WHAT EFFECT SHOULD THE PLAINTIFF'S SUBSTANDARD CONDUCT HAVE ON HIS RIGHT TO RECOVER FROM THE NEGLIGENT AND STRICT LIABILITY TORTFEASOR? by: Bruce Hodge Products Liability Seminar S p r i n g , 1983 Prof. J . Hadley E d g a r , Instructor 00246 TABLE OF CONTENTS I. II. ITT. IV. V. INTRODUCTION 1 - 7 A PRELIMINARY PRACTICAL MATTER CAN NEGLIGENT CONDUCT AND STRICT TORT LIABILITY INDUCING PRODUCTS BE COMPARED? 7 9 TYPES OF SUBSTANDARD CONDUCT 9 24 A. Assumption of Risk 10 14 B. What is Misuse? 14 19 C. Contributory Negligence 19 23 D. Summary of the Types of Substandard Conduct 24 SHOULD DAMAGE APPORTIONMENT BE ACCOMPLISHED ON THE BASIS OF THE COMPARATIVE CULPABILITY OF THE PARTIES? 25 POLICY - SAFE CREATION AND S A L E , AND SAFE USE OF PRODUCTS 26 - 40 A. Product Safety - Society's Cry for Protection 26 29 Economic Aspects from Three Sides 29 40 DRAWING THE LINE - THE DEFENSES FROM A POLICY PERSPECTIVE 40 45 VII. WHAT ROLE 45 46 VIII. WHAT ROLE THE RULE? 46 47 IX. SHOULD THE DAMACE APPORTIONMENT RULE FINALLY ADOPTED TREAT STRICT PRODUCTS DEFENDANTS DIFFERENTLY THAN NEGLIGENT PRODUCTS DEFENDANTS? 48 - 49 SHOULD NON-PRODUCTS TORTFEASORS AND PRODUCTS TORTFEASORS BE TREATED EQUALLY? 49 - 51 XI. PROPOSED GUIDELINES 51 - 54 XII. PRE-CONCLUSTON SUMMARY 54 - 58 XIII. EXISTING DAMAGE APPROTIONMENT SCHEMES 58 - 60 CONCLUSION 60 B. VI. X. FORESEEABILITY? - 61 WHAT EFFECT SHOULD THE PLAINTIFF'S SUBSTANDARD CONDUCT HAVE ON HIS RIGHT TO RECOVER FROM THE NEGLIGENT AND STRICT LIABILITY TORTFEASOR? I. INTRODUCTION There the is wholesale disagreement among the courts and writers answer to the issue found in the title to this p a p e r . agreement conduct that at least some of the various forms of should rcduce liability actions. forms concerning There is plaintiff general substandard or bar the plaintiff's right to recover in products The disagreement surfaces when the issue of which of the of plaintiff substandard conduct should be set up against his right recover in whole or in p3rt is a d d r e s s e d . to The Uniform Comparative Fault Act would simply lump all of the various forms together and reduce the plaintiff's 1 recovery in proportion to the quantum of his fault. Fundamental fairness is 2 said to be the virtue of this approach. that particular blameworthy types of plaintiff Other views proceed from the notion substandard conduct are either so or so minimally culpable that they should be in the first case a complete bar to the plaintiff's right to recover or should be no impediment 3 whatsoever to his recovery in the second c a s e . In T e x a s , assumption of risk is a complete 4 whatsoever. bar, and simple contributory negligence has Not everyone would agree with the Texas approach; no effect nevertheless, there is general agreement that products manufacturers are not i n s u r o r s , thus some of the plaintiff's substandard conduct will be chargeable to h i m . 5There is also general disagreement as to what role a damage-apportionment rule is liability to law. play in light of the perceived policy At reduced to two v i e w s . objectives of the risk of oversimplification the disagreement products can be The perhaps more defense oriented view is that in terms of furthering perceived safety g o a l s , the imposition of strict liability in and of itself provides the necessary incentive for manufacturers to make safer products. The more plaintiff oriented approach is that strict liability in and of itself is just a start toward increased product safety and that damageapportionment rules should be used and are needed to coerce m a n u f a c t u r e r s making safer products by denying the consideration of 7 plaintiff substandard c o n d u c t . cry Predictably, for pure comparative fault. culminates in The s e c o n d , against main injury-causing the first view culminates in more plaintiff oriented a cry for selective comparison of the 8plaintiff's conduct when deciding the damage-apportionment The some a view, substandard issue. purpose of this paper is to inquire into the treating into joint and severally liable negligent and reasons strict for or liability tortfeasors the same way w h e n it comes to apportioning damages b e t w e e n each of 9 them and the substandard plaintiff. apportioning damages between the substandard and strict liability tortfeasors and the substandard plaintiff in one c a s e , plaintiff in another c a s e , is involved. This issue is the same issue involved in negligent tortfeasors and but where the same or similar substandard conduct It is just that the issue is more sharply defined in the joint and several liability c a s e . As will be s e e n , some rather incongruous results appear in such situations. The following hypotheticals bring the issues into focus. HYPO I: Assume the p l a i n t i f f , having just purchased a spanking new 1984 Corvette, fabulous decides to take it for a spin on a country r o a d . 10 sound system in the $28,000 c a r , he reaches for his cassette but drops it onto the passenger side floorboard. reaches moment down and over for it, To test the favorite The plaintiff taking his eyes off the road for just a - just long enough for a farmer on a John Deere tractor to emerge 2 from behind plaintiff because Though hits injury. onto road. Although the plaintiff applies the emergency brake and managing to reduce his speed avoid with terrible force and suffers they frantically considerably, the tractor The farmer simply wasn't paying attention when h e the road, the when he sees the farmer and applies the brakes downshifts the t r a n s m i s s i o n , he the is traveling at a prudent rate of speed he is unable to collision, fail. some scrub trees and drive onto grave personal pulled out or he would have seen the plaintiff's car and could have avoided the a c c i d e n t . The plaintiff hires a recent Tech Law School graduate and sues farmer on a negligence t h e o r y . the He sues General M o t o r s , the m a n u f a c t u r e r , in strict tort liability and n e g l i g e n c e , alleging a defect in the braking 11 system. plaintiff been Special issues are submitted and the jury finds that was 20Z negligent in failing to keep a proper lookout (had looking he could have avoided the accident even though his driving this was his tractor, $10,000,000. was plus Plaintiff's personal injury His car is totally d e m o l i s h e d , worth $20,000. As who failed to use ordinary care in the jury finds the. farmer 80% negligent a proximate c a u s e . he brakes failed) and that this contributory negligence was a proximate c a u s e . between the plaintiff and the farmer, the and damages that are and the jury finds that it Thus the plaintiff recovers from the farmer $8,000,000 $16,000 for the c a r . As between the plaintiff and General Motors in the strict liability action the plaintiff proves that the brakes were defectively designed and unreasonably d a n g e r o u s , that they were in the same condition as when they 12 13 left GMj and that they were a producing c a u s e . Applying Texas law, the plaintiff recovers the full $10,000,000 + $20,000 for the car, 179 contributory The negligence not being a defense in strict tort plaintiff against CM, hoped but to get punitive damages in the the jury denies the claim for liability. negligence action 15 damages. punitive N e v e r t h e l e s s , he proves that the manufacturer failed to exercise ordinary care in the design of the brake system and that this negligence proximate c a u s e . in Texas, more was a Since contributory negligence is only a partial defense at least up to the point where the plaintiff's negligence that the negligence of the defendant where it becomes a is complete 16 bar, the plaintiff only recovers $8,000,000 + 16,000 from GM in negligence - just like he does from the farmer. HYPO II: Same facts, dealer's of except that when the plaintiff pulled out of the lot he discovered that the brakes were "real spongy." his pure lust for his new 'Vette, Here, the danger; plaintiff he has But he decides to take a spin voluntarily proceeded to out anyway. encounter 17 a has assumed the risk that the brakes might fail. known Against General Motors in strict tort liability the plaintiff recovers absolutely nothing, assumption of 18risk being a complete bar to recovery in tort liability in T e x a s . he recovers But against GM and the farmer in actions the comparative because negligence negligence, $5,000,000 for his personal injury and $10,000 for the because nssumption of risk of treated the same as contributory 19 under strict the nogligence statute. jury finds that his He takes assumed negligence less in these risk-contributory (instead of his failure to keep a proper lookout) was 20 car 50% the negligence involved in each c a s e . Of course the plaintiff's lawyer moves for judgment on the plaintiff's strict liability claim against General Motors in the first hypothetical 4 of 179 and against CM in negligence in the second hypothetical. In the first fact situation several problems appear: (1) How can we be justified in rewarding the negligent farmer reduction forced to in the pay, 20% GM can be even though the same plaintiff substandard conduct "As a matter of fundamental fairness, a a damage he owes and not reduce the amount involved and even though in strict liability GM is at least 22 non-negligent? (2) with was conceptually [isn't thej negligent plaintiff in strict products case whose negligence is i g n o r e d . . . the recipient of a fortuitous unfair advantage when we penalize a plaintiff in a negligence 23 action for the identical substandard conduct[?l" (3) Isn't it rather silly to allow a plaintiff to take more from GM in strict liability when in negligence he would have taken less from GM on the same 24 facts? In the second hypothetical a few different problems a p p e a r . (1) As a matter of fundamental fairness, isn't the plaintiff the recipient of an unfair advantage when we treat his assumed r i s k as a damage factor in assumption reducing a judgment against a negligent tortfeasor and when of risk totally bars his recovery from a his strict same products tortfeasor? (?) As opposed tortfeasors to the the negligent tortfeasors, aren't strict recipients of a fortuitous unfair advantage liability where the plaintiff is proven to have assumed the risk? CO Isn't it odd that a plaintiff who assumes the risk can proceed against the negligent manufacturer and recover at least part of his damages the same plaintiff who proceeds against the same manufacturer in when strict liability on the same facts will be totally barred from recovery? This paper is not limited to | | | ^ ^ | ^ a t i o n of Texas l a w . 5 Texas law is used here because at this point in time it permits the holdings of hypothetical two above hypothecicals. rapid growth the two and sheds little light on the problems presented by the These the problems would seem to hnvi* choir origin experienced in the field of strict products in liability. courts had barely become acclimated to strict liability when they were to "The forced encounter the comparative negligence revolution and assess its impact on 25 the newly-emerging theory." Only a few months before 26 Henderson v . Ford Motor Company was d e c i d e d , the Texas legislature had adopted Article 2212a, the Comparative Negligence S t a t u t e , 27 applicable to strict products l i a b i l i t y . which was not It would have been extremely difficult for the Supreme Court to have explained satisfactorily or justified a rule of law in Henderson by which a slightly negligent plaintiff could recover nothing from a strict liability tortfeasor while a plaintiff negligent to the same slight degree could recover a substantial amount of money from a negligent tortfeasor by virtue of comparative n e g l i g e n c e . Thus, a balance was struck - contributory negligence was no defense at all and voluntary assumption of risk was a complete bar to recovery.28 V While the history of this quandry m a y help t o e x p l a i n it, it. We are formulation historical here of a concerned with building a damage-apportionment rule, rationale it does not justify for independent the of judicial fortuitous events. A writer faced with a "should issue" has the difficult task of separating "what the law is" from "what the law should be." careful The reader is urged to notice of footnoted material so as to avoid confusing these issues. 00253 6 take separate The road tedious o n e . to the final resolution of the issue is a long and somewhat To attempt to answer the issue without inquiring into the issue of whether substandard conduct can be compared to the manufacturer's product, the liability types and of substandard c o n d u c t , products and the liability law in g e n e r a l , without leaving the h a r b o r . policy defective behind would be to strict put to sea I believe that by investigating these issues, any answer to be found to the main issue will be more easily d i s c o v e r e d . 1 believe it will be helpful if the reader will consider the distinguishing traits of the m a n u f a c t u r i n g , d e s i g n , and marketing defect cases in products liability II. It is actions. A PRELIMINARY PRACTICAL MATTER - CAN NEGLIGENT CONDUCT AND STRICT TORT LIABILITY INDUCING PRODUCTS BE COMPARED? that in strict tort liability the focus is on the 30 - is it unreasonably dangerous? Can the non-personal unreasonably 29 product often said dangerous product be compared with the personally blameworthy plaintiff who is 31 31a guilty of substandard conduct? Though many would d i s a g r e e , the answer is yes; when into the flows with stream of commerce in its dangerous c o n d i t i o n . from the without argue the question is framed so as to consider how the product 32 a perceived impropriety of comparing the manufacturer's negligence. liability which is "can" plaintiff's at least issue negligence conceptually Those writers who take this technical problem to strict liability comparing put heart culpable conduct or fault with the 33 defendant's strict liability - a non-fault d o c t r i n e . To compare negligence to against strict The was liability is plaintiff's to compare two it fundamentally different is t h o u g h . And there is no doubt that in so far as 34 tort analysis" is effective or even d e s i r e d , the argument passes 00254 bases of "pristine doctrinal muster. But The when this argument is subjected to substantive analysis improper hypertech, fruit, becomes the proper substantive comparison between two 35 rotten f r u i t . manufacturers can To illustrate, produce all the unreasonably dangerous defective wan without incurring the wrath of strict tort liability. when the manufacturer from product or introducing into commerce an unreasonably refrain from selling 37 an product without adequate w a r n i n g . use reasonable care in the d e s i g n , negligence subject duty, him It to but tort unreasonably on key duty dangerous dangerous defective non-defective strict tort the breach liability. that the unreasonably dangerous product was placed in imposing compare liability t o r t f e a s o r , damage l i a b i l i t y . strict of In which liability can strict tort it commerce. is The "non-negligent" sufficient blameworthiness is found to justify "The short answer to the dilemma of how one liability and 38 negligence is that one must simply close eyes and accomplish the task." Strict to m a n u f a c t u r e , and sale of his p r o d u c t s , the notion is that in both the substandard plaintiff and the strict the Phrased in duty liability actions we d o not care whether he exercises reasonable care; enough only This is a different duty from the duty to it is a duty n e v e r t h e l e s s , liability, that is manufacturer is held strictly liable for failing in its refrain of products unleashes the unreasonably dangerous 36 product public that it runs the risk of incurring strict liability. of product consider they the kinds The unreasonably dangerous defective is not really all that can be b l a m e d . terms, fails. comparison of rotten apples and rotten oranges in the realm albeit alone it can one's in warranty is essentially a non-fault concept as is 39 strict liability in t o r t . The basic elements of the warranty action and 40 strict tort action are the same in the products liability c o n t e x t . Whatever objection can be raised to a comparative blameworthiness (fault) system in apportioning damages between substandard plaintiffs and a manufacturer sued in warranty is largely the product of a focus on the contract element in warrantv 41 action. To the extent that warranty can be said to do the job of the negligence more and strict tort actions in products l i a b i l i t y , problem in comparing warranty to negligence than there is strict liability proceed from negligence the there should be no that b a s i s . comparing and the following discussion Notice that the conclusion that we can of them. the larger and more complex issue of whether will compare to strict liability and warranty liability brings use just threshold compare in tort to n e g l i g e n c e , 42 in we beyond should Because one can buy a house is no reason that one should buy It is relatively easy to compare the negligent defendant to the negligent plaintiff in negligence c a s e s . perceived theoretical Both are personally c u l p a b l e , therefore this impropriety of comparing non-fault and fault does exist in the simple negligence c a s e . While we have the means to compare both strictly liable defendant and negligent defendants with substandard under comparative fault principles despite the technical these technical what effect problems problems are not to be entirely discounted when plaintiff's conduct should have on his plaintiffs right involved, considering to recover against the strict liability tortfeasor and the negligent tortfeasor. It may very the not well be that these theoretical problems can be backed up b y reasons for treating the two types of tortfeasors III. [ strict substantive differently. TYPES OF SUBSTANDARD CONDUCT am inclined to agree with the position that the various defenses to a 43 products liability action tend to overlap each o t h e r . This overlap O a iO^SP 9 tends to bolster an argument that the various defenses should be stripped their technical distinctions and lumped into one batch of substandard 44 to be simply differences called "plaintiff fault." But there are some of conduct important between the various types of substandard conduct that need to be a d d r e s s e d , as these differences may become useful later on in this discussion. A. ASSUMPTION OF RISK 45 There are two basic ways of assuming a products r i s k . products For risk One can assume a 46 by express agreement in advance of the use of the product. example, one may purchase a product "as is" or with a warranty which is 47 to the exclusion of all other w a r r a n t i e s , express or i m p l i e d . This given way of assuming the risk is largely a matter of contract law and to the extent that the exclusive warranties or disclaimers are enforceable at law they will be binding on the plaintiff when he sues to recover a loss which results from 48 an "assumed risk." Unfortunately this particular way of assuming risks, 49 i . e . , by express a g r e e m e n t , is rare in products liability c a s e s . The other way is implied assumption of risk and this is the assumption of 49a risk most often encountered in products c a s e s . The essence of this defense is voluntary exposure distinguished act to known and appreciated This can be from plaintiff substandard conduct which consists of failing to as a reasonably prudent person under the same or i.e., risks. contributory negligence. A similar circumstances, plaintiff can objectively be viewed as having acted unreasonably without inquiring as to whether he subjectively knew 50 and appreciated the risks involved in the given s i t u a t i o n . of T h u s , assumption risk can be distinguished from contributory negligence on the basis of the plaintiff's product subjective knowledge and appreciation of the risks a dangerous poses. There is general agreement as to three of the elements of 10 ut/ewtjf § the defense: "(1) a subjective (2) subjective the dangers likely to result from that defective 51 and (3) a free and voluntary choice in encountering the danger." condition; appreciation knowledge of the dangerous condition; of This quote sets out the volenti non fit injuria "(one who consents may not be injured)" 52 defense. This formulation of the assumption of risk d e f e n s e , hereinafter 53 called v o l e n t i , is the formulation used in T e x a s . It derives from a purely subjective examination of the plaintiff's decisional s i t u a t i o n . purport to compare his conduct to the conduct of a prudent p e r s o n , the test. objective the Texas Under hypothetical view, contributory negligence the Restatement view adds "Assumption failure to act reasonableness to the the Restatement formulation we are faced with test rather than a purely subjective t e s t . risk, or not reasonably the objective test for contributory n e g l i g e n c e . of the risk is 54 the defense; reasonably is not." To 55 It does a subjective- "Melding assumption of which is predicated entirely on a subjection standard, with the objective standard of contributory negligence creates a hybrid defense that is neither56 tradit anal contributory negligence nor traditional assumption of the risk." beyond In It is not traditional assumption of risk or volenti because we look the consent issue to decide whether the consent was reasonable or n o t . speaking of the reasonableness r e q u i r e m e n t , Johnson v . Clark Equipment C o . apparent reasonableness encountered 57 the d a n g e r , so." the If of stated, the "[w]e the Oregon Supreme are physical conduct view negligence either. concerned through which with when we talk of assumption of risk we are not talking about The reasonably prudent person standard in the plaintiff but rather the reasonableness of his decision to Oregon Supreme Court is c o r r e c t , Restatment not Court about do the contributory of contributory negligence is traditionally compared to the plaintiff's c o n d u c t . Only to the extent that the plaintiff's decision to proceed to encounter the danger can be said to be c o n d u c t , can we apply the traditional standard of This hybrid d e f e n s e of which Professor Sales speaks will be called 59 v o l u n t a r y a s s u m p t i o n of To illustrate found negligent risk. the s u b s t a n t i v e d i f f e r e n c e s b e t w e e n the three a s s u m p t i o n of risk c o n s i d e r the following h y p o s . 2 58 reasonableness. in the i n t r o d u c t i o n of this p a p e r , Going back to types Hypothetical first assume that the plaintiff drove his C o r v e t t e off the d e a l e r ' s lot knowing that something w a s very with his brakes. condition T h e plaintiff k n e w the facts c o n s t i t u t i n g of his c a r , anyway the wrong dangerous and he knew that d r i v i n g the car with d a n g e r o u s brakes posed a danger or risk of h a r m to h i m . lot of And yet he d r o v e the car away from the as a m a t t e r of his v o l u n t a r y choice fully a p p r e c i a t i n g the fact that he may be faced with a situation w h e r e he would be unable to stop his car fast enough to avoid a c o l l i s i o n . defense w i t h o u t g o i n g further to q u e s t i o n the r e a s o n a b l e n e s s of h i s to drive the c a r . Secondly, if volenti decision Tt is enough that he v o l u n t a r i l y chose to do s o . we add the element of r e a s o n a b l e n e s s to the w h e t h e r he assumed the r i s k , with This is enough to c o n s t i t u t e the we could question find that h i s leaving the d e a l e r ' s full k n o w l e d g e and a p p r e c i a t i o n of the risk was u n r e a s o n a b l e . of lot Deciding to drive off the lot w h e n there was ready access to the d e a l e r ' s r e p a i r shop and when stopping the car and telling the dealer about the b r a k e s would have posed no threat to the p l a i n t i f f w a s u n r e a s o n a b l e . "take a The p l a i n t i f f ' s desire to spin" in h i s n e w car was simply not a good enough r e a s o n h i m s e l f to such a d a n g e r . to expose His action was u n r e a s o n a b l e , and he n e g l i g e n t l y and v o l u n t a r i l y assumed the risk by d r i v i n g the c a r . But let us assume that after d i s c o v e r i n g the spongy b r a k e s and while the car was at a full stop and still in the d e a l e r ' s l o t , realized that his three year old s o n , suddenly w h o came with him to pick u p the h < J ewti<J 12 the p l a i n t i f f car, had just swallowed a quart of antifreeze that was lying in the f l o o r b o a r d . He still an knew that there was a risk of his being unable to stop his car emergency. But because the hospital was a mile down the r o a d , and because he feared for his child's h e a l t h , to accept it. a in he drove the car knowing the risk and choosing "Since a reasonably prudent person might do the same thing..., jury could properly find that it was non-negligent voluntary assumption 60 of the risk." Notice two that situations by adding reasonableness to the volenti test in the described immediately plaintiff another chance to r e c o v e r . drinks the a n t i f r e e z e , above we have seemingly second given the In the third situation, w h e r e his child we are in effect saying that even though h e meets the requirements not of the v o l e n t i test we will allow him to recover b e c a u s e he was 61 negligent in assuming the r i s k . Does this mean that in the child situation the plaintiff cannot recover in Texas where volenti test is used? that the Not n e c e s s a r i l y . only the subjective The Supreme Court of Texas recognizes reasonableness of the plaintiff's decision to encounter the danger 62 may affect the voluntariness requirement found in the volenti d e f e n s e . is to say child's that the plaintiff may have been compelled by his fear well-being to such an extent that he did not voluntarily encounter the known d a n g e r . This for proceed It may have been an involuntary d e c i s i o n . the to H e , in e f f e c t , may have had no c h o i c e . In any given case the fact finder must consider the age, intelligence, e x p e r i e n c e , maturity of judgment and perception of the plaintiff in being able 63 to recognize knowledge of requirement. dangers the dangerous condition of the product. "Mere general the hazards or dangers posed by a product does not satisfy the Rather, the the knowledge must actually sensitize the user to 64 that u l t i m a t e l y cause the injury." The spongy brake case is not as clear cut a case as where the brakes completely fail. It is conceivable that the plaintiff in the Corvette hypothetical might have not the danger if the brakes were spongy but still marginally When actually realized functional. faced with an assumption of risk case we might ask ourselves these quest ions: (1) Did the plaintiff actually know that the product was in a dangerous condit ion? (2) Did the plaintiff actually realize the seriousness of the danger? (3) Did the plaintiff voluntarily choose to encounter the danger? Finally and according to the Restatement (4) formulation: If ( 1 ) , (2) and (3) are answered affirmatively, was this reasonable? The traditional concept of assumption of risk contemplates that a party may not recover for injuries received from a free and voluntary exposure to a fully appreciated danger. Because the doctrine is acknowledged as h a r s h , it is generally recognized that assumption of risk will not be applied beyond the salutory purpose of precluding recoveries that a r e , and should b e , avoidable by the ac tor.65 The latter part of the quote means that we do not ask whether should have known of the dangerous c o n d i t i o n , risk of h a r m . plaintiff or should have appreciated the This indeed would be to apply the reasonably prudent person or contributory negligence standard to the issue. have the assumption of risk; If this is done we would we would have contributory n e g l i g e n c e . not Subjective knowledge and understanding of the risk are the keys to the assumption of risk type of plaintiff substandard conduct. B. The the key WHAT IS MISUSE? to distinguishing misuse from assumption of risk is the use 66 product without specific knowledge of the d a n g e r . unusual or extreme or The use must have amounted to such a substantial A A O ^ I MliwVi. change be in of so the character of the product that it can no longer be called a normal use of 67 product. Having no specific knowledge of the dangerous condition of the the 63 product is enough to set it apart from assumption of risk just d i s c u s s e d . There are three broad categories of m i s u s e . illustrated Unitended or abnormal use is 69 by a man who uses a butcher knife for a t o o t h p i c k . butcher knife is for c u t t i n g , not p i c k i n g . Clearly 70 A second category of misuse might be called extreme u s e . draw the line negligence. might in Driving the a extreme use case between misuse It is hard to and be classified contributory n e g l i g e n c e , to legal while driving at 80 speed miles per It is a clearer of misuse when the product user has been forewarned of the maximum safe 71 of a p r o d u c t . Consider the case of a tire represented to be safe at 70 use mph, contributory car 10 miles per hour over the maximum hour over the speed limit would seem to be more like m i s u s e . case a but which is driven by the plaintiff beyond 70 m p h , pushing the product 72 its utmost c a p a b i l i t y . This case is distinguishable from the simple abnormal use case because the tire is still being used as a tire and butcher knife or step l a d d e r , an obvious m i s u s e . use per se as much as it is an extreme use. the This case also begins to take on It is not the same h o w e v e r . capability asking One who uses a product to its maximum may have notice of the dangerous condition and yet still not subjective unusual of safe operational speed for recognizing the dangerous condition of the product. risk. a Thus it is not an abnormal flavor of an assumption of the risk case if one substitutes a warning maximum the not actual knowledge of the danger that is required to 73 We may say that the misuser should have known or for extreme use of the p r o d u c t . it" "he even though at74 the time he misuses the product he subjectively know what "it" i s . We m a y , with r e a s o n , f'a O C O a an is just does not charge the negligent misuser with notice that by making the abnormal or extreme use of the C assume that he was making In colloquial terms, have product he takes on a responsibility for the increased liklihood of a dangerous 75 product defect causing injury because of his own a c t s . This is in effect to constructively 76 causes. put The him on notice that he may be charged for the same can be said for the plaintiff in the third injury he category of misuse. The third type of misuse is material alteration. The state of the law on what constitutes a substantial change is in disarray. The courts do not seem to adopt the same legal theory. Some place it under ordinary rules of contributory negligence; others relate it more to the matter of causation of the injuries, while others treat it as a question of whether or not the identity of the product has been preserved.77 A good illustration of an immaterial or insubstantial c h a n g e , that is a change which does 78 Hopkins. not is General Motors v. The plaintiff took an original equipment quadrajet carburetor off of his truck, the change the identity of the product, replaced it with a high performance c a r b u r e t o r , quadrajet back on his truck. lousy j o b . and later put When he put the quadrajet back on he did a One of the eleven mistakes he made in replacing the quadrajet was noted by the Texas Supreme Court as perhaps having a causal relation to the 79 accident which caused his injury. Hopkins did not make a material alteration care in the identity of the product; he merely failed to use ordinary making a material mistake in replacing it - classic contributory 80 negligence. But the Court could not hold that this contributory negligence would by be a defense. Both prediscovery and postdiscovery contributory negligence were not defenses to strict liability in t o r t , in Texas at the 81 time. The Court then had to find something more than contributory negligence in unforeseeable Hopkins, which the had order misuse to create a defense was on those particular f a c t s , and 82 the name given to i t . "The p l a i n t i f f , Robbie 'misused' the carburetor in that he had mishandled it in a way 83 manufacturer could not have reasonably foreseen." Clearly mishandling extreme connotes a c a t e g o r y of m i s u s e d i f f e r e n t use c a t e g o r i e s d i s c u s s e d a b o v e . from the abnormal and The truth of the m a t t e r is that it was u n f o r e s e e a b l e c o n t r i b u t o r y n e g l i g e n c e in failing to use o r d i n a r y care in the handling in of the c a r b u r e t o r . This c a s e d e m o n s t r a t e s the d i s t i n g u i s h i n g c o n t r i b u t o r y n e g l i g e n c e from m i s u s e . been m a t e r i a l in terms of c a u s a t i o n , difficulty His m i s h a n d l i n g may have b u t it did not change the n a t u r e of the product. The m a t e r i a l a l t e r a t i o n c a t e g o r y of m i s u s e is b e t t e r i l l u s t r a t e d by following light hypotheticals. Putting a trailer h i t c h on a family c a r to pull trailer or p l e a s u r e boat would be an a l t e r a t i o n of the c a r , but it not m a t e r i a l since a u t o m o b i l e s h a v e b e e n t r a d i t i o n a l l y used for such But if gear ratios are c h a n g e d , b i g g e r tires are a d d e d , family car h a s b e e n transformed truck or the l i k e . changed g e a r s , materially objects. into a h e a v y towing altered to appartus, for The jury should be able to d r a w the line if p r o p e r l y Some crashing been heavy whether For i n s t a n c e , w h e n misuse is defined as a " p a r t i c u l a r the q u e s t i o n of f o r e s e e a b i l i t y c l o u d s the issue of w h e t h e r the should the instructed. use that is not f o r e s e e a b l e or o b j e c t i v e l y r e a s o n a b l e to e x p e c t " the use is heavy towing c o u r t s tend to c o n f u s e the q u e s t i o n of what m i s u s e is w i t h it should be a d e f e n s e . of a the family car has b e c o m e a truck or s i m i l a r v e h i c l e is the nature of S o m e w h e r e b e t w e e n the a d d i t i o n of the t r a i l e r h i t c h , tires and added w e i g h t to the f r a m e , a purposes. and m o r e w e i g h t added to the frame in o r d e r to pull a m a s s i v e trailer or y a c h t , the the be called a m i s u s e of the p r o d u c t . 84 a car is a m i s u s e of the c a r . There is little injection particular doubt Cars are not p r i m a r i l y d e s i g n e d taht as b a t t e r i n g rams; they are primarily d e s i g n e d to t r a n s p o r t p a s s e n g e r s in m o r e or less comfort from one point to a n o t h e r . It is true that it is that cars will be c r a s h e d (indeed it is i n e v i t a b l e ) . fiOf* < [•• 17 ••• t\* ' foreseeable But f o r e s e e a b i l i t y of car crashes has little to do with the question of whether crashing a car is a 35 misuse. Foreseeability has everything to do with whether misuse ought to be 86 a defense to an action in products liability. and very often each d a y . crashing vehicles vehicles. The justification burden of actually if Car crashes occur every There is a grave risk of injury to the drivers manufacturers do not design crashworthiness foreseeabiity of car crashes is the injects cars reasonably crashworthy. negligence into the c a s e , The even if it policy the dictated their foreseeability proceeds of into for imposing liability on manufacturers who do not carry making day issue in strict liability. The following test for misuse approximates what the test ought to be: use or handling expect the which so unusual that the average consumer could not product to be designed and manufactured to withstand the seller, therefore need not anticipate and provide "a reasonably it 87- a for." use This test does try to get the experience of the jury into the d e t e r m i n a t i o n , but it goes further to ask the juror as to whether he could expect a manufacturer to design and manufacture the product to withstand the u s e . Jurors need not know what the manufacturer's design capability is to decide whether the product has been m i s u s e d . Why not simply ask them whether "the [productl was used for purpose and average c o n s u m e r . . . | ? 1" question a manner 88 not unlike that which could be If so, it was not m i s u s e . expected If the is to be submitted to the jury to determine whether the foreseeable Professor judge, in or not, Twerski then that submit it separately. I am in the foreseeability question is better from a the foreseeability misuse agreement left to was with the so whether analysis. that he may respond to public policy considerations in determining 89 the misuse should be a d e f e n s e . This may be done by duty-risk 90 In this r e g a r d , question of fact. foreseeability becomes a question of l a w , not a If there was a design defect because the particular misuse C02S5 18 was the very thing to be prevented, or the injury from the misuse was the very thing to be lessened or avoided, then the misuse would as a matter of law not 91 be a defense. Such misuse would as a matter of law be foreseeable. To hold otherwise the would be to negate the reason for holding the design defective at 92 outset. The design defect case is the case which is hard to separate the foreseeability issue from the misuse issue. But the two are not identical questions and can both be answered separately. 93 is much easier in this regard. The manufacturing defect case No matter which category of misuse the plaintiff's substandard conduct falls under, we may be more justified in making his misuse a d e f e n s e . In each of the categories, abnormal use, extreme use, material alteration a n d , if you will indulge m e , unforeseeable contributory negligence as in the Hopkins case, the plaintiff has voluntarily, if not with subjective appreciation of the dangers involved, put the product to a use that the average consumer would not 94 expect. We may be justified in placing a greater burden on him where his 95 reasonably unexpected conduct has contributed to his h a r m . C. CONTRIBUTORY NEGLIGENCE Contributory negligence is a broad enough term to encompass all forms of 96 negligent contributory plaintiff substandard c o n d u c t . In the following discussion the term will be defined so as to limit it to some very special if not absolutely discreet m e a n i n g s . Contributory negligence is distinguished virtue from assumption of risk by of the tests applied to determine their existence. Volenti requires 97 subjective knowledge of the plaintiff. Contributory negligence is measured 98 by our reasonably prudent person standard, an objective standard. e .TlOCf® i^Ot? 19 Misuse and contributory negligence are blood brothers. The same objective standard is applied in both c a s e s , though the special issue may be 99 framed d i f f e r e n t l y . Misuse and one of the forms of contributory negligence can be distinguished on the basis of the relationship between the conduct and the p r o d u c t . in the introduction's lookout. So negligence extent the did To illustrate, consider our plaintiff Corvette owner 100 first h y p o t h e t i c a l . He failed to keep a proper contributory 101 only marginally related to the use of the product. To the is the substandard farmer in that hypo. This type of that the particular conduct cannot be said to be aided or use of the p r o d u c t , it is different from m i s u s e . induced by The plaintiff did not need to use the product in order to fail to keep a proper lookout. He could have done the same thing by tripping over a crack in a sidewalk or by hoisting a board over his shoulder only to hit someone standing behind h i m . other h a n d , the a misuser of the product cannot misuse it without using Corvette owner who drives 150 mph has misused it, he had product to get himself and the car to the speed of 150 m p h . merely been fails this time while he happened to be in a the it. If use the In contrast if he to keep a proper lookout while driving the c a r , negligent to On car. he has To merely give this marginally product related form of contributory negligence a n a m e , let us call it inc idental contributory negligence. A plaintiff may also be contributorily negligent as a result of more than his "incidental" relationship with the product. To the extent that the particular conduct can be said to have been aided or induced by the use of the product it negligence is, depending on the degree of the use, either contributory But if it is contributory n e g l i g e n c e , it is product 102 related contributory n e g 1 i g e n c e . 103 104 There are also the prediscovery and postdiscovery forms of contributory or m i s u s e . negligence. Conduct 20 can be called C02S7 prediscovery contributory negligence so long as the plaintiff has not discovered the dangerous condition of the product. product, his But conduct if from he discovers there is something that point forward, if wrong negligent contributes to his injury, is postdiscovery contributory with and the if it negligence. By what standard are we to determine whether the plaintiff discovered the defect? It would seem that if we are going to keep assumption of contributory negligence s e p a r a t e d , risk and we should adopt an objective standard in keeping with the generally recognized definition of contributory negligence as unreasonable c o n d u c t , as compared to the "reasonable man." has done s o . At least one court "[W)e affirm the doctrine that failure to discover or foresee dangers which the ordinary person would have discovered or foreseen as well as negligent conduct after discovery of the danger and in use of the product will 105 constitute a that court this negligence defense to an aciton based on strict liability...." would apparently consider or product r e l a t e d , contributory and it should not go so far as to put an affirmative duty on the plaintiff inspect "(0]ne incidental postdiscovery would106 hold the plaintiff liable for his objective failure to discover the d a n g e r . But the court whether all Notice the product to guard against the possibility of a product to 107 defect. of the inherent policies in strict products liability is the right of 108 the consumer to rely upon the integrity of the product." is to plaintiff be charged for his negligent failure to discover the defect objective inspect there If the standard, the product? is plaintiff something who haven't 109 we placed at least an implied duty on Charging the plaintiff who knows wrong with his brakes is far different from should have known of the faulty brakes in that the voluntary assumption of risk. Such conduct might be C02S8 21 an him to subjectively conduct that amounts to more than mere contributory n e g l i g e n c e , negligent under that charging a former is and less than called post actual discovery contributory n e g l i g e n c e . Is this the creation of another 110 hybrid contributory plaintiff this negligence - assumption of recognizes that something is w r o n g , risk defense? If then his actions which recognition are different from the prediscovery contributorily plaintiff. Whether or seriousness of the danger as is required by the assumption of risk he does have n o t i c e . not he goes on to subjectively question presented we negligence is a hybrid There are two mentioned. Failure illustrated by provided follow negligent appreciate must say that post actual the doctrine, But to avoid placing an affirmative duty to inspect the plaintiff we should adopt a subjective test for n o t i c e . the on In answer to the discovery contributory defense. other types of contributory negligence that need to use safety equipment is one type. It the failure to use a safety belt or the like which 111 by the m a n u f a c t u r e r . This type of conduct will most to be is best has been often fall into the prediscovery c a t e g o r y , but could become assumption of risk if the act of discarding safety equipment brings the danger home to the user and he goes on to voluntarily expose himself to the d a n g e r . failure to service or maintain the p r o d u c t . form of contributory Ilia case, negligence, but The other type of conduct is It is most likely a prediscovery it may become misuse in a proper though it is arguable that it is always a foreseeable m i s u s e . Thus we see several types of contributory negligence that do not to misuse or assumption of risk as previously d i s c u s s e d . amount There is incidental contributory n e g l i g e n c e , product related contributory n e g l i g e n c e , prediscovery and postdiscovery (subjective recognition of product malfunction or condition dangerous without subjective understanding or appreciation of the seriousness of the danger) contributory n e g l i g e n c e . By now the reader may be applauding the Uniform Comparative Fault Act for lumping all of the forms of substandard conduct under one term: 002S9 fault. But the reader is asked to postpone final judgment for the m o m e n t . may make a difficult problem easier to solve, not to solve the more difficult question plaintiff conduct should be d e f e n s e s . Though the Act to make the problem easier of what forms of is substandard D. We have SUMMARY OF THE TYPES OF SUBSTANDARD CONDUCT examined the various types of substandard conduct. On a decreasing scale of culpability these would fall in the following order: MOST CULPABLE: negligent assumption of risk LESS CULPABLE: misuse and post discovery contributory negligence (using a subjective test for discovery)l12 LEAST CULPABLE: prediscovery contributory negligence Negligent assumption of risk is the most culpable substandard c o n d u c t , because the plaintiff voluntarily and unreasonably proceeds to encounter a danger that he has fully a p p r e c i a t e d . He is the most c u l p a b l e , danger has in a sense explained itself to h i m , himself more to the d a n g e r . culpable constructive postdiscovery plaintiff the more than we contributorily negligent actually h a s . assumed risk t a k e r . the misuser does n o t . something like wanton and w i l l f u l , takers, because may place on the misuser and the actual In either disregard. which is Both basically He does actually The post discovery plaintiff's is of the notice the case the The postdiscovery plaintiff may even culpable than the misuser in this r e s p e c t . reckless negligence, the expose has come capability to save himself though to a lesser extent negligent notice; and yet he consents to Misuse and postdiscovery contributory negligence prediscovery contributory notice because in effect have than be the scienter is where the misuser is roughly equivalent to of these plaintiffs fall below what an assumed risk taker is, intentional above the 113 prediscovery plaintiff who may only be guilty of ordinary c a r e l e s s n e s s . CC271 24 and risk IV. SHOULD DAMAGE APPORTIONMENT BE A C C O M P L I S H E D ON THE BASIS OF THE COMPARATIVE CULPABILITY OF T H E PARTIES? 114 No, fault not in products liability a c t i o n s . concept plaintiff and If strict liability is a non- substandard plaintiffs are always faultful, ever hope to recover from manufacturers in strict the plaintiff substandard conduct is present? deciding factor, how liability, a the plaintiff will not r e c o v e r . strict liability tortfeasor. reasons which instance. in support the when But personal culpability is It cannot b e , imposition a If personal culpability is the not really the issue when apportioning damages between a substandard and can of strict because of liability plaintiff the in policy the first To compare the parties purely on the basis of personal culpability the products case would be to ignore the purposes of strict liability and tort law in g e n e r a l . law What we are looking for is a rule which will foster the achievement of the perceived policy goals of maximizing product safety and consumer protection encourage general, safe in keeping with strict liability theory and consumer use of the product in keeping which seeks to encourage the prevention of harm by can be done without regard to personal c u l p a b i l i t y . personal capability failed with to approaches liability avoid the to it. type avoid the l o s s , everyone. will law in This What we should look at is the loss having more nearly compare strict The following policy discussion should of blameworthiness that can be used to bring an understanding as to why this must be s o . 25 tort not personal culpability for Personal capability to avoid and plaintiff n e g l i g e n c e . which V. POLICY - SAFE CREATION AND S A L E , AND SAFE USE OF PRODUCT Policy, tendency "as applied to a ... rule of law, denotes its general purpose or considered as directed to the welfare or prosperity of the state 115 community." or In our accident prone society, rules of law should be directed to the achievement of the desired policy goal of increased safety. Products liability l a w , as a subspecies of tort l a w , should be aimed at benefitting the community by encouraging the safe d e s i g n , manufacture and sale of manufactured goods. As far as it is p r a c t i c a b l e , a damage apportionment rule should as a rule of products liability l a w , be directed at the same desired There are apportionment is two stages in the life of a product rule can be a i m e d . which the damage Safety can be put into a product before it used b y the consumer in proportion to the combined measure of safety is actually put into the d e s i g n , is the pre-use safety s t a g e . to at objectives. the measure and sale of the p r o d u c t . A product can also be made safer in of care the user of the product actually applies product is being u s e d . aware manufacture, This is the use safety stage. A. This proportion while the Until the plaintiff is of the risks he is not avoiding by his substandard should not fall on h i m . that conduct, the loss This is w h y . PRODUCT SAFETY - SOCIETY'S CRY FOR PROTECTION From the dawn of man through the early 1800's, the common man largely understood at least intuitively the basic dangers in his tools and the basic principles of safety by which such risks could be reduced to acceptable l e v e l s . . . . Somewhat over a century a g o , all this began to change....[T]he 1960's witnessed a general awakening to the variety of sacrifices that accompanied industrial growth.116 As larger, industry the inevitable. progressed and the stream of manufactured evolution of new legal doctrines to meet emerging The creation goods problems and ^^gyit^r^. of strict tort liability is a 26 became was prime example of perceived a societal formulating into legal doctrine formulated to expedite the achievement 117 goals. Societal goals are valid considerations any rule of l a w . "[C]ourts cannot and should not escape consideration in the determination of tort and other cases the of in taking interest 118 of 'we the people' at large...." It is generally recognized "that a manufacturer or even a dealer responsibility sufficient to fact the ultimate c o n s u m e r , a public protection have no would than interest and do harm if they are defective." in human life and safety requiring a the to There maximum legal against dangerously defective p r o d u c t s , against which consumers 120 realistic ability to protect themselves." This public interest not appear the classification 121 action under which the action p r o c e e d s . By the act of particular the more that he has so dealt with the goods that they are likely 119 come into the hands of a n o t h e r , is based on nothing has to change upon the nature of of the placing product in the m a r k e t , the maker is said to warrant the product's safety 122 and expects the consumer to use the product in reliance on the w a r r a n t y . "The...safety incentive rationale seeks to place the burden of paying for the harm on the party in the best position to prevent that if lack the skills and knowledge to avoid or prevent It presumes design or warning caused an i n j u r y , the 123 manufacturer can and should market safer products." " C o n s u m e r s , who often should defective injury. receive construction, full compensation those presumption that reality debatable when dealing with a specific p r o d u c t . is manufacturers for product-related injuries, 124 injuries." Whether the can market safer products here to say that this p r e s u m p t i o n , of strict is 125 It is in enough which forms part of the basis for adoption liability does not discourage bona fide manufacturer make safer p r o d u c t s . C0Z7-1 27 justified attempts to The presumption would seem to be justified when one observes the types and the potential severity of products induced loss. various Losses in terms of p r o p e r t y , personal injury or d e a t h , lost or strained family r e l a t i o n s h i p s , and ultimately Needless caused in to lost say, to quality of life are to be avoided if where at all possible. money alone cannot really compensate for an individual, rules are needed and are particularly the harm justified, where they can be formulated to reduce the potential for h a r m . Thus safety, designed to allocate plaintiffs. We as a paramount o b j e c t i v e , should be fostered by any loss between blameworthy defendants and blameworthy 126 insurors. But this is not an argument for making manufacturers ultimately seek a rule which in and of itself will rule accommodate societal 127 notions of fairness. substantial producing Safety in blameworthy is plaintiffs 128 so. justice a two could Thus blameworthy the Making manufacturers a legal system such as insurers ours, which conduct with liability for the party affair. The reporters are have avoided products related h a r m s , rule products finally formulated to plaintiffs and not awards harm caused full of the should serve injury thereby. cases and yet apportion defendants will did not loss serve where do between to foster plaintiff and defendant safety in the use and manufacture and sale of products if p o s s i b l e . So far, only safety concerns have been d i s c u s s e d . But safety costs money and this brings us to another societal interest - the interest in the supposed benefit to be m a n u f a c t u r e d , useable g o o d s . derived from having a continued This interest has clear economic but is discussed here in the safety c o n t e x t . preserving flow of considerations, Requiring manufacturers to make products so safe that no one could conceivably get hurt would no doubt cost large fortune by anybody's standards. could make products so expensive Too strict of a loss apportionment that few Cfe275 to none could afford a rule them. Moreover, some inherently even if products dangerous absolute are made useful by the very fact propensities. they Thus a rule requiring absolute safety was not impossible, practical or economic r e a l i t y . that would have no firm have safety, basis in The point is made here that the apportionment rule finally formulated must balance safety against the economic and practical realities of 129 society. Thus producing affordable and useable goods to the society's answering the plea for safer products is in reality issue as to what effect the plaintiff's benefit of all Janus-faced. In substandard should have on his right to recover against products liability due and the societal manufactured g o o d s . A. tortfeasors, consideration must be given to both the societal interest in safety interest in preserving the flow conduct 130 encouraging of beneficial The issues break down as follows: Safety (1) Can we formulate a rule which will maximize consumer (2) Can we formulate a rule which will maximize protection? overall safety incentive? (3) B. Can we formulate a rule that is fundamentally fair? Socio-economic (I) Can we formulate a rule that does all of the above without unduly restricting the beneficial flow of useable goods? B. Before economic we p r o c e e d , ECONOMIC ASPECTS FROM THREE SIDES a caveat is needed and it can simply be stated considerations in and of themselves pose a great danger to a that legal philosophy which has as its ultimate aim the just adjudication of c l a i m s . The 131 tactical search for a deep pocket is a good e x a m p l e . The unequal access a 29 C0276 poor person has to the courtroom is a n o t h e r . though in Let it also be said that economics in and of itself poses a greater danger to our legal proportion formulation there is even system to the emphasis placed on economic factors when coming to of a rule of l a w , perhaps when it comes to enforcing the rule no greater motivator than judicial pressure to one's the provident of the law, application of pocketbook. (I) MANUFACTURERS "The conventional economic theory underlying strict products liability is that d e f e n d a n t s , who are manufacturers or s e l l e r s , are in a better position to distribute the loss among the consuming public through insurance or product 132 pricing." This loss distribution idea is precisely the view of §402A of 133 the R e s t a t e m e n t . But it is argued that this may not be workable in 134 practice small where business competitive small or highly competitive businesses are may business not be able to suffer the loss concerned. at all. could be put out of business b y raising its A A highly prices to A manufacturer who cannot afford the loss cannot spread it. cover the loss. Thus, the loss spreading idea may be workable for RCA of General M o t o r s , yet be unworkable when applied to a mom and pop business that a manufacturer manufacturer price, if has can pay a products c l a i m , loss that figured in the payment of future claims a Assuming forward-looking into his current the price of the product passes beyond the point where its utility and desirability make it a f f o r d a b l e , Thus, or concern. and spreading alone is the manufacturer will not long unjustified to the extent differing manufacturing concerns equally across the b o a r d . loss spreading is to be found e l s e w h e r e . * 30 that survive. it treats Justification of Manufacturers are in the unique position of being able to risk of harm products will cause when they are placed on the they are placed justification damage with for on the market. This risk evaluating the idea of loss spreading just evaluate market, be fore capability 135 discussed. the is a Aiming a apportionment rule at the pre-use safety stage is perfectly consistent policy dictated protection. formulated goals Therefore, should of any safer damage products, thus apportionment rule encourage the manufacturer to make an increased that consumer is finally evaluation of the risks their products pose to members of the public likely to come into contact 136 with the product. If we adopt the view that manufacturers, large or small, are in the better position to evaluate the risks created by distributing their products, risks we they can be justified in concluding that where manufacturers must be prepared to spread the losses resulting therefrom place or be prepared to face the consequences if they cannot. Therefore, mom and pop are placed Motors 137 via on an economic level with RCA or General pre-use risk evaluation and loss spreading are the premises upon which the idea evaluation capability and its incentive, loss spreading. Risk of enterprise liability is justified. which it can be made to work. At the same time they are the means by Enterprise liability is the theoretical precept by which manufacturers are held liable for the harm caused by their products come because "(they) have so dealt with the goods that they are likely to 138 into the hands of another, because defective and do harm if they are defective," they are theoretically able to spread losses when they spreading, being evaluate risk, justified because of the capability of occur. manufacturers and Loss to is the means by which society can be made to foot the bill for living the improved life which supposedly flows from having a plentiful supply of manufactured goods. evaluate But again the unique capability of manufacturers risk and spread loss do not go so far as to support an argument to for making loss manufacturers i n s u r o r s . does However, not this mean The mere economic feasibility that all loss should be capability placed on the of spreading manufacturer. is to be a factor to be considered in enforcing a rule by which we can apportion damages between plaintiffs and manufacturers in 138a products liability c a s e s . b 32 1 <J> (2) It absorb is INJURED PLAINTIFFS said that "[blecause few consumers have the financial ability the costs of unanticipated product-related injuries, public to policy places the financial burden on the party who placed the defective product on 139 market...." Taken as a whole this statement has no place in products the liability law. It does not mean what it s a y s . It is makeweight at best for 140 imposition of strict liability. The invalidity is clearly pointed out the in jurisdictions conduct will reduce or negate his award of d a m a g e s . plaintiffs whether the phrase are Certainly guilty of recovery reducing substandard statement manufacturers What as a w h o l e , it is an argument spreading there conduct for or making products notion by which the loss spreading concept can be justified. capability in and of itself is nothing more than a purely incidental to running a business incidental enterprise. is must evaluate the risks the product p o s e s , C3n them. interest in as a Public policy demands this to be d o n e . the But whole (a class of potential plaintiffs) has assuming just compensation to plaintiffs 33 purely public l A ^ o u for life, because they nothing to do with the individual plaintiff's inability to absorb Society the At the pre-use stage in a product's manufacturers evaluate Loss Small and must both evaluate the risks they impose on they market their p r o d u c t s . is economic It capability in formulating a damage apportionment r u l e . manufacturers the Risk evaluation manufacturer's ability to evaluate risk that justifies the use of this when not. validity that can be attributed to the quote above is found in phenomenon large are insurors. "who placed the defective product on the market." key substandard in those jurisdictions who cannot afford to pay for their d a m a g e s , they Taking the holding that at least some forms of plaintiff 141 alone this has loss. an products economic related injury. But individual this interest plaintiffs apportionment the poor. may is not be unable absorb supported the just because A damage loss. Society's interest is only indirectly served by the purely economic putting before to or rule should not be designed for the redistribution of wealth to business phenomenon of loss shifting. by affected manufacturers Society's interest is directly on notice that they must evaluate selling products to the public, served products' risks and refrain from selling them if they pose an unreasonable risk of harm to the ordinary consumer. for Cut-reaction notions of justice place the loss on the person responsible 142 creating unreasonable risks of harm to themselves or others. In cases To this person will be a defendant and in others it will be a plaintiff. fail to avoid the avoidable injury is to create a risk of harm. given situation, some If in the capability to avoid creating unreasonable risks of a harm is on the one or the other of the parties and he 143 fails to avoid the risk, then the loss caused by such failure should be his. apportionment should be rule so at products safely. wholly use. the But is preventing Manufacturers should be encouraged pre-use irrelevant What can be realistically directed at directed. products To the extent that a damage stage. Plaintiffs should be to make encouraged the plaintiff's inability to absorb to the encouragement of safer products and relevant is: injury, injury safe it safe to use loss is products (1) the unique capability of manufacturers evaluate risks before the product is unleashed on an unsuspecting public; to (2) the practical capabilities of plaintiffs to evaluate risk at the use stage; and (3) the buying the ability of the manufacturer to shift the loss on to pub lie. 00281 C. SOCIETAL ECONOMIC INTERESTS While the individual plaintiff's inability to absorb the products related loss has society no bearing on the issue of who should ultimately pay for the has individual a legitimate interest in preserving the economic well plaintiffs. It must be remembered that society is than an aggregate of potential products liability p l a i n t i f f s . the being nothing and political and social endeavors is to be objective to be achieved? In the first p l a c e , protected. Undue encouraging safe consumer use of manufactured Society product In the second p l a c e , by products. also has an economic interest in preserving the flow of useable products offer members of society a means for making a living. goods. Many Product suppliers offer j o b s . prices at an affordable l e v e l , what How is by encouraging safety before the product is unleashed on the p u b l i c . more industry, financial hardship is to be avoided in furtherance of this o b j e c t i v e . this of Preservation of individual's ability to participate in the advancement of a r t , technology, loss, Society has an interest in keeping both directly and i n d i r e c t l y . products' But consider can happen if this societal economic interest is given undue weight when it is not considered in conjunction with safety p o l i c y . It is argued that since a manufacturer's loss is u l t i m a t e l y to the consuming p u b l i c , plaintiff to the argument it is unfair as between consumers and the individual that consumers should have to pay the portion of damages attributed 144 plaintiff's own substandard c o n d u c t . But as persuasive as this may seem at first g l a n c e , 145 itself r e v e a l s . entirely when First of a l l , one there is more at stake than the argument blameworthiness is taken out of the picture argues that the damage apportionment issue battle between the plaintiff and the consuming p u b l i c . is distributed ; 'vnq/-* be a And yet this argument used by t s advocates as an argument for pure comparative C should fault. Surely the public cannot be blamed for buying products in the first instance and only incidentally subsidizing the defendant's forced payment of money damages to 146 the p l a i n t i f f . In a fault conscious legal system of tort liability such as ours, the reduction of the blameworthiness comparison issue between the plaintiff and the manufacturer to a loss spreading formula between a faultless consuming public and faultful plaintiff is to take comparative blameworthiness 147 entirely out of the p i c t u r e . If this is the true nature of strict l i a b i l i t y , t h e n comparing fault between plaintiffs and defendant manufacturers is i n d e f e n s i b l e . To say that a faultful plaintiff should lose the issue to a faultless public is truly to compare stepladders to a p p l e s . this inventive undeniably attempt divert society's attention away primary safety r e s p o n s i b i l i t y , Consider encouragement justifiable hits that of means loss from the In so far as it is a product's an defendant's 148 pre-use s a f e t y , the argument is m i s l e a d i n g . spreading is simply an economic means toward pre-use safety on the part of the m a n u f a c t u r e r . because it encourages risk evaluation be fore It the the is a product the market and because manufacturers have the unique ability to evaluate these risks before m a r k e t i n g . at importantly, rhetorical argument does absolutely nothing to encourage valid goal of encouraging pre-use safety. to More The closer the manufacturer is required to look the potential risks his product p o s e s , its dangerous p r o p e n s i t i e s . policy standard dictated Indeed, the less likely he is to "loss spreading" is nothing more than a legal restatement of what everyone knows is and business practice - the shift of loss to all c o n s u m e r s . put the loss on the manufacturer only because he can shift it; the manufacturer evaluation. manufacturer, to encourage better product safety The substandard plaintiff product u s e r , is overlook through must be We do we put it better as between him and a not on risk the usually in a much lesser position to evaluate the potential eM r ' ' - - risks the involved in using p r o d u c t s . This disparity is widened appreciably premarketing stage where plaintiffs have n £ chance to risks. evaluate at products To say that between a plaintiff and the consuming public (shifting the focus away from the manufacturer) a plaintiff should suffer a proportionate or complete bar to his r e c o v e r y , plaintiff is research, and capacity to act on such k n o w l e d g e . patently equal to the is indirectly to say that in safety terms unjustified manufacturer, equation. in foresight, knowledge, design Such an argument presents a The so called socio-economic justice to derived from reducing plaintiff's recovery pursuant to pure comparative principles is dangerous and m i s c o n c e i v e d , to encourage 149 evaluate. as the optimal the pre-use be fault because it does absolutely nothing risk evaluator, the manufacturer, to The so called safety incentive which is directed at plaintiffs 150 a result of a pure comparative fault damage-apportionment rule is more of a pipe dream than sound legal p o l i c y , because it assumes that substandard plaintiff w o u H have the rule in mind before and during the time he engages in 151 substandard conduct. I would venture to say that no p l a i n t i f f , is suicidal or a s a d i s t , substandard conduct. increasingly loss expects that anyone will get hurt when he engages in This is not to say that somewhere risk responsible Compared potential of to m a n u f a c t u r e r s , anyone else in the w o r l d , targets for the with for every conceivable type of substandard conduct grounds that society's pocketbook will b e n e f i t , evaluation scale of the to It is m e r e l y to say that holding manufacturers who is to ignore the should be evaluate risks and take reasonable steps to prevent or reduce poor a Where a plaintiff has a realistic capability avoid loss he should be encouraged to do s o . the on culpable substandard conduct he should not be saddled his conduct p r o d u c e d . plaintiffs unless he on unique encouraged to them. who should know their products better than substandard plaintiffs and the consuming public are safety incentive which is written into a damage apportionment particular the to rule. It is safe to say that where the consuming public plaintiffs will not even know about a damage apportionment manufacturer or his lawyer will know about it because it is his and rule, business know what liabilities will flow from the risks that are created by placing products into the stream of c o m m e r c e . can be Therefore, any safety incentive that written in to our damage-apportionment rule should be aimed at those who will consider it and who can take realistic measures to prevent losses keeping with the safety incentive. position to consider the rule Defendant manufacturers are in the and take pre-use a c t i o n . Plaintiffs are potentially in the position to avoid the injury when become actually aware in of the d a n g e r . In today's society it is a they bigger problem to be aware of products' dangers than it used to b e , when dangers were more self produce evident. As far as plaintiffs are c o n c e r n e d , results which are substantially j u s t . liability on the p l a i n t i f f , That is, the rule should they should impose giving due consideration to the realities of plaintiff risk evaluation and plaintiff ability to avoid the injury at the use 152 stage in the life of the p r o d u c t . Safer products will not be encouraged by "pouring out" a plaintiff to the extent of his marginal substandard conduct. And this rule yet fashioned in may very accordance well result if the damage with the argument for so between consumers and a particular p l a i n t i f f . be prevented at the outset by a m a n u f a c t u r e r , apportionment called economic is justice If the plaintiff's injury can then we should encourage him to do so within bounds of r e a s o n . There to a battle substandard should is one other problem with reducing the damage-approtionment over the out of pocket expenses that plaintiffs, will p a y . opposed to What the bill be for increased pre-use safety measures or lost a r m s , legs, 00285 moral as question. 38 It is in part a society, scheme p r o p e r t y , and their respective collateral damages? will produce fewer injuries. money judgment unreasonably damages he liabilities dangerous Are we to subsidize the manufacturer's more products, often because he continues or are we to subsidize the The safer a product is, found unreasonably dangerous and thus, lesser to produce larger pays less often through increased product safety which will ultimately pay for. The P r e s u m a b l y , safer products money again we the less likely it will be the less likely it is to hurt someone. argument is made h e r e that society's overall interest in preserving h u m a n life and preventing waste may justify holding manufacturers liable for entire loss to which a plaintiff may have contributed if the injury risk of the producing harm was such that it could have been better avoided at the pre-use s t a g e , than at the use stage of the product in any given s i t u a t i o n , and if the plaintiff's practical ability to perceive the risk of harm was less than manufacturer's ability to perceive it and take reasonable steps to the prevent 153 This again is not to argue that manufacturers are to be held liable as it. insurors. policy Where objective i.e., where of can be furthered by placing the loss on the no valid manufacturer, the plaintiff was in a better position than the manufacturer avoid the r i s k , face the plaintiff's substandard conduct is such that to holding the plaintiff liable for the loss does not fly in the valid products liability policy objectives.'IP Thus we arrive at the conclusion that the bill society pays should be for improved pre-use safety to the extent that pre-use safety measures can be effectively applied to prevent abhorrent personal and property injury, notwithstanding that the plaintiff is in part responsible for his own injury. This is to do more than gut reaction justice between should not manufacturer that the immediate p a r t i e s . suffer at losses where such The bottom line is that losses were preventable the pre-use stage by giving consideration to a plaintiff might create an unreasonable risk of harm to the plaintiffs by the liklihood himself while using the product due to his inability to perceive the risk or take action to 154 dispel i t . To hold otherwise would be to equate manufacturer and plaintiff capability to legitimacy of enterprise liability theory and the representational nature the products liability argument product liability on tort - which form the harm, basis and would for case. There are 155 This would seem already p r e s e n t . encourage manufacturers independently of to two types of cases in which deny imposing to injecting foreseeability of plaintiff conduct into arguably brake created risks of manufacturers in the first p l a c e . for liability avoid the strict be back plaintiff is But strict liability is the preferred means to produce safe products. It is supported a defective members of 157 the substandard that we encourage manufacturers to produce safer products society to u s e . the Substantial justice requires that we bring the from the battle between faultless consumers and and an strict that fails when plaintiffs are negligent will most often fail when 156 focus of foreseeability foreseeability issues when one considers that plaintiff is n o n - n e g l i g e n t . the Some of these members will be negligent for at times. At what plaintiff point conduct on can a we scale of increasingly blameworthy say that policy goals will not be substandard furthered by placing the loss on the defendant manufacturer? VI. A DRAWING THE LINE - THE DEFENSES FROM A POLICY PERSPECTIVE plaintiff who has assumed a risk is an aware p l a i n t i f f . the danger and proceeded nevertheless to encounter i t . He has faced If we say his action was u n r e a s o n a b l e , we are in fact saying that he shouldn't have encountered the danger; the he should have avoided i t . « The assumed risk case is therefore 00287 best case from a safety policy standpoint for placing loss on the The plaintiff. assumed risk taker is not a helpless p l a i n t i f f . Some courts h a v e placed 157a the entire loss on the plaintiff in the assumed risk c a s e . But unless the plaintiff's actions were the sole cause of the injury the result seems unjust in a similar way that contributory negligence as a complete bar to recovery in 158 negligence actions plaintiff has unreasonably has assumed injury. cases where there is the dangerous plaintiff's been criticized risk or n o t , product If as unjust. the But manufacturer whether has on the market which did help to the manufacturer is to be held strictly placed an cause the liable the plaintiff's conduct is less than an assumption of the little policy based reason for not holding him the liable in risk, in the assumption of risk case; he has still placed an unreasonably dangerous product 159 on the market which has caused i n j u r y . The assumed the post-discovery contributorily negligent plaintiff is similar to the risk taker to the degree that he knows of the dangerous condition 160 of product. does While he may not have subjective knowledge of the have notice of the d a n g e r . plaintiff. risk, This notice makes him more than a Depending on what attitude a court holds toward strict he helpless liability, this notice can form the basis of a duty which can be placed on the p l a i n t i f f . The court establishes might phrase the duty question this way: Where the evidence that a plaintiff has actual notice of the dangerous condition of the product, using a subjective test to determine n o t i c e , the plaintiff's post notice or the conduct must conform to the standard of the reasonably prudent plaintiff will run the risk of a reduction in his person recovery in proportion to the amount that his negligent conduct contributes to the i n j u r y . If the the jurors find subjective notice then they may be instructed damage a c c o r d i n g l y . to apportion Notice that when the duty issue is framed in terms the assumption of risk case is automatically taken under CC288 these consideration. Presumably, if che plaintiff has assumed the risk the jury would find that he contributed more to the accident and thus his recovery should be reduced more than the plaintiff with mere n o t i c e . It would seem that the court which abolished the assumption of risk defense in negligence cases would welcome the 161 abolition of it in strict products liability actions as w e l l . The question for appreciation of the Texas Supreme Court to decide is whether the subjective the danger and voluntary encounter elements of the volenti defense both of which go beyond mere notice of the dangerous condition, are enough to increase plaintiff culpability 162 to the point where making assumption of risk a complete bar and is justified. comparative If s o , then notions of personal culpability blameworthiness will do s o . Even in an assumption of risk c a s e , unless the plaintiff has caused all of the loss, But what about the misuse cases? the defendant is blameworthy Here we have a plaintiff without actual notice so that the risk evaluation and injury avoidance capability are than the post n o t i c e , not or assumed risk p l a i n t i f f . lesser And yet oddly e n o u g h , in Texas misuse is a partial defense where post notice contributory negligence is not. The injury only reason that I can see for holding the misuser liable for causing conduct can again be framed in duty-risk terms. his Where a plaintiff has made a use of the product which differs from the use an ordinary consumer might reasonably e x p e c t , the user will be deemed to be on notice of that part of the injury producing danger which can be attributed to his misuse 163 of the injury product. This is in effect to hold the plaintiff liable for producing conduct when he undertakes to use the product in a way his that 164 ordinary consumers might not reasonably e x p e c t . 165 within limits seems j u s t . C0289 This seems fair, and And finally, what is to be done about the pre-discovery negligent plaintiff? reduce the contributed discover contributorily I am hard pressed to find a rationale that would bar or plaintiff's recovery when his pre-discovery negligence has 166 to the injury. To bar or reduce his recovery for failing to the defect is to impliedly place a duty on him to discover or guard against the harm. This would be antithetical to his right to rely on product 167 integrity. In the products related case, "the tool of (the plaintiff's) 168 negligence is the product of the defendant." Where the action is for the defendant's failure to provide a safety device or adequate warning, plaintiff's negligence was in concurrently creating with the product a that a safety device or warning could have prevented or lessened, is clear. and where the risk answer "To censure the plaintiff for failing to act reasonably when that was the very problem to be guarded against is to march up the hill in order to 169 march down again." Plaintiff's conduct should not be considered in this context. But where his conduct is merely incidental to his use of the product such as where the plaintiff failed to keep a proper lookout while driving his car, the case is more difficult. the introduction. its capability. Take the Corvette owner hypothetical number on in There the plaintiff was using his new car clearly His negligence was his failure to keep a proper lookout. is only incidentally related to his use of the product. aware that his brakes will fail when he applies them. farmer earlier was lulled into failing to keep a proper lookout by It The plaintiff is not He might have seen the if he had been keeping a proper lookout, hadn't failed he could have avoided the accident anyway. he within but if his To the extent the brakes that representations that his car had good brakes, are we to penalize him for his failure to keep a proper lookout which would not have mattered if the brakes could have best avoided the loss? 43 063290 had held. Who Consider another s i t u a t i o n . zone. The Corvette owner drives 50 mph in a 30 mph Suddenly from a side street another car a p p e a r s . brakes, they fail, and he hits the c a r . could have avoided c o l l i s i o n . Plaintiff applies his There is evidence that at 30 mph he Here again the plaintiff is using the car well within its design limits. brakes had held. If we say h e must pay for a proportionate damage, His negligence would not have mattered share if the of the aren't we saying that manufacturers only need to make safe brakes for 170 people who Professor travel at the speed limit? Twerski: "The This is basically the position factor of reliance on product performance of is so significant that it is simply unfair to penalize the plaintiff for relying 171 on the set of consumer expectations which the defendant led him to rely There is a lot to be said for this p o s i t i o n . rely on it on." One who uses a product comes to to do what it is represented to d o . In the simple negligence action the two negligent parties have similar duties and pose similar risks to 172 each o t h e r . Their actions have independent significance from each 173 other. In the products a c t i o n , if in relying on the product the plaintiff is also creating a risk of harm by using the faulty p r o d u c t , the action of the plaintiff is not entirely independent of the defendant's p r o d u c t , the even though negligence can be said to have been incidental to the use of the product. To hold the plaintiff liable for failing to keep a proper lookout and speeding in these product There failure is to tell him that he has to be 174 all of the time. This is not what will on guard happen is little deterrence in putting one to a duty to guard against failure when one buys products on the representations that the function lived hypotheticals properly. From a pure product safety v i e w p o i n t , up to the expectations of the Corvette o w n e r , been avoided by furnishing the car with good b r a k e s . 44 0C2P1 against however. product product will if the brakes had the accident would have In such c a s e s , it is not so much the plaintiff's negligence as it is the manufactuer's failure to manufacture good brakes that causes the h a r m . But what about the case where the plaintiff would have hit the car with good brakes? we are If the defendant escapes liability altogether in this case, impliedly saying that he only needs to manufacture good brakes brake failure is not a concurrent producing cause of the h a r m . will even not maximize consumer protection. when Such a result Consumers are always safer when the product performs as represented. VII. If WHAT ROLE FORESEEABILITY? we can downplay the distinctions between strict liability (non-fault) and negligence (fault) in order to compare blameworthiness, not to downplay the perceived impropriety of requiring foresight manufacturer in the proper c a s e , 175 strict liability. into the product. discs of Plaintiff metal on it and then operating a footswitch to engage its w o r k , safety built the press. free that is why it is operated by a footswitch. frees the user's hands so that he can place and remove The inevitable accident h a p p e n s . disc is improperly placed on the press. error a of The product is designed to the The discs Plaintiff places a disc the press and at the same time that he presses the footswitch, his of Plaintiff uses a ten ton punch press by placing fiat round knows the press is dangerous if his hands aren't entirely more rapidly. metal out Consider that many types of plaintiff conduct are metal discs rapidly, footswitch reason even though the products action proceeds in the punching area when he steps on the footswitch. punch I see no on he notices the He reaches for it to correct at the same time the ten tons of press machinery comes down to do but in the process the plaintiff's hands are severed or c r u s h e d . A device which could have 45 prevented , n o r v r > the e sic / ••• injury was available at 176 reasonable c o s t . W h e n the product left the h a n d s of the m a n u f a c t u r e r , the m a n u f a c t u r e r k n e w there would be a p l a i n t i f f with injured h a n d s . He just did 177 not k n o w the p l a i n t i f f ' s n a m e . This is the s i t u a t i o n giving rise to the argument for p u t t i n g f o r e s e e a b i l i t y into the d a m a g e - a p p o r t i o n m e n t the strict liability But case. for we issue, in into the case. can h a n d l e this c a s e w i t h o u t injecting f o r e s e e a b i l i t y T h e p r o b l e m is b e t t e r solved with a directed v e r d i c t for the p l a i n t i f f all d a m a g e s , b e c a u s e this w a s c o n d u c t which the v e r y thing 178 prevented. The trouble is that f o r e s e e a b i l i t y of c o n d u c t is not implied in the jury findings of the d e f e c t i v e n e s s of the p r o d u c t . The m a y h a v e b e e n d e f e c t i v e b e c a u s e of a flawed m a n u f a c t u r i n g p r o c e s s . is gained by requiring relationship to defectiveness unreasonable the defect determined risks itself. by structural to benchmark then must the some design weaknesses created b y o v e r h e a t i n g or the l i k e , f o r e s e e a b i l i t y of p l a i n t i f f c o n d u c t . related In defect, only cases in product a be tenuous we the it flawed. L i t t l e will f o r e s e e a b i l i t y of conduct w h e n it h a s be always True, f o r e s e e a b l e that the m a n u f a c t u r i n g process will s o o n e r or later be But this f o r e s e e a b i l i t y d o e s not focus on plaintiff c o n d u c t . to may see product or that d o not go to The plaintiff's c o n d u c t is so m a r g i n a l l y that f o r e s e e a b i l i t y cannot be said to be for h o l d i n g the m a n u f a c t u r e r liable for all d a m a g e s . be rejected as a standard by which the war o v e r 179 a viable Foreseeability plaintiff caused d a m a g e s c a n be w a g e d . VIII. - the W H A T ROLE THE RULE? It is argued that s t r i c t l i a b i l i t y is enough to e n c o u r a g e p r o d u c t safety m o n e y d i f f e r e n c e d o e s n ' t m a t t e r . 180 I am not c o n v i n c e d . In our C 0 2 3 3 46 Corvette hypothetical , it is hard for me to imagine that even a company as large as General Motors does not care about the $2,000,000 it will have to pay because its product did not live up to the owner's e x p e c t a t i o n s . least it can be said that it will not discourage GM from design or manufacture of the b r a k e s . At the very making a better It will not encourage use safety to put the burden on the plaintiff for this $2,000,000; it is too late for h i m . It is most likely that average consumers will not consider the effect of a damage apportionment rule in going about their business in every day life. rely T h e y will on common sense to tell them when they are in danger and use it to avoid the danger whey they know of i t . reason to put blame on t h e m . If they don't use common s e n s e , then we have But until they have notice of the danger, not even common sense will h e l p them and this is what m a n u f a c t u r e r s can and should realize. them They will be more inclined to realize it if the loss is placed 181 for prediscovery negligence of the p l a i n t i f f . point At the of the or where he should be aware because of his extraordinary use of the where product, a plaintiff Money t a l k s . on becomes aware of the dangerous condition p r o d u c t , and only then, should the plaintiff be required to pay any portion of his damages realistic product reduce created risks of h a r m . At any r a t e , a plaintiff recovery too s o o n . the because only then will he have had ability to avoid the loss produced by what may often protection only if he is to pay at a l l , requires this to be s o . product caused we should not be insidious willing to The encouragement of maximum consumer The imposition of strict damage without regard to the type substandard conduct used to reduce his recovery is not enough by 47 be any liability of for plaintiff itself. IX. SHOULD THE DAMAGE APPORTIONMENT RULE FINALLY ADOPTED TREAT STRICT PRODUCTS DEFENDANTS DIFFERENTLY THAN NEGLIGENT PRODUCTS DEFENDANTS? Up to this point in this paper little emphasis has been placed different types of tortfeasors in products liability law. on the When the action is brought against a products m a n u f a c t u r e r , irregardless of whether the action is in strict liability or in n e g l i g e n c e , to be a d o p t e d , they should apply equally without regard to the type of action under which the plaintiff p r o c e e d s . must admit negligence when we that a negligent "As a matter of fundamental f a i r n e s s , we plaintiff in a strict products case is ignored becomes the recipient of a fortuitous unfair penalize substandard the and whatever comparative principles are a plaintiff in a 182 conduct." negligence action for whose advantage the identical I agree with this statement to the extent that both strict liability defendant and the negligent defendant are both products de fendants. One need only to consider blameworthiness to come to the conclusion products liability t o r t f e a s o r s , 183 blameworthy p l a i n t i f f s . products tortfeasors both strict and n e g l i g e n t , can be compared to The same argument holds true in comparing negligent (i.e., where negligence must be proved) and liability tortfeasors ( i . e . , where negligence need not be p r o v e d ) . hold strict I n d e e d , to that a negligent products tortfeasor's obligation to pay for plaintiff's injury not that is to be reduced by plaintiff's contributory substandard to defendant so hold in the strict products a c t i o n , is to reward conduct one products for being "negligent" and to penalize the strict liability products defendant for being conceptually "non-negligent" and even though as far as know he and we has used all due care in the m a n u f a c t u r e , d e s i g n , and sale of his 184 product. Such holdings have no real basis in furthering the policy goals 185 already discussed a b o v e . All holds of the previous argument in support of encouraging safer equally sound whether the products defendant is negligent liable. In either case, the manufacturer is blameworthy. products tortfeasor and or products strictly Both the negligent the strict products liability tortfeasor have ability to evaluate at the pre-use stage the potential products related Both are manufacturers. spreading the loss Both types of products tortfeasors are suffered as a result of their manufacture the risks. capable and of sale of injury producing products. Societal interests in products liability law do not change upon the basis of whether liability the or action in negligent manufacturer liability. reduction of loss, in reduction tortfeasors actually pleaded and proved is 186 of be in strict Consumer products protection, and the societal preference for paying the bill for safety personal or property encouraged to make safer injury dictate products. that all Unreasonably products dangerous products do not better the lives consumers lead. Since general products liability goals do not change because of the of products whether should liability action, plaintiffs any effect the rule formulation may substandard conduct should effect his right to not change because of the type of products liability action type have on recover, involved. But this is as far as the argument goes for equal treatment of tortfeasors. X . SHOULD NON-PRODUCTS TORTFEASORS AND PRODUCTS TORTFEASORS BE TREATED EQUALLY? To observe that the strict products liability actions have been created is to observe the fundamental difference between products tortfeasors and nonproducts tortfeasors. Consider that where non-product negligent as opposed to products tortfeasors, are concerned, PftOQft 49 tortfeasors, the non-product negligent defendant and the substandard plaintiff pose the similar risks to each other 187 risks of casualty loss created by the failure to use ordinary care. Plaintiffs pose no threat of casualty loss to by marketing defective products, create manufacturers. such risks of Manufacturers, casualty loss to plaintiffs - it is just that they are not "personally responsible," as are the non-products negligent parties. Comparative negligence systems, apportion damages between non-product negligent defendants and negligent to a contributorily plaintiffs are inadequate to apportion damages between the products case because of their failure to consider special designed to the parties manufacturer's risk evaluation capability and loss distribution capability. If we are going to compare blameworth iness, then the system used should take account of these considerations. The duties suggest that analogize the which they are owed between the parties to are nonreciprocal duties. It is a not duty of a manufacturer to the duty owed by a products action inappropriate landowner to to a 188 business invitee. product, they when If manufacturers reap the benefit of selling the should owe a greater duty to the product buyer (quasi-invitee) the product does not live up to manufacture created buyer expectations. This analogy is in keeping with enterprise liability theory. Thus, from and we s«>e that products tortfeasors are in an entirely separate class non-products tortfeasors precisely because the special loss products risk evaluation spreading capabilities of manufacturers are not found in tortfeasor. The risks manufacturers pose to consumers the non- are non- reciprocating, unlike the risks generally posed between non-products negligent defendants and parallel way. around negligent plaintiffs. The duties owed are different in a In short, the policy of products liability laws which revolves increased pre-use product safety and loss distribution, absent in the non-product related negligence case. 50 are totally It is true that we should encourage people to be careful when living working in society, tortfeasors for of but the best we can do between negligent general tort law p r i n c i p l e s . But that is not all products tortfeasors and substandard plaintiffs. liability law is a discreet area of tort l a w , liability rule responsible Such is the task we can do between If we consider that products we should realize that products goals of increased pre-use safety can be fostered by formulating which takes advantage of the manufacturer's unique capability and enterprise. treat non-products and contributorily negligent plaintiffs is hold them the losses they generate by their substandard c o n d u c t . the loss spreading and scheme already in pre-use place a evaluation in business In hopes of preventing needless products related injury we should products tortfeasors differently than where n e c e s s a r y , by adopting a rule which simple negligent tortfeasors, justifiably places a greater burden 189 of safety on the products t o r t f e a s o r . be criticized as unfair at first g l a n c e , use safety benefit does not justify a the increased burden To the extent that such a rule deeper concerns for encouraging preon products manufacturers. plaintiff receives because he sues a products tortfeasor receive may against a negligent non-products tortfeasor shall Any that he not be fortuitous, but shall be the result of encouraging the achievement of products liability g o a l s . XI. The general PROPOSED GUIDELINES special policy considerations underlying products liability and the special pre-use risk evaluation and loss capabilities of the in products liability cases on a pure comparative parties f}§238 in distribution manufacturers militate against apportioning damages 5 law fault between basis. These policy considerations and superior capabilities of manufacturers do not change proceeds. The receives when with present a fortuitous against firm the plaintiff advantage a products plaintiff products manufacturers in strict tort liability policy liability law, to type of action under which apparent proceeding has the basis in the relatively specialized area concession systems to those currently plaintiff who perceive unfairness in place in some American in the superior risk jurisdictions, evaluation unwilling In damage-apportionment the plaintiff has a realistic capability to avoid the loss. the products manufacturers. some substandard conduct do deserve reduction in d a m a g e , situations, of notwithstanding cries of "unfair" coming from those focus upon the superior risk evaluation capability of actually forms that is of where But even in these capabilities of products manufacturers dictate that justice b e served by placing all of the loss on the manufacturer when the substandard conduct of the plaintiff is the very thing which was to be avoided and the failure of the product to avoid or lessen the risks reason the guidelines are created in part by the conduct of the plaintiff is 190 the product is found to be d e f e c t i v e . In proposed. to keeping with these considerations the following The damage apportionment guidelines are applicable without regard the nature of the action pleaded and proved in so far as the proof191 shows that the defendant is a seller as defined under the Restatement §402A, the product which caused the plaintiff injury was unreasonably dangerous and in a 192 defective condition as defined under the Restatement, and in so far as the loss is a casualty loss. Sellers who are not manufacturers should be full contribution and indemnity rights in keeping with policy 193 already d i s c u s s e d . (1) Pre-discovery substandard conduct should be no bar to the plaintiff's right to recover.194 given considerations whatsoever (2) (a) Post actual discovery negligent plaintiff conduct, including assumption of r i s k , should reduce damages in oroportion to the amount that the injury was caused by such conduct using comparative causation principles.195 (3) Product misuse should be determined objectively when the seller proves that the product was used for a purpose and in a manner unlike that which could b e expected from the average consumer.196 If such misuse is n e g l i g e n t , then recovery should be reduced as in guideline (2) a b o v e . (4) Guidelines (2) and (3) are not to be applied in those cases where the product was defective for the very reason that it should have been designed or marketed in such a w a y as to reduce or negate the potentiality of harm arising from the particular substandard plaintiff conduct without regard to the personal culpability of such conduct.197 (5) In no event should the manufacturer avoid payment for the damages the unreasonably dangerous defective product has caused using comparative causation principles.198 (6) If damage reducing plaintiff conduct is present and has caused injury, the manufacturer should pay 50% of the percentage of the total damages that the plaintiff's conduct has caused.199 (7) Damages should be apportioned the parties to a non-products negligence case using traditional comparative negligence principles whether the non-products action is joined with a products action or not.200 The following special issues should help clarify the guidelines and given an idea of h o w the guidelines might b e implemented on the damage-apportionment issue. 201 Question 1: Did the plaintiff misuse the product? Question 2: Did the plaintiff have actual knowledge of condition of the product? 202 the dangerous Question 3: If you have found in question 1 above that the plaintiff misused the p r o d u c t , was this misuse unreasonable when it is compared to a reasonably prudent person under the same or similar c ircumstances?203 Question 4: Was this unreasonable misuse a proximate plaintiff's injury?204 cause of the Question 5: If you have found in question 2 above that the plaintiff had actual knowledge of the dangerous condition of the p r o d u c t , do you find that the plaintiff's post-discovery conduct was unreasonable when compared to a reasonably prudent person under the same or 53 mm similar circumstances? Question 6: Was this unreasonable conduct which followed the plaintiff's actual knowledge of the dangerous condition off the product a proximate cause of the plaintiff's injury? Question 7: If you have answered yes to either questions 4 or 5 above or to both of these questions, determine on a percentage basis what amount of the plaintiff's conduct contributed to the cause of the plaintiff's injury and what amount the defect in the product contributed to the cause of the product, totaling 100% of the cause205 Product defect % + Plaintiff conduct % = 100 % Question 8: What amount of money would compensate the plaintiff for all the injury he has sustained without regard to whether he or the product caused these injuries? XII. You have PRE-CONCLUSION SUMMARY already seen how I would resolve the issue as to plaintiff substandard negligent and strict liability tortfeasor. what conduct should have on his right to recover In a capsule, even effect from the though the results derived from applying Texas law to the introductory h y p o t h e t i c a l seem incongruous, they at first concerned results it is my feeling that the results are not so far off the mark as I appear to b e . have no As far as the plaintiff and argument for treating them any in both hypotheticals. the farmer are than the differently Modified comparative negligence can operate between them to do justice as it does in any non-products negligence case. At least part of the absurdity in the products actions can be ameliorated by placing products tortfeasors, whether negligent or liable under warranty or strict tort liability, in a separate class from non-products negligent tortfeasors. I have already given what I feel are good reasons for drawing a line the two classes. between products Products tortfeasors can spread tortfeasors cannot in the normal c a s e . Products loss; non- tortfeasors have unique pre-use tortfeasors risk do not evaluation have and safety capability because they are not that manufacturers non-products of products. Products tortfeasors pose nonreciprocal risks to c o n s u m e r s , where non-products negligent tortfeasors and negligent consumers pose generally reciprocal to each o t h e r . with the Products tortfeasors make representations about their products expectation tortfeasors risks that consumers will rely on do not make any such r e p r e s e n t a t i o n s . money off of c o n s u m e r s . them. Non-products Products tortfeasors make Non-products tortfeasors do n o t . T h e only conclusion to be drawn from all of this is that there is no grave h a r m done to justice by treating products tortfeasors and non-products damage apportionment r u l e s . tortfeasors with In fact, grave injustice would result if the two classes of tortfeasors were treated equally across the b o a r d . that damage a apportionment rule can be used to action I have already d i s c u s s e d , under warranty, strict l i a b i l i t y , valid products differently. policy does not change with the which a products plaintiff p r o c e e d s . or To the extent further liability goals it should treat the two types of tortfeasors As different Whether in type of negligence, the blame will most often come home to manufacturer unless the non-manufacturing seller should take part of i t . the For this reason, personal c u l p a b i l i t y , as found in the negligence products a c t i o n , should rules. the be the basis upon which we draw different damage apportionment Whether the manufacturer is personally negligent or strictly liable, defenses should be the same because we are still dealing with an 206 optimal pre-use of not risk evaluator in any c a s e . reducing products the action, extinguished. impropriety damages a plaintiff should receive in a negligence type and not reducing them in the strict products action will be Such of Once this is recognized the absurdity a result is truly a b s u r d . If we can downplay comparing non-fault liability to fault when comparing the strict liability to plaintiff negl igence, pristine tort "justness" then we can downplay the virtues which is to be derived from reducing of plaintiff's judgment just because he proved that the manufacturer was personally in any culpable his action and because two personally culpable parties should not benefit from their personal culpability to the extent it contributed to the h a r m . reduce plaintiff's culpable judgment because he and the manufacturer were To personally is to reduce the action theoretically to a simple negligence action and to forget that we are talking about products liability and that one p a r t y , the m a n u f a c t u r e r , to avoid wants harms before the product ever hits the m a r k e t . to prove damages, are has pre-use risk evaluation capability that can be utilized then designed actual is to the worthy he should by all means be allowed to do s o . plaintiff of punitive Punitive damages punish the extremely culpable tortfeasor whether manufacturer or n o t . actual personal culpability which If negligence it But a plaintiff should not be discouraged from is proving because of the risk that his compensatory damages will reduced if he proves i t . a be That is a b s u r d . Failure to discover or guard against product defects should not be termed substandard integrity, express conduct at a l l . and duty this right should not be derogated by placing an on him to discover or substandard c o n d u c t , reduce guard principles the and recovery to plaintiffs more s a f e . Guidelines (2) against a defect. the damage in this situation or Incidental should not because nothing would be gained that is not already gained by existing reduce product implied if it occurs before discovery of the d e f e c t , the plaintiff's right to r e c o v e r , reducing general would not by tort make Guideline (1) recognizes these two t h i n g s . and (3) recognize that we should encourage consumers use products more s a f e l y , the The plaintiff has the right to rely on to and that is is substantially unjust to allow all of loss to be attributed to one party when two are 56 responsible. Guideline (4) properly injects the element of foreseeabi1ity into the strict action, duty liability and would give the judiciary the support it needs to answer difficult questions applicable. factors by But to using even which the foreseeability in this c o n t e x t , consideration can be concept where it is foreseeability is only one given. It is not an most of the absolute requirement to arriving at a just duty d e c i s i o n . Guideline (5) recognizes that the harshness of the all or nothing rule is to be avoided not withstanding the degree of culpability chargeable plaintiff's conduct. If the defendant's product caused harm he to the should be liable for that h a r m . Guideline unique (6) pre-use evaluate is risk direcced at encouraging manufacturers evaluation capability to go further what injuries their products will c a u s e . to use than their to merely It is added incentive for them to prevent the injury to the plaintiff and thus maximize consumer safety. If manufacturers are encouraged to look more carefully at their products presumably foreseeable risks can be ameliorated dangerous products do not benefit s o c i e t y . the plaintiff should owes owe to least liability out of negated. Unreasonably The liability for an added 50% of caused injury also recognizes the face that the manufacturer a dury to the consumer that is greater than the one the himself manufacturer. at or a because of the pre-use risk evaluation consumer capability of It is also supported by loss spreading capability which part action. then of the foundation for the emergence of the the forms strict tort It is supported by the fact that m a n u f a c t u r e r s make money selling their p r o d u c t s . The added 50% also recognizes that we are talking about products liability and its goals as opposed to simple negligence actions and its g o a l s . if To treat the products defendant and the plaintiff the action were only a negligence a c t i o n , 57 as would be to equate them in pre- use risk evaluation c a p a b i l i t y . Lastly, that if the plaintiff has injured h i m s e l f , product was introduced into c o m m e r c e . in his the added 50% recognizes the he has done so in part because the If the defendant had not been derelict duty to refrain from unleashing his unreasonably dangerous product into c o m m e r c e , fact the injury could have been totally a v o i d e d . defective Guideline (7) recognizes that comparative negligence statutes that h a v e been directed at simple negligence cases are inadequate in the products c a s e . XIII. EXISTING DAMAGE APPORTIONMENT SCHEMES Pure comparative fault, as outlined in the Uniform Comparative Fault A c t , fails to draw the line between products and non-products t o r t f e a s o r s , fails to recognize and the realistic risk evaluation disparity between products manufacturers, and in so doing fails to treat products liability law the discreet area of tort law that it i s . Any fault, between prediscovery of postdiscovery fault, fault and without distinguishing would reduce the plaintiff's damages a c c o r d i n g l y . only the defect caused i n j u r y , This takes By holding the seller liable we do not encourage the refrain from selling the p r o d u c t . as is included in its definition of 207 some of the strictness out of strict liability. for plaintiffs manufacturer to 208 The Model Uniform Product Liability A c t , is preferred over the Uniform Comparative Fault Act because it would not hold a plaintiff liable for failure to discover a d e f e c t . But it does hold the plaintiff to an objective standard 208a for failing to discover an apparent defective c o n d i t i o n . close to putting an implied duty of discovery on h i m . modification or use plaintiff's recovery with a known defective 208b proportionately. 58 00305 This comes Misuse, condition, would very alteration or reduce the A majority of the courts have adopted comparative principles to apportion damage between substandard plaintiffs and strict liability tortfeasors. courts are split as to whether prediscovery negligence will be considered reducing the plaintiff's damages. prediscovery Generally speaking, The in drawing the line at plaintiff substandard conduct brings them into line with one or the other of the acts mentioned above. Some courts negligence liability have legislation, actions, merely even apply to declared that their though not expressly apportion state's comparative applicable damages between the to products parties to a products action, because it is in keeping with the general policy of the 209 state. Wisconsin has gone so far as to suggest that strict liability is the equivalent of negligence per se, and thus the comparative 210 negligence 211 statute should apply. Supreme Court reversed a judgment for the plaintiff when it found that matter of In Schuh v . Fox River Tractor Co., the Wisconsin law the negligence of the plaintiff exceeded that of the as a product 212 supplier's the harm, negligence per se. Thus even though the product contributed to the plaintiff lost all right to recover. Such a holding is not in keeping with policy considerations already discussed. Recently, 213 principles, actions. usually Alaska as The and opposed California have used to comparative negligence, difference is more than semantic. a in strict the principle applied between negligent tortfeasors. less negligence, action. questions applying liability comparative principles in To the doctrine, proper term than "fault," which would include when fault Comparative negligence that strict liability is a liability without negligence is comparative the extent negligence liability strict is without liability This approach can be viewed as a refusal to face the difficult policy presented by products liability law as already discussed. 00306 Finally some jurisdictions simply say that their comparative negligence 214 statutes are 215 nor applicable or that fault and non-fault cannot bo compared. CONCLUSION This area discriminating strict of when products the law is unsettled. deciding liability what M a n y of the courts have been defenses should be action in keeping with increased product safety and consumer protection. clear however. products the applicable perceived The author's views on the subject have 216 whether these decisions will be accepted by other derogation of Comparative principles will in some form be applied in strict liability actions. seen goals a The trend for the future is been rejected by at least two courts, California and A l a s k a . be to already It remains to jurisdictions of what I feel to be overwhelming policy concerns for in encouraging manufacturers to make safer products before the product is m a r k e t e d . The guidelines set forth in the earlier section filter out the types substandard conduct that cannot with certainty be said to be foreseeable to the manufacturer and the rule will thus impose no duty of reasonably to go to extreme measures to make products safe for every conceivable plaintiff. At the same time the guidelines will encourage manufacturers to make reasonably safe products. The encouragement of pre-use risk evaluation is factored into the and guidelines recognized. recognized general as and determined be The given. are realistic plaintiff capability to evaluate risks is differences between product and non-product tortfeasors is the differences between the policy behind products liability law in particular, in so far as tort law in it can be to be a discreet legal area to which special consideration A comparison of these guidelines O03O7 60 with the various should existing approaches discussed understanding of the above wiLl various hopefully bring to issues perplexing area of products liability There is no which emerge the reader upon a better examining this law. boilerplate answer to the main issue of what effect the plaintiff's substandard conduct should have on his r e c o v e r y . given One case thing The facts of any 217 may require judicial modification of any hard and fast rule. is clear h o w e v e r . Treating products cases as if they were mere negligence cases is simply inadequate when consideration is given to the goals of products strict tort liability law and the bases for the creation and liability. 61 imposition of 1 U N I F O R M C O M P A R A T I V E FAULT A C T <Sl(b)(1977) p r o v i d e s : (b) " F a u l t " includes acts or o m i s s i o n s that are in any m e a s u r e n e g l i g e n t or r e c k l e s s toward the p e r s o n or property of the actor o r o t h e r s . . . . " 2 See W a d e , Products L i a b i l i t y and P l a i n t i f f ' s Fault - The Uniform C o m p a r a t i v e Fault A c t , 29 M E R C . L . R E V . 373 (1978); S a l e s , A s s u m p t i o n of the Risk and Misuse in Strict Tort L i a b i l i t y - P r e l u d e to Comparative F a u l t . 1 1 T E X . TECH L . R E V . 7 2 9 , 775 ( 1 9 8 0 ) . A c c o r d : F i s c h e r , P r o d u c t s L i a b i l i t y - A p p l i c a b i l i t y of C o m p a r a t i v e N e g l i g e n c q . 4 3 M O . R E V . 431 (1978). See O w e n , 1980). Restructuring Products Liability Law. 16 T r i a l 58, 61 (Nov. 4 H e n d e r s o n v . Ford M o t o r C o m p a n y , 519 S.W.2d 87 ( T e x . 1 9 7 4 ) . 5 The term " d a m a g e - a p p o r t i o n m e n t rule" is here used to m e a n a rule by which the e f f e c t the p l a i n t i f f ' s s u b s t a n d a r d conduct can be m e a s u r e d and applied a g a i n s t his right to r e c o v e r . T h e r e are s e v e r a l types of damageapportionment rules. C o m p a r a t i v e n e g l i g e n c e r u l e s , of e i t h e r the pure or m o d i f i e d v a r i e t y , are a p p l i e d to the " n e g l i g e n c e " of the p a r t i e s . These rules h a v e b e e n a d o p t e d primarily to apply to n o n - p r o d u c t s cases. C o m p a r a t i v e fault is a n o t h e r type of r u l e . Fault is a b r o a d e r term than n e g l i g e n c e and for this r e a s o n it more aptly d e s c r i b e s the strict p r o d u c t s l i a b i l i t y d e f e n d a n t ' s b l a m e w o r t h i n e s s , which is c o n c e p t u a l l y without negligence. Pure c o m p a r a t i v e fault is to b e d i s t i n g u i s h e d from those comparative fault rules w h i c h are selective in d e f i n i n g s p e c i f i c types of s u b s t a n d a r d plaintiff c o n d u c t as f a u l t . 6 C o m p a r e F i s c h e r , supra note 2 at 4 4 9 . 7 See T w e r s k i , The Use and Abuse of C o m p a r a t i v e N e g l i g e n c e in Products L i a b i l i t y , 10 1 N D . L . REV., 797,829 ( 1 9 7 7 ) w h e r e it is argued that the fundamental duty of m a n u f a c t u r e r s to make safe p r o d u c t s will be negated under p u r e c o m p a r a t i v e fault p r i n c i p l e s . 8 See g e n e r a l l y , i d . 0 0 3 0 9 62 157a 202 This is not the issue of contribution and indemnity rights between concurrent tortfeasors. Contribution and indemnity rights have only a collateral relationship to the main issue. Contribution and indemnity rights are a current problem in states where there is no applicable comparative negligence statue. See Ceneral Motors Corp. v . Simmons. 558 S.W.2d 855 (Tex. 1977). Some states draw no distinction between the degrees of culpability found in negligent as opposed to strict liability tortfeasors. See Ladwig v . Ermanco Inc., 504 F. Supp. 1229 (ED W i s . 1981) (applying Wis. law). 10 28 Car and Driver 39 (No. 9 , March 1983). The magazine does some of General Motors' sales work for it by touting the four-wheel-disc brake systems as making "the car stop as if it had been dropped into a sand bank." Id. at 36. 11 The third type of products action, warranty, is excluded because for all practical purposes and to the extent it should be considered applicable to the facts of this hypothetical, nothing would be gained by addressing it separately. "Negligence, breach of warranty, and strict liability in tort have basically the same elements in a products liability context. None of the three theories allows recovery against the manufacturer or seller unless, "(1) the product was defective; (2) the defect existed at the time the manufacturer or seller relinquished control; and (3) the defect caused the injury." Epstein, Products Liability Defenses Based on Plaintiffs Conduct; 1968 UTAH L. REV. 267, 283 (May 1968). 12 The elements of a cause of action in strict tort liability are set out in the RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS 5402A (1966). The Restatement view has been adopted in Texas. See McKisson v . Sales Affiliates, Inc. 416 S.W.2d 787 (Tex. 1967). 13 "Producing cause differs from proximate cause in that the former does not, in Texas, include the element of foreseeability." J.H. Edgar, Products Liability in Texas, 11 TEX. TECH L. REV. 23 (1979). Alaska and Connecticut use the term proximate cause to describe the causation ascribed to the product defect. See Butaud v . Suburban Marine & Sporting Goods, Inc., 555 P.2d 4 2 , 46 (Alaska, 1976); DeFelice v . Ford Motor Company, 28 Conn. Supp. 164, 255A.2d 636, 639 (1969). 519 S.W.2d at 89. 15 Punitive damages are not allowed in Texas in a strict liability action. Presumably, there is no personal culpability to which they could be directed. This is a "modified" comparative negligence statute. See TEX. REV. CIV. _STAT. JVNN. art. 2212a. The pure comparative negligence statues make contributory negligence in any degree a partial defense. 00310 63 135 See 519 S.W.2d at 8 9 - 9 2 . 18 Id. For criticisms of the Henderson Court's decision to make assumption of risk a complete bar to recover see E d g a r , The Effect of Plaintiff's Conduct in Strict Products Liability in Texas: A Time for R e e v a l u a t i o n , 43 T E X . BAR J R N L . 1103, 1106-07 (Dec., 1980); C o m m e n t , To Bar Plaintiff's Recovery in Strict L i a b i l i t y , Conduct After the Discovery of a Defect Must Amount Only to a V ^ r u n t a r y " E n c o u n t e r of the R i s k , 6 ~ T E X . TECH IT REV. 1211 ( 1 9 7 5 ) . 19 See E d g a r , (1979). Products Liability in T e x a s , 11 T E X . TECH L . REV. 23, 42 20 See supra note 16. 21 General Motors is more likely to have a deep pocket than the farmer in the negligence case and will have to pay more under strict liability in the first h y p o . 22 See infra notes 29-38 and accompanying text. 23 E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1104. 24 "(W]e see no reason that a manufacturer found strictly liable under the lesser standards of proof of Section 402A should be more culpable than the negligent manufacturer." General Motors C o r p . v . S i m m o n s , 558 S.W.2d 855,861 (Tex. 1977) (in a discussion about contribution and indemnity). Consider the following quote from Pizza Inn v . T i f f a n y , 454 S.W.2d 4 2 0 , 4 2 3 (Tex. C i v . A p p . 1970), (emphasis added): "When the strict liability rule attaches or is a p p l i c a b l e , conventional contributory negligence of plaintiff is not a defense; nor is contributory negligence of failure to discover the defect in the p r o d u c t , or guard against its e x i s t e n c e , a defense." The court apparently recognizes the nonsense of the holding presented by the text. It resolves the question by concluding that the contributory negligence of the plaintiff should not change his recovery because he has plead and proved n e g l i g e n c e , if strict liability is applicable. This holding would not hold the plaintiff liable for going beyond proving strict liability to prove actual manufacturer negligence. It makes good s e n s e . 25 T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 7 9 7 . 142 519 S.W.2d 8 7 . 123 E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1104. 28 Id. 29 Edgar, 31 s u P r a note 19 at 2 5 . Id. Usually the issue is phrased in terras of comparing manufacturer strict liability (non-fault) with the negligence (fault of the p l a i n t i f f ) . See W a d e , supra note 2 at 3 7 6 . The question as I have phrased it is somewhat d e c e p t i v e , but if the focus is on the p r o d u c t , it would seem that this phrasing is r e q u i r e d . "[The reasons for adopting strict liability] stem from a desire to change risk distribution p r i n c i p l e s , to fulfill consumer e x p e c t a t i o n s , and to free the plaintiff from proving fault when it is supposed fault is present but cannot be easily d e m o n s t r a t e d . Given such a multiplicity of reasons for the adoption of strict l i a b i l i t y , it is not untoward to suggest that the seriousness of the defect should be equated in some rough sense with a percentage of fault." T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 807 (footnotes o m i t t e d ) . The "supposed fault" mentioned in the quote derives in part from what Dean Leon Green suggests is a breach of duty, even if it is not a "negligent" b r e a c h . See infra, notes 3 2 , 37 and accompanying t e x t . Compare the dissenting opinion of Justice Mosk in Daly v . General M o t o r s , 575 P.2d 1162,1181 (arguing the impossibility of comparing strict liability to plaintiff negligence) with Justice Clark's concurring o p i n i o n , ick at 1175 and Justice Jefferson's concurring and dissenting o p i n i o n , ici. at 1177, where both argue basically that there is a lack of a trustworthy standard for making the c o m p a r i s o n . 32 Unreasonably dangerous products do not enter the stream of commerce all by themselves. This is the reason that strict liability is only "technically" a non-fault c o n c e p t . See infra note 37 and accompanying text. "(S]imply maintaining the bad condition or placing the bad product on the market is enough for liability....[I]t is not n e c e s s a r y to prove negligence in letting the [product] get into the dangerous condition or in failing to discover or rectify it. This is legal fault, and it can be mixed w i t h , and compared w i t h , fault of the morally reprehensible type." W a d e , supra note 2 at 3 7 7 . 33 See T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 805-06; supra note 2 at 7 6 1 . 34 See T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 0 6 . 134 See id. 65 Wade, supra note 2 at 376; Sales, 135 "[Slection 402A dons not apply to products not introduced into the stream of commerce." E d g a r , supra note 19 at 24 citing Armstrong Rubber C o . v . U r q u i d e z , 570 S.W.2d 374 (Tex. 1978) (tire being tested not in c o m m e r c e ) . 37 G r e e n , Strict Liability Under Section 402A and 402B; Decade of L i t i g a t i o n 5 4 T E X . L . R E V . 1 185 (1976) reprinted 'in G r e e n , The Litigation Process in Tort Law 6 0 3 , 604 (2d.ed. , 1977). See W a d e , supra note 2 at 376-77. 38 T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 0 6 . 39 See L e v i n e , Buyer's Conduct as Affecting the Extent of Liability in W a r r a n t y , 52 M I N N . L . R E V . 6 2 7 , 628 ( 1 9 6 8 ) . Manufacturer's 40 See supra note 11. 41 See L e v i n e , supra note 39 at 6 4 5 - 4 7 . 42 See J o h n s o n , The Interests Protected by Strict Product Liability, (unpublished), presented for Products Liability Seminar Texas Tech University (Spring 1 9 8 3 ) . CAVEAT: What the law should be and what it is, widely d i f f e r s . In Signal Oil and Gas C o . v . Universal Oil P r o d u c t s , 572 S.W.2d 320 (Tex. 1978) the court applied comparative causation principles to apportion the damage between a contributorily negligent plaintiff and a strict warranty d e f e n d a n t . Contributory negligence was held to be a partial defense in the action because of the Texas Business and Commerce Code §2.715 setting out the rule on buyers incidental and consequential damages. These damages are not unlike casualty losses which are the object of tort law in general and to the extent that these are the losses to be redressed under tort principles, which have always redressed such losses, to apply a different rule in products cases on the basis of the type of action pleaded and proved is very hard to j u s t i f y . 43 See Epstein, supra note 11 at 268 "Contributory n e g l i g e n c e , generally defined is sufficiently broad enough to encompass categories." Id. See also L e v i n e , supra note 39 at 6 4 3 . as it is all three 44 See supra note 1. 142 N o e l , Defective P r o d u c t s : Abnormal U s e , Contributory Negligence and Assumption of R i s k , 25 V A N D . _L. R E V . 9 3 , 120-28 (1972); K e e t o n , Assumption of Products Ris»-s, 19 S W . L . J . 62 (1965). 123 N o e l , supra note 45 at 120. Id. at 120-21. 48 See id; K e e t o n , supra note 45 at 6 3 - 6 7 . 49 N o e l , supra note 45 at 121. Id. 50 Assumption of risk is a stricter measure of plaintiff contributory than simple contributory negligence due to the subjective s t a n d a r d . fault 51 S a l e s , supra note 2 at 7 4 0 - 4 1 . 52 C o m m e n t , To Bar Plaintiff's Recovery in Strict L i a b i l i t y , Conduct After tlvi? Discovery of _a Do feet Must Amount Only to j> V o l u n t a r y Encounter of the R i s k , 6 T E X . TECH _L. R E V . 1211, 1215 ( 1 9 7 5 ) . 53 See id. at 1211. 54 519 S.W.2d at 9 1 . 55 See Comment n to 5402A of the R e s t a t e m e n t . 57 S a l e s , supra note 2 at 7 4 3 - 4 4 . Id. at 746 quoting from Johnson v . P.2d 132, 140 (1976). Clark Equipment C o . , 274 O r e . 4 0 3 , 547 58 Compare S a l e s , supra note 2 at 745 where it is noted that other jurisdictions inquire into the reasonableness of the use of the product as distinguished from the user's decision to use i t . 59 Negligent voluntary assumption of risk is the term Professor Edgar uses in a helpful hypothetical discussion of the types of plaintiff substandard conduct and the effect this conduct should have on the plaintiff's recovery. See E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1106-08. 134 E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1108. 67 C031-5 A much more difficult case is presented when the facts suggest that employment or business pressures rather than health emergency is involved. Consider Micallef v . Miehle C o . , 39 N.Y.2d 3 7 6 , 348 N.E.2d 5 7 1 , 384 N.Y.S.2d 115 (1976). Plaintiff was operating a large printing press which took three hours to put into a run posture when it was s t o p p e d . A foreign object was interfering with the quality of printing as the m a c h i n e was running. Plaintiff knew of the danger of "chasing hickies," i.e. the process by which the application of a piece of plastic to the p l a t e , which was wrapped around the machine's printing c y l i n d e r , would remove the foreign object and restore printing q u a l i t y . He informed the supervisor that he would chase this "hickie" on the r u n . It was the usual procedure in the industry to do s o . Experts testified that a safety guard could be placed near the rollers to avoid the contact of human hands with the obviously dangerous r o l l e r s . Was the three hour downtime enough to make the plaintiff's assumption of risk reasonable? T w e r s k i , The Many Faces of Misuse: An Inguiry[. into the Emerging Doctrine of Comparative Causation, 29 "MERC. L . "REV. "403 , 429-30 ( f978) 62 See C o m m e n t , supra note 52 at 1216. 63 S a l e s , supra note 2 at 7 4 7 . For a good example of h o w important these factors are in the outcome of a case see Sperling v . H a t c h , 10 C a l . A p p . 3d 5 4 , 5 8 , 88 C a l . R e p t r . 704 (1970), noted in N o e l , Supra note 45 at 12223 (husband with mechanical experience held to have assumed the risk of brake failure as a matter of law, while wife's assumption of the risk was held to be a j u r y q u e s t i o n ) . 64 S a l e s , supra note ?. at 748 (footnotes o m i t t e d ) . 65 I d . at 7 4 1 - 4 2 . 66 See L e v i n e , supra note .39 at 6 4 3 . 67 See g e n e r a l l y , T w e r s k i , supra note 60; L e v i n e , supra note 39; S a l e s , supra note 2; E p s t e i n , supra note 11; and C o m m e n t , Substantial Change: A1 terat ion of ^ Product as ji Bar to ji M a n u f a c t u r e r ' s L i a b i l i t y , 80 DICK L . R E V . 245 (1976)(all discussing various views on m i s u s e ) . 68 See supra note 51 and accompanying text. 69 T w e r s k i , supra note 61 at 4 1 7 . Other examples are the failure to heed instructions and w a r n i n g s , failure to properly maintain and service a p r o d u c t , which can be viewed as an abnormal or unintended u s e . See Sales supra note 2 at 7 5 5 . 68 157a See Twerski, supra note 7 at 818-19. Id. 72 Id, 73 This is the objective standard generally applied to misuse cases. 74 While his conduct may be viewed as more reprehensible negligence, he still has not assumed the risk subjectively. than simple 75 Cf. Levine, supra note 39 at 643. 76 In General Motors Corp. v . Hopkins, 548 S.W.2d 344, 349 (Tex. 1977) the court held that if there had been enough evidence that the plaintiff's conduct had somehow caused the loss he would be charged with the damages flowing from his contribution to the cause since his conduct was unforeseeable. See Twerski supra note 60 for an exhaustive analysis of this case focused on the comparative causation principles espoused by the Texas Supreme Court in the case. 77 Comment, supra note 67 at 246 (footnotes omitted). 78 548 S.W.2d 344. 79 See Twerski, supra note 61 at 409. 80 "(A primary problem of the misuse defense] has involved the overlap of misuse with the traditional defense of contributory negligence." Sales, supra note 2 at 749. 81 Edgar, supra note 18 at 1103. 83 548 S.W.2d at 351. Twerski, supra note 61 at 431. 202 See cases cited in Twerski, supra note 61, 420-21 n32. 69 115 Foreseeability does have something to do with the issue of whether the misuse was a proximate c a u s e , that is from the plaintiff's standpoint. The term proximate cause is used in negligence c a s e s . See Dallas R y . C . Terminal C o . v . B l a c k , 152 T e x . 3 4 3 , 257 S.W.2d 4 1 6 , 417 (1953). 86 In the Hopkins c a s e , the court made it clear that foreseeable misuse would not be a d e f e n s e . 548 S.W.2d at 3 5 1 . For a criticism of the bifurcated nature of the foreseeability issue in the Hopkins case see S a l e s , supra note 2 at 7 5 2 . ~ ~' S a l e s , supra note 2 at 750 quoting from Findlay v . 265 O r e . 3 0 0 , 509 P.2d 28 (1973). Copeland Lumber Co., 88 T w e r s k i , supra note 61 at 425 quoting from Instructions - Civil §2: 141 (Vol. 1, 1974). New "* York Pattern Jury 89 See T w e r s k i , supra note 61 at 4 2 3 - 2 4 . 90 I d . , discussing Dean Leon Green's approach to foreseeability by including it in the judge made duty d e c i s i o n . Id., at 4 2 1 . 92 I d . , Strict liability is said to focus on the p r o d u c t . Negligence is said to focus on the conduct of the m a n u f a c t u r e r . If in strict liability we find a product unreasonably dangerous as designed b e c a u s e of the failure to include a safety device we are in effect saying that it should have included o n e . Who should have included it in the product? The manufacturer, of course. There is no escaping the fact that foreseeability is involved here as a matter of p o l i c y . General Motors C o r p . v . Hopkins is on p o i n t . Foreseeable misuse is not a d e f e n s e , only the unforeseeable m i s u s e . Can strict liability d e s i g n cases have a focus only on the product? Y e s , t h e o r e t i c a l l y . Not a l w a y s , in p r a c t i c e . 93 "A defectively manufactured product is one that is not manufactured as intended." E d g a r , supra note 19 at 2 5 . A defectively designed product may create an unreasonable danger even though manufactured exactly as intended. Id., at 2 8 . If the injury results either in w h o l e or in part from a manufacturing defect in the product a strong argument can be made for keeping foreseeability out of the case unless there was also a contributing design d e f e c t . Foreseeability and d e s i g n are inseparable. But foreseeability of misuse and manufacturing process are n o t . In the case of a manufacturing defect I would hold that only post-discovery negligence of the plaintiff should be the only d e f e n s e . The relation of design defect cases and negligence (foreseeability) has prompted a move to return to negligence principles in litigating these c a s e s . See Uniform Product Liability A c t , 44 F e d . Reg. 6 2 , 714-50 (1979) and Senate Bill 4 4 , C03.1.7 98th C o n g . , 1st Sess. (1983) discussed in Polewski, M a n u f a c t u r i n g , Design and Marketing D e f e c t s , (unpublished) presented by the author at Products Liability S e m i n a r , Texas Tech University (Spring, 1983). 94 See text accompanying note 8 8 , s u p r a . 95 See L e v i n e , supra note 39 at 6 4 3 . 96 E p s t e i n , supra note 11 at 267. 97 Supra note 51 and accompanying text. 98 "Contributory negligence is conduct of the plaintiff that falls below the standard of conduct expected of ordinary prudent man under the same or similar circumstances...." C o m m e n t , supra note 52 at 1215. Compare note 98 supra with text accompanying note 83 s u p r a . Text at note 10 supra 101 See T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 1 6 . "In product liability a c t i o n s , ... land) |i]f the plaintiff is n e g l i g e n t , the tool of his n e g l i g e n c e is the product of the defendant." Ld. at 8 0 4 . 102 See T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 1 6 . 103 See Shamrock Fuel and Oil Sales C o . v . T u n k s , 416 S.W.2d 779 ( T e x . 1967); A n n o t . , 46 A.L.R.3d 2 4 0 , 248 (1972). 519 S.W.2d 87; A n n o t . , supra note 103 at 2 6 2 . N o e l , supra note 45 at 114 quoting Stephan v . A.2d 855 (N.H. 1970). Sears, Roebuck & C o . , 266 106 See N o e l , supra note 45 at 114. 107 To put such a duty on the plaintiff would go far beyond Restatement §402a, Comment rK_ I d . 108 E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1106. ,00318 7 179 Compare hypotheticals N o . 2 and N o . 3 used by Professor Edgar to explain pre-discovery and post-discovery n e g l i g e n c e . I d . 110 Compare foregoing discussion with text accompanying note 56 s u p r a . 111 Daley v . Ceneral Motors C o r p . , Rptr.|3R0 (1978). 1 1 la Wenzel v . Rollins Motor C o . , ref. n.r.e.) 20 Cal.3d 7 2 5 , 575 P.2d 1142, 598 S.W.2d 895 (Tex. Civ. 144 Cal. A p p . 1 9 8 0 , writ 112 The Hopkins case would seem to fall into the post-discovery contributory negligence category because he was aware that the quadrajet carburetor had a propensity for hanging in the open position before he replaced it with the high performance Holley c a r b u r e t o r . See Twerski supra note 60 at 4 3 0 . A p p a r e n t l y , by the time he replaced the Holley carburetor with the original quadrajet carburetor he had "dismissed this from his mind," in a similar way to Professor Edgar's hypothetical N o . 3 . See supra note 109. A much more difficult task would be to fit the Hopkins case into the culpability scheme presented in the text if Hopkins had not had the Fulton Street encounter with the original carburetor where he learned of its dangerous c o n d i t i o n . If he would have had no subjective knowledge of the defect his case would not be a post-discovery contributory negligence case as I have defined it. It would not be a misuse case as I have defined it either. Hopkins did alter the carburetor but the alteration was not material in the sense that the product was changed into a product intHied for another p u r p o s e . The alteration was material in the sense that it was found to be a change which bore a causal relationship to the accident. Perhaps the best way to describe this hypothetical Hopkins case would be to call it a "mishandling" case and place it somewhere between prediscovery contributory negligence and misuse and post-discovery contributory negligence on the culpability scale set forth in the text. See Twerski supra note 61 at 430 where Professor Twerski recognizes the problem but does not attempt to solve it and compare his discussion with S a l e s , supra note 2 at 749-59 who calls it simply an "alteration...rather than a misuse or unintended use" and does resolve the question of how to classify by calling it misconduct and making it a d e f e n s e . 113 The analogy to criminal scienter is intentional and hopefully to explain the culpability s c h e m e . appropriate 114 An argument will be made later on that the type of products liability action pleaded should make no difference if it proceeds against the manufacturer of the injury inflicting p r o d u c t . See text beginning at Section I X . 72 cestf) 115 Rlacks Law Dictionary (5th E d . 1979). O w e n , supra note 3 at 5 8 . 117 Section 402A of the Restatement is designed to do m o r e than m e r e l y reduce plaintiff proof p r o b l e m s . It was also designed to eliminate the privity requirement in warranty a c t i o n s . See E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1 1 0 4 . It is a subpart of the more or less discreet area known as products liability l a w , which has as its aim the improvement of products and consumer protection. These aims are not to be overlooked by focusing too narrowly on the proof problems and privity requirements §402A was designed to a m e l i o r a t e . See S402A Comment I 18 G r e e n , Tort Law Public Law in D i s g u i s e , 38 T E X . L . R E V . , 1, 2 (1959) reprinted in G r e e n , The Litigation Process in Tort Law 116 (2d e d . 1977). 119 P r o s s e r , The Law of Torts 642 (4th e d . 1971). 120 n I d . at 6 5 1 . Seie Greenmae-e v . Yuba Power P r o d u c t s , 59 C a l . 2d 57 , 6 3 , 27 C a l . Rptr i. 697 , 701 , 377 P.2d 8 9 7 , 901 (1963); Restatement (Second) of T o r t s , Comment £ (1965). ~ ~ 121 The public interests in improving product safety and consumer protection will remain constant without regard to whether the products action proceeds in w a r r a n t y , n e g l i g e n c e or strict tort l i a b i l i t y . Any holding as to what the defenses ought to be to the action which focuses on the difference between fault and non-fault concepts discussed earlier will very likely derogate these policy g o a l s . If we can overcome this hypertechnical problem in determining to compare fault we should be able to overcome it by considering what defenses should apply to the products liability a c t i o n , w i t h o u t fine line distinctions b e t w e e n the types of products liability a c t i o n s . 122 P r o s s e r , supra note 119 at 6 5 1 . For a discussion of the affinity between warranty and tort principles and the "representational grounds" for imposing strict liability see G r e e n , supra note 3 7 . See also Twerski, supra note 7 at 802-04 and authorities cited t h e r e i n . One writer has called the representational nature of the products liability tort a "de facto victimization" of the c o n s u m e r . E p s t e i n , supra note 11 at 6 8 4 . To explain, the representational theory of liability means that when m a n u f a c t u r e r s , through massive hard-sell advertising campaigns extolling the virtues of the p r o d u c t , induce the buyer to b u y , and when the buyer is lulled into a sense of security about the product h e m i g h t otherwise not h a v e , he has been victimized by the manufacturer and should not be forced to pay for injury he receives when the product turns out to be unreliable and injurious. See Green supra note 37 at 608; M c C o w n v . International Harvester C o . , 342 A.2d 381 (Pa. 1975) cited in W a d e , supra note 2 at 733 n . 12. 73 e§32fi 123 Comment, Product Liability Reform Proposals in Washington Policy Analysis, 4 U . PUG. SOUND L. REV. 143, 146 (1980). - A Public Id. 125 Is the product unreasonably dangerous? Frequently, this question is resolved using a risk versus utility analysis. Edgar, supra note 19 at 28-29. See generally Prosser, supra note 119 at 659 (general discussion of the tests). 126 The majority of courts do not hold manufacturers or insurers. Levine, supra note 39 at 631. sellers liable as 127 Just adjudication is no less a valid goal than safety concerns. 128 Take any negligent assumption of risk case and you have a case where injury could have been avoided. Risk avoidance capability comes with subjective knowledge of the defect. Where this capability arises, there arises policy oriented defense potential. 129 For a recent argument that manufacturers are with products liability recoveries of massive Venditor; Failure to Heed Instructions is Products Liability Actions, 30 DEPAUL L. REV. being forced out of business damages, see Comment, Caveat Not a Defense to Illinois 477, 495-98 (1981). 130 No distinction is made here between strict tortfeasors and negligence tortfeasors so long as they are both manufacturers. See text at Section TX. 131 See Sales, supra note 2 at 730 where he states that "(i|n some jurisdictions adoption of the doctrine (of strict liability] has been predicated on the deep pocket theory; that is, the product supplier, as part of an enterprise liability, is better able to absorb the costs of injuries than the consumer by a proportionate distribution of these costs to the purchasing public" (footnote omitted). 132 Plant, Comparative Negligence and Strict Tort Liability, '•03, 416 (1980). 133 See Restatement §402A, Comment 134 Plant, supra note 132 at 416. 74 40 LA. L . REV. 135 Compare K n e p p e r , Review of 1976 Tort T r e n d s , 26 D e f . L . J r n l . I, 5 (1977) "[The doctrine of strict liability] is based on the concept that the m a n u f a c t u r e r is an expert who should be able to avoid defective products, and is better able to bear the cost of accidental injuries than are his injured customers." 136 Foreseeability is an issue here without regard to the type of action a plaintiff may plead and prove. It is an express issue in negligence and implied in strict l i a b i l i t y . 137 Mom and Pop businesses do not have the risk evaluation capability of General M o t o r s . But compared to c o n s u m e r s , Mom and Pop h a v e exclusive pre-use evaluation c a p a b i l i t i e s . 138 Supra note 119. 138a Loss spreading has played a major role in the evolution of strict tort liability. I have gone further to try to justify the use of loss spreading which in and of itself is a purely incidental phenonenon to running a b u s i n e s s . I am always suspect of any rule of law which focuses too much on e c o n o m i c s . But loss spreading is real and is a h i g h l y useable means for achieving the overall goal of product s a f e t y . T feel it is justified when one looks at the pre-use risk evaluation c a p a b i l i t y of manufacturers as opposed to product u s e r s , even though approaching strict liability in this fashion does conjure up the ugly head of negligence which of course requires focus on a manufacturer's c o n d u c t , not the product, and which predictably would upset the strict liability applecart to many p u r i s t s ' way of t h i n k i n g . C o m m e n t , supra note 123. 140 This statement is makeweight because it is not the plaintiff's inability to absorb the l o s s , but a manufacturer's ability to shift l o s s , justified by a manufacturer's ability to evaluate and spread risk that is a basis for imposing strict l i a b i l i t y . Strict liability should not be a search for a deep p o c k e t . Economics simply should not play this role in imposing strict l i a b i l i t y . To argue that deep pocket theory is all that strict liability is a b o u t , is to unduly discredit a valuable legal d o c t r i n e . 141 The Texas assumption of risk cases are e x a m p l e s . 142 This is thought to be the major virtue of pure c o m p a r a t i v e fault. 179 This is an oversimplification of the thinking behind pure comparative causation principles which reduce plaintiff's recovery in proportion to the amount of his injury causing conduct in whatever degree of c u l p a b i l i t y . See g e n e r a l l y , T w e r s k i , supra note 6 1 . It differs from pure comparative fault in that it avoids the technical problem of comparing strict liability with negligence discussed in the text at Section I I . See P l a n t , supra note 132 at 4 0 7 . W a d e , supra note 2 at 3 7 9 , 387-88; S a l e s , supra note 2 at 7 6 1 , 7 7 8 . 145 See g e n e r a l l y , Twerski supra note 7 . 146 To argue for the adoption of comparative fault p r i n c i p l e s , and then argue that the public should not have to pay for the plaintiff's f a u l t , is to forget that it is the manufacturer who made the product that injured the plaintiff. And yet this is what Professor Wade and Attorney Sales would seem to h a v e us d o . Comparative fault principles do not compare plaintiffs to the public; they would compare manufacturers to plaintiffs without undue doctrinal weight given to non-fault and fault comparison problems. 147 This is the danger of arguments that focus too much on economic justice. 148 Professor Twerski considers that comparing any and ail substandard plaintiff conduct may dilute the duties placed on manufacturers to make reasonably safe p r o d u c t s , whether the duties are derived d i r e c t l y from negligence theory or impliedly from strict liability. See T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 1 0 . Accord: O w e n , supra note 3 at 6 1 . 149 See T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 0 2 . 150 There will be some i n c e n t i v e , at least to the extent people hear of each other's misfortunes at the hands of a manufacturer who has successfully defended on comparative fault g r o u n d s . 151 Even if the individual is an assumed risk taker. 152 Even if it is assumed that plaintiffs and manufacturers are equal in terms of risk evaluation it is silly to assume that a plaintiff who has not discovered the dangerous product has any capability to avoid the injury. The duty to inspect the product is on the m a n u f a c t u r e r . If we place a duty on the plaintiff to inspect the product we are in effect saying the plaintiff has no right to rely on the product's i n t e g r i t y . That is precisely what would be accomplished if pure comparative fault principles are a d o p t e d . We cannot in reality asume that they are on equal footing in terms of risk evaluation even if we put an express d u t y or implied duty 76 (using pure comparative fault principles) on the plaintiff. The more insidious the danger the less evaluation capability is in the plaintiff. 153 See Twerski supra note 7 at 804. 154 See Mohr v . B.F. Goodrich Rubber Co., 371 A.2d 288, 292 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div., 1977) wherein it is stated: "Contributory negligence can be a bar to recovery in strict liability, with the exception of those cases where the consequences of plaintiff's contributory negligence could have been avoided by the manufacturer's exercise of due care" (citations omitted). See also Shamrock Fuel & Oil Sales Co. v . Tunks, 416 S.W.2d 779, 785-86 (Tex., 1967) wherein it is stated: "Under modern conditions of advertising and marketing, there exists a strong consumer reliance upon the integrity of the manufacturer and vendor of a product. The representation of safety in use is not restricted to those consumers of the reasonably prudent variety. It would be incongruous to hold that one could not recover upon the representation that a product was safe because he had failed to meet the test of the reasonably prudent man in discovering that the representation was not true." 155 I am aware that apples and oranges are mixed when foreseeability is injected into strict liability in a similar way that there may be a perceived impropriety in comparing strict liability to plaintiff substandard conduct. But substantively speaking, I see no policy reason for not injecting foreseeability into the matter in the strict liability marketing case. "(Tlhe duty to warn arises only if the manufacturer knows or should know of the potentiality of h a r m , that duty becomes opertive only with respect to foreseeably unreasonable risks." Edgar, supra note 19 at 31. We cannot ignore the element of foreseeability that goes into designing a product. Even if strict liability supposedly focuses on the product, the finding of a defective design which poses an unreasonable danger, at the very least implies a finding that it should have been designed differently. If it should have been designed differently, the manufacturer was impliedly negligent because of the failure to design the product as a reasonbly prudent manufacturer would have designed it. If strict liability is to reduce proof problems, so be it. But we should not say that this is a reason for denying considerations of the foreseeability of the substandard conduct of the plaintiff from a policy perspective. To inject foreseeability into some strict liability design and marketing cases is to do no more than to take the concept out of the cupboard and put it on the table. 156 See Twerski, supra note 7 at 808 (speaking of second collision 814-17 (use within product tolerance). 157 See supra note 154. 77 cases), 157a Mulcahy v . Harris C o r p . , 487 F . S u p p . 499 (ND 1 1 1 . , 1980) (applying 111. law); Brown v . Luik Belt C o r p . , 565 F.2d 1107 (9th C i r . , 1977) (applying O r e . law); Henderson v . Ford Motor C o m p a n y , 519 S.W.2d 87 (Tex. 1974); Green v . Edmands C o . , 639 F.2d 286 (5th C i r . 1981) (applying T e x . L a w ) . See other cases collected at A n n o t . , 46 ALR 3d 240 e t . s e q . (1972). See Butand v . Suburban Marine & Sporting G o o d s , (Alaska, 1976); W a d e , supra note 2 . Inc., 555 P.2d 4 2 , 46 159 This would seem to be the rationale in those jurisdictions applying comparative principles in such c a s e s . See Butaud v . Suburban Marine & Sporting G o o d s , Inc., 555 P.2d 42 (Alaska, 1976); Bacceleri v . Hyster C o . , 287 O r e . 3, 597 P.2d 351 (1979) (assumption of risk treated as subspecies of contributory negligence under comparative negligence); Devaney v. S a r n o , 125 N . J . S u p e r . 4 1 4 , 311 A.2d 208 (1973). 160 Both have n o t i c e . The assumed risk taker goes further assume a subjectively understood d a n g e r . to voluntarily 161 The El Paso Court of Appeals has laid the groundwork for doing s o . See Wenzel v . Rollins Motors C o . 598 S.W.2d 895 (Tex. C i v . A p p . 1 9 8 0 , writ r e f . n.r.e .). 162 Jurisdictions applying comparative principles do not hold that assumption of risk is a complete b a r . See Daly v . General Motors C o r p . , 575 P.2d 1162 (1978); Butand v . Suburban Marine & Sporting G o o d s , Inc., 555 P.2d 42 (Alaska, 1976). 163 C f . L e v i n e , supra note 39 at 6 4 7 . 164 See supra note 88 and accompanying text. 165 See text beginning at Section V I I . 202 The prediscovery plaintiff has no real risk evaluation capability. 167 Such a duty is inconsistent with the representational theory for imposing strict l i a b i l i t y . See supra note 122. T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 0 4 . I d . at 8 0 5 . 78 115 See i d . at 8 1 3 . 171 I d . at 8 1 7 . 172 See F l e t c h e r , Fairness and Utility in Tort T h e o r y , 85 H A R V . _L. R E V . 537, (1972) reprinted in R a b i n , Perspectives on Tort L a w , 2 1 3 , 217-18 ( 1 9 7 6 ) . Fletcher's article is specifically directed at non-products c a s e s . His basic theory is that non-reciprocal risk takers should bear the loss. Reciprocal risk takers who cause damage should not be held liable. He apparently recognizes that the interests of the victim or of the class he represents may have a bearing on the paradigm of r e c i p r o c i t y . Assuming that these considerations do have a bearing on the p a r a d i g m , it.would seem that m a n u f a c t u r e r s of dangerous products pose non-reciprocating risks of harm to members of the p u b l i c , whether c o n s u m e r s , u s e r s , or b y s t a n d e r s . See T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 0 4 . See supra note 108 and accompanying text. 174a See T w e r s k i , supra 7 at 8 1 3 . 175 See supra note 5 5 . 176 These are the basic facts of Bexiga v . Havir Manufacturing C o r p . , 290 A.2d 281 (N.J. 1972). 177 T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 0 0 . 178 "Foreseeabilitv may be a relevant factor for the judge to consider; other factors may and are usually more important in the determination of the defendant's duty; the fact of risk in the particular case is what actually took place as a result of defendant's c o n d u c t , not what was foreseen b y the actor as likely to take p l a c e , and it is this risk that must be brought into focus by the court's judgment on the duty issue." Twerski, supra note 61 at 423 quoting from G r e e n , D u t i e s , R i s k s , C a u s a t i o n , D o c t r i n e s , 41 T E X . L . R E V . 4 2 , 58 (1962) (emphasis in o r i g i n a l ) . "Under a duty-risk a n a l y s i s , the issue of the scope of the legal system's protection never goes to a jury....The only question would b e for the court; and it could or could not factor in foreseeability in its determination of the duty risk issue." I d . at 4 2 4 . 179 "We realize that there is some dispute...concerning the foreseeability of misuse of products....[W]e are not convinced that the doctrine provides a viable conceptual basis upon which to predicate a defense in products liability cases....To require foreseeability is to require the manufacturer to use due c a r e . fl]n strict liability...[foreseeability] is hard to apply." Butand v . Suburban Marine & Sporting G o o d s , Inc. 555 P.2d 42,46 ( A l a s k a , 1976) (footnotes o m i t t e d ) . "(A) court must first decide whether the basic purposes of product liability law will be furthered by permitting the affirmative d e f e n s e . This is a duty question that cannot be avoided by asserting that in all products cases assumption of the risk is a defense or that foreseeable misuse is not a d e f e n s e . These blunderbuss statements cover too much territory with too broad a brush." T w e r s k i , supra note 61 at 4 3 0 . 180 S a l e s , supra note 2 at 771-777 discussing Daley v . General Motors C o r p . , and Butand v . Suburban Marine & Sporting G o o d s , I n c . , both cited supra note 162. 181 "The |Daly] majority deny their opinion diminishes the therapeutic effect of products liability upon producers of defective p r o d u c t s . It seems self-evident that procedures which evaluate the injured consumer's conduct in each instance, and thus eliminate or reduce the award against the producer or distributor of a defective product, are not designed as an effective incentive to maximum responsibility to c o n s u m e r s . The converse is more accurate: the motivation to avoid polluting the stream of commerce with defective products increases in direct relation to the size of potential damage awards." Daly v . General Motors C o r p . , 575 P.2d 1 1 6 2 , 1186, (Cal. 1978) (Mosk, J . , dissenting and arguing against apply/ comparative negligence to strict liability c a s e s ) . 182 E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1104. 183 See text at Section I I . 184 See P l a n t , supra note 132 at 4 1 8 . 185 See supra notes 120-124 and accompanying text. 186 See supra notes 121, 157 and accompanying text. 187 Compare note 172 s u p r a . 188 See generally P r o s s e r , Law of Torts §61 (4th E d . , 1971) 80 157a T believe Professor Twerski would agree with this c o n c l u s i o n . See generally T w e r s k i , supra note 7 . See also Caterpillar v . B e c k , 593 P.2d 871, 893 (Alaska, 1979) (Dimond, Senior Justice diisenting and concurri n g ) . See T w e r s k i , supra note 7 at 8 0 5 . See also Mohr v . B . F . Goodrich Rubber C o . , 371 A.2d 2 3 8 , 292 (N.J. Super. C o u r t . A p p . D i v . , 1977); Bexiga v . Havir Manufacturing C o r p . , 290 A.2d 281 (N.J. 1972). 191 RESTATEMENT j)F TORTS (SECOND) 5402A, Comment £_. 192 I d . at comments g , h , and i. 193 See generally Heil Company v . G r a n t , 534 S.W.2d 916 (Tex. C i v . A p p . 1976, writ r e f . n.r.e.); authorities cited in General Motors C o r p . v . S i m m o n s , 558 S.W.2d 8 5 5 , 860-61 ( T e x . 1977). See supra notes 108, 166-173 and accompanying text. 195 See supra notes 110-111, 160 and accompanying text. Conduct is not substandard if it is not negligent or unreasonable when the conduct amounts to assumption of the r i s k . The discovery test should be a subjective one to avoid placing a duty to inspect the product on the plaintiff. See generally T w e r s k i , supra note 61; E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1110 n.29 for a discussion of comparative c a u s a t i o n . See text accompanying note 8 8 , s u p r a . 197 Compare supra notes 89-93 and accompanying text with notes 175-178 and accompanying text. This maximizes policy objectives by making the defendant liable damage his unreasonably dangerous defective product has c a u s e d . 199 See text at page 5 1 - ^ 8 . See text at Section X . 202 See text accompanying note 88 s u p r a . See text following notes 102 e t . s e q . C03'"Q 81 for supra all 203 See text accompanying note 88 supra for a test for m i s u s e . 204 I'he causation issue should be phrased as proximate cause in regard to plaintiff's contributory n e g l i g e n c e . See supra note 13 and accompanying text. 205 Notice that the but for causation issue is separated from the proximate cause i s s u e , h o p e f u l l y to reduce possible confusion of the issues because of the foreseeability element in proximate c a u s e . Compare E d g a r , supra note 18 at 1108, 1110 n . 2 9 . 206 The text does not mean that we put a duty of care in terms of foreseeability on the manufacturer and thereby inject negligence into the strict liability c a s e . It would encourage pre-use risk evaluation in hopes of maximizing consumer protection without regard to whether the conduct of the plaintiff was foreseeable or n o t . Compare E d g a r , supra note 19 at 44 n.98 noting that the Court in Hopkins would reject foreseeable uses of the product as a defense if the product is unreasonably dangerous for those u s e s . This would seem to put a duty to protect the consumer on the manufacturer at the risk of being saddled with the whole loss if the duty is b r e a c h e d . Professor Edgar goes on to note that where the substandard plaintiff concurs with the defect of the product to cause injury to a third p e r s o n , the substandard plaintiff's causative conduct should not alter the duty to the third person who is basically a bystander in such a situation, unless he too is guilty of substandard c o n d u c t . 207 T o compare fault in this manner is to reduce the action to a negligence action even if plaintiff proof benefits are preserved in strict l i a b i l i t y . 44 F e d . R e g . 62,714-50 (1979). 208a S a l e s , supra note 2 at 7 7 5 . 209 I d . at 7 7 5 - 7 6 . See Sun Valley A i r l i n e s , I n c . v . Avco-Lycoming C o r p . , 411 F . S u p p . 598 (D. Idaho 1976) discussed in S a l e s , supra note 2 at 7 6 6 . See Sales supra note 2 at 7 6 2 - 6 6 . 21 I 63 Wis.2d 7 2 8 , 218 N.W.2d 279 (1974). 212 S a l e s , supra note 2 at 7 6 4 . See Btitaud v . Suburban Marine & Sporting G o o d s , Inc., 555 P.2d 42 (Alaska 1976); Caterpillar Tractor C o . v . Beck, 593 P.2d 871 (Alaska 1979); Daly v . General Motors C o r p . , 20 Cal.3d 7 2 5 , 575 P.2d 1162, 144 C a l . R p t r . 380 (1978). 214 See Seay v . Chrysler C o r p . , 93 Wash.2d 319, 609 P.2d 1382 (1980) (fearing that to apply the state's comparative negligence would usurp legislative authority). 215 See Kirkland v . General Motors C o r p . , 521 P.2d 1353 (Okl. 1974); Melia v . Ford Motor C o . , 534 F.2d 795 (8th C i r . 1976); Kinard v . Coats C o . , Inc., 553 P.2d 8 3 5 , 837 (Colo. A p p . 1976) all discussed in Daly v . General M o t o r s , supra note 213 (dissenting opinion of Justice M o s k ) . 216 Compare authorities at note 213, supra. S e e , Twerski supra note 7 at 8 1 0 . 00330 83