Ficino and Pomponazzi on the Place of Man in the Universe Author(s): Paul Oskar Kristeller Reviewed work(s): Source: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 5, No. 2 (Apr., 1944), pp. 220-226 Published by: University of Pennsylvania Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2707386 . Accessed: 11/02/2013 10:35 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . University of Pennsylvania Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of the History of Ideas. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded on Mon, 11 Feb 2013 10:35:07 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions NOTES AND DOCUMENTS FICINO AND POMPONAZZI ON THE PLACE OF MAN IN THE UNIVERSE BY PAUL OSKAR KRISTELLER In attemptingto understanda given body of ideas, the studentof intellectual historywill not only seek to determineits truthor its philosophical and historicalsignificance;he will also inquire how far theseideas were old or novel at the time a writerfirstexpressedthem. To be sure, the history of thoughthas shiftedback and forthbetweenan emphasis on originality and an adherenceto permanentprinciples,and the emphasisprevailing at of authors. Yet neitherextreme a givenperiodhas oftenguided the efforts has ever at any timebeen realized. What we actually findeverywhereis a mixtureof old and new elements,in varyingproportionsto be sure. There are several reasonsforthe acceptanceand repetitionof old ideas. One factoris certainlythe intellectualinertiawhichleads a man to receive without question what he has been taught, or to reject without proper examinationother proposed ideas which would conflictwith his familiar views. More important,in the case of a moderatelyindependentmind, is the impossibilityof any individual's constructinga new systemof the universe from the ground up withoutthe use of borrowedmaterials. This fact makesclear the importanceof investigatingthe sourcesand background of a philosopher,providedwe do not stop withnotingthat certainideas have been takenfromcertainsources,but proceedto inquire whytheyhave been borrowedand how they have been transformedto become part of the new synthesis. Another factor which definitelymakes for continuity,though this may sound like a paradox, is polemic and discussion. The current views against which a thinkerreacts mark also the starting-pointfor his own thought,determinethe range and directionof his ideas, and oftenconstitute the necessary complementto his own system. This is one of the reasonswhypupils seldomsucceed in maintainingintactthe systemof their masters. Ideas lose theirforeewhen the conditionsin oppositionto which they were conceiveddisappear, just as a man leaning with all his force against a wall will collapse when the wall is suddenlytaken away. Moreover,everyphilosophicalthoughtis a responseto a commonworld. There are certainbasic facts whichno thinkercan disregard,and certainenduring problemswhichgive continuityto theirvaryingsolutions. Finally, certain problemsadmit of only a limited number of basic solutions,which recur moreor less regularlyin the historyof ideas, thoughthe details may vary. This accountsforthe fact that thereare a few persistenttrendswhichmay be tracedthroughthe entirehistoryof thought. 220 This content downloaded on Mon, 11 Feb 2013 10:35:07 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions FICINO AND POMPONAZZI ON MAN 221 On the otherhand, thereare no less powerfulfactorscontributingto a continual change and variety of ideas. Most thinkersderive some degree of noveltyfromtheir own personal outlook,or even from a conscious endeavor to be original or "up-to-date." Favorable circumstancesmay help them to reach conclusionsfor which the premiseshave been prepared by their predecessors. Intellectual, political, or social conditions prevailing at the time may force them to modifyideas they would preferto restate, circumstances. More importantis the whichwere conceivedunder different basic fact that each individual and each age starts life anew, has a new approach to truth,and may hence make a specificallynew contributionto the realm of ideas. Even in the extremecase in whicha thinkeris merely copying or summarizingthe work of previous writers,his selection and emphasiswill depend on his preferences,if not on specificideas. In view of this necessarycombinationof old and new elements,the historyof ideas will oftenappear like the variationson a musical theme. This point of view is particularlyhelpful in understandingthe history of a specifictrend or traditionwhich may be traced over a longer period, such as Platonismor Aristotelianism. Such a traditionis held togetherby a commonorientationtoward a great thinkerof the past and toward some of his basic ideas. But it is by no means a successionof simple repetitions of theories established once and for all at the beginning. Otherwise it would have no interestwhatsoever. What actually takes place is a process of continualadaptation,in whichthe basic ideas are gradually transformed historicaland intellectualsituationand and readjustedto the ever-changing to thespecificinterestsand problemsof individualthinkers. A later thinker who triesto interpretor to restatethe ideas of an earlierthinkerwill always translate old conceptsinto new termsand will reconstructthe old system according to his own views. He will select and emphasize some elements of the previoustraditionand omit or disregard others. He will also combine themwithideas borrowedfromoutsidesources or added by himself. It is obviousthat the historianof philosophymust adjust his methodto this state of affairs. For a long time the entirestudy of past philosophies had beenlimitedto statingand criticizing" opinions," and this still remains the necessarybasis or the final goal of any interpretation. But more recentlythe historyof philosophyhas come to be a special discipline aiming at a philosophicalunderstandingof past thinkersthroughthe resourcesof historical and philological scholarship. In pursuing this task, some students have been inclinedto treat the great thinkersas isolated figuresand to emphasizeonly the novel and original aspects of theirthought. Others, on the contrary,have been more interestedin the continuingtradition of certain ideas and tendencies,and have emphasized the permanent and recurringfactors at the expense of the changing and varying details. I should thinkthat a combinationof both methodsis needed. The historian This content downloaded on Mon, 11 Feb 2013 10:35:07 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 222 NOTES AND DOCUMENTS should recognizethe recurringbasic ideas and attitudes in their various appearances,but he should also describeand explain what is specificin the different appearances and its relationto the basic principles. The method should be flexible,of course, according to the number and significanceof the novel elementsfound in each representativeof a given tradition. In thisway the historianof philosophywill do justice to the fact that an intellectual traditionconsistsin the varyingmanifestationsof permanent,basic principles. When we apply this methodto the historyof Platonismor Aristotelianthat Platonism and ism, we are confrontedwith the additional difficulty Aristotelianismare, so to speak, complementaryto each other. Closely related fromthe beginning,their very relation has been subject to a continuallychanginginterpretation. The reason is to be found in the relation betweenPlato and Aristotlethemselves. Modernhistoricalresearchhas led to the conclusionthat the philosophiesof Plato and Aristotlewere not simsystemsof thought,but ratherstages ply two oppositeor merelydifferent in a gradual developmentwhichled fromthe matureworksof Plato through the dialogues of his old age and throughthe early works of Aristotle (as reconstructedout of preservedfragments) to the treatises of Aristotle's mature period. But this historicalinsightcannot preventus fromrecognizing that there really is a basic differencebetween the philosophiesof Plato and Aristotle. This ambiguous relation has determinedthe historyof Platonism and Aristotelianismever since. There were periods in which the contrast betweenthe two traditionswas stronglyemphasized,but even then the followers of Plato could not help borrowingproblemsand conceptsof Aristotelian origin,nor could the Aristotelianseliminatethe Platonic elements containedin the systemof theirmaster. At othertimesa so-calledeclectic tendencyheld that Plato and Aristotle"disagreed in words,but agreed in theirdoctrines"; but the disagreementin words still remainedquite puzzling for the interpreters,and they were obliged in their attemptedsynthesis to subordinatethe views of one masterto those of the other. Thus the two currentsrepresenttwo different poles of philosophicalorientation, of each other. withoutbeing entirelyexclusive On the contrary,we might say thateach belongsto thehistoryof the other,and that just in thosetimes when one of the two traditionsdefinitelyprevails over the other,it is also bound to continueand to representthe heritageof that othertradition. In medievalEurope, Platonismas modifiedby Augustinewas theprevailing trend in philosophy and theology up to the twelfth century, and remainedan importantsecondarycurrentlong thereafter. Aristotelianism on the otherhand became predominantin the thirteenthcentury,and retained much of its hold up to the sixteenthcenturyand even afterwards. Yet from the fifteenthcentury on both Platonism and Aristotelianism This content downloaded on Mon, 11 Feb 2013 10:35:07 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions FICINO AND POMPONAZZI ON MAN 223 entereda novel phase under the influenceof the new humanisticmovement. Both currents,to be sure, continuedthe precedingtraditionsof the Middle Ages, but at the same time they formulatedthe traditionalproblemsand doctrinesin novel termsand thus representnew stages in the historyof thosetraditions. Let us considereach of themin one of their chiefrepresentatives,that is, in Ficino and in Pomponazzi. Ficino's main work,the Theologia Platonica, is an attemptto prove the of thesoul by rationalarguments. The problemof immortality immortality acquires this importancefor him for the followingreasons. Ficino argues that we are taughtby a basic experiencethat contemplationof the invisible and of God is the major activityof human life and constitutesthe very goal of our existence. But at the same timewe findthat in our presentlife this goal is attained only in an imperfectfashion,that is, by veryfew persons,and by themonlyfor a brieftime. Hence we must assume that there will be a futurelife in whichthe highestaim of our existence,the immediate knowledgeand enjoymentof God, will be attained by a large number of of thesoul thus humanbeingsand in a permanentfashion. The immortality appears as a necessarypostulatefor maintainingthat contemplationis the goal of human life.' Pomponazzi also dedicates one of his mostimportantworksto the problem of immortality,but his solution is just the opposite from Ficino's. There are no rational proofsfor the immortalityof the soul; and since the doctrineof immortality mustbe upheld as a religioustruth,it can be based only on the authorityof the Bible and of the Church, but not on philoat least in the sphere of sophical arguments. This denial of immortality, reason,is based on a characteristicpremisewhichagain is just the opposite ofFicino's emphasison contemplation.The human intellectalways depends on corporeal,empiricalobjects,and thereis no reason to assume any higher activityof the human mind whichwould bring it into contactwith purely intelligibleentities. But Pomponazziis no materialist. Althoughthe intellect is corporealwithregard to its objects,as a subject of thoughtit is immaterial,and in thissense it may be said thatthehumansoul,thoughmortal in its essence,does at least participate in immortality. Pomponazzi thus replaces the conceptof immortalityas a perfectlife after death with that of a participationin immortalityduring the present life. The meaning of this change becomes apparent in his coneeption of virtue. Whereas Ficino still accepted the conventionalopinion that immortalityis a moral postulate in order that virtue and vice may be properlyrewarded after death,Pomponazzi emphaticallydenies the moral value of such recompense. The essentialreward of virtue is virtue itself,the essential punishmentof vice, vice itself. Thus moral doctrineis freed of all metaphysicalpremises, and at the same timethe goal of human existenceis conceivedas something 1 See: P. 0. Kristeller,The Philosophy of Marsilio Ficino (New York, 1943). This content downloaded on Mon, 11 Feb 2013 10:35:07 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 224 NOTES AND DOCUMENTS attainable during our present life, and not to be expected in another, futurelife.2 Ficino and Pomponazzi thus represent two philosophical attitudes from,if not opposed to each other,whichmay be roughly basicallydifferent identifiedwiththe generaltrendof the Platonic and Aristoteliantraditions that in spite of this contrast respectively. It is henceall the moresignificant theyhave somethingin commonwhichseemsto be characteristicof Renaissance thought. The veryfact that such basic importanceis attachedto the showsa predominantinterestin man and his metaproblemof immortality physicalposition,not nearly so markedin the previousperiod.3 Moreover, the contrastingideas of futurecontemplationand of self-containedvirtuous conduct are but alternativesolutions to the same basic problem,that is, to the question: what is the ultimateaim of human life? Finally, in the passages we have selected in order to illustrateFicino's and Pomponazzi's doctrineof the place of man in the universe,bothof themmake verysimilar statements,emphasizingthat man is the center of the universe and is related to all otherparts of the world. Even if Pomponazzi borrowedthe idea fromFicino, the fact that these statementsare found in entirelydifferentand evenopposedcontextsmakesthe coincidenceall themoreinteresting. The passages acquire additional significancefromtheir similarityto Pico's famousOration on theDignity of Man.4 of man was a It would be entirelywrongto claim that the glorification new discoveryof the Renaissance. The praise of man because of his invention of the arts is quite familiar in Greek literatureand thought,and so is the simile of man as microcosm. The intermediateposition of the soul betweenthe corporealand the intelligibleworld is definitelysuggestedby Plato and furtherdeveloped by the Neoplatonistsand Hermetics. On the otherhand, the superiorityof man over other creaturesis definitelyindicated in Genesisand in severalotherpassages of the Old Testament. Early Christianemphasison the salvation of mankindand on the incarnationof Christimplieda conceptionof the dignityof man whichwas furtherdeveloped by someof the ChurchFathers,Lactantiusand Augustinefor example.5 These ideas were neverentirelyforgottenduringthe Middle Ages. But I am under the impressionthat since the beginningof Renaissance humanism the emphasis on man becomes more persistent,more systematic,and 2 Petrus Pomponatius,TractatusDe ImmortalitateAnimae, translatedby William Henry Hay II (Haverford, 1938). 3 G. Gentile,II concettodell'uomonel Rinascimento,in 11 pensiero italiano del Rinascimento(Florence, 1940). 4 "Of the Dignityof Man," translatedby Elizabeth L. Forbes, this Journal III (1942), 347-54; E. Cassirer,ibid., 123-44; 319-46. 5 G. Garin, "La 'dignitas hominis' e la letteraturapatristica," Rinascita, I, no. 4 (1938), 102-46. This content downloaded on Mon, 11 Feb 2013 10:35:07 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions FICINO AND POMPONAZZI ON MAN 225 moreexclusive. Petrarch,who in his unsystematicway oftenexpressesideas which were to be elaborated in the sueceedingperiod, insists that nothing is admirable but the soul, and that thereis only one importantsubject of human thought,man himself.6 Before the middle of the fifteenthcentury Giannozzo Manetti, the Florentine humanist,composed a treatise On the Excellency and Dignity of Man as a counterpartto Innocent III's work On the Misery of MalJ.7 With Ficino the glorificationof man assumes a moredefinitephilosophicalsignificance. He emphasizesmainlytwo aspects: man's universalityand his centralposition. Man's universalityis reflected in his relationto all parts of the universeand in his unlimitedaspirations. His positionin the centerof the universe,moreover,gives man an importance unrivaled by any other being except God himself. Pico, obviously followingFicino, modifieshis theoryon one characteristicpoint. Man is no longerthe centerof theuniverse,but he is detachedfromthe entireseries of existingthingsand freeto choosehis own formof life. Thus the dignity of man is no longer conceivedin termsof his universality,but in termsof his liberty.8 These ideas of Ficino and Pico exerciseda wide influencein the later Renaissance. A good example of this influenceis Vives' Fable on Man, based entirelyon Pico's conception.9 The passages from Ficino about the universal rule of man over the elementsseem also to have somethingin commonwith the Baconian program of the dominionof man over nature. His conclusion that man is endowed with an almost god-like mind because Archimedeswas able to constructa model of the heavenlysphere,may even suggestGalileo's assertion that God's knowledgeof mathematicsis differentin quantitybut not in kind fromour own mathematicalknowledge.10Of course in the latter two cases no direct influenceis likely, and the emphasis and contextare but the comparisonmay help to clarifysome implications entirelydifferent; on bothsides. The positionof man in the universehas a bearing not only on man, but also on theuniverse. Hence the statementsof Ficino, Pico, and Pomponazzi have a definitesignificancenot only in the historyof the conception of man, but also in the historyof cosmology. The medieval conceptionof the universewas dominatedby the idea of a hierarchyof substances,whichgoes 6 Francesco Petrarea, Le familiari,bk. IV, no. 1 (ed. V. Rossi, v. I [Florence, 1933], 159). Id., Le traiteDe sui ipsius et multorumignorantia,ed. L. M. Capelli (Paris, 1906), 24 f. 7See Gentile,op. cit., 90 ff. 8 See Kristeller,op. cit., 117 ff.,407 ff. 9 Joannes Ludovicus Vives, Fabula de homine,in Opera Omnia, IV (Valencia 1783), 3-8. 10 Galileo Galilei, Dialogo sopra i due massimi sistemi del mondo, giornata prima (Edizione Nazionale, VII [Florence, 1897], 128 f.). This content downloaded on Mon, 11 Feb 2013 10:35:07 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 226 NOTES AND DOCUMENTS back to Neoplatonicsources. Whereas in the fieldof biology this idea of hierarchysurvivedup to fairlyrecenttimes,in the fieldof cosmologyit was definitelyabandoned by early modernscience. In the astronomyof Kepler of rank and perfectionbetween and Galileo thereis no roomfor differences heaven and earth, or between the various stars or the various elements. But even beforethe new astronomywas definitelyestablished a gradual disintegrationof the old idea of hierarchytook place, most definitelyin Nicholas of Cusa and later in GiordanoBruno. It would seemthat the conceptionsof Ficino and Pico played theirmore modest part in this disintegration. To be sure, Ficino takes a hierarchy of his metaphysicalsystem. But of fiveprinciplesas theverystarting-point he immediatelyasks how the various levels of that hierarchyare related to each other; and he seeks a central link which throughits attributescould mediatebetweentheoppositeextremesof theuniverse,and throughits manifold aspirations and movementscould transmitforces and qualities from one end of the universeto the other. This questionactually transcendsthe limits of the traditionalnotion of hierarchy,and implies a dynamic conception of the universesuch as was developed by the natural philosophers of the sixteenthcentury. Whereas on this point Pomponazzi merelyfollows Ficino, Pico goes one step farther. He also maintainsthe notion of a hierarchy;but forhimman is no longera definiteelementin the hierarchial series, not even its privileged center: he is entirely detached from the hierarchyand can move upward and downwardaccordingto his free will. Thus the hierarchyis no longerall-inclusive,while man, because of his possessionof freedom,seemsto be set entirelyapart fromthe orderof objective reality. The last observationpoints to a more general characteristicof Renaissance thought: it is a period of transition,in a specificsense which does not apply to most otherperiods of thought. To be sure there are always varietiesof opinionand orientation. But the philosophiesof the thirteenth or of the seventeenthcenturywere based on commonprinciples. Renaissance thoughthas commonproblemsand commonaspirations,but no common principles or solutions. The disintegrationof old principles that appears during the Renaissance has not only a negative value in clearing the way for the formulationof new principles that was bound to come. It has also a positivesignificance,because it is generatedby new formsof experienceand new problemswhich were destined to be absorbed in the succeedingsynthesisof the seventeenthcentury. ColumbiaUniversity. This content downloaded on Mon, 11 Feb 2013 10:35:07 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions