PATERNALISM AND THE ADULT ~1ENTALLY COMPETENT A PECULIAR MEDICAL ETHIC PARTS I & II Dax s. Cowart Independent Research Professor Benson December 1985 000f.6 Paternalism and the Mentally Competent Adult -A Peculiar Medical Ethic Part I Introduction Can coercive medical treatment of a mentally competent adult be justified? I will argue that, ordinarily, it cannot. If we correctly perceive freedom to be a universal normative value that is desirable to maintain as a part of society, then we should require a clear demonstration of need before allowing this value to be limited. The traditional medical ethic often contravenes personal freedom and many other universal normative values as well. At times, it is contrary to state and federal constitutions, state and federal statutes, and the common law as well. I will examine the appropriateness of traditional medical ethics by first inquiring into the desirability of personal autonomy in general. Patient autonomy issues will then be examined to determine if there are meaningful distinctions that can justify the use of a standard different from that used for personal autonomy in general. Part II will begin with a discussion of legal issues concerning patient autonomy and focuses primarily on the question of whether patient autonomy is protected by the fundamental right to privacy guarantee of the United States Constitution. Discussed last is what I believe to be the indicated course of action. Unless otherise stated, all discussions are in reference to a mentally competent adult, the 000~7 2 definition of which is also in controversy. I. Personal Autonomy in General The word "autonomy" is derived from the Greek stems for "self" and "law." It means, literally, the having or making of one's own laws. Its sense is one of self-rule, self-determination, self-government, and independence. Philosopher Joel Feinberg suggests: "Indeed, it is plausible to suppose that the original application and denials of these notions are to states, and that their application to individuals is derivative, in which case personal autonomy is a political metaphor." 1 In a lengthy discussion, he analogizes 2 personal sovereignty to that of a nation. 2 Feinberg's concern is not from where or the manner in which national sovereignty is derived, but rather that it is in fact recognized that is assumed to exist. The right of a sovereign nation to govern its own affairs is generally not questioned. Feinberg freely admits his inability to demonstrate that the doctrine of sovereignty is equally applicable to individuals. However, there are a number of implications that it is. Since nations can exist only in the minds of men, England, France, and the United States exist only because we think of them existing. They cannot think, they cannot feel, and they can have no awareness of, nor appreciation for, sovereignty. Thus, one who recognizes the right to national sovereignty and who recognizes 3 national sovereignty as a desirable concept would seemingly be required to also recognize that its ultimate reason for desirability is that it confers autonomy on a person or persons. By this, I mean to suggest nothing more than the idea that bestowing sovereignty on a nation is nothing more than the bestowing of sovereignty on a group of persons. Autonomy may be exercised collectively, as in a democracy, an ideology of which we generally tend to approve, or it may be exercised by only one or only a few individuals, as in a totalitarian state, an ideology of which we generally tend to disapprove. Whether we agree with a nation's particular form of government or the manner in which it chooses to govern its own affairs has little or no relevance in terms of internationally recognized sovereignty. Except for nations who have expansionist policies or who engage in similar other-regarding acts that are morally difficult to defend, a nation's sovereignty will usually not be challenged by other sovereigns. Of course, a nation that perceives a threat to its own sovereignty may violate the sovereignty of a threatening nation, but that is due to a belief that the threatening nation is engaging in other other-regarding acts, rather than a failure to respect sovereignty. No doubt, one can argue that a nation is collectively recognized as sovereign, sovereign only for reasons such as international and economic stability rather than for any ultimate 4 belief that these people should exercise any freedom of choice over those matters that affect primarily themselves as individuals or that affect the affairs of their nation. However, even if the concept of recognition of sovereignty were to provide to the world no benefit such as international stability, I believe that any attempt of one nation to coercively govern the affairs of another is basically repugnant to most intelligent men and women. If Japan were able to govern Mexico better than Mexico could govern herself, would it be appropriate for Japan to do so and thereby impinge on Mexico's national sovereignty? Again, I believe that most intelligent individuals would consider such an act to be repugnant, not to mention any thoughts that Mexican nationals might be expected to have. I believe that the usurping of personal autonomy is equally repugnant. Daniel Callahan and others have argued in favor of adopting values that enhance benefits to society in a holistic sense, thereby subordinating values that emphasize the desirability of personal autonomy. Therefore, it appears that the Callahan school would probably consider as other-regarding many of the acts which John Stuart Mill would consider as self-regarding. Indeed, it is difficult to read "Autonomy -- A Moral Good, Not a Moral Obsession" without questioning if Callahan is actually advocating a socialist society. He may, in fact, believe, as the title to his article suggests, that autonomy is a moral good. 00030 3 5 However, my perception of a Callahan society is more likened to the regimentation of a hive of bees or a colony of ants than one which provides the opportunity for self fulfillment and happiness. It is not clear how Callahan would have his social base set of values implemented in a pluralistic society or who would make a final determination as to what set of values would promulgate his social objectives. Is personal autonomy to be limited by a group of intellectual elitists and, if so, how are they to be selected? If a majority of the voting public favors personal autonomy values, are they to be subjected to a paternalistic veto, or does Callahan simply favor enlightenment by re-education, i.e., persuading one to autonomously limit his own autonomy? I believe that Callahan ignores human realities and that a society modeled according to his social value criteria would not be one in which many of us would care to live. Some have said that a desire for personal autonomy is mere selfishness and that it is in opposition to altruism and other desirable values. 4 This attitude displays a total lack of understanding, not only of autonomy, but of altruism as well. It is wrong to view a desire for autonomy simply as a desire to act in one's own interests, since we know many individuals autonomously choose to help others. Indeed, if altruism is a selfless concern for others, autonomy is not in opposition to altruism but is in fact required before altruism can exist. True 6 concern for others is an autonomous state of mind, and it cannot be paternalistically mandated or imposed on others. If the autonomous mental state is absent, we have no altruism but simply a tax that has been levied for the welfare of others. While at least the potential exists that such a tax may help the needy, it certainly does nothing to instill the value of altruism in those who are being taxed. The notion that by limiting autonomy, we may enhance altruism is a classic example of treating the symptom rather than the disease. The characterization of personal autonomy as selfishness is also troublesome because of the assumptions that seem to be inherent in any alternative. Autonomy can obviously not be limited unless there is a paternalist or some other person to restrict the exercise of free choice. The proposition that superior results will accrue from such limitations seems to presuppose that it is possible with at least some degree of accuracy to select a proper ruling party who will not himself act in a selfish manner. Perhaps this is possible, but it is my impression that history speaks more kindly of societies that have emphasized personal autonomy and less kindly of societies that have restricted it. I agree with Callahan that personal autonomy should not be treated as a moral obsession, as I do not believe it is a value that necessarily transcends all others. However, it does seem to 7 be very important for self fulfillment and for living a meaningful life. In this respect, autonomy helps to ensure that the individual is treated responsibly and fairly, since he may be expected to choose that alternative which he perceives to be in his own best interest. Without the freedom to choose, he must accept whatever is selected for him regardless of its fairness or quality. This economic principle is clearly reflected in both the prices and quality of food and other items that are often sold in airline terminals, coliseums, ball parks and other similar places where options are either severely limited or simply nonexistent. I believe that it is fair to say that most reasonable men prefer a policy of personal autonomy over one of paternalistic intervention as to those matters which are primarily self regarding. If one agrees that personal autonomy is generally a desirable value, then what parameters are proper? First, autonomy can generally be perceived as freedom of choice over those matters which primarily affect oneself, i.e., self regarding acts such as killing and stealing are perceived as other regarding acts because of their profound effects on other individuals. 1he restriction of such other regarding acts enhance personal autonomy in the sense that it has the effect of allowing the protected individual to carry on in his self regarding activities. Admittedly, many acts that are normally considered to be 8 self regarding in nature can have a ripple effect on others in · S For 1ns . t ance, a homeowner who constructs his roof soc1ety. of cedar shingles primarily affects himself. However, his neighbors may be impacted by a ripple effect, because his actions subject them to a higher risk of fire. A city ordinance prohibiting the use of cedar shingles on the basis that their use creates an unreasonable degree of risk to the community might possibly be controversial as to the issue of unreasonableness, but the principle on which the ordinance was based -- the right of persons to be protected from the unreasonable acts of others can be expected to produce little serious controversy. Suppose, however, that the ordinance were passed strictly to protect the homeowner who is using the cedar shingles. Here, one might expect controversy not only as to the issue of unreasonableness, but also as to the principle upon which it is based, i.e., that of protecting the individual from his own acts. In his writing On Liberty, John Stuart Mill makes what is known as the moral-muscles argument. This argument consists of (i) ([t]he explicit departure from hedonism): The highest good for man is neither enjoyment nor passive contentment, but rather a dynamic process of growth and self-realization, in which uniquely human faculties -perception, judgment, discriminative feeling, powerful human emotion, mental activity, and moral preference are progressively perfected. (ii) These powers, like the muscular powers, are improved only by being used (exercised). (iii) Exercise of the moral muscles requires constant choice-making, which in turn requires freedom to make even foolish (self-regarding) choices, freedom not only from legal coercion, but from the 9 tyranny of customs. (iv) Therefore, interference with free choice hampers the development of distinctive human propensi5ies and whose fulfillment consists of a person's good. Feinberg presents other arguments made by Mill and states in reference to them that [s]ometimes the emphasis is on the actual likelihood of error when an outsider presumes to know an individual's interest better than he: "[T]he strongest of all the arguments against the interference of the public with purely personal contact is that when it does interfere, the odds are that it interferes wrongly, [mistakenly] and in the wrong place." In other places the emphasis is on the advantages of the individual over the others in knowing his own interest: (W]ith respect to his own feelings and circumstances, the most ordinary man or woman has means and knowledge immeasurably 'urpassing these that can be possessed by anyone else. Feinberg later discusses four standard interpretations of the right of self determination. In discussing one of them, he states: A third standard interpretation of the right of self determination holds that it is entirely underivative and morally basic as the good of self fulfillment itself. There is no necessity on this view that free exercise of a person's autonomy will promote his own good, and even where self-determination is likely, on objective evidence, to lead to the person's own harm, others do not have a right to intervene coercively "for his own good." By and large, a person will be able to achieve his own good by making his own decisions, but even where the opposite is true, others may not intervene, for autonomy is even more important than things and personal well being. The life that a person threatens by his own rashness is after all his life; it belongs to him and no one else. For that reason alone, he must be the one to decide -- for better or worse -what is to be done with it in that private realm were the interests of another are not directly involved. I cannot conceal my own preference, at least initially, 10 for position (iii). As the only view consistent with conception of personal sovereignty, it accords uniquely with the self-perception deeply imbedded in the moral attitudes of most people, and apparently presupposed in many of our moral idioms, especially when used defensively, ("my life life §o live as I please," "no one else's business," etc.). Also important to the issue of autonomy are distinctions between de jure and de facto freedom. His option to chijose was closed, even though his option to act was open. An alcoholic who is unable to refuse a drink that is offered to him or a moral individual who wished to engage in a specific act but cannot bring himself to do so because he perceives it as immoral are two examples. "Freedom of action, then, is understood the way the 'unsophisticated person' in Schopenhaver's account understands it: 'I can do what I will: If I will to go to the left; I go to the left; if I will to go to the right, I go to the right. This dependf entirely on my will. Therefore, I am 0 free.' In arguing for the principle of autonomy, Mill prefers to rely on a rationale based on utility rather than a philosophy based on naturalism. This is reflected in his statement: "His voluntary choice is evidence that what he so chooses is desirable or, at least endurable to him, and is good on the whole best provided for by allowing him to take his own means of pursuing it." 11 Here, Mill simply seems to be stating his belief that the maximization of personal good bears a positive correlation to the maximization of personal autonomy, not necessarily in every case, but in most cases. I do not believe that mere coincidence can account for the striking resemblance between the autonomic philosophy expressed 11 by Mill and that of another well known British subject, Adam Smith. Where Mill advocates free choice to maximize utility in terMs of personal good, Smith advocates free choice to maximize utility in the market place. The common feeling expressed by both men is that, when an individual acts on his own volition, net benefits will be enhanced. Neither man claims that this shared principle of free choice will function perfectly on every occasion. Whether it be on an individual or on a collective basis, they only assert that such a policy will normally produce results that are superior to a policy of intervention, regardless of the good intentions or of the claimed expertise of the would-be interventionist. A useful observation can be made regarding the interrelationships between personal autonomy and free markets as they relate to each other and as each of them relates to a sovereign nation. If a gravity test is used to determine majoritarian perception of economic and autonomic desirability, I believe that the directional flow will be the same in each case. Therefore, if I am correct, individuals wishing to relocate could generally be expected to move in a direction that is away from the more restrictive sovereign nations in favor of those nations which are less restrictive. The phenomenon of the Berlin wall and the boat people from Vietnam both seem to suggest the validity of such a hypothesis. I would not expect to hear a serious argument 000~ 12 as to the directional flow in these two examples. However, a determination of the motivating factors responsible for the directional flow might possibly be questioned. As to this matter, formal research is beyond the scope of this discussion. However, based on both my formal and informal education, I. am convinced that personal freedom and economic opportunity are priority considerations for most individuals. In contemplating the subject of autonomy during the last 12 years, I have reached a number of conclusions as to how society generally seems to view personal autonomy, as well as some of the distinctions society seems to make. They primarily revolve around four principles which I refer to as (1) presumption of autonomy, (2) sporting chance, (3) mobility, and (4) identifiable party. Society in general seems to believe that, as to most self regarding acts, an individual has the right to make his own choice regardless of how foolish or dangerous the act may be, as long as the individual has a sporting chance to survive that act, and as long as the individual is sufficiently mobile to be able to assert independence. I will not discuss the presumption of autonomy other than to refer to what has already been stated. However, if the sporting chance and mobility principles are indeed valid, they would seem to implicitly suggest a presumption of autonomy. 13 Sporting Chance Regardless of what rights to autonomy are actually provided for by law, individuals appear to display a belief that they should be free from outside intervention as to their actions that are primarily self-regarding. Even if this should not be true, it could probably be said that, absent a familial, friendship, or other special relationship, this is how the public tends to treat autonomy in practice. However, one restriction that society does seem to place on autonomy might be called the "sporting chance principle." If an individual has at least a sporting chance to survive his act, people tend not to intervene. This appears to be true even in respect to those individuals who might consider intervention desirable. A situation that is analogous to respect for national sovereignty, even where intervention might be thought of as desirable, is the apparent lack of serious efforts to intervene in Evil Kenevil's ill-fated attempt to jump the Snake River Canyon. The federal government did earlier refuse him permission to jump the Grand Canyon; however, this is more properly viewed as a refusal to cooperate or participate rather than as an act of intervention. A similar non-interventionist attitude seemed to exist when Kenevil attempted to jump 14 buses following a spectacular accident that resulted from his failure to complete a jump involving only 13 buses. In each of the foregoing instances, 14 there was substantial risk of death or at least a substantial risk of serious injury. I believe that, because he was perceived as having at least a sporting chance to survive his act, no intervention did, in fact, occur. However, if Kenevil were to attempt a leap from the top of Sears Tower aided only by an ordinary umbrella, active intervention would probably result. The public's tolerance of auto racing, sky diving, and rodeos are other exaQples of the sporting chance philosophy. 12 But how can the public be expected to react if a young man, 18 years old and having no experience in jumping motorcycles, began making final preparations to atte~pt to junp the Snake River Canyon? If intervention occurred, and I believe that it probably would, the sporting chance principle seems to provide the most plausible explanation as to why his attempt should be treated differently from that of his predecessor. 13 However, if the same 18-year-old youth had routinely performed during motorcycle feats since the age of 6, one might expect the public to perceive that he had at least a sporting chance to survive the jump and therefore not intervene. Humorist Jerry Clower refers to this sporting chance philosophy when he says that they never shoot a raccoon while he is still up in the tree. Instead, they shake him out of the tree into a pack of 'coon dogs, because this at least gives the raccoon a sporting chance. A sportsman who will only shoot when a 15 bird is on the wing or one who believes it is unfair to spotlight deer, questions of legality aside, provide other examples. Close ties to the individual, especially those of familial relationships, will often alter the sporting chance philosophy as it relates to personal autonomy, just as it alters reactions in many other areas, as well. However, I believe the sporting chance principle is a valid one in that it explains much of society's behavior and attitudes in matters involving personal autonomy. Hobility The sporting chance principle just discussed does not provide carte blanche assurance of non-intervention. However, once mobility is impaired to such an extent that dependence attaches to the afflicted individual~ a green light is seemingly flashed to society's would-be interventionists. Of course, it is the element of dependence, rather than the lack of mobility itself, that opens the door to restrictions on autonomy. Dependence is relevant only because it confers on the would-be interventionist the most essential element of the paternalism equation. That element is the power to control. Unless the paternalist has or is perceived by the subject as having control, the subject is free to act in whatever manner he may wish. The great importance of mobility is made quite clear when viewed in terms of options that may be lost when one becomes immobilized. The option to leave an undesirable or unendurable 16 environment is completely closed unless there is another party who is willing to assist the immobilized individual. Communications and amenities such as food, drink, clothing, and entertainment are available only at the will of the provider. If the immobilized individual objects too strongly or refuses to cooperate, he risks losing what services are being offered and other retaliatory measures that are calculated to promote compliance. In short, one who is immobilized often finds himself with few, if any, viable alternatives, in which case the provider becomes "the only game in town." To a large degree, the rules are determined by the discretion of the provider. He is able to choose among total compliance, total dominance, or an intermediary course of action. However, once mobility is lost, autonomy that is otherwise respected, will often be disregarded or severely curtailed. The sporting chance decision making process has been discarded in favor of a more restrictive one, i.e., decisions are made on the basis of what the paternalist believes to be in the best interest of the immobilized individual. To some degree, the mobility principle just discussed casts doubt on the validity of the sporting chance principle that was discussed earlier. One could argue that, since the vitality of the sporting chance principle seems to be limited to that time 17 when the individual is still mobile, then there is no general approval or respect or personal autonomy. Unfortunately, there are many instances in which such an argument has merit. The sovereignty of nationalist individuals alike are all too often not recognized out of a respect for sovereignty, but merely as a function of the relative strength and power that another sovereign is able to exercise. Such behavior would tend to indicate that paternalistic instincts are often present, but merely waiting on the sidelines until a more favorable balance of power is obtained. There are also other explanations of why intervention seems to accompany immobilization. Illness and infirmity seem to fan latent paternalistic emotions as a result of pity for or a desire to help the immobilized individual. I believe that this occurs because of a tendency by the paternalist to equate physical disability and illness with mental incapacity to make decisions for oneself. I am inclined to suggest that this tendency is so strong that there almost seems to be a presumption of incapacity in such situations, but, alas, as all true presumptions are rebuttable, the term would probably be inaccurate if so used. Identifiable Party As was earlier mentioned, relationships will often alter one's behavior and attitude regarding autonomy. Therefore, we often act differently in situations that involve close friends or 18 relatives than we do in instances that involve total strangers. We also tend to act differently in instances that involve what I refer to as the identifiable party. The identifiable party concept is a first cousin to the sporting chance principle. While t·he sporting chance principle is concerned with the likelihood that death or serious injury will occur, the identifiable party concept is more concerned with a determination of which party will ultimately die or incur serious injury. I believe that most of us are convinced that cigarette smoking will in ~any instances lead to fatal lung cancer. It also seems evident that a large percentage of society would nevertheless favor a policy of auonomy regarding an individual's decision to smoke. Therefore, society seems to reason that, even though cigarette smoking will often lead to fatal lung cancer and even though little can be said for the necessity or benefits of smoking, we should allow individuals the autonomy to smoke, because we do not know which individuals will die and, therefore, each individual who does smoke has a sporting chance to survive. However, I do not believe that it would be entirely speculative to suggest that society would be much less tolerant of an autonomous right to smoke if all smoking produced an absolute certainty of death. In respect to self-regarding matters, most of us have the autonomy to make those choices that we perceive to be in our own best interest. But even in those instances where we choose a 19 course of action that we know not to be in our own best interest, we still usually desire and indeed expect the freedom to make those choices as well. Most of us will concede that junk food, smoking, drinking, and speeding are not particularly conducive to the maintenance of our own health and safety. Those of us who engage in all or some of these activities probably prefer that our freedom to do so not be restricted. As anyone who has been exposed to constitutional law should well know, the sword that is used to restrict personal freedom can, and does, cut both ways. Before any of us attempt to restrict the personal autonomy of others, we should first examine our own autonomous desires and consider the inherent jeopardy in which they are placed when attempting to restrict the self-regarding acts of others. II. Medical Ethics and Paternalism Most arguments seeking to justify medical paternalism, or at least those of which I am aware, seem to follow two basic strands. The dominant strand tends to concern itself with best interests of the patient, while the other strand tends to concern itself with best interests of society. If one is to justify medical intervention under either of these concepts, he should also be able to demonstrate the validity of the concept as well. Therefore, challenges in these areas will be included in my overall argument opposing medical paternalism. 20 Medical Ethics -- Universal or Professiona1 14 In discussing what he believes to be the proper approach to forQulating a medical ethic, ethicist Robert Veatch contends "A medical ethic should be an integral component of a universal ethic, one which neither dichotomizes the ethical and the scientific nor oakes ethical rightness dependent on membership in . 1 ar pro f ess1ona . 1 group. any part1cu II 15 II . e later questions: What is this concept of professional ethics which is appealed to so frequently as the unique responsibility of a professional group, and why is it that the professional is thought to be in a better position than laymen, including the ethicist, to make the policy choices necessary to 15solve problems in his field of technical competence? To answer the second question, Veatch relies upon what he calls "the fallacy of generalization of expertise." Stated simply, it is the view that professionals with technical competence in a particular area also have some peculiar expertise in the nontechnical system of values from which criteria are drawn to make decisions from questions which make y~e of the technical information in their area. According to Veatch, the decision making process consists of primary and secondary components. One secondary factor is the cathectic identification with certain groups. This generates psychological predispositions to formulate problems in peculiar ways and identify with the interests of the reference group. Another is the cultural identification with certain systems of meaning which generate cultural predispositions to use synbol systems, understand words, and interpret reality in characteristic patterns. Primary factors in the decision-making process include, 21 first, empirical data about the "relevant facts" in the situation and, second, a system of evaluation of those facts to lead to a policy decision. It is often observed that the secondary factors influence greatly the perception of the relevant facts as well as the system of evaluation. Further, the system of evaluation itself influences the selectioy of "relevant facts" and the perception of those facts. 8 He illustrates the problem of generalization of expertise by quoting a physician who is sensitive to the problem: "[a]n abortion is no more a medical question than capital punishment through execution is a problem in electrical engineering." 19 Dr. Adrian Rogers recently expressed a similar view when he stated "Whereas the social well being of a person is the legitimate concern of his or her doctor, doctors have no special professional knowledge of how to improve their patients' social well being: This remains the concern of all men." 20 Rogers goes on to say that [d]octors are more inclined to enter into public controversy about issues such as abortion, contraception for those under-sixteens and euthanasia than about any other areas of medical practice. In fact, what these three areas have in comnon is that they primarily involve doctors in judgmental decisions which are far more social than medical. In each case, the medical component is almost irrelevant and it is the personal ethics of the individual doctor which decides that doctor's behaviour. He offers several si@ple examples: (l) The selection of a method for euthanasia is a medical decision, to implement the method is a social one. (2) The selection of a method of abortion is a medical decision; the decision to implement the method is 99 per/cent a social one • . (3) The selection of a method of contraception for a girl of fourteen is 22 a medical one. The decision to issue the contraception is a purely social one. These are areas where the doctors have assumed god-like roles and where their ethical behavior has b2~ught them into greatest conflict with society. "There is need to distinguish between clinical and social decisions made by doctors and to admit that social decisions are better made by more than one person and preferably by people from different professions." 22 In essence, Dr. Rogers is presenting his version of ''the fallacy of generalization of expertise," which was earlier presented by Veatch. Although I certainly would not consider Dr. Rogers to be a friend or advocate of personal autonomy, "[u]nless doctors make public their agreed ethical principles patients will effectively be left to shop around and try to have their wishes fulfilled." 23 lie does at least recoBnize the physician's limitation of expertise . 1 1ssues. . 24 t o d ec1'd e soc1a Several "clinical caveats" are offered by Drs. David Jackson and Stuart Younger. "Physicians \~ho are uncomfortable or inexperienced in dealing with the complex psychosocial issues facing critically ill patients may ignore an important aspect of their professional responsibility by taking a patient's or faoily's statement at face value without further exploration or clarification." 25 In the same article, they later state: If the depression is adequately treated, or as is more frequently encountered, is reactive to physical discomfort that can be relieved, the patient may well change his or her mind. The astute must be alert for a 23 history of endogenous depression, vegetative signs of depression and any acute conditions to which the patient may be reacting. Vigorous attempts to treat the causes of depression should be made before automat~gally acquiescing to the patient's wishes. Dr. Jackson's and Dr. Younger's concerns are legitimate ones that if, properly implemented, do not violate the concept of autonooy. As it is generally understood, autonony requires competency, knowledge, etc. However, the inquiry \vhich they advocate is subject to caveats of its own. ''If the HICU team can deal effectively with the underlying real problem, the plea for death with dignity may change radically." 27 Based on observations as well as my own personal experiences, many individuals within and without the medical profession assign underlying "real" reasons where there are none. In my own case, there were physicians who stated that I was incompetent to refuse treatment because of the physical discomfort I was experiencing. Their alternative argument for those times during which I experienced at least some degree of relief from pain was that I was incompetent to make such a . decision because my thinking was being impaired by the pain shots that I was receiving. This is a Catch-22 situation in the truest sense. My own physician' refusal to respect patient autonomy persisted even after the two psychiatrists, called in to assess ny mental competency, had declared me mentally competent to make any decision that I wished. 28 However, even the psychiatrists 24 who declared me to be mentally competent mistakenly assessed the "real" cause. The Hasting Center report published by Dr. Robert \~hite and Trish Englehart, identified the "real" cause of my refusal as a desire on my part to "control" the situation. In their report, they incorrectly concluded that my eventual consent to skin grafts, which I had earlier successfully refused, was a result of my finally being able to demonstrate that I was in control. 29 This analysis could not have been more incorrect. My consent to surgery was the direct result of a conversation in which the head nurse on night duty informed me that I was going to live regardless of whether I consented to the skin grafts and that all I was doing was prolonging my stay in the hospital and extending the period during which I would have to continue to undergo the painful tanking. If I had been given actual control, I would have neither consented to surgery nor remained in the hospital. Even the terminology "physical discomfort" used by Jackson and Younger is indicative of part of the problem. It seems to be common practice for physicians to refer to even extremely painful procedures as "physical discomfort." The deceitfulness which is inherent in such terminology may result in a patient consenting to treatment which he would otherwise refuse. It does little to enhance the physician-patient relationship, including the physician's credibility as perceived by the patient. Physicians 00050 25 also appear to actually view pain in terms of physical discomfort, which might well be accountable for the unwillingness of many physicians to accept pain as being the "real" cause for refusal. Therefore, I am pleased that Jackson and Younger assert that pain can be a real reason for a patient's refusal of treatment, even though their reference is made via an exceedingly understated term. There are those, however, who remain unconvinced that "medical expertise does not a value judgment expert make." 30 Clements and Sider contend "Previously, a physician-patient consensus was assumed based on medical values through the act of consulting an expert on those values -- the physician." 31 • 32 They spend much time lamenting the move away from a traditional medical ethic to an ethic that emphasizes patient autonomy. "We want to make clear that the move from naturalist ethics to formalist ethics has never been justified sufficiently." For an ethic appropriate to medicine, we require a clinical ethic, an ethic that begins with an understanding of the status of norms in medicine. Such norms are discoverable, and, while they are refined by consensus, they are not merely social constructs or subjective choices or minor factors in total well-being. On the contrary, they are basic: biological bottom lines. Moreover, within the clinical context, ethical conduct is determined by the facts of the situation, understood in terms of these norms. Thus, clinical ethics is concerned primarily with adaptation, function, and best interest. But such an ethic is also modest. It claims no infallible principles by which treatment decisions may be made. :loreover, medical norms merely fit limits on the range of what is adaptive. They do not prescribe with precision. And it 26 is only as normative function is reestablish that the patient as decision maker that he is truly free to take control of his life. So although clinical ethics recognizes the importance of respecting the patient's wishes and the value of sharing relevant information with the patient, these issues take their rightful place within a larger context. Such a posture is not arrogant or Godlike paternalism. More consistent with the Hippocratic tradition it insists that autonomy or formalism is an inappropriate foundation upon which to build medical ethics. When we as physicians act in the best interests of our patients, we do so with the firm hope that, when 3~e time comes, our physicians will do the same for us. At this point I believe it useful to reflect on the foregoing views. Veatch has basically argued that mere technical expertise does not automatically confer expertise over values which are related to that technical area. However, he does acknowledge that technical expertise may provide some special insight in some instances. 34 Rogers seems to hold little regard for patient autonomy, but he does agree with Veatch in that he strongly emphasizes the distinction between decisions which are primarily medical in nature and those that are primarily social in nature. Along with his belief that physicians have no special expertise when it comes to decisions that regard social values, his view is that such social values are better made by all men, preferably of different professions. He appears, however, to be concerned as much with the image of the medical profession as he is with patient welfare. 35 Clements and Sider appear to believe that the medical profession alone has the ability to make medical decisions, including the making of value 27 judgments related to medical practice. Their recommended clinical approach to medical ethics seems to be heavily based on th~ir belief that physiological factors usually impair the patient's decision-making capacity. However, they also seem to imply that, even when not physiological, these decisions should be left to 36 J . . . the wh 1m o f t h e p h ys1c1an. ac k son an d y ounger are supportive of patient autonomy, but emphasize the need to determine the "real" or underlying reason that a patient may be refusing treatment rather than merely accepting his autonomous demands at face value. 37 Most, if not all, fundamental universal normative values are difficult, if not impossible, to prove from an intrinsic point of view. Therefore, arguments will generally assume a naturalist, utilitarian, religious, or similar approach. Therefore, though most of us have an innate belief that killing or stealing is wrong, we have difficulty demonstrating that they are wrong unless we use an approach similar to one of those just mentioned. Otherwise, the argument is reduced to a mere shouting match. I believe that it is helpful to subject universal normative values to utilitarian or other types of analysis, because by doing so we may sometimes better understand the reasons why we hold these values. Pragmatically, I believe that from a pragmatic standpoint we can start from a standpoint of accepting a number of these values as being true. Therefore, in this vein, I would 28 like to suggest that killing, stealing, lying, cheating and slavery are properly perceived as being wrong, while not killing, not stealing, truth-telling, fairness, and freedon are properly perceived as being right. If agreement here can be reached, and for the most part I believe it can, these values so stated are at least in a general sense desirable values and ones which we wish to maintain in our society. The next step then is to decide when, if ever, exceptions should be made to these rules or at least when, if ever, there should be special applications applied to such values. It is in this area that most controversies are likely to arise. Does self defense, war, or capital punishment for one who has killed another human being justify killing? Is stealing justified in those cases where one is starving or one is economically discriminated against? Is it proper to lie if, by doing so, we are able to shield one from anguish? May personal freedoo be limited for the good of society overall or when we believe is in the individual's best interest? Also relevant is the question of determining the appropriate manner in which to ~ake a decision when these values compete with each other. Thus, one may have to decide between preserving the freedom of oneself and of one's country and the competing value of not killing. Some would assign a higher importance to the value of freedom and would therefore kill in order to preserve freedom, while others, {)(J0~4 29 such as some religious sects, place a higher importance on not killing. Therefore, when questions of free exercise of religion and free speech, both of which are guaranteed in the First Amendment, have been raised by the school prayer issue, they have been balanced against the Establishment Clause in the same amendment. A mother's fundamental right to privacy, e.g., the right to an abortion, has been balanced against the State's interest in potential life. The traditional medical ethic has apparently, either consciously or subconsciously, engaged in such a balancing procedure. Under that ethic, the highest value could probably be stated as "do[ing] no harm to the person." 38 Therefore, one could expect a physician, if he follows the traditional school in medical ethics, to deceive a patient if he feels it would be in the patient's best interest. Therefore, he might lead the patient to believe that he will recover when actually his condition is terminal. He might lie to a patient who has a history of heart problems in order to prevent psychological trauma that could create a risk of heart attack. And he might be expected to force a mentally competent adult to undergo unwanted medical treatnent if he felt it were in that individual's best interest. The limitations that the traditional medical ethic has placed on universal normative values or, at a ninimuQ, the manner 30 in which they have been applied has gone virtually unchallenged for years. However, with technological advances, a heightened sensitivity to civil liberties, and various other changes have resulted in serious attacks on the traditional medical ethic. If universal normative values are to be contravened, especially those which are reflected to at least some degree in the U.S. Constitution, I do not think that it would be unreasonable to require a clear showing to be made that such an action is justified. Most arguments that attempt to justify the usurping of universal normative values that flow from the traditional medical ethic tend to gravitate around one or more of the following areas: (1) the physician's oath, duty, and responsibility; (2) the physician's expertise in knowing what is in the best interest of the patient better than that patient knows for himself; and (3) the best interests of society. 39 I will address each of these issues in order. Physician's Oath, Duty, and Responsibility The denial of patient autonomy on the ground that to do otherwise would be a breach of the physician's oath "to do no harm" or by reason of the physician's duty and responsibility to the patient is probably the hardest argument to defend. It can basically be reduced to the assertion that "I have the right to control your actions because (1) I have given my commitment to 31 the medical profession to act in your best interests, i.e., to do no harm; and (2) because of the duties and responsibilities which I perceive. Such an argument cannot even withstand the most superficial scrutiny. I believe that the following two analogies will demonstrate the fallacy of such reasoning. (1) The "icaruscratic" oath. For the sake of argument, suppose that following the first flight at Kittyhawk, the Wright brothers reflected on their accomplishment and became solemnly aware that unless the utmost care was used in training the pilots who would fly in years to come, the lives af these men would be placed in great danger. As a result, they agree to require that before any pilot was to be given his wings, he must recite the "icaruscratic oath, which stated in part "I will fly in a manner that will not endanger the lives of my passengers nor that of myself. I will only operate that craft for which I am well qualified, fly only in weather conditions that are clearly suitable for safe flight, and maintain the highest degree of proficiency so as to maintain the safety of all. I will watch over those who in my judgment are incompetent to operate their craft in a safe manner and, if necessary, physically restrain their flight until that time when their proficiency is restored." If the "icaruscratic" oath sounds totally ridiculous, I agree. Any intervention which seeks justification by reason of an oath one has taken of a duty and responsibility which he 32 perceives is equally ridiculous. I believe that any experienced aviator would agree that the lives of many pilots, their families and other passengers could have been saved if veteran fliers had acted in a manner so as to intervene in the autonomous acts of those who obviously lack the desired proficiency for either the aircraft or adverse weather conditions. (2) The new testament commands Christians to "Go into all the world and preach the gospe 1 • " 40 Because o f t h eir re 1 igious beliefs, many Christians feel a commitment to God to convert as many others to Christ as possible and sincerely feel a duty and responsibility to those they feel are "misguided" or "lost." Reasonable oen would clearly not consider such perceptions as justification for the Christian to impose his religious beliefs on those of the Jew1sh faith. Admittedly, there are distinctions when these two analogies are compared with the physician. Religious beliefs are spiritual and intangible, and there is no bright line which separates spiritual life and spiritual death. And the Sunday afternoon pilot who troops merrily out to his aircraft has not placed himself nor has he been placed under the care of a veteran onlooker. However, here we are only concerned with the analogy of justification by reason of oath-taking and duties perceived, and in this regard I think both analogies are valid. No oath taken, nor duty perceived can justify intervention in the affairs of those who do not share such values. 33 Physician's Expertise To many if not most individuals, this is probably the most convincing of arguments seeking to justify medical paternalism. It can probably be stated as follows: A physician's technical expertise in the field of medicine bestows upbn hin superior decision making capabilities not only over technical matters but over value judgments that are related to the medical field as we11. 41 Thus, those who embrace the traditional medical ethic could be expected to favor the restricting of the right to refuse life-saving treatment, i.e., allowing the physician to determine what is an acceptable quality of life, and other similar decisions made in what he feels is the best interest of his patient. The physician is seen as knowing what is best for the patient better than the patient knows for himself. Although they disfavor the use of the term "paternalism," Clements and Sider have chosen a extreme position in advocating paternalistic medicine and the denial of patient autonomy. They give one example, 42 hypo- and hyper-tension, of how a patient's physiological condition can diminish his capacity to make competent decisions. They then make the gen~ralization that a patient's dininished capacity to make competent choices is standard in most cases. They strongly emphasize that there are "discoverable norms," but if I understand then correctly, insist that they are only discoverable by those in the medical 34 44 Th · . profess1on. e spec1. f.1c1ty as to how this is accomplished and why this assertion is a valid one leaves much to be desired. The argument that certain physiological conditions can cause depression, etc., can result in choices that the patient would not otherwise have made is well taken. This is very close to the message that Jackson and Younger convey in pres.enting "clinical caveats" against accepting a patient's refusal at face value. However, where Clements and Sider seem to advocate a blanket denial of a patient's right to autonomy, Jackson and Younger appear only to be saying that a physician should look for factors that may be influencing a patient's decision which, if discovered and addressed, ~ight cause the autonomous desire to be more in line with that position the doctor has advocated himself. 45 The Clements and Sider article, including the general tone and attitude that it displays, provides an excellent illustration of several points which Veatch makes in discussing the fallacy of generalization of expertise. The influences on perception what empirical data is considered relevant certainly appears to be at work in the Clements and Sider article. Clements and Sider also seem oblivious to the distinctions between value judgments that are primarily social and technical decisions which are primarily medical, as Rogers discussed. 46 Or at least, if they do recognize the distinctions, they do not recognize the right of others in society which are outside of the medical profession to 00060 35 determine such matters. Although they claim that their intent is to restore the patient to a condition where he can exercise "true autonomy," the general tone of the article makes it difficult to believe that the authors respect the notion of autonomy to any great degree even outside of the medical profession. I agree.with Culver and Gert in their response which said that such an attack does little to bring about a responsible resolution to the controversy. 47 I could not help but think, when I was reading the article, what it would be like to live in a country governed by these authors. Values, like duty, are often only in the eye of the beholder. As an example, I do not believe that anyone would seriously argue that physicians do not vary, at least to some degree, as to the amount of risk that they are willing to assume in a given situation. For instance, at what point does the risk of death become so small so as to justify the foregoing of a medical procedure so that eyesight or limbs may be preserved. If the patient was a renowned artist or concert pianist, whose career would be terminated by the procedure, does the physician consider this in his decision-making process? Is it rea~onable to assume that the physician will sometimes be influenced by nonmedical factors, such as his own appreciation or lack thereof for art and music? One might possibly argue that even though physicians may be 00061 36 expected to differ in respect to particular values and issues, a paternalistic ethic, on the whole, will produce better decisions than patient autonomy. Our society obviously does not choose to use such tunnel vision in nonmedical areas, as evidenced in some of the dangerous recreational sports in which we now engage. Even here, however, physicians under the auspices of the AMA are currently attempting to outlaw boxing, and one physician recently appeared on the network news advocating the abolition of auto racing. Best Interests of Society The Millian view of an autonomous self has received criticism from a societal standpoint, a criticism which has also been directed at the more narrow area of patient autonomy. Phrases such as "no man is an island" and "the ripple effect on society" have been used in order to justify paternalistic action. The concept of personal autonomy has also been criticized as "selfish" and detrimental to altruism and other admirable traits. Actually, however, we engage in very few acts that do not have at least some ripple effect on society. For example, if one has a cold, every breath he takes has the potential of expelling harmful bacteria in the area which others will be forced to breathe. 48 Therefore, the only meaningful issue seems to be the determination of which self regarding acts produce reasonable ripple effects and which do not. :(Hlf)f;2 37 Societies that value freedom seem to use a balancing test to distinguish between reasonable and unreasonable acts. Therefore, in the U.S., we allow citizens the personal autonomy to engage in free speech but prohibit a false yelling of fire in a crowded theater. lloth the United States and England rely heavily on the reasonable prudent man standard to determine whether one has exercised appropriate care when he engages in acts that may adversely affect others in society. The application of a totally different standard to matters involving patient conduct appears to be irrational and quite inconsistent. While outside the confines of a hospital and except for those instances where the mobility principle has taken effect, an individual suffering from severe emphysema or other smoking related illness may freely exercise personal autonomy and continue smoking, regardless of the fact that others may regard such acts as .foolish. Why, then, is a physician allowed·to veto the same autonomous act once that individual as been confined to a hospital? In 1980, I personally observed an elderly person who had been admitted to a state supported hospital for reasons that were not related to smoking. However, at the request of the man's family, the physician and the hospital staff restricted his smoking to only two or three cigarettes a day. On many occasions, I heard him exclaim, "I've been smoking since I was 12 years old, and you're telling me I can't have a damn cigarette?" How would 38 Clements and Sider react if an automobile mechanic finished the repairs they requested, but refused to return their automobile without first replacing four badly worn tires? If their clinically discoverable norm theory is indeed valid and proper to justify paternalistic medicine and the determination of values for the patient, should we not then apply a similar ethic throughout society? Adult children could then restrict their parents from engaging in dangerous recreational activities, parents could restrict their children from seeking employment in hazardous occupations. We could have a neatly packaged, regimented society where all of society could paternalistically care for and manage the affairs of his fellow man. Unless one accepts the Clements and Sider notion that almost all patients suffer from diminished capacity to make proper decisions regarding their own care, there appears to be no intelligent basis for the imposition of a double standard. Footnotes 1. J. Feinberg, Autonomy, Sovereignty and Privacy, SO Notre Dame L. Rev. 445, 446 (1982). 2. Feinberg has chosen to use the term "sovereignty" since it denotes a supreme authority while political usage someimes assigns autonomy a more restrictive meaning. I will use the words interchangeably to denote a general sense of independence or freedom of choice. 3. D. Callahan, "Autonomy: A Nora! Good, Not a Noral Obsession," The Hastings Center Report 40 (1984). 4. Id. at 42. 5. Feinberg, supra note 1, at 455-56, quoting J.S. Mills, On Liberty, 99 (1956). 6. Id. at 458, quoting Hills at 67-74. 7. Id. quoting Mills at 93. 8. Id. at 459-60. 9. Id. at 463. 10. Id. 462, quoting A. Schopenhauer, Essay on the Freedom of the Will 19 K. Kolenda trans. (1960). 11. Id. at 473, quoting Mills at 125. 12. The reference to auto racing has become somewhat dated even as I write this paper, since on a recent television newscast, a physician recomm.ended the banning of auto racing in the United States. This desire was based both on the inherent dangers of auto racing and also on the circumvention of the 40 advertising ban by companies who sponsor these races. 13. Social and moral views on suicide interact in this area as well. 14. R. Veatch, Medical Ethics: Professional or Universal? 65 Harv. Theol. Rev. 531, 531 (1972). 15. Id. at 533. 16. Id. at 534-35. 17. Id. at 535. 18. Id. 19. Id. at 536. 20. A. Rogers, The Restoration of Medical Ethics, 10 J. Med. Ethics 117, 117 (1984). 21. Id. at 119. 22. Id. at 120. 23. Id. 24. Id. 25. D. Jackson & S. Younger, Patient Autonomy and Death With Dignity, 301 N. Eng. Med. J. 404, 407 (1979). 26. Id. at 407-408. 27. Id. at 408. 28. I fir~ly believe that the true ~otivation in ordering a psychiatric examination was not for the purpose of determining my state of mental competency but to have me declared mentally incompetent so that a legal guardian could be appointed who would 41 give the consent which was necessary to perform the skin grafts. 29. R. White & T. Englehardt, A Demand to Die, 5 Hastings Center Report 9, 47 (1975). 30. Veatch, supra note 14, at 559. 31. C. Clements & R. Sider, Medical Ethics' Assault Upon Medical Values, 250 J. Am. Med. Ass'n 2011, 2013 (1983). 32. I believe there was only consensus in the sense that a patient would sometimes agree with his physician, but where it could not be reached, coercive treatment would be imposed. 33. Clements & Sider, supra note 31, at 2015. 34. Veatch, supra note 14, at 532-35. 35. Rogers, supra note 20, at 118-20. 36. Clements & Sider, supra note 31, at 2012-13. 37. Jackson & Younger, supra note 25, at 408. 38. Veatch, supra note 14' at 539. 39. Callahan, supra note 3, at 42-43. 40. fvla t thew 2t>:19, The Bible. 41 • Veatch, supra note 14' at 535. 42. Clements & Sider, supra note 31 ' at 2015. 43. Id. 44. Id. 45. Jackson & Younger, supra note 25, at 407-08. 46. Rogers, supra note 20, at 118. 47. C. Culver & B. Gert, Philosophy in Medicine, New York: ooom 42 Oxford University Press (1982). 48. The Japanese choose to wear masks to cover their noses and mouths to help prevent this. 1 Paternalism and the Hentally Competent Adult -- A Peculiar Nedical Ethic Part II Just as I choose a ship to sail in or a house to live in, so I choose a death for my passage from life • Nowhere should we indulge the soul more than in dying • . A man's life should satisfy other people as well, his death only himself, and whatever sort he likes best. 1 -- Seneca "I esteem it the office of a physician not only to restore health, but to mitigate pain and dolours; and not only when such mitigation may conduce to recovery, but when it may serve to make a fair and easy passage." -- Francis Bacon 2 "The makers of our Constitution . i n t he i r • sought to protect Americans b e 1 i e f , t h e i r t h o u g h t s , t h e i r e r1 o t i o n s a n d t h e i r sensations. They conferred, as against the Government, the right to be let alone -- the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilized." --Brandeis, J. 3 Nothing in this utterance suggests that Justice Brandeis thought an individual possessed these rights only as to sensible beliefs, valid thoughts, reasonable emotions, or well-founded sensations. I suggest he intended to include a great many foolish, unreasonable and even absurd ideas which do not conform, such as refusing medical treatment even at great risk. 4 -- Warren Burger "Put in another \vay, the law, equity and justice must not 2 themselves quail and be helpless in the face of modern technological marvels presenting questions hitherto unthought 0f 0 " Hughes, C.J. New Jersey Supreme Court 00070 5 3 III. Legal Concepts in Paternalism and Autonomy A. Introduction For the most part, the judiciary has followed one or both of two legal theories in deciding medical treatment cases in favor of patient autonomy. The principal theory and by far the most recognized is the doctrine of informed consent, which is deeply rooted in common law. The second theory is based on the constitutional right of privacy, which is still somewhat suspect as valid federal constitutional law as the United States Supreme Court has yet to speak on the matter. However, insofar as individual states have found the right to privacy to be guaranteed by their own constitutions, this recognition should be controlling. State legislation such as the Natural Death Acts passed by a number of states have been enacted to supplement one or both of the previously mentioned strands. The discussion that follows primarily examines case law in order to identify the process used by various courts in reaching medical treatment decisions. B. Constitutional Right of Privacy in General Nowhere does the United States Constitution expressly guarantee to the individual a right of privacy. Olmsted v. United States 6 Justice Brandeis, dissenting in a 1928 case which dealt with illegally seize evidnce in a criminal action, stated: 00071 4 The makers of our Constitution undertook to secure conditions favorable to the pursuit of happiness. They recognized the significance of man's spiritual nature, of his feelings and of his intellect. They knew that only a part of the pain, pleasure and satisfactions of life are to be found in material things. They sought to protect Americans in their beliefs, their thoughts, their emotions and their sensations. They conferred, as against the Government, the right to be let alone -the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilized men. To protect that right, every unjustifiable intrusion by the Government upon the privacy of the individual, whatever the means employed, must be de7med a violation of the Fourth Amendment. Griswold v. Connecticut 8 The United States Supreme Court struck down a Connecticut statute that made the use of contraceptives a criminal offense. In declaring the statute an unconstitutional invasion of the right of privacy of married persons, Justice Douglas discussed various peripheral rights which had been recognized by the Court as necessary to make the express rights guaranteed by the Constitution more secure. He concluded: "specific guarantees in the Hill of Rights have penumbras, formed by the emanations froM those guarantees that help give them life and substance. Various guarantees create zones o f To date, • pr1vacy. II the United States Supreme Court has recognized a right of privacy in only the following areas: marriage, procreation, contraception, family relationships, and child . . 10 r ear1ng an d e d ucat1on. (}(}072 5 C. Selected Case Study Cases that discuss right of privacy have relied heavily on common law. In the foregoing areas, the Supreme Court has clearly recognized a constitutional guarantee of the right of privacy. While the United States Supreme Court has yet to acknowledge the right of privacy in the area of patient autonomy, there has been rich legal history of the Supreme Court's and lower federal and state courts' respect for the individual to be free from unwanted medical intervention, drawing from both common and constitutional law. Also, at the state level some courts have recognized both a federal and a state constitutional right of privacy. Union Pacific Railway Co. v. Botsford 1 1 Justice Gray in a 1891 United States Supreme Court decision stated: No right is held more sacred, or is more carefully guarded, by the common law, then the right of every individual to the possession and control of his own person, free from all restraint or interference of others, unless by clear and unquestionable authority of law. As well said by Judge Cooley, "[t]he right to one's person may be said to 2e a right of complete 1 immunity: to be let alone." In Botsford, 13 the Court considered not a specific patient autonomy issue but "whether, in a civil action for an injury to the person, the court, on application of the defer ;}ant, and in advance of the trial, may order the plaintiff, without his 6 or her consent, to submit to a surgical examination as to the extent of the injury sued for." 14 Schloendorff v. Society of New York Hospital 1 5 In a 1914 New York Court of Appeals case involving a hospital patient who had consented to an examination but not to the subsequent surgery which was performed on her, Judge Cardozo stated: "Every human being of adult years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with his own body; and a surgeon who performs an operation without his patient's consent commits an assault, for which he is liable in damages." 16 Natanson v. Kline 17 The Kansas Supreme Court in 1960 in discussed a patient's right to informed consent. The Court was particularly interested in determining the extent of a physician's duty to confide in his patient regarding his recommended treatment along with the nature, consequences and risks associated with such treatment. While discussing these issues, the Court stated: Anglo-American law stars with the premise of thorough-going self determination. It follows that each man is considered to be master of his own body, and he may, if he be of sound mind, expressly prohibit the performance of life-saving surgery, or other medical treatment. A doctor might well believe that an operation or form of treatment is desirable or necessary but the law does not permit him to substitute his own judgment for ty~t of the patient by any form of artifice or deception. 00074 7 Wilson v. Scott 19 In a 1967 case, the Texas Supreme Court adopted the foregoing view, stating that a physician's duty to make a reasonable disclosure is based upon the patient's right to information adequate to exercise an informed consent to or refusal of the procedure. 20 Cobbs v. Grant 21 In a 1972 California Supreme Court case also involving informed consent, the court stated: "In many instances, to the physician, whose training and experience enable a self-satisfying evaluation, the particular treatment which should be undertaken may seem evident, but it is the prerogative of the patient, not the physician, to determine for himself the direction in which he believes his interests lie." 22 In re Osborne 23 Later in .1972, the District of Columbia Court of Appeals decided in favor of a patient who sought to refuse a life-saving blood transfusion because of religious convictions. The court stated: "The degree of state interest justifying intrusion by court order has been viewe d as 'compell1· ng. '" 24 The court indicated that this test had not been met when it discussed what it considered to be the two critical issues of the case: "{1) has 00075 8 the patient validly and knowingly chosen this course for his life, and (2) is there compelling state interest which justifies overriding that decision?" 25 The court decided the first critical issue in the affirmative. Apparently, the court's primary consideration in resolving the second critical issue was based on evidence tending to show that the patient believed he would be deprived of life everlasting even if he involuntarily received the transfusion 26 and that the patient had made material and spiritual provision for the well-being of his two children. Therefore, any interest of the state was outweighed by those of the patient. Matter of Quinlan, 27 By far the most highly publicized and controversial court decision regarding the issue of patient autonomy is found a ~ew Jersey Supreme Court case. Karen Quinlan, a comatose 21-year-old woman, was described by the court as follows: extremely poor, "Her prognosis is she will never resume cognitive life. And the bodily invasion is very great, she requires 24 hour intensive nursing care, antibiotics, the assistance of a respirator, a catheter and feeding tube." 28 The legal issues addressed ranged from the constitutional right of privacy to the . h constitutional prohibition of cruel an d unusua 1 pun1s ment. 29 Because the patient was comatose and therefore incompetent to (}(}fl76 9 express her own desires, the patient autonomy issue is not readily apparent. Its applicability, however, is understood when viewed in terms of substituted judgment; i.e., a decision to do for Karen what she would have done if able to communicate her own wishes. In the court's words: If a putative decision by Karen to permit this non-cognitive, vegetative existence to terminate by natural forces is regarded as a valuable incident of her right of privacy, as we believe it to be, then it should not be discarded solely on the basis that her con~iti~B prevents her conscious exercise of the cho1ce. Here, the court recognized both a New Jersey and a Unites States constitutional right to privacy by looking to language used by Justice Douglas regarding the penumbras of rights that emanate from expressed constitutional guarantees. "Presumably this right is broad enough to encompass a patient's decision to decline medical treatment under certain circumstances, in much the same way as it is broad enough to encompass a woman's decision to . . . . " term1nate pregnancy un d er certa1n con d 1t1ons. 31 Th us, t he New Jersey Supreme Court has recognized patient autonomy as included within a constitutional right of privacy although the United States Supreme Court has not yet spoken on the matter. 32 The New Jersey Court considered the relevant state interests in this case to be "the preservation and sanctity of human life and defense of the right of the physician to administer medical 10 treatment according to his best judgment." 33 Discussion of the sanctity of life issue was primarily limited to the characterization of discontinuing life-sustaining treatment as s u i c i d e o r a s h om i c i d e • 0 n t h e i s s u e o f s u i c i d e , t he y s t a t e d : " '•·' e would see, however, a real distinction between the self-infliction of deadly harm and a self-determination against artificial life support or radical surgery, for instance, in the face of irreversible, painful and certain imminent death. " 34 On the issue of homicide, they stated: "There is a real and in this case determinative distinction between the unlawful taking of the life of another and the ending of artificial life-support systems as a matter of self-determination." 35 The court indicated sympathy for the ethical dilemma presented in this case and noted, "The medical obligation is related to standards and practice prevailing in the profession." 36 The court went on to state: The question is whether there is such internal consistency and rationality in the application of such standards as should warrant their constituting an ineluctable bar to the effectuation of substantive relief for pla~~tiff at the hands of the court. We have concluded not. [T]he law, equity and justice must not themselves quail and be helpless in the face of modern technological mar~Bls presenting questions hitherto unthought of. As to right of control over the decision-making process, court stated: "Decision-making within health care if it is OOO?R the 11 considered as an expression of a primary obligation of the physician, primum non nocere, should be controlled primarily within the patient-doctor-family relationship, ,39 In recognizing the need for procedural safeguards, the court referred to Dr. Karen Teal's recommendation in a Baylor Law Review article for a hospital ethics committee comprised of "physicians, social workers, attorneys, and theologians" with an official status "more that of an advisory body than an enforcing body. " 40 "We cons1· der that a pract1ce · · o f app 1 y1ng to a court to confirm such decisions would generally be inappropriate, not only because that would be a gratuitous encroachment upon the medical profession's field of competence, but because it would be impossibly cumbersome." 41 As to judicial overview, the court continued: "This is not to say that in the case of an otherwise justiciable controversy access to the courts would be foreclosed; we speak rather of a general practice and procedure." 42 The court's holding in the Quinlan case ordered declaratory relief which instructed: Upon the concurrence of the guardian and family of Karen, should the responsible attending physicians conclude that there is no reasonable possibility of Karen's every emerging from her present comatose condition to a cognitive, sapient state and that life-support apparatus now being administered to Karen should be discontinued, they shall consult with the hospital "Ethics Committee" or like body of the institution in which Karen is then hospitalized. If that consultative body agrees that there is no reasonable possibility of Karen's ever emerging from 01107~ 12 her present comatose.condition to a cognitive, sapient state, the present l1fe-support system may be withdrawn and said action shall be without any civil or criminal liability the~efor on ~h~ part of any participan~ whether guard1an, phys1c1an, hospital or others. 3 Hatter of Conroy 44 In 1985, the New Jersey Supreme Court handed down what is probably the most comprehensive, well-reasoned decision regarding the removal of life-sustaining treatment, and exhaustively discussed this topic on both terms of a mentally competent and mentally incompetent patient. The court thoughtfully addressed a host of the controversial matters that are inherently intertwined in the area of patient autonomy. We thus approach this case with caution, conscious that life-and-death decisions like these are an awesome responsibility that can be undertaken only with a profound sense of humility and reserve. The case of Claire Conroy raises moral, social, technological, philosophical, and legal questions involving the interplay of many disciplin~s· No one person or profession has all the answers. Claire Conroy was an 84-year-old bedridden nursing home patient who suffered from serious and irreversible mental and physical impairments. She suffered from arteriosclerotic heart disease, hypertension, and diabetes mellitus; her left leg was gangrenous to her knee; she had several necrotic decubitus ulcers (bed sores) on her left foot, leg and hip; an eye problem required irrigation; she had a urinary catheter in place and could not control her bowels; she could not speak; and her ability to swallow . . d • 4o was very 1 1m1te 0()08() 13 Although she manifested periodic confusion, "she interacted with her environment in some limited ways," 47 as indicated by an occasional moan, smile or eye movement. The court was cognizant of the seriousness and difficulty of deciding on a course of treatment for an incompetent patient. "To err either way -- to keep a person alive under circumstances under which he would rather have been allowed to die, or to allow that person to die when he would have chosen to cling to life -- would be deeply unfortunate. 48 In embracing the deeply rooted common law doctrine of informed consent, the court noted: There are three basic prerequisites for informed consent: the patient must have the capacity to reason and make judgments, the decision must be made voluntarily and without coercion, and the patient must have a clear understanding of the risks and benefits of the proposed treatment alternatives or nontreatment, along with a full understaH§ing of the nature of the disease and the prognosis. They stated that ''[t]he patient's ability to control his bodily integrity through informed consent is significant only when one recognizes that this right also encompasses a right to informed refusal." 50 The federal constitutional right of privacy, earlier enunciated in Quinlan, was reaffirmed, but the court declined to determine its applicability in Conroy, "since the right to decline medical treatment is, in any event, embraced within the u51 n . . common-law right to sel f -determination. uu t un d er ei'th er ftll0~1 14 of the two legal theories, "the right to decline life-sustaining medical treatment is not absolute." 52 "Courts and commentators have commonly identified four state interests that may limit a person's right to refuse medical treatment: preserving life, preventing suicide, safeguarding the integrity of the medical profession, and protecting innocent third · " part1es. 53 I n stat1ng . t h at "[ t ]h e stat(· ' s interest in preserving life is commonly considered the most significant of the four state interests" 54 which "may be seen as embracing two separate but related concerns: an interest in preserving the life of the particular patient, and an interest in preserving the sanctity of all life," 55 the court distinguished between an individual who competently declines life-sustaining treatment for himself and individuals or potential lives that cannot adequately protect themselves as in Roe v. Wade. As in Quinlan, the court here rejected the characterization of refusing life-sustaining treatment as being tantamount to suicide by stating: "Refusing medical intervention merely allows the disease to take its natural course; if death were eventually to occur, it would be the result, primarily, of the underlying disease, and not the result of a self-inflicted injury." 56 As to the interest in safeguarding the integrity of the medical profession, the court's view was that "[t]his interest, like the interest in preventing suicide, is not particularly (}(}0~2 15 threatened by permitting competent patients to refuse life-sustaining medical treatment. Medical ethics do not require medical intervention in disease at all costs." 57 Here, the court quoted Francis Bacon as writing in 1624: "I esteem it the office of a physician not only to restore health, but to mitigate pain and dolours; and not only when such mitigation may conduce to recovery, but when it may serve to make a fair and easy passage. u58 Another reason courts have refused to recognize a mentally competent patient's right to refuse treatment has been where he has equivocated in his refusal. Typical cases of equivocation have involved the refusal of life-saving blood transfusions by Jehovah's Witness members. The Conroy court advanced three alternative tests for decision making and discussed the circumstances concerning the applicability of each -- a subjective test, a limited objective test, and a pure objective test. Under the subjective test, "life-sustaining treatment may be withheld or withdrawn from an incompetent patient when it is clear that the particular patient would have refused the treatment under the circumstances involved." 59 "The question is not what a reasonable or average person would have chosen to do under the circumstances, but what a particular patient would have done if able to choose for himself." 60 16 The court indicated that a patient's desires could be determined in many ways, including a living will, earlier oral directives, durable power of attorney or proxy, reactions previously voiced regarding medical treatments of others, religious beliefs, and patient's consistent pattern of conduct regarding his own prior medical decisions. The court recognized that "for some incompetent patients it might be impossible to be clearly satisfied as to the patient's intent either to accept or reject the life-sustaining treatment." 61 Therefore, where a third party decision-maker does not possess such knowledge, his substituted judgment could not be seen as advancing the patient's right to self-determination. Because the court did not want the lack of prior indication of the patient's wishes to foreclose humane action that would allow the termination of treatment, the court relied on its parens patriae authority over incompetents and outlined two "best interests" test. The first of these tests is a limited objective test that would be applicable in situations similar to the instant case: "when there is some trust-worthy evidence that the patient would have refused the treatment, and the decision-maker is satisfied that it is clear that the burdens of the patient's continued life with the treatment outweigh the benefits of that life for him (emphas1s · a dd e d) • " 62 Th e court stated that "medical evidence will be essential" in weighing 17 these benefits and burdens to the patient and emphasized the need for doing what the patient would have wanted. "Information is particularly important with respect to the degree, expected duration, and constancy of pain with and without treatment, and the possibility that the pain could be reduced by drugs or other means short of terminating the life-sustaining treatment." 63 A purely objective test would be applicable in the absence of any trustworthy evidence that a patient such as Claire Conroy would have declined the life-sustaining treatment. Under that test, as under the limited objective test, the net burdens of the patient's life with the treatment should clearly and markedly outweigh the benefits that the patient derives from life. Further, the recurring, unavoidable and severe pain of the patient's life with the treatment should be such that the effect of administering life-su~taining treatment would be inhumane (emphasis added). J Here it is important to note that the standard is "clearly and markedly" rather than "clearly" as was used in the limited objective test where at least something is known of the patient's desires. In further recognition of the patient's right to self-determination, the court went on to state that "[n]evertheless, even in the context of severe pain, life-sustaining treatment should not be withdrawn from an incompetent patient who had previously expressed a wish to be k ept alive in spite of any pain that he mig h t . experience. u65 In an apparent effort to address the "slippery slope" and 18 similar arguments, the court emphatically states that "we expressly decline to authorize decision-making based on assessments of the personal worth or social utility of another's life, or the value of that life to others. We do not believe that it would be appropriate for a court to designate a person with the authority to determine that someone else's life is not worth living simply because, to that person, the patient's 'quality of life' or value to society seems negligible." 66 The court held that in Claire Conroy's case, none of the three tests were flet; however, its decision to hear the case despite Mrs. Conroy's death indicates the Court's belief in the substantial importance of the issues raised as well as their desire to reaffirm the right of patient autonomy. Superintendent of Belchertown State School v. Saikewicz 67 Joseph Saikewicz, a 67-year-old resident of a Massechusetts state mental institution, had an I.Q. of 10 and a mental age of approximately two years and eight months. He had been retarded since birth and contracted a leukemic condition at the age of 67. The question to be resolved was whether he should be treated for this condition in view of pain, side effects and other factors associated with the chemotherapy treatment. Important considerations included the institution's belief that Saikewicz would perceive the pain associated with such treatment as 000~ 19 punishment as well as the diminished effectiveness of the treatment for patients older than the age of 60. Issues concerning suicide, third party interests and ethical integrity of the medical profession were addressed and resolved in a manner similar to Quinlan and other cases already discussed. Regarding sanctity of life and the right of self-determination, the court stated: The constitutional right to privacy, as we conceive it, is an expression of the sanctity of individual free choice and self-determination as fundamental constituents of life. The value of life as so perceived is lessened not by a decision to refuse treatment, but by the failure tg allow a competent human being the 8 right of choice. The court indicates a disposition to somewhat limited self-determination by stating that [t]here is a substantial distinction in the State's insistence that human life be saved where the affliction is curable, as opposed to the State interest where, as here, the issue is not whether but when, for how long, and at what co~9 to the individual that life may be briefly extended. However, the Massachusetts court went on to say that "we should make it plain that the primary test is subjective in nature that is, the goal is to determine with as much accuracy as possible the wants and needs of the individual involved." The relevance of this case to the issue of patient autonomy can be found in the court's statement: In short, the decision in cases such as this should be that which would be made by the incompetent person, if 000~7 20 that person were competent, but taking into account the present and future incompetency of the individual as one of the factors which would necessarily enter into the dec~aion-making process of the competent person. The court held that the state's interests did not outweigh Saikewicz's right to privacy and self-determination and upheld his right to decline life-prolonging medical treatment. The Massachusetts court emphasized that the quality of life criteria used by the lower court did not equate with value of life. The court noted the lower court's special concern for Saikewicz's vulnerability and stated that "[t]he judge, as well as all the parties, were keenly aware that the supposed ability of Saikewicz, by virtue of his mental retardation, to appreciate or experience life had no place in the decision before them." 71 Matter of Quackenbush In 197~, 72 a New Jersey court directly addressed the right of a mentally competent 72-ycar-old man to refuse life-saving treatment. Quackenbush suffered from gangrene in his legs, both of which were in a partially mummified condition. He had for 40 years shunned medical treatment and was described by his doctor as "a conscientious objector to medical therapy." 73 After several days of discussion with his physician which seemingly more than satisfied all requirements of informed consent, Quackenbush agreed to the amputation of both legs but withdrew 21 the consent later that day. Facts resented indicated that chances for recovery were good if the surgery were performed, but without it he would probably die within three weeks. A psychiatrist appearing for the hospital found Quackenbush to be incompetent "to make an informed decision concerning the operation." 74 A second psychiatrist who was appointed by the court, as well a the judge who made a personal visit to speak with Quackenbush, both concluded that Quackenbush was competent to make an informed decision. It is significant to note that the latter two decisions were reached after taking into account the fluctuations in mental lucidity which they considered normal for a 72-year-old man under the circumstances. The court also considered Quackenbush's hope that a miracle would occur as well as his doubt that it would. They rejected hospital assertions that the refusal was equivalent to suicide in favor of the right to privacy and self-determination argument advanced by Quackenbush. Having determined Quackenbush to be mentally competent, the court relied heavily upon the "extensive bodily invasion" as "sufficient to make the State's interest in the preservation of life give way to Robert Quackenbush's right of privacy to decide his own future . ..75 regardless of the absence of a dim prognos1s. Lane v. Candura 76 This case considered a matter similar to that of 22 ~uackenbush. 77 A 77-year-old widow suffered from a gangrenous foot and persisted in her refusal to allow life-saving 78 amputation. Her doctor characterized her refusal as suicide and stated that in his opinion she " was . 1ncompetent to make a rational choice whether to consent to the operation.•• 79 The court, however, stated that the physician's opinion was "not one of incompetency in the legal sense, but rather that her ability. to make a rational choice (by which he means the medically rational choice) is impaired by the confusion existing in her mind by virtue of her consideration of irrational and emotional factors." 8 ° Following this statement, the court noted that "[u]ntil she changed her original decision and withdrew her consent to the amputation, her competence was not questioned." 81 The court found in favor of Mrs. Candura, stating: We hold that Mrs. Candura has the right under the law to refuse to submit either to medical treatment or a surgical operation, that on the evidence and findings in this case the decision is one that she may determine for herself, and that therefore her leg may not be amp~tat81 unless she consents to that course of act1on. Satz v. Perlmutter 83 The Florida Court of Appeals in 1978 considered the case of Abe Perlmutter, a 73-year-old victim of LOU Gehrig's disease whose life was being sustained by a respirator. Although there 00090 23 seemed to be no question as to his mental competency and his family was in accord with his wishes, the hospital had refused his wishes to be disconnected from the respirator. The State advanced many of the traditional arguments such as unlawful homicide and injury to the integrity of the medical profession. The Florida court rejected these arguments and also distinguished the instant case from those where refusal of treatment had been denied, stating that "[i]n the blood transfusion cases, the patient is either incompetent to make a medical decision, equivocal about making it .. • or it is a family member making the decision for an inert or minor third party patient." 84 Agreeing with prior cases holding that "a competent adult patient [has the right] to refuse treatment for himself," the court stated "because Abe Perlmutter has a right to refuse treatment in the first instance, he has a concomitant right to discontinue it." 85 Respecting the patient's constitutional right to privacy, freedom of choice and self-determination, the court concluded: It is all very convenient to insist on continuing Nr. Perlmutter's life so that there can be no question of foul play, no resulting civil liability and no possible trespass on medical ethics. However, it is quite another matter to do so at the patient's sole expense and against his competent will, thus inflicting never ending physical torture on his body until the inevit~gle, but artificially suspended, moment of death. 24 Significant here is that in upholding Abe Perlmutter's right to be removed from the respirator, the court narrowly restricted its decision to the facts of the instant case, stating, "[t]he problem is less easy of solution when the patient is incapable of understanding and we, therefore, postpone a crossing of that more complex bridge until such time as we are required to do so." 87 The fact that the disease was incurable, the patient's condition wretched, that death would ensue shortly even with the respirator, and that the patient did not induce his condition also influenced the court's decision. Matter of Storar 88 In a 1981 case consolidating Storar v. Soper and Eichner v. Dillon, the New York Court of Appeals considered termination of treatment issues involving a 52-year-old retarded man who was dying from terminal cancer of the bladder and also considered whether a respirator could be removed from a 83-year-old priest in a vegetative condition. The court determined that life-sustaining blood transfusions should be continued as to Storar but that Brother Fox could be removed from the respirator. The court's primary reason for distinguishing between these cases was due to Storar's never having been mentally competent for his entire life and therefore never having been able to competently express what his desires might be in the matter, while on the 25 other hand there was clear an convincing evidence that Brother Fox did not wish to be kept alive in such a condition since he had expressed this desire while competent. In both cases, the court rejected the lower court's finding of a constitutional right to privacy, noting that although the United States Supreme Court has had many opportunities to speak on the matter, hey have declined to do so. Instead, the court relied upon common law. As to Storar, the court relief upon parens patriae authority, stating: Thus it is unrealistic to attempt to determine whether he would want to continue potentially life prolonging treatment if he were competent • • that would be similar to asking whether "if it snowed all summer would it then be winter?" Hentally John Storar was an infant and that is the on1~ realistic way to assess his rights in this litigation. 9 However, a dissenting opinion seemed to display more humanity and insight when it stated: [H]is mother over his lifetime had come to know and sense his wants and needs and was acutely sensitive to his best interests; • she had provided more love, personal care, and affection for John than any other person or institution, and was closer to feeling what John was feeling than anyone else; • • • his best interests were of crucial importance to her; • in his mother's opinion it would have been in John's best interests to discontinue the transfusions, and sh9 0 believed that he would wish to have them stopped. The dissent would have allowed the mother to exercise the son's rights and to discontinue treatment. 26 Barber v. Superior Court of State of California 91 In 1983, a California Court of Appeals heard a criminal case involving two doctors who were charged with murder and conspiracy to commit murder as a result of discontinuing use of a respirator and intravenous feeding. The patient never regained consciousness after surgery. The physicians consulted with the family, telling them that the patient's prognosis was dim. Three days following the surgery, the family drafted a written request to remove the life support systems mentioned. The court found that the California Natural Death Act "does not represent the exclusive basis for terminating life-support equipment in this state," 92 and relied upon both the co!'!lmon law and other California legislation that recognized "the legal right to control one's own medical treatment." 93 Oral testimony was introduced that the patient had "expressed to his wife his feeling that he would not want to be kept alive by machines or 'become another Karen Ann Quinlan.'" 94 In discussing a physician's duty to his patient, the court stated that "[w]e deal here with the physician's responsibility in a case of a patient who, though not 'brain dead," faces an indefinite vegetative existence without any of the higher cognitive brain functions." 95 It went on to determine that "[a] physician as. no duty to continue treatment, once it has proved to be ineffective." 96 However, "whenever possible, the patient 27 himself should then be the ultimate decision-maker."9 7 In the instant case, there was agreement between the patient's wife and his eight children that treatment should be withdrawn, ad the court found no evidence "that they were motivate in there decision by anything other than love and concern for the dignity of their husband and father." 98 They also ruled that a formal appointment of guardianship was not legally required. After commenting several times upon the need for more legislative guidance. 99 In such cases, the court concluded, "we find no legal requirement that prior judicial approval is necessary before any decision to withdraw treatment can be made." 100 Foody v. Manchester Memorial Hospital 101 In 1984, a Connecticut court relied on substitute judgment exercised by the father of a semi-comatose 42-year-old victim of multiple sclerosis in reaching their decision. The court found that a federal constitutional right to privacy as well as a common law right to self-determination were present in the instant case. After considering state interests and the absence of improper motivations for discontinuing treatment, the court concluded that "(i]f the decision is made to discontinue the use of all such devices and as a result death should occur, hospital personnel and attending physicians shall not be subject to criminal or civil liability because of such 00~5 28 . . .. 102 discont1nuance. Bartling v. Superior Court of California 1 03 The California Court of Appeals in December 1984 reversed a lower court's ruling that "as long as there was some potential for restoring Mr. Bartling to a 'cognitive, sapient life,' it would not be appropriate to issue an injunction" (ordering disconnection of Mr. Bartling's ventilator). 104 The patient suffered from several acute and apparently incurable illnesses which had not been d i a g nosed as term in a 1 a t the time of t ria 1 ·but nonetheless were expected to result in death in a very short 105 · "1 Bart 1.1ng h a d state d t h at "h e wante d to 1 ive but t1me. 1·r. preferred death to his intolerable life on the ventilator." 106 Commenting upon Mr. Bartling's occasional vacillation as to his resolve to disconnect the respirator, the court stated that ''[t]he fact that Mr. Bartling periodically wavered from this posture because of severe depression or for any other reason does not justify the conclusion of [the hospital]and his treating physicians that his capacity to make such decision . u107 was impaired to the point of legal 1ncompetency. Although the patient had executed a Living Will, it did not conform to the narrow provisions of the California Natural Death Act. Also noteworthy was his wife's support of Mr. Bartling's decision. After considering traditional arguments such as the 000~6 29 constitutional right of privacy, the individual right to self-determination, and state interests, the court concluded that Mr. Bartling should have been allowed to have t~e respirator removed despite the fact that death would have quickly ensued. Matter of Hier 108 In 1984, the Appeals Court of Massachusetts considered the case of Mary Hier, a 92-year-old woman requiring that nutrition to be given by artificial means involving surgery. She had been institutionalized in a psychiatric hospital for 57 years. In declining to adopt New York precedent involving incompete~ts, the Massachusetts court stated [The Storar case] explicitly rejected the substituted judgment approach [citing Storar] and seemingly left New York law with no vehicle to enable withholding of life-prolonging measures to a patient incompetent to make the decision for himself, unless the patient (1) had, at some time, been competent, and (2) had expressed a wish when competent not to receive such measures. It is the essential function of the substituted judgment analysis, formulated in the Saikewicz case and applied here by the probate judge, to secure to incompetent persons the same right to choose or reject treatment that is accory 0§ to competent persons by the law of consent. Tune v. Walter Reed Army Nedical Hospital 110 In March 1985, the United States District Court for the . ' s request to District of Columbia considered a competent pat1ent be removed from a respirator. When she was first placed on the respirator the 30 physicians were unaware of the full extent of her illness. In combination, her malignancy and lung disease import a mortality rate approaching 100 percent, and had they known the circumstances they would not have ordered the respirator originally. Having doe so, however, they are constrained to continue life support, despite i~I wishes of patient or family, by Army medical policy. The Court noted that: Although the Supreme Court has recognized the primacy of individual autonomy in certain matters of the more intimate and sensitive nature encountered in the course of human affairs, it has yet to do so in the context of natural death. Roe v. Wade, supra, however, is instructive for purposes of this case, because the Supreme Court there proceeded upon the premise that a competent adult has a paramount right to control the disposition to be made of his or her own body, absent a compelli~¥ countervailing governmental interest 2 opposed. [I]t is now a well-established rule of general law, as binding upon the government as it is upon the medical profession at large, that it is the patient, not the physician, who ultimately decides if §reatment -- any 1 treatment -- is to be given at all. After discussin8 the countervailing state interests and concluding that they were insufficient to outweigh the patient's "interest in dying as she chooses," the court held that "[c]ompetent adult patients of federal medical facilities with tercinal illnesses and in the circumstances presented here have a right to determine for themselves whether to allow their lives to be prolonged by artificial means, including the right to deQand "114 the cessation of life support once b egun. 31 John F. Kennedy Hospital v. Bludworth 115 The ·supreme Court of Florida heard a 1984 case involving a living will and issues regarding civil and criminal liability relating to the withdrawal of a mechanical ventilator. The patient had suffered irreversible brain damage and had been declared incompetent by the probate court. This case illustrates the importance of a "living" or "mercy" will as persuasive evidence in respect to the exercise of an incompetent patient's right to self-determination regarding his or her medical treatment. It appears that the living or mercy will is generally not considered to be legally enforceable except as it conforms to a natural death act or other legislation in a particular state. 116 However, the Florida court stated that such a declaration should be given "great weight" by those exercisine substituted judgment. As to issues regarding liability, the court stated that "[t]o be relieved of potential civil and criminal liability, guardians, consenting family members, physicians, hospitals, or their administrators need only act in good faith." 117 As in the California case of Barber, the Florida court held that "[i]f there are close family members such as the patient's spouse, adult children, or parents, who are willing to exercise this right on behalf of the patient, there is no . 118 requirement that a guardian be judicially appointed. 32 Andrews v. Ballard 11 9 A 1980 federal district court applying Texas law discussed the right of a patient to have at least some choice as to the particular type of medical treatment that he wishes to receive. John Walter suffered from lower back pain and had not been able to find relief by traditional Western medical treatment. The state would not allow a highly skilled practitioner of acupuncture from Nevada to perform acupuncture treatment in Texas because he did not meet the Texas licensing requirements. This practice was limited to licensed physicians only. That limitation was ironic in that the court found that the State of Texas provided no instruction or testing of its physicians regarding acupuncture skills. In reaching their decision, the court concluded: "Thus, the decision to obtain or reject medical treatment, presented in the instant case as the decision to obtain acupuncture treatment, is both personal and important enough to be encompassed by the right of privacy." 120 Because of the burden and significant interference imposed by the licensing requirement, the court found that the rational basis test did not apply. Therefore, the compelling state interest test was applicable, and because the licensing requirement was not "narrowly drawn" to a "compelling state interest," 121 the court found the statute to be invalid. 00100 33 IV. Conclusions and Trends As legal, medical, social and classical literature clearly indicate, the concept of patient autonomy is no radical modern day notion. However, the ability of modern medical technology to sustain life or prolong death under thoroughly wretched circumstances has created a host of moral, ethical and social dilemmas never before experienced. The posture taken by what appears to be the majority of federal and state courts when called upon to decide such issues has been surprisingly consistent regardless of wether their primary reliance was upon constitutional, common or statutory law. The courts' reverence for an individual's right to self-determination as to matters involving his or her medical treat~ent is quite evident. It appears that medical treatment that is administered in the absence of informed consent is still considered by most courts to create a cause of action for the tort of battery. I am exceedingly impressed by the insight, sensitivity and thoroughness that is reflected in most courts' opinions. I am also pleased by the primacy that most courts give to the needs and wishes of each patient on an individual basis even in many of the instances where I would have decided differently. A number of the courts have spoken of the need for more legislative guidelines, and these will probably be forthcoming. In the interim, it appears that most courts will tend to proceed slowly, 34 with caution and further toward the right to self-determination. Terms sue h as "l"f 1 e " an d "d eat h" wh"1ch once seemed clear and absolute are now having to be redefined. The concept of me ani n g f u 1 1 i f e , d e a t h wi t h d i g n i t y , q u a 1 i t y of 1 i f e , and "d 0 in g no harm to the patient" must be viewed from many nevi perspectives. Questions regarding the distribution of scarce and costly medical resources must be answered in terms of economic realities. A number of individuals have expressed fears that discontinuing life-sustaining treatment in any situation would lead to a standard based upon a particular patient's utility and value to himself or to society. I believe that reasonable men would find such a standard appalling. As long as our courts continue to emphasize the individual's right to self-determination, fears that utility will become as a determinant have little merit and will remain unrealized. If courts were to adopt a utility standard it would clearly be the greatest reversal and breach of individual rights ever enunciated by the court. I question whether any meaningful rights would remain if the chief guardian of our personal freedoms were to adopt such standards. 001"2 1. President's Comm'n for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine & Biomedical & Behavioral Research, Deciding to Forego Life-Sustaining Treatment 22 (1983), quoting Seneca, Suicide, in the Stoic Philosophy of Seneca 506. 2. F. Bacon, New Atlantis, quoted in Matter of Conroy, 486 A.2d 1209, 1225 (N.J. 1985). 3. Olmstead v. United States, 227 U.S. 438, 478 (1928) (Brandeis, J., dissenting). 4. Application of President & Directors of Georgetown College, 331 F.2d 1010, 1017 (D.C. Cir. 1964) (Burger, dissenting). 5. Matter of Quinlan, 355 A.2d 647, 665 (N.J. 1976) (Hughes, C.J.). 6. 227 u.s. 438 (1928). 7. Id. at 478. 8. 381 u.s. 479 (1965). 9. Id. at 484. 10. See Andrews v. Ballard, 498 F. Supp. 1038, 1045 (S.D. Tex. 1980), citing Carey v. Population Services Internat'l, 431 u.s. 678, 684-85 (lq77). 11. 141 u.s. 250 (1891). 12. Id. at 251, citing Cooley on Torts. 13. Union Pacific Ry. Co. v. Botsford, 141 U.S. 250 (1891). 14. Id. at 251. The law now recognizes the right of the defense under similar circumstances to requie such an 0010~ 36 examination, but for reasons of fairness to the defense rather than from any reason of favoring the allowance of bodily intrusion. 15. 211 N.Y. 125, 105 N.E. 92 (App. Ct. 1914). 16. 211 N.Y. at __ , 105 N.E. at 93. 17. 186 Kan. 393, 350 P.2d 1093 ((1999960). 18. 186 Kan. at __ , 350 P.2d at 1104. 19. 412 S.\,J.2d 2999 (1967). 20. I d. 21. 8 Cal.3d 229, 502 P.2d 1, 104 Cal. Rptr. 505 (1972). 22. 8 Cal.3d at __ , 502 P.2d at 10, 104 Cal. Rptr. at __ • 23. 294 A.2d 372 (D.C. App. Ct. 1972). 24. Id. at 374. 25. Id. at 375. 26. In similar cases, some courts have ordered involuntary blood transfusions where the patient indicated that, despite religious convictions, he would not resist the court order. 27. 70 N.J. 10, 355 A.2d 647, cert. denied sub nom., ·Garger v. New Jersey, 429 U.S. 922 (1976). 28. 70 N.J. at __ , 355 A.2d at 664. 29. The court found the Eighth Amendment's protection against cruel and unusual punishment not relevant to this case as it·applies only to penal sanctions. 30. 70 N.J. at , 355 A.2d at 664. 0011l4 37 31. 70 N.J. a t _ , 355 A.2d at 663, citing Roe v. \.Jade, 410 u.s. 1973). 32. Quinlan's father asserted that he had a constitutional right of privacy that encompassed the right to make decisions regarding medical treatments on his daughter's behalf. He also asserted a similar claim as to his constitutional right to free exercise of religion. The court held against the father as having these rights on both issues. 33. 70 N.J. at _, 355 A.2d at 665. 34. 70 N.J. at _, 355 A.2d at 670. 35. 70 N.J. at _, 355 A.2d at 666. 36. 70 N.J. at _, 355 A.2d at 670. 38. 70 N.J. at _, 355 A.2d at 665. 39. 70 N.J. at _, 355 A.2d at 669. 40. 70 N.J. at _, 355 A.2d at 668, citing 27 Baylor L. Rev. _, 355 A.2d at 669. _, 355 A.2d at 671. 37. Id. 6, 8-9 1975). 41. 70 N.J. at 42. Id. 43. 70 N.J. at 44. 98 N.J. 321, 486 A.2d 1209 (1985). 45. 98 N.J. at __ , 486 A.2d at 1220. 46. 98 N.J. at _, 486 A.2d at 1217. 47. Id. 0011'5 38 48. 98 N.J. at , 486 A.2d at 1220. 49. 98 N.J. at , 486 A.2d at 1222, citing 310 New Eng. J. Hed. 955. SO. 98 N.J. at ___ , 486 A.2d at 1222. Informed consent can be implied in certain instances involving emergencies and patient unconsciousness. See Conroy, 98 N.J. at ___ , 486 A.2d at 1222, and cases cited. 51. 98 N.J. at ___ , 486 A.2d at 1223. 52. Id. 53. Id. 54. Id. 55. Id. 56. 98 N.J. at , 486 A.2d at 1224. 57. Id. 58. 98 N.J. at 486 A.2d at 1225. 59. 98 N.J. at 486 A.2d at 1229. 60. Id. 61. 98 N.J. at 62. 98 N.J. at 63. 98 N.J. at -· 486 A.2d at 1231. 486 A.2d at 1232 (emphasis added). 486 A.2d at 1232. 64. Id. (emphasis added). 65. 98 N.J. at 486 A.2d at 1232. 66. 98 N.J. at 4~6 A.2d at 1233. 67. 373 Hass. 728, 370 N.E.2d 417 (1977). 00106 39 68. 373 Mass. at 69. 373 Mass. at 70. 373 Mass. at 71. 373 Mass. at __ , __ , __ , 370 N.E. at 426. 370 N.E. at 425-26. 370 N.E. at 431. , 370 N.E. at 432. 72. 156 N.J. Super. 282, 383 A.2d 785 (Co. Ct. 1978). __ , __ , __ , 73. 156 N.J. Super. at 74. 156 N.J. Super. at 75. 156 N.J. Super. at 383 A.2d at 787. 383 A.2d at 788. 383 A.2d at 789. 76. 376 N.E.2d 1232 (Mass. App. Ct. 1978). 77. Mr. Candura's daughter was seeking to be appointed as guardian to effectuate consent to the surgery. 78. The court refused to find legal incompetence based on the fact that she had earlier vacillated in her resolve to refuse the operation. 79. 376 N.E.2d at 1235. 80. I d. 81. Id. 82. Id. at 1233. 83. 362 So.2d 160 {Fla. App. 1978). 84. Id. at 163. 85. Id. 86. Id. at 164. 87. Id. at 162. 88. 52 N.Y.2d 363, 420 N.E.2d 64, 438 N.Y. Supp.2d 266 (App. 00107 40 Ct. 1981). 89. 52 N.Y.2d at ___ , 420 N.E.2d at __ , 438 N.Y. Supp.2d at 275. 90. 52 N.Y.2d at __ , 420 N.E.2d a t _ , 438 N.Y. Supp.2d at 280-81. 91. 147 Cal. App.3d 1006, 195 Cal. Rptr. 484 (App. Ct. 1983). 92. 147 Cal. App.3d at 195 Cal. Rptr. at 490. ' 93. 147 Cal. App.3d at 195 Cal. Rptr. at 489. ' 94. 147 Cal. App.3d at 195 Cal. Rptr. at 493. ' 95. 147 Cal. App.3d at 195 Cal. Rptr. at 488. ' 96. 147 Cal. App.3d at 195 Cal. Rptr. at 491. ' 97. 147 Cal. App.3d at 195 Cal. Rptr. at 492. ' 98. 147 Cal. App.3d at 195 Cal. Rptr. at 493. 99. Courts in other states have also emphasize this need. 100. 147 Cal. App.3d at t 195 Cal. Rptr. at 493. 101. 40 Conn. Sup. 127, 482 A.2d 713 (Sup. Ct. 1984). 102. 40 Conn. Sup. at ' 482 A.2d at 722. 103. 209 Cal. Rptr. 220 {App. Ct. 1984). 104. Id. at 223. 105. This assessment was indeed accurate as Mr. Bartling died the day before the appellate decision was rendered. 106. Id. at 223. 107. Id. at 223-24. 0011~ 41 108. 18 Mass. App. 200, 464 N.E.2d 959 (App. Ct. 1984). 109. 18 Mass. App. at __ , 464 N.E. at 963. 110. 602 F. Supp. 1452 (D. D.C. 1985). 1 1 1 • Id. at 1453. 112. Id. at 1454 (citations omitted). 113. Id. at 1455. 114. Id. at 1456. 115. 452 So.2d 921 (1984). 116. See Nartyn & Jacobs, Legislating Advance Directives for the Terminally Ill: The Living \vill and Durable Power of Attorney, Neb. L. Rev. 779, 7HH. 117. 452 So.2d at 926. 118. Id. 119. 498 F. Supp. 1038 (S.D. Tex. 1980). 120. Id. at 1048. 001ft9