARNOLD ET AL., PROCURING ORGANS FOR TRANSPLANT: THE DEBATE OVER NON-HEART-BEATTNG CADAVER PROTOCOLS (1995); Jerry Menikoff, Doubts About Death: The Silence of the Institute of Medicine, 26 J. L. MED. & ETHICS 157 (1998); Jerry Menikoff, The Importance of Being Dead: Non-HeartBeating Organ Donation, 18 ISSUES L. MED. 3 (2002); MENIKOFF, supra note 57, at 462-66. 60 JONSEN, supra note 15, at 21. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1147 2005-2006 1148 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1148 2005-2006 [VOL.9.2: 1133 BOOK REVIEW: IS THERE AN ETHICIST IN THE HOUSE? ON THE CUTTING EDGE OF BIOETHICS Authored by: Jonathan D. Moreno* Is There an Ethicist in the House? explores a 25-year personal and professional journey through the field of bioethics just as it was getting off the ground. I was a young philosophy professor who found himself with a rare opportunity: to be part of a new field and help define its issues, as well as a new profession, helping to define its role. This work has taken me from the hospital bedside to congressional hearing rooms and presidential commissions. In these writings I reflect on my experience as clinical ethicist, medical philosopher, historian of medical ethics, and bioethics policy analyst. REFLECTIONS ON AN IMPOSSmLE PROFESSION: A FIRSTHAND ACCOUNT OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF CONTEMPORARY, MULTI-DISCIPLINARY BIOETHICS Reviewed by: Jennifer S. Bard** Jonathan D. Moreno holds an honored place in American society as one of the most credible voices in the application of philosophical training to contemporary moral, ethical and legal problems in clinical medical care and human subject research. 1 This book relates his personal • Jonathan D. Moreno, Ph.D., is the Kornfeld Professor and Director of the Center for Biomedical Ethics at the University of Virginia and a Senior Fellow at the Center for American Progress. He is an elected member of the Institute of Medicine of the National Academies, has served as senior staff for two presidential advisory commissions, and is an advisor for numerous academic, scientific and professional organizations. He is a past president of the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. •• Jennifer Bard, J.D., M.P.H., is an Associate Professor and the Director of the Health Law Program at Texas Tech University School of Law. She is also an Associate Professor (adjunct) Department of Neuropsychiatry, Texas Tech University School of Medicine 1 He became a public figure following his appointment by President Clinton to the President's Advisory Committee on Human Radiation Experiments when he helped uncover a secret Government program of experiments conducted in the late 1940's through the 1960's on the effects of radiation on the human body. These experiments were conducted by the most prominent and respected medical researchers on unHeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1149 2005-2006 1150 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VOL.9.2: 1149 experiences making the transition from a philosopher to. a bioethicist and reflects his views on the ethical issues that concern medical decision making and human research. 2 Apart from and in addition to his status as a public figure, Moreno is well-known in the field of bioethics. Moreno has written a respected text book on clinical ethics, 3 many other books4 and dozens of well-respected articles. 5 He was recently appointed to the highly prestigious Institute of Medicine-an honor awarded to few non-physicians. Because Moreno has achieved success in the fields of individual clinical medical decision making and the ethics of medical research on human populations, the story of his life encompasses all the major developments in two very large and often distinct fields. It is a tribute to the richness of this book that it is difficult to review. There is so much important information that to emphasize some chapters risks the impression of de-emphasizing others. Some of the very best portions of this book are those in which Moreno discusses his own personal experiences. Moreno's recounting of his journey from a professor of philosophy to a hospital ethics consultant, and his reflections on the relationship between the two endeavors represents a suspecting vulnerable populations. The experiments included "feeding radiationlaced breakfast cereal to institutionalized adolescents" without their parents' consent, "exposing cancer patients to total-body irradiation, and irradiating the testicles of subject research. prisoners in state penitentiaries."l Moreno described his discoveries in a well-received book. This led to his continuing interest in the role of the Government in human subject research. He is perhaps best known to the public for refusing an unsolicited appointment to President Bush's National Human Research Protections Advisory Committee; he was quoted as rejecting the appointment because he felt that the other members did not represent a diversity of viewpoints. Rick Weiss, New HHS Panel Makeup Draws Ire of Patient Advocates, WASH. POST, Jan 5, 2003, at A9. 2 JONATHAN D. MORENO, Is THERE AN ETHICIST IN THE HOUSE? ON THE CUTTING EDGE OF BIOETHICS 200 (2005). 3 See, e.g., JUDITH C. AHRONHEIM & JOHNATHAN MORENO ET AL., ETHICS IN CLINICAL PRACTICE (2000). 4 See, e.g., JONATHAN D. MORENO, IN THE WAKE OF TERROR: MEDICINE AND MORALITY IN A TIME OF CRISIS (2003); ETHICAL AND REGULATORY ASPECTS OF CLINICAL RESEARCH (2003); JONATHAN D. MORENO, UNDUE RISK: SECRET STATE EXPERIMENTS ON HUMANS (2001); EZEKIEL J. EMANUEL & JONATHAN MORENO ET AL., JONATHAN D. MORENO, DECIDING TOGETHER: BIOETHICS AND MORAL CONSENSUS (1995); and JONATHAN D. MORENO, ARGUING EUTHANASIA (1995). 5 Most recently Moreno questioned the value of bioethics in the face of the glaring inequalities of access to health care exposed in New Orleans after Hurricane Katrina. See, e.g., Jonathan D. Moreno, In the Wake of Katrina: Has "Bioethics" Failed?, 5 AM. J. BIOETHICS Wl8 (2005). HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1150 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1151 rich resource to all current and asprrmg clinical bioethicists. His chapters recounting the history of medical research on human beings and how it came to be regulated in the United States are meticulously researched and beautifully written. The following chapters, on specific problems in human subject research with vulnerable populations and on the current recognition of the need for protection of the cognitively impaired, are also models of clarity. These will become required reading for anyone seeking to understand how the history of human subject research impacts the current state of regulation and seeking to evaluate the effectiveness of these regulations in contemporary society. But this book is far more than a memoir, a precis, a history, a bedside guide to bioethics, or a reflection on contemporary problems in bioethics. It is an important work of philosophical and sociological thought on the role of the philosopher in bioethics and the role of medical research in society. Moreno takes on the ambitious projects of securing bioethics' place in the history of Western Philosophy and of linking the history of human subject research regulation to the social history of the United States. He shows how bioethics is rooted in the American-developed philosophy of pragmatism and how the growth of regulation of human subject research tracked an erosion of trust in authority during the 1960's and 1970's. Given the depth and richness of this book, I approach my task as a reviewer as first highlighting the achievements of this work and then by reflecting on what it offers to the readers of a journal on health law. In so doing, I take advantage of the privilege of an academic reviewer to apply the book in a way not specifically contemplated by the author. One of the many ways this book succeeds is, as noted above, as a sensitive memoir of the personal events which shaped Moreno's remarkable empathy for the vulnerability of human beings in the face of illness. What becomes clear in this book is that Moreno's understanding of the sick, and especially of the cognitively impaired, goes back to his experience as a child where he grew up on the grounds of a private psychiatric hospital run by his father. 6 There, Moreno knew the patients as friends and saw their vulnerability to the good-will of those who had charge of them. 7 He also attributes his [rrst thoughts about bioethics at the end of life to his feelings of doubt about whether J. L. Moreno, a prominent, Austrian trained psychiatrist who ran the Moreno Sanitarium in Beacon, New Yark. 7 See MORENO, supra note 2, at 154-56. 6 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1151 2005-2006 1152 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL,9.2: 1149 his family understood and correctly carried out his father's wishes to forgo further medical care after what would become a fatal stroke. 8 He writes that his later work, teaching ethics to medical students and consulting in an academic medical center was, and continues to be, impacted by his understanding that it is human nature to see the sick and the vulnerable as "others" because of the inherent fear we all have of becoming like them. 9 This fear is based on the reality that we will all become sick and will depend on others for our care, our comfort and, eventually, to manage our deaths. Moreno is exceptional in his ability to embrace this realization of what will be our common experience and apply it in the service of others. This ability combined with a powerful intellect and an unusual talent to convey subtle and complex ideas in writing and in speech have made him a highly honored teacher, scholar, member of the bioethics community and one of the most important voices in the contemporary debate over medical and research ethics. In this book, Moreno shares aspects of his life with the reader. As a teacher, he presents clearly written and exhaustively researched histories of bioethics in the context of both medical decisions made about individuals and large-scale human subject research. He similarly presents current developments such as the role of bioethics in times of war and the much belated movement to provide protections for the cognitively impaired. As a scholar and philosopher, Moreno fIrmly places clinical bioethics into the tradition of Western Philosophy and shows how it is an important part of the uniquely American philosophy of pragmatism as developed by William James, John Dewey and Charles Pierce. 10 He further shows how bioethics uses the method of Naturalism, which privileges the experience of the philosopher over the application of abstract forms and concepts." As a prominent member of the community of bioethicists, he addresses the role of the bioethicist in the hospital setting. He identifIes the inherent tendency to identify with the doctors and medical staff, who become friends, rather than to maintain the viewpoint as an outsider or patient advocate. 12 He also discusses the criticism that bioethicists lose their ability to provide objective analysis when they are paid for their services, either by the See id. at 35-36. 9 See id. at 26-32. 10 See id. at 49-50. 11 See id. at 51-66. 12 See MORENO, supra note 2, at 15-32. 8 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1152 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1153 medical centers that employ them or by the increasing number of private companies that seek to employ ethical oversight boards. 13 Finally, in his role as a public voice, he explains the history of both clinical and research bioethics as being closely linked to the social climate of the United States. He identifies bioethics as a "child of the sixties" in that it values individual over societal rights and seeks justice for otherwise marginalized members of society. 14 By putting bioethics in the context of social history, he shows that the trend towards greater protection for human research subjects and greater respect for individual patient autonomy are not inevitable, but rather, can and are likely to change should the United States experience severe resource shortages, alone or accompanied by real threats to National Security. Moreno ends the book by speculating that the fear of terrorism brought on by the September 11, 2001 attacks on New York will result in greater interest in public safety and in less individual protection. IS His speculation is founded on how the United States has reacted to past threats to national security by conducting what were at the time secret human experiments. 16 He continues to be a careful observer of the balance between the interests of the individual and society. In Part One "A Hospital Philosopher,,,17 Moreno relates his personal journey from professor of philosophy to bed-side ethicist. Although he attributes the career shift in part to being in the right place at the right time, he turns his remarkable powers of self-reflection and analysis to understanding what it meant for him to move between these two very difficult worlds. Was he a philosopher? A teacher? A healer? Moreno's account of what he learned the medical staff needed from an outside "ethicist" is a blueprint for those entering the field today and also a warning of the inevitable shifting of boundaries when one moves from being an observer of medical decision making to a participant. In Part Two, "Naturalizing Bioethics in Theory and Practice,,,18 Moreno does no less than anchor bioethics in the American school of philosophical pragmatism. He creates a provenance for a subject that has long struggled to define itself within the world of philosophy, which views bioethics' interest in the "real" as evidence of it,S lack of 13 14 15 16 17 18 See id. at 245-47. Id. at 234. See id. at 240-42. See id. at 236. See MORENO, supra note 2, at 3-45. See id. at 49-101. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1153 2005-2006 1154 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1149 intellectual rigor. That will no longer be possible after this book's placement of Bioethics in Western philosophy. Moreno begins his quest to locate the bedside clinical ethicist in the context of philosophy with the observation that ''This encounter with sickness is extraordinarily challenging for one whose primary professional identification is that of philosopher, for the intellectual detachment usually associated with philosophical speculation is at least as difficult to sustain in the oncology unit, for example, and may even seem voyeuristic.,,19 He rejects the charge of voyeurism, however, by noting that rather than seek out this close contact with the sick, "we [philosophers] have been fairly dragged into the fray by beleaguered doctors" who are struggling to balance the new emphasis on patient autonomy with rapid growth in the available medical interventions. zo Moreno writes that the reason doctors feel beleaguered today is that along with rapid advances in medical knowledge and technology that allow doctors to make far more effective interventions have come "during a period in which self-determination has also asserted itself in an equally unprecedented manner, the most obvious expression of this trend being the various civil rights movements."ZI Moreno traces the problem of the relationship between the goals of philosophy and that of medicine back to the earliest recorded intersections between the two, noting that "Plato's Socrates frequently expressed skepticism about the usefulness of a call on the physician. Yet tradition has it that, just before his death, Socrates asked that one of his students give an offering to Aesculapius, the god of healing arts.',zz Moreno sees bioethics as firmly rooted in the Socratic Western 19 See id. at 22. Id. The literature of physician "belaguerment" is vast. For example, in 1998 Professor Fran Miller pointed out the stress to physicians brought on by the rapid change of their role from trusted authority figures, with an essential monopoly on what "precious little" knowledge they had about how to cure disease, to that of being challenged by patients with greater skill at accessing cutting-edge medical information [from the internet]. See Frances H. Miller, Health Care Information 20 Technology And Informed Consent: Computers And The Doctor-Patient Relationship, 31 IND. L. REv. 1019, 1024 (1998); see also Catherine T. Struve, Doctors, The Adversary System, and Procedural Reform in Medical Liability Litigation, 72 FORDHAM L. REv. 943, 948 (2004)(recounting physicians' perception of being under siege by malpractice litigation fueled by improvements in medical knowledge and technology that have heightened consumer expectations, and have led to lawsuits over imperfect results where previously-under less sophisticated treatment-no suit would have been possible). 21 Id. at 28. 22 MORENO, supra note 2, at 22. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1154 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1155 tradition as reflected in the "contextual approach to moral theorizing" which the "major philosophical theorists in the 1980s" such as Richard Rorty and Alasdair Macintyre, were claiming was necessary to free moral philosophy from the reductive process of developing conclusions based on an abstract, Platonic concept of "the good.,,23 Moreno frames the questions that "emerge from this novel relationship between philosophy and medicine" as: "First, does this experience, fascinating as it may be on other counts, have anything to contribute to the ancient line of philosophical inquiry per seT' and "Second, what exactly the philosopher quo philosopher is contributing at the bedside.,,24 His answer to these questions in the remainder of part two is destined to become a foundational document for those seeking to place reflection on medical decision making for individual patients as a branch of "moral philosophy" in the American twentiethcentury movement of "pragmatic naturalism." Moreno explains that the bioethicist must be an activist philosopher participating in the experiences about which he is called upon to evaluate in ethical terms. 25 In Part Three "Human Use,,,26 Moreno limns the history of human subject research in the United States and explores the contemporary debates on protection of vulnerable populations. He accomplishes this by describing the contemporary situation in which human subject research is governed by Federal and State Law and enforced by agencies and persons outside of the research community. In the fIrst section, "Goodbye to all that: The End of Moderate Protectionism in Human Subjects Research," he states that his goal is "neither to challenge nor defend" the current state of regulation but "[r]ather, to note how inured we have become to this grim view of investigator discretion and how far we have traveled to reach this pass.'>27 He divides the history of oversight or regulation of human subject research in the United States into three periods: weak protectionism, moderate protectionism and strong protectionism. 28 He writes that he uses the term "protectionism" to mean "the view that a duty is owed those who participate as subjects in medical research.,,29 Id. at 26. 24 Id. at 22. 25 See id. at 50. 26 See id. at 105-172. 27 MORENO, supra note 2, at 111. 28 Id. at 110-11. 29 Id. at 126. 23 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1155 2005-2006 1156 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1149 He go~s on to state, ''The underlying problem is how to resolve the tension between individual interests and scientific progress, where the latter is justified in terms of benefits to future individuals.,,3o Within that definition, he defines "Weak Protectionism" as "the view that this problem is best resolved through the judgment of virtuous scientists.,,3! Thus, under Weak Protectionism there is no outside oversight of medical research except whatever professional norms develop within the culture of physicians and scientists. Weak Protectionism characterizes the history of human subject research in the United States until the revelations of the horrific actions of physicians in Nazi Germany, which were revealed in the war crimes trial at Nuremberg. Moreno's concise but rich account of the history of human subject research should be required reading for everyone interested in the history of human subject research. It is easy to view the history of human subject research as a series of horrendous ethical lapses,32 followed, upon discovery, by sweeping denunciations and new regulations intended to prevent all future abuses. Moreno's account, however, shows that the reality is far less clear cut. For example, Moreno shows that American physicians and scientists were immediately dissatisfied with the "legalistic" requirements of the Nuremberg Code which demanded informed consent from all research subjects, and this requirement was almost immediately softened in the 1954 declaration of Helsinki to allow for researcher discretion. 33 Moreno explains that rather than seeing the excesses of the holocaust as a danger that could befall anyone, the United States medical community insisted that protections against acts by Nazi's were not needed by men of good character like themselves. 34 This inability or refusal to see the way real commonality between the [d. !d. 32 See e.g., The Tuskegee Syphilis Study, the deprivation of poor, Black sharecroppers of life-saving penicillin in order to study the natural course of syphilis. See Wikipedia, Tuskegee Syphilis Study, at http://en.wikipedia.org/wikifTuskegee _Syphilis_Study (last visited Apr. 6, 2006) (a clinical study, conducted around Tuskegee, Alabama, where 400 poor, mostly illiterate African American sharecroppers became part of a study on the treatment and natural history of syphilis. This study became notorious because it was conducted without due care to its subjects, and led to major changes in how patients are protected in clinical studies. Individuals enrolled in the Tuskegee Syphilis Study did not give informed consent and were not informed of their diagnosis; instead they were told they had "bad blood" and could receive free treatment). 33 MORENO, supra note 2, at 123. 34 See id. at 198-99. 30 31 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1156 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1157 medical experiments of the Nazi period and the prevailing western norms is reflected in consistent chafing against what are often described as "legalistic" regulations that are not relevant to scientists with good moral character and will not stop scientists who lack good moral character. 35 In the fourth part of his book,36 Moreno reminds the reader that the U.S. has been in an almost constant state of war, the Cold War, since the end of World War II. In that context, he details how the Pentagon has always chafed against human subject research regulation seeing it as a threat to their efforts at providing for national defense. Moreno uses clear, clean prose to take the reader through the most difficult and troubling historical incidents of human subject research on "convenient and captive" populations 37 and shows how the same ethical issues exist today as those present when Walter Reed was first conducting Yellow Fever studies on workers digging the Panama Canal. Moreno does not, however, present this history as a tale of the "bad old days" but rather addresses head-on the central problem of human subject research; that it "is a complex, expensive and valued social activity [and that] [o]ne of the conditions that makes it possible is a subject population that is convenient, both in terms of availability for recruitment and for monitoring through the course of a study.,,38 He notes that "[0 ]ne element that crops up repeatedly in the research context is that human subjects are often used in research that is not intended to benefit them but instead other individuals.,,39 Likewise, a population may be used in studies that develop treatments intended mainly, or even exclusively, to benefit other groups. Any reasonably well-formed conception of justice in research will need to reckon with these special circumstances.,,40 He reminds us, however, that "much human-subject research has contributed greatly to human well-being and has been conducted according to sound ethical standards.,,41 By putting research performed on vulnerable or captive populations into the context of scientifically valid efforts by careful researchers to develop new, effective treatments for serious diseases, Moreno avoids presenting this history as some sort of 35 36 37 See id. at 176. See id. at 175-207. See id. at 131-36 (referencing prisoners, institutionalized persons, military personnel, students, and employees of research institutions). 38 MORENO, supra note 2, at 129. 39 Id. at 131. 4° Id. 41 Id. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1157 2005-2006 1158 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1149 Island of Dr. Moreau 42 parade of horribles presided over by scientists with little or no concern about the well-being of their subjects. Moreno describes contemporary regulation of human subject research as being "[t]he essence of strong protectionism [which is] the minimization of clinical researchers' discretion in governing their conduct with regard to human subjects.,,43 This is achieved by "thirdparty monitoring of consent and study procedures, disclosure of financial arrangements or other potential conflicts of interest, required training of investigators in research ethics and research regulations, and independent review of the decision-making capacity of potential subjects.,,44 Moreno recognizes that all research using humans involves the inherent conflict between the needs of the many and the rights of the few. Although it is sometimes confusing that human subject research is in the purview of both clinical medicine, concerned with individuals, and public health, concerned with populations, Moreno shows why this must always be so. He returns to this at the end of the book where he speculates whether the fear of terrorism created after the events of September 11 th , 2001 will result in a backlash against human · . 45 su b~ect protectIon. He writes that: A new preoccupation with "homeland defense" and a renewed respect for the professionals engaged in these efforts, including the granting of greater legal flexibility for espionage activities, could easily spill over into an enhanced image for civilian institutions whose mission is to protect our national survival and therefore less concern about protecting the individual rights of individuals. 46 He further speculates that this lessened concern about individuals could change views about disproportionate allocations of health care resources on "moral strengths.,,47 This concern about the role of bioethics in a time of war is an on-going theme in his current research H.G. WELLS, THE ISLAND OF DOCTOR MOREAU (Leon Stover ed., McFarland 1996) (1896). 43 MORENO, supra note 2, at 110. 42 44/d. 45 See id. at 240-42. at 237. [d. 46/d. 47 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1158 2005-2006 BOOK REVIEW 2005] 1159 and is reflected in wntmgs published subsequent to this book. 48 Moreno suggests that if indeed human subject protection is weakened it will be consistent with what has happened in the United States during other periods of perceived national danger, such as the cold war. 49 Reflecting further on the pressures of bioethics in wartime, the chapter "The Meaning of Nuremberg" raises what continues to be a troubling bioethical issue of the current war on terrorism: the role of physicians in the conduct of war. Moreno shows how ''The Pentagon's ambivalent relationship with Nuremberg Code" has resulted in constant tension between the Code's emphasis on openness and consent and the military's need for secrecy in pursuit of national security. 50 He also returns to the theme of the relationship between human subject protection and fears about national security. Following his book about the human radiation experiments,51 he was often asked by what he then considered "conspiracy" theorists whether there were "secret" human experiments being carried on. 52 At the time he did not think this possible.53 However, hearing that the US had developed a strain of anthrax previously linked to the Soviets, he expresses doubt. 54 Given the news that there are "secret" US interrogation prisons in Eastern Europe, it is not difficult to conclude that these same pressures have resulted in secret human experiments.55 As this was being written, in February 2006, the American tendency to question authority proved to still be vigorous even in the face of foreign threat. There is vigorous debate over the use of torture even though there is little doubt that the US faces serious threats from terrorists. Further, it seems likely that we will eventually be hearing revelations about experiments or research intended to find the most effective torture methods. As the debate on the morality of torture and, in particular, the role of the medical profession in conducting torture continues,56 Moreno's voice will be an important for seeking a rational 48 See, e.g., Jonathan D. Moreno, Detainee Ethics: Terrorists as Research Subjects, 3 AM. 1. BIOETIDCS W32 (2003); Jonathan D. Moreno, In the Wake of Katrina: Has "Bioethics" Failed? 5 AM. J. BIOETHICS W18 (2005). 49 MORENO, supra note 2, at 236-37. 50/d. at 177. 5l JONATHAN D. MORENO, UNDUE RISK: SECRET STATE EXPERIMENTS ON HUMANS (2001). 52 MORENO, 53/d. supra note 2, at 236. at 235. 55 See Robert Jay Lifton, Doctors and Torture, 351 NEW ENG. 1. MED. 415-16 (2004). 56 Id. 54/d. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1159 2005-2006 1160 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2:1149 balance between fears about national security and the danger of losing the hard-won American belief in the value and dignity of all human beings. Finally, part Five of Moreno's book57 considers various challenges to bioethics, many of which come from advances in both medicine and technology, including the ability to read an individuals' genetic code. Moreno considers his own mortality in a new way as he reflects upon his fortieth birthday and speaks quite candidly about his mother's struggle with cancer. 58 Specifically, he comments on the changing relationship between the physician and the patient and how a physician who almost routinely uses the word "cancer" with their patients today would never have done so forty years ago, choosing a more placating euphemism such as "growth" instead. 59 In his next chapter, Moreno discusses the impact that neuroscience has had on society, and specifically the law, with regard to selective serotonin reuptake inhibitors and traumatic brain injury and their implications from the standpoint of determining criminal culpability.60 In this chapter, Moreno also addresses a growing concern of his and of the research community's with the lack of regulation for research with individuals whose cognitive impairments make it difficult for them to give informed consent. In doing so, he proposes addin~ "impaired consent" to the list of legally protected vulnerable subjects. 1 He writes that although medical testing on those with impaired "decision making abilities" is not a new issue as institutionalized persons have always been attractive subjects because of their confinement and ability to be monitored. 62 He also looks at what has become another area of growing concern, which is decision-making by the cognitively impaired. These patients are often researchers' favorite subjects to further advances in Alzheimer's and other such illnesses, but the fact remains that these patients are cognitively impaired and are perhaps unaware of the ramifications of participating in such research. Moreno therefore presents a very serious issue for incapacitated adults, which is the uncertainty of who may authorize such research if these . 63 patients cannot. See MORENO, supra note 2, at 211-50. Id. at 213. 59 Id. at 214. 60 Id at 224-225. 6\ Id at 227. 62 MORENO, supra note 2, at 228. 63 Id. 57 58 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1160 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVlEW 1161 In closing, he addresses a contemporary dispute among bioethicists as to the propriety of serving as paid advisors to commercial entities seeking to develop new medical drugs and devices. 64 As expected, Moreno confronts the most substantial critique of this practice, which is that bioethicists are induced to promote a product because of their financial incentive and therefore their "advisement" is motivated more by their financial gain than their expertise. 65 Moreno then disclosed his own personal experience in serving on a similar board and conveys that he shares a similar perspective as those who defend this practice, which is that "no respectable ethics expert would allow his or her opinion to be bought" and that the problems, which drive corporations to seek ethics advice, are in fact genuine. 66 The Role of the Lawyer-Bioethicist Since this review is written for a law journal and therefore will most likely be read by law students and lawyers interested in clinical ethics, I will give most emphasis to how Moreno's work can inform the role of the "lawyer-ethicist." In so doing, I will also take advantage of the privilege an academic book reviewer has to apply the book in a context, in this case the lawyer-bioethicist, which is not the primary intent of the author. This book is written by a philosopher about the role of philosophy in bioethics, particularly the practice of bioethics. Moreno makes almost no mention of lawyers in his book except to note that although legal training imparts many of the same important skills as philosophy, the natural distrust of lawyers by doctors makes the lawyer somewhat less effective than a philosopher in conducting bioethics consults. 67 In writing about the advantage of his role as a philosopher, he cites "specific advantages for the philosopher as compared to the lawyer in this role, for lawyers are commonly so stereotyped by physicians that it can be difficult for them to be heard as sympathetic or at least neutral. Philosophers can occupy a certain moral high ground, the same high ground that theologians used to be able to claim.,,68 By implication lawyers lack "moral high ground," which impairs their credibility to physicians. ld. at 245-47. 65 ld. at 245. 66 ld. 67 See MORENO, supra note 2, at 29. 68 ld. 64 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1161 2005-2006 1162 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2:1149 I feel comfortable applying Moreno's experience and observation to those with legal training because he, himself asserts that the qualifications of a successful bioethicist are not particular to Philosophers. 69 This is based on his answer to the question he poses early in the book in a section called "Who Teaches Virtue" when he considers the typical dual roles of the bioethicist in an academic medical center. That role involves not just consulting at the bedside but also teaching ethics to medical students. 7o Now what uniquely qualifies philosophers to take on this educational job [educating medical students about ethics]?" The answer is nothing uniquely qualifies the philosopher. Anyone comfortable with the free play of ideas, capable of formulating and assessing arguments, sensitive to connections between seemingly unrelated subjects, and with sufficient intellectual curiosity and selfconfidence to become engaged with a variety of technical languages, can take this on. It does happen that, among the academic disciplines, philosophers are likely to have been trained specifically in the acquisition of these skills and to be self-selected in the possession of the necessary qualities (Moreno, 1991). Clearly, however, individuals from a variety of backgrounds, includin~ law, medicine, or nursing, could be equally qualified." I He notes, however, that lawyers may not be effective because there are specific advantages for the philosopher as compared to the lawyer in this role because "lawyers are commonly so stereotyped by physicians that it can be difficult for them to be heard as sympathetic or at least neutral."n At another point, he notes that the contribution of a lawyer is limited because there is already a defined role for the hospital's lawyers in an ethical dispute-presumably to shield the hospital from liability. 73 Indeed, this is a job of the hospital's lawyer, but it is accomplished every day either by highly skilled individual lawyers who can separate their roles as ethicist and risk manager or by involving two or more lawyers. 69 70 71 72 73 See [d. at 28. See [d. at 26. [d. at 28 (emphasis added). MORENO, supra note 2, at 29. See id. at 19. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1162 2005-2006 BOOK REVIEW 2005] 1163 Moreno's list of desirable traits in a clinical ethics consultant also point to the value of legal training. Moreno notes that "one must be acquainted with relevant statutory and case law, the institutional structure of the healthcare system, the financing of health care, and the prevailing consensus and current issues in health policy.,,74 In reflecting on those "aspect[s] of my philosophical education that is most helpful is the ability to analyze a conceptual problem in a way that may clarify the issues.,,75 He states that to be effective in "work[ing] on ethical problems directly with health care professionals in the real setting of healthcare delivery requires a further range of skills that have little to do with traditional training in any single discipline, including philosophy.,,76 In addition, "some understanding of the economics of health care is very useful, and an appreciation for the sociological and political processes of the clinical setting is essential.,,77 It is no wonder then that Moreno later describes being a bioethicist as an "impossible profession.,,78 Moreno draws an analogy to the observation that "psychoanalysis [is] the impossible profession" because "[h]ow could anyone hope to see into the psyche of another, apart from the vantage point of one's own?" by describing the competing and conflicting demands on the bioethicists as equally impossible. 79 We are expected to be original scholars not only in our own basic disciplines but also in connection with issues in health care. As hu'manists addressing clinicians and scientists, we are also expected to speak with authority on the economics and politics of health care, the system for allocating resources, the psychology of physician-patient relations, and the culture of medicine, among other diverse topics. Who in their right mind would take this one? 80 While the definitive history has yet to be written, lawyers in their capacity of hospital counsel have probably been consulted on difficult bioethical issues for as long as such issues have presented themselves. It has been my personal experience that doctors are able to 74Id.at31. 75/d. at 30. 76 I d.at31. 77 MORENO, supra note 78 Id. at 243. 2, at 33. 79/d. 80/d. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1163 2005-2006 1164 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL,9.2: 1149 make the distinction between lawyers in general and an individual lawyer who is sympathetic to both the very real pressures of having responsibility for the life and well-being of another human and the medical team's deep personal commitment to their patients. Perhaps this is because many doctors have family members who are lawyers and are therefore prepared to accept the possibility that a lawyer is there to help. Finally, and perhaps most helpfully, my experience is that along with the fear doctors have of lawyers there is also a respect for our training in analyzing complex problems and our ability to put thoughts into words. Although it may not be comfortable to be viewed as one of the few "good" or "trustworthy" lawyers, the fact is that the role is sufficiently established to allow the lawyer-ethicist a voice at the table. Further, Moreno's observations about philosophers are more closely analogous to that of lawyers than to bioethicists with medical training. Both lawyers and philosophers must address the primary question of how someone trained outside the medical fraternity can be of use. Moreno defines the work of the ethics consultant as influencing policy rather than simply solving a series of individual problems. S! Lawyers, too, can and do play this role of "policy scientist" or "policy humanist."s2 In this context, Moreno's thoughts, informed by nearly 20 years of experience in this role, are critical to anyone who wants to take on the role of an "ethics expert" in the process of making decisions for other human beings, which arise in a medical context. Since, of course, Moreno is not writing about the lawyerbioethicist, he does not address what is really the primary problem for a lawyer in this situation, which is not that her ideas will be dismissed, but rather that she will be asked to solve the problem by "saying what the law is." Given all their supposed hostility to the law and lawyers, I have found doctors have a completely baseless confidence that there is a definitive legal solution to every problem. The unfortunate truth, which every lawyer dealing with doctors must learn to convey, is that the law establishes boundaries but does not prescribe solutions. In reality, the actual legal issues that arise in bedside clinical ethics are usually so well settled that their resolution plays no role in resolving the issue. If these problems had solutions dictated by law there would be no role for ethical consultation beyond communicating the result to the famil y. 81 I d. at 65. 82 MORENO, supra note 2, at 65. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1164 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1165 It is often the role of the lawyer-bioethicist to clarify for the medical team what, exactly, is meant by the concept of law and the legal system in the United States. First of all, it is important for all lawyers to remember that no matter how many legislators or their aids have legal degrees, lawyers do not make the law. Laws, according to the Constitution, are made by the directly elected representatives of the American people, enacted by the President who is elected through the Constitution's provisions for an electoral college and enforced by citizen juries and, what is in many states the directly elected, judiciary. Thus, every lawmaker casting her vote is in fact representing a very specific, geographically based population of individuals who have voted her into office and can just as easily vote her out. A practicing attorney, even the much maligned "trial lawyer," can do no more than form and present arguments based on existing laws. The second function of the law is to adjudicate disputes between individuals. The power of judges and juries to make binding decisions is delegated to them by society, the same voting public. The law, then, is not imposed on society but rather created by it. The role of law in resolving an issue of patient care is, therefore, completely dependent on whether the issue is law as "prescriptive limit setting," for example outlawing physician assisted suicide, or law as "dispute resolution," such as determining which family member will be allowed to make a decision about terminating life sustaining treatment. Unfortunately, the most bitter disputes arising around medical decision making come from the need to resolve disputes among family members. The Terri Schiavo case which gripped the nation last year is, unfortunately, a quite typical example of how the law shapes medical decision making. 83 The representatives of the citizens of the state of Florida adopted the law which determined that a husband could make medical decisions for his incompetent spouse. 84 Floridians also adopted the judiciary system which determined that Michael Schiavo was Terri Schiavo's lawful husband, that she had not designated any See generally Steven G. Calabresi, The Terri Schiavo Case: In Defense of the Special Law Enacted By Congress and President Bush, 100 Nw. u.L. REv. 151 (2006); see also Schindler v. Schiavo, 780 So. 2d 176, 26 Fla. L. Weekly D 305 (2001); Schiavo ex reI. Schindler v. Schiavo, 358 F. Supp. 2d 1161, 18 Fla. L. Weekly Fed. D 375 (2005). See generally University of Miami Ethics Programs, http://www.miami.edu/ethics/schiavo_projects.htm (last visited Mar. 6, 2006). See also Robert Schindler v. Michael Schiavo ex reI. Theresa Marie Schiavo, 789 So.2d 348 (Fla. 2001). 84 FLA. STAT. ch. § 765.401 (2000). 83 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1165 2005-2006 1166 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VOL.9.2:1149 other decision maker and that he was followin~ her wishes in removing the feeding tube that was keeping her alive. 5 The only role for an ethicist in such a dispute is to attempt to reach a compromise between warring family members. Barring agreement, the family's dispute must be referred to some outside form of decision making. 86 Moreno writes that he discovered early in his career as an ethics consultant that "More often than not, the problem with a current case has to do with a concern or disagreement with a patient's family about the most appropriate course of treatment.,,87 The frequency with which these disputes arise leads Moreno to list "sound interpersonal skills, particularly tactfulness and the ability to mediate among deeply felt differences while honoring them" as a quality which "can vastly enhance the value of the ethics consultant.,,88 So what is the role of the law in resolving clinical bioethical dilemmas? It is that the parameters within which ethicists work in issues such as physician assisted suicide are based on laws created by society, not by lawyers. If individual voters in an individual state wish to allow physician assisted suicide then it is their prerogative to enact a law such as Oregon's.89 The fact that except for Oregon no state allows physician assisted suicide is not an artifact of fancy lawyering; it is the will of the people. Therefore, absent a practice prohibited by specific law, the law does not affect medical decisions. Indeed, the law offers so little help in most situations that many hospitals have their own "folk" beliefs about the law, which, not coincidentally, foster their administrative needs. For example, no state has a law specifying when a hospital must remove the equipment which had been sustaining the physical body of a patient after he is declared brain-dead. The law establishes criteria for brain death and is then silent. Routinely, however, hospitals will The legal drama was Congress' decision to preempt the fact finding role of the Florida state courts and giving it to the Federal court system. 86 Although there is within bioethics a movement to resolve family disputes by mediation rather than adjudication, it is inevitable that as in the case of the Schiavo family some disputes will be left to the courts. See generally NANCY NEVELOFF DUBLER & CAROL B. LIEBMAN, BIOETHICS MEDIATION: A GUIDE TO SHAPING SHARED SOLUTIONS (2004). 87 MORENO, supra note 2, at 13. 88/d. at 31. 89 The Oregon Death with Dignity Act, OR. REv. STAT. § § 127.800-.897 (2003) (permitting physicians to prescribe lethal doses of controlled substances to terminally ill residents of Oregon, but also utilizing certain procedures intended to protect those not "capable" of making an "informed decision"). 85 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1166 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1167 hurry along families by telling them "by law" they must remove their loved one from the machines and refer the "corpse" for burial. This was evidenced in the debacle at Duke University Hospital when the mother of Jesica Santillan, the 12-year-old girl who due to medical error received incompatible organs, was told that the law required Jesica to be removed from the machines within hours of her being declared brain dead. 9o Lawyers are often criticized for discussing this gap in the law in public because of the "harm" it would cause families to know that if they had the money and the inclination they could keep their brain-dead child's body oxygenated indefinitely. What these always extremely well-meaning clinicians seek to avoid is an ugly confrontation with a grieving family in which the hospital must acknowledge that it is no longer willing to provide the patient with a bed. Therefore, unless the family can, at their expense, find a facility willing to accept the patient, the patient will be disconnected from the machines and transferred to a funeral home for burial. Clearly this will create hard feelings at the bedside, but it will not be because of the hospital's requirement to follow the law. So if knowledge of the law itself is not a necessary skill to solving most of the morally difficult decisions that arise when there is no chance of a medical cure, yet no prospect of imminent natural death, what is the role of an ethics consultant-whether she is a lawyer or philosopher or nurse? Moreno accurately identifies that often the most valuable role of the consultant is to provide a perspective outside of the medical model. The consultant, he writes, is the person without medical training who can see the situation as the patient herself might. 91 This truth, the role of the ethicist as a sympathetic outsider, is to me the true value of including outside clinical ethicists in high stakes decision making. The role of the lawyer, as an outsider, is one of our greatest contributions. Reading Moreno's accounts of his early experiences as a consultant in bioethics reminds me of a series of 19th century children's stories 92 which center around the power of the The stories outsider in solving seemingly intractable problems. concern the Peterkins, a large family consisting of a mother, father and six children. 93 The Peterkins were intelligent, educated, kind hearted See generally Jean P Fisher, Duke University Health System Maintains Financial Health, NEWS & OBSERVER, Oct. 6,2005. 91 See MORENO, supra note 2, at 29. 90 LUCRETIA P. HALE, THE PETERKIN PAPERS (The Riverside Press Cambridge 1960) (1914). 92 93 See generally id. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1167 2005-2006 1168 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1149 people who often found themselves in dilemmas from which they could not, as a group, extract thernselves. 94 On one notable occasion, Mrs. Peterkin put salt instead of sugar in her coffee. 95 This, of course, rendered it undrinkable. One by one, members of the family attempted to solve the problem by adding ingredients they hoped would turn the increasingly foul liquid back into coffee. 96 Finally, at desperation's edge, they turned to what would become their final resort in all such situations: they summoned ''The Lady from Philadelphia.,,97 Never named further, ''The Lady from Philadelphia" was a family friend with no special expertise or other training. 98 Yet on this occasion, as on many others, she knew exactly what to do. 99 On arrival, she suggested that Mrs. Peterkin spill out the noxious brew, wash out the cup and pour a new cup of coffee. loo Immediately the problem was solved and all were delighted. 101 No one felt stupid, nor was there ever any indication that the Peterkins lacked normal problem solving abilities or common sense. 102 Rather, they became enmeshed in a group decision making process from which they could see no way out. Only a sympathetic outsider with no personal stake in creating the problem could recognize a solution with which all were happy. Without trivializing the role of the philosopher or lawyer ethicist, it is this position as the sympathetic outsider which can be of the most use in solving a problem that has evaded resolution through the normal model of medical decision making. Moreno provides a perfect example of the ethicist as thinking outside of the prevailing paradigm in recounting a solution devised by his friend, noted bioethicist Art Caplan, a philosopher from Philadelphia. 103 Faced with an emergency room overwhelmed by elderly people suffering respiratory effects of an unusual heat wave, Caplan asked whether Medicaid or Medicare funding could be used to purchase air conditioners. 104 A call to the department of social services found out See generally id. 95 LUCRETIA P. HALE, The Lady Who Put Salt in Her Coffee, in THE PETERKIN PAPERS, at 6 (The Riverside Press Cambridge 1960) (1914). 96 !d. 97 [d. at 12. 98 [d. 99 [d. 100 HALE, supra note 95, at 12. 101 [d. 102 See id. at 6-12. 103 See MORENO, supra note 2, at 71-72. 104 Id. 94 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1168 2005-2006 2005] BOOK REVIEW 1169 that this was possible. The frail elderly were therefore kept safe and comfortable in their homes and no longer needed to seek care in the emergency room. This solution had no basis in the skills of managing an emergency department, developing cost effective treatments for heat stroke or even developing standards for rationing scarce resources. Rather, by thinking of a solution to the problem outside of the world of the hospital, Dr. Caplan was able to devise a solution satisfactory to all parties. Although most problems are not susceptible to such elegant solutions, often an outsider can make a suggestion or see an option simply because she is not tied to the medical model. Moreno recognizes that the lawyer's or philosopher's role as an outsider is most at risk when a lawyer or a philosopher becomes a member of the "team." He writes that to be effective, the consultant must struggle against identifying with the medical team who become colleagues and friends. IDS This natural tendency to identify with people we spend time with can be seen as a form of Stockholm syndrome l06 and is especially dangerous for lawyer-ethicists who are happy to go along with their physician/friends construct because they are anxious to prove themselves a "good" lawyer and not one of the "bad" lawyers who doctors hate. We are so eager to avoid this unfair label and to prove ourselves friendly and sympathetic that we stand to lose what is our real value to the team: our status as a clear-thinking outsider. The title of Moreno's book alludes to this role confusion, and he discusses it further by telling a story about his own tendency to "identify with the physician role." He writes that during a long airplane flight he was "struck by an urgent desire to answer the flight attendants" call for a physician to tend an ill passenger. 107 All of us who seek to do this difficult work must give our thanks to Jonathan Moreno for the careful, self-effacing analysis of the role of ethics consultant which he provides us in this book. As we are all patients and all beneficiaries of the medical advances from human subject research, this latest book by Jonathan Moreno earns its place as an important, rewarding, and delightful addition to the canon of works recounting bioethics' history and setting policy for its future. Id. at 15-32. Wikipedia, Stockholm Syndrome, at http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Stockho1m_ syndrome (last visited Apr. 6, 2006) (a psychological response sometimes seen in a hostage, in which the hostage exhibits seeming loyalty to the hostage-taker, in spite of the danger (or at least risk) the hostage has been put in. Stockholm syndrome is also sometimes discussed in reference to other situations with similar tensions, such as battered woman syndrome, child abuse cases, and bride kidnapping). 107 MORENO, supra note 2, at 15. lOS 106 HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1169 2005-2006 1170 DEPAUL JOURNAL OF HEALTH CARE LAW [VoL.9.2: 1149 In conclusion, the depth and breadth of Is There an Ethicist in the House? is an entertaining read and a valuable contribution to the field of bioethics, whether it is enjoyed by reading it straight through as I recommend - or by dipping into specific chapters of interest. The reward will be an increased understanding of bioethics and, just as important, the opportunity to get to know an extraordinary man. HeinOnline -- 9 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1170 2005-2006