Section: Teaching philosophy to other disciplines Paideia and an ancient quarrel Martin Warner I Any consideration of the teaching of philosophy to other disciplines has at least three variables with which to contend. As a preliminary orientation I shall focus on teaching at university level in English-speaking universities towards the end of the twentieth century, and treat as ‘philosophy’ what is there predominantly taught as such. Even with this narrow focus the notion of what counts as ‘another discipline’ is not wholly straightforward. Partly this arises from the obscurity of the notion of a ‘discipline’, and partly from the fact that philosophy’s boundaries are not always clear-cut; some work in mathematics and in physics is also philosophy, and some work in the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of language is difficult to disentangle, respectively, from psychology and from linguistics; further, there are a number of disciplines on the borders of philosophy such as political theory, jurisprudence and critical theory. Further, in those cases where a discipline clearly lies outside the boundaries of philosophy what counts as teaching philosophy to its practitioners or students may itself vary, depending on whether the focus is primarily on the content or on the methods of philosophy. Attention to content may be in place either when a distinct area of philosophy has a direct bearing on some aspect of the discipline (as in the teaching of medical or business ethics) or when philosophy’s general concern with fundamental categories may provide relevant insight into the foundations of a discipline - whether sociology, cosmology or theology. Attention to method may be of more general application, but can also be double-edged. It is usual, at least in the analytic tradition, to stress philosophy’s argumentative rigour, its use of logic and techniques of analysis, its inculcation of the values of clarity and precision - what might be called its Aristotelian heritage. But there is also the Socratic, subversive, 1 heritage - gestured to by Yeats’s haunting refrain: ‘“What then?” sang Plato’s ghost, “What then?”’1- which encourages us to examine and question our assumptions, and which may disrupt clear and orderly results. Content and method can, of course, come together when attention to a discipline’s fundamental categories, analytic rigour and unsettling questioning can disrupt that discipline, as theology knows both to its cost and to its benefit; but they can also be unfortunately separated, as in some versions of applied ethics where an ethical model seems so apt to some preferred versions of a discipline or practice that it is analytically refined, absorbed into that practice’s protocols, and taught to students and practitioners without due attention to its limitations and problems. In the pursuit and teaching of philosophy, of course, content and method are intimately related. Certain types of issue have traditionally been regarded as the preeminent concern of philosophy, narrowly conceived; ontology, epistemology, theories of meaning and truth, theories of rational inference and proof, and theories of value would be included in most scholars’ designations of the philosophical heartlands. The types of procedure found apt for serious engagement with these issues constitute philosophical methodology. Some of these methods are as ancient as the discipline itself: the Socratic elenchus is a form of reductio ad absurdum which as late as the mid-twentieth-century was seen by Gilbert Ryle as exemplifying, in one of its forms, distinctively philosophical rigour; the Platonic diairesis (division) and synagoge (collection) prefigure both the analysis and synthesis championed by Descartes (who notes the geometric antecedents) and the underpinnings for twentieth-century notions of ‘analysis’ as characteristic of philosophy; while Aristotle’s conception of logic as a propaedeutic study for philosophy remains entrenched in much philosophical teaching across the world. Other procedures are more controversial, being associated with different contemporary paradigms of philosophy - analytical, phenomenological, hermeneutic, deconstructive and so on - though all have roots in a common philosophical tradition and engagement with the core philosophical issues. Forms of engagement with other issues may be regarded prima facie as having philosophical credentials where they employ such procedures, most obviously when the issues in question connect the philosophical heartlands with other areas of human concern - 2 hence, in part, the appeal of ‘applied ethics’ and, more generally, ‘applied philosophy’. Not only, then, are the boundaries of philosophy to some extent contestable, but what on any given account of philosophy lies outside its boundaries may be judged to be more or less remote from it both in terms of content and in terms of method. The relevance of philosophy to any such discipline or practice may therefore differ accordingly. Further, philosophy’s relevance, in one mode or another, may be much more immediate with respect to some specialised aspect than to the fundamentals of some specific discipline or practice, and where it is relevant to the fundamentals this may either be directly or because of some apparent conflict between the presuppositions of different disciplines giving rise to dilemmas which connect with the philosophical heartlands - such, for example, as may arise between the criminal law and psychology with respect to the notion of responsibility, or between cosmology and theology with respect to the concepts of creation and causality. It is therefore doubtful whether a great deal can be usefully said in any detail about the teaching of philosophy in relation to other disciplines in general; circumstances alter cases. There is, however, a fund of experience and reflection on the teaching of philosophy to those concerned with specific other disciplines and practices, and it may be worth considering particular instances of these in the light of the general considerations sketched above. II The example I shall take relates to what, right from philosophy’s emergence, has been seen at least as ‘other’, and often as inimical, to philosophy: poetry or, more generally, imaginative literature. Neither term, of course, designates a discipline, but the composition, reception and, where appropriate, performance of poetry, plays, prose fictions and related genres constitute an overlapping set of practices. Out of these practices have arisen a variety of second-order practices of discourse about literature: literary criticism, poetics and, more generally, literary study - the latter at least having come to be seen as a discipline in its own right to which the relevance of philosophy is a contested matter. 3 ‘There is from of old’ remarks Plato’s Socrates, ‘a quarrel between philosophy and poetry’. In the Republic he argues for the banishment of the ‘honeyed Muse in lyric and epic’ from his ideal city; he expresses some unease but regretfully holds to his conclusion, ‘for reason constrains us’ (607a-c). Despite Aristotle’s attempt to provide a modus vivendi, the ancient enmity has continued through the centuries; David Hume remarked that poets are ‘liars by profession’ (A Treatise of Human Nature I. 3. x), and the logical positivists went one better: poets do not lie because they characteristically talk literal nonsense. Further, the principles underlying a good deal of the Platonic critique can be extended to much imaginative literature. As so often with quarrels, the enmity has been focussed over rival claims to the same territory, for both philosophy and literature have traditionally been held to share a concern with both the great and the small truths of the human condition. It was Plato’s conviction that only philosophy had access to at least the greater of such truths which led to his banishment of the rival claimant; reason and imagination were in genuine tension - only reason held out credible promise of enabling us to see the world clearly and see it whole, and the imagination’s claims to do this as well or better were counterfeit. (Overlap of content, one might say, he saw as being subverted by incompatible methods.) There have, of course, been various attempts to end the quarrel but the most recent is perhaps the most radical: while literature has no access to the truths of the human condition, neither has philosophy - for philosophy is itself a kind of writing inescapably enmeshed in the procedures of imaginative literature; the very notions of such ‘truths’, particularly if conceived of as relating to ‘the ultimate nature of reality’, itself represents a kind of mirage brought about by failure to grasp the essentially rhetorical character of all dialectic. In the English-speaking world this latter ‘deconstructive’ manoeuvre is most frequently encountered as a leading element of literary theory, part of the discipline of literary study, although its Derridean origins are firmly in a Germano-French philosophical tradition reaching from phenomenology to post-structuralism; it is therefore susceptible to both literary and philosophical critique, as is that earlier attempt to overcome the ancient enmity pioneered by Aristotle. With certain reservations, one might interpret the treaty terms proposed by Aristotle as favouring 4 philosophy (that poetry is ‘more philosophical’ than history is seen as an important feature in the positive valuation of poetry [Poetics 1451b]), whereas those proposed by Derrida do not; to some degree they favour the poetic camp but more fundamentally that of rhetoric.2 Philosophy’s quarrel with rhetoric is at least as old as Plato’s disputes with the sophists (his proposed modus vivendi in the Phaedrus making philosophy very much the senior partner), and the rise of deconstruction can with some plausibility be seen as a major element in a new, late twentieth-century, ‘sophistic’. Institutionally, the study of rhetoric is greatly decayed, but significant elements of it - most obviously of the figures and tropes - have been absorbed by departments of literature complementing their engagement with poetics. Philosophy’s relationship to literature is thus many layered. At the primary level of the literary texts themselves, their production, performance and reception, literature is autonomous - no more intrinsically dependent on philosophy or needing to be taught by it than with respect to any other element of culture. This is the level of the ancient quarrel; Plato’s Socrates was concerned to argue that there are extrinsic reasons - to do with reason, truth, psychological health, and morality - why it should be so dependent, which its own internal dynamic is prone to resist; and much of this applies also to rhetoric. Next there is the level of discourse about particular texts, interpreting, comparing and appraising, which we call literary criticism; to the extent that this discourse is characteristically designed to persuade it may be classified as a form of rhetoric, and philosophical analysis of rhetoric has an impressive pedigree; even in its most austerely analytical mode there remains scope for philosophy to submit the arguments of literary critics to logical and linguistic analysis. Then there is the level of theorisation about literature; the great philosophical landmarks here are Aristotle’s Poetics with its development of the notion of mimesis, and Kant’s Critique of Judgement where such theorisation becomes subsumed under general aesthetics, but there are a number of other elements. From the philosophical side there is the tradition of hermeneutics, with its bearing on the principles of interpretation of literary texts, and the perennial debate between dialectic and rhetoric with its recent deconstructive twist running in sometimes strange channels as it becomes incorporated into literary practice and theorising 5 deconstruction as encountered in literary departments is often several stages removed from Derrida. On the literary side there is the recurrent resistance to appraisal by philosophic protocols and procedures, from those noted by Plato - not only in the Republic but also in the Ion and, more sympathetically, in the Phaedrus - through (to take just English examples) Keats’s Lamia and Shelley’s Defence of Poetry, to F.R. Leavis’s insistence that literary criticism’s engagement with the concrete experience of poetry is wholly distinct from and independent of the abstractions of philosophy3. However it should be noted that there is at least a case for maintaining that any such claims to the autonomy, including independence from philosophy, of a discipline or practice are themselves philosophical in character. So far as the teaching of philosophy in this context is concerned, much depends on the level of interconnection with literature in question - and much also of course on the literary experience, scholarly background and overall sophistication of the students to be taught. With respect to the latter aspect Aristotle’s well-known concern that ethics should not be taught to those without sufficient experience to grasp what is at stake and judge accordingly can be extended to poetics and, more generally, to philosophical engagements with literature and literary criticism. Barren logicchopping or empty theorising without serious engagement with literature, and lacking a personal background of honest attempts to interpret, appraise and share one’s responses to it, are not merely unprofitable but also capable of impoverishing one’s capacity to be enriched by literature and develop an educationally invaluable capacity - recently characterised by Frank Kermode as ‘an appetite for poetry’4. It is in part for this reason that I have chosen to focus on teaching at university level, both undergraduate and graduate, for university students of literature may reasonably be expected to have significant literary experience and some appetite for literature on which philosophical probing can work and which what I have called philosophy’s ‘Socratic’, subversive, heritage can unsettle to the students’ benefit rather than lasting loss. As Aristotle remarked in the case of ethics, however, this is not a matter of age but of experience (Nicomachean Ethics 1095a); some are ready for philosophical exploration of their literary experience and discourse about it well before university studies, and it is unfortunately the case that some university students 6 of literature are not; the ease with which a significant number of students are seduced by quasi-philosophical literary theory into transforming what appetite for poetry they may have had into a delight in theoretical abstractions concerning - and often deflationary towards - literature is a testimony to the dangers here, analogous to too early an exposure to the more subversive elements of moral philosophy leading students to lose what unsteady grip they may have had on the difference between right and wrong. With this caveat, I shall turn now to consideration of ways in which philosophy may be brought to bear on the study of literature, primarily at first degree level but with some reference to how this might be built on in Master’s programmes. To do this it will be necessary to take account of the differential layering of philosophy’s relation to literature, and experience suggests that it makes educational sense to mark some separation between philosophical consideration of discourse about literature (roughly, literary criticism, historical contextualisation, and poetics or ‘theory’) and consideration of literature at the primary level of literary texts (and where appropriate their performance) themselves. Since the latter type of consideration necessarily involves the former, it is wise to start by considering the status and variety of discourse about literature before moving on - self-reflexively - to engaging in it. This is the order that will be observed here. III Philosophy, remarked Aristotle, begins in puzzlement (Metaphysics 982b), and unless there is something problematic in a student’s engagement with literature which is already a matter of concern, or which he or she can be readily brought to see as such, it may be well for that student to steer clear of philosophy in this context. However in most students’ experience the status of their discourse with others about literature, and their reading of the critics, throws up questions about objectivity. On the one hand attempts are made to share responses and perceptions, often with some degree of success, while on the other full agreement seems always a mirage. 7 Students are inducted into a ‘canon’ of literature which appears to incorporate some degree of settled stability of comparative valuation, yet exposure to historical scholarship shows that canon shifting while most are aware of strong contemporary cultural currents (concerning gender, race and more traditional political concerns) seeking to reshape or downgrade established canons. Again, attempts to understand complex works of literature lead to apparently competing interpretations, often seeming equally plausible, together with a sense that all are somehow inadequate. Such considerations may lead students to doubt the value of discourses concerning literary appraisal and interpretation, or to see them simply as elements in a form of cultural politics where norms are partly determined by persuasive success; correctness of evaluation or interpretation, from this perspective, is relative to a given group of the like-minded, and canonicity (of value or interpretation) determined by the most powerful group; which group, if any should have such power is not a literary matter. But for many such devaluing of the integrity of their literary responses and discourse is at best unwelcome and at worst rings false; the analogy with ethics is obvious enough. Once one’s questioning has reached this level it has touched on philosophy, and the teaching of philosophy to students thus puzzled is not an impertinence. There are at least three levels, of apparently decreasing generality, at which philosophy can usefully operate here. The first is to set such concerns in the context of general sceptical considerations of which that sketched above is a species. The analogy with ethics has already been remarked but of course the issue is a more general epistemological one, relating to the types of agreement and warrant it is appropriate to seek for conclusions in different contexts. The Aristotelian perception that ‘it is the mark of an educated man to look for precision in each class of things just so far as the nature of the subject admits’ (Nicomachean Ethics 1094b) has an obvious bearing on the problems about interpretation and, as for canonicity, the shifts brought about in literary canons (for example from ‘classic’, though ‘romantic’ to ‘modern’ literature) may be instructively paralleled by interpretations of the history of the physical sciences in terms of ‘paradigm shifts’; the extent to which the phenomena pointed to by the latter term can - or cannot - be accommodated within non-relativist models of 8 the philosophy of science may point students to seek analogies in the history and their experience of literature. The second level is that of aesthetics, and here an introduction to the Kantian notion of judgements coming within the category of the ‘taste of reflection’ whose topic is, ultimately, the beautiful (see Part I of Kant’s Critique of Judgement) can be instructive. His account of the aspiration to the assent of everyone or ‘universal voice’ which we nevertheless cannot postulate, as we could in the case of an ordinary empirical judgement, picks up that sense of claiming something beyond our own perceptions - that the response which is the ground of our judgement is somehow appropriate, that that which we perceive should also be perceptible by others - which is part of the experience of the students in their articulation of their perceptions and rereading of literary texts in the light of what they hear and read about them. A consideration of the status of such judgements, of the aesthetic as a category between pure subjectivity or relativity on the one hand and hard empirical verification or refutation on the other, is plainly relevant to such students’ condition. And this can properly lead to consideration of the particular norms, characteristic moves and even ‘paradigms’ employed in literary criticism; of the varying roles of mimesis and expression in different types of literature and its associated criticism; of the Aristotelian criteria of necessity and probability, Keatsean ‘negative capability’, the aspirations of symbolist poetry and so on. More generally, one may seek to untangle the different strands of what William Righter has pointed to as the enduring end of criticism: ‘opening up as much of the work as one can, and relating as much as seems relevant to both literary and personal situation’.5 While the orientation of teaching at the first two levels is primarily towards content, at this third level both content and method are involved, the latter in both the ‘Aristotelian’ and ‘Socratic’ modes. And here what at first seemed to involve decreasing generality, as we focus down on specifically literary discourse, by a counter-movement opens up as its different strands connect with other ranges of discourse. Thus Leavis’s insistence upon literary criticism’s concrete particularity (as contrasted with the theoretical abstractions of philosophy) connects with that ancient 9 philosophical problem of the One and the Many. The evaluative inferences made in the best criticism have sometimes been argued to be criteriological rather than deductive or inductive,6 such that where A is a criterion for B it is necessarily the case that A is evidence for B - that necessity arising from the relation of the concepts in question; such suggestions clearly bring in their train a whole host of issues not simply in general value theory but in the philosophy of logic and - indeed - epistemology and the philosophy of mind. The problems about interpretation raise, on the one hand, issues about their status (are they descriptive - and if so probabilistic or otherwise - or evaluative or performative?) and, on the other, issues in the philosophy of language concerning their connections with questions about meaning more generally: What are the relations between questions concerning the meaning of a poem and those concerning the meaning of the words making it up? In either case what role, if any, does author’s or utterer’s meaning play - or, indeed, matters concerning illocutionary force? Do any such considerations sponsor a principled distinction between objective meaning and subjective significance? How does the meaning of ‘poetic’ language such as metaphor - relate to ‘literal’ language? And of course behind all such matters of interpretation loom the more general issues traditionally the concern of hermeneutics. Even with an agenda thus developed, major contemporary currents in poetics remain unaddressed. Some - such as certain forms of feminism or marxism - are associated with forms of criticism that may usefully be addressed in the terms already given; but other forms of these, together with distinct intellectual movements such as deconstruction, propose their own categories of rationality which need to be explored and engaged at a broader philosophical level. So at this stage it is worth stepping back and considering how one might structure the teaching of a programme that thus ramifies. One is faced here with the problem of the relation between scope and the time available. If one takes seriously the requirement that one is teaching philosophy to literature students no more than half their study time should be taken up with philosophical input; on the other hand, much less than this is likely to involve serious oversimplification or shallowness. This provides a case for an undergraduate degree 10 where the literary and philosophical elements are fairly evenly balanced - either a joint (dual) programme or a major/minor structure with the ‘minor’ element maximised. One such structure, with which I have been involved, that has worked well is a three-year joint programme where the philosophical components in the first year include logic and the philosophy of language, an introduction to general problems of scepticism, and some value theory including aesthetics. Scholarly background in the history and contemporary context of literature, literary criticism and its concepts is properly furnished as part of the literary component - as well, of course, as the study and discussion of literary texts - and towards the end of that year an enquiry is launched into reflection, in the light of the other studies, on the procedures and status of literary criticism. This enquiry can be profitably pursued through dialectical interchange - not infrequently subversive of the orthodoxies - between literary and philosophical instructors into which the students are drawn in discussion seminars, ranging over the issues sketched above, so that neither the literary nor the philosophical voice is marginalised. I have sometimes found it pedagogically effective, as an aid to self-reflection, to observe earlier in the year practical criticism classes in which the students are participating, analyse what is said in sequence, and then ask them to reflect on the nature of the moves made and the status of the claims proposed, as part of this enquiry. Courses in later years can engage more fully with aesthetics - perhaps the most obvious point at which philosophical ‘content’ bears directly on the study of literature -developing for example the Kantian framework in its wider ramifications, as well as wider study of the classic philosophers and the standard discussions of scepticism, truth and value theory. Here or at Master’s level there is scope for serious engagement with such contemporary intellectual currents as deconstruction - which requires preparatory background at least in terms of Nietzsche, Husserl, Saussure and Heidegger. Especially, though not only, in literary contexts deconstruction also draws on the long tradition of rhetorical scholarship and has serious engagement with traditions of hermeneutics, but undergraduate degrees should not be overloaded. I have found it convenient to teach not only hermeneutic theory but also the theory and 11 practice (including literary practice) of rhetoric - the latter in dialogue with a scholar of literature - as part of Master’s programmes. IV Thus far the primary level of direct philosophical consideration of literary texts, where philosophy and literature’s ancient quarrel takes its rise, has only been touched on by implication. In the programme I have been sketching the issue is adumbrated towards the end of the first year by including literary texts with their own rhetorical and philosophico-theological agendas among those with which the literary criticism discussed deals (such texts as Rochester’s ‘Satire Against Mankind’, Johnson’s ‘Vanity of Human Wishes’, Wordsworth’s ‘Ode: Intimations of Immortality’ and Stevens’s ‘Sunday Morning’). But full engagement is delayed until the final year when the students have experience in reading and discussing in a wide variety of literary genres, as well as a grounding in the history of philosophy and contemporary philosophical discussions and techniques, together with experience of reading philosophical texts. And here, to avoid taking sides in that quarrel, the investigation is carried on using the technique of dialectical exchange mentioned above, with both literary and philosophical instructors involved and the students themselves participating in the light of their own responses to the texts in question; the discussions have been most fruitful when we have kept closest to the texts. Also, in order not to skew the agenda to one side or the other, we have not only considered literary texts concerned with issues that also come within the province of philosophy, but philosophical texts with an eye to their literary (most obviously rhetorical) elements, and also texts - from Plato to Nietzsche and beyond - which have a foot in each camp. Despite its evident inadequacies one may use as an expository device in the classification of texts the analogy of a spectrum. The philosophical end may be defined in terms of overlapping issues and methods, where the truth or falsity of propositions about issues traditionally regarded as ‘philosophical’ is argued for by standard patterns of logical inference, and all non-logical elements are placed in subordinate position. It is rare, one notes, for this ideal to be fully realised in major texts and even apparently paradigm cases (such as Spinoza’s Ethics or Kant’s 12 Critiques) gain much of their power from their ‘non-logical’ elements: capacity to illuminate experience remains significant even in the face of ‘geometric’ austerity, and where this is so one is dealing with issues important to literary critics. As one moves toward the centre of the spectrum different elements of the philosophical end’s defining features drop away. Perhaps most often we have texts where the truth or falsity of ‘philosophical’ issues is the centre of concern, but the standard logical models are downgraded or abandoned. Other more ‘literary’ devices are employed in a persuasive role so that matters may be placed, for example, ‘in a fresh light’. There is room here for wide variety; Plato’s Phaedrus comes to mind, as do (with reservations) Pascal’s Pensées, Dickens’s Hard Times, Nietzsche’s Zarathustra and Sartre’s La Nausée; we have also experimented with different genres - dialogue, aphorism, philosophical fiction, philosophical poetry and even the philosophical autobiography. In all such cases the concern to persuade about the truth or falsity of the issues involved challenges the philosopher to rational assessment, but such an assessment can only be carried through by means of a thorough understanding of the nature of the rhetoric involved, which traditionally comes within the purview of the literary critic. The literary end of the spectrum is characterised in terms of distinctive forms of language use, expressive, emotive, indirect, imagistic. euphonic, fictive, generic, depending on the level of analysis. Only the last category applies intrinsically to the philosophical end, and that in a subordinate position as the genre that is specified by the appropriate concerns and procedures. At the generic level poems, plays and novels are the classic literary forms. Other genres are regarded as ‘literary’ in so far as either they are closely analogous to the traditional forms or if they exhibit certain merits that are customarily associated with them, and a crucial role of literary criticism is the discrimination of such merits. Since literary criticism is centrally concerned with the relation between how a thing is said and what is said, it may be employed wherever form/content relations are at issue; thus it may explore and even claim in the name of literary merit philosophical works (for example, Hobbes’s Leviathan) far removed from the traditional genres. And just as literary criticism may be appropriate in the case of clearly philosophical works, so philosophical probing - laying bare and 13 assessing the framework of assumptions which render a text intelligible - may sometimes be in point even with regard to texts far towards the literary end of the spectrum, belonging to one of the traditional genres and without overt philosophical pretensions. It has been our experience that, over wide ranges of material, discussion of texts incorporating the approaches of both philosophy and literary criticism have been mutually reinforcing and organically related. It is notorious that philosophical debates do not wholly fit the standard logical models (if they did, they would soon be satisfactorily resolved) and detailed attention to the manner in which they are carried on is an essential element in the philosopher’s attempts at rational assessment. On the other hand, it has been a recurrent complaint that literary criticism tends either to ignore its own assumptions or else to read models constructed a priori into the texts it considers; thus the practice of examining and criticising assumptions which are either embedded in, or integrally related to, the close reading of particular texts provides one way of coming to terms with a perennial critical difficulty: how to retain the integrity of one’s sensibility and freshness of one’s response without pleading theoretical innocence. Such teaching requires intense and extended discussion, with detailed attention to texts, scholarly contextualisation, critical perception and philosophical sophistication, in all aspects of which the students should be invited to participate. Here the seminar discussion must take priority over the lecture. In such contexts we should be less concerned to teach philosophy to another discipline than to incorporate it in the educational process - less with instruction than with paideia; further, the separation between the pursuit and the teaching of philosophy is here particularly problematic. The instructional work elsewhere in the programme is essential, but the aim of the process should be to help the students to think clearly, read discriminatingly, respond with integrity and judge wisely for themselves - to find their own balance between ‘Aristotelian’ order and ‘Socratic’ disruption. But what of the quarrel? Recognition of rhetoric, and indeed metaphor, in the text of philosophy should only lead us to collapse or deconstruct the difference between 14 philosophy and literature, or declare victory to the poets, if the picture of philosophy as a ‘rigorous’ discipline, with ‘rigour’ defined in terms of deduction more geometrico holds us captive. Study of the sort I have outlined helps students to see that this is too simple and schematic. The geometric model for philosophy is but partial; important philosophical argument is inevitably to be assessed in part by such criteria as capacity to ‘illuminate experience’ and so on; thus part of philosophical education should be to help students explore these criteria and integrate them into their overall accounts of rationality. Such considerations lay behind a remark that impeccably analytic philosopher, John Wisdom, put into the mouth of an exuberant character in one of his philosophical dialogues: ‘Logic is rhetoric, proof persuasion, and philosophy logic played with especially elastic equations’;7 neither he nor his character saw this as justifying a retreat from the ideal of proof to that of conversation with the abandonment of truth as a regulative ideal in the manner recently popularised by Richard Rorty.8 Rather, rhetoric is reconceived as a suitable tool for philosophical self-analysis, and for this to be possible on Wisdom’s terms it is necessary to discriminate rational from non-rational forms of persuasion without simply falling back on the well known procedures of deduction and induction. Here ancient traditions of rhetorical analysis and more modern procedures of hermeneutics and literary criticism may all, inter alia, have their part to play. The point is reinforced if we consider what I described as texts towards the centre of the spectrum. Here the obvious question arises of whether, and if so how, the rhetorical strategy of such a text is apt for its particular concern with truth. Such questions can only be adequately answered if we explore the nature of the text’s rhetoric, together with the relations between its form and what it is seeking to say and for these explorations we need to employ procedures conventionally associated with literary criticism. Here we have urgently forced upon us meta-questions about how far the rationality of an argument may be separated from the manner of its presentation, together with questions about the canons appropriate to assessing its rationality; but if the difficulty of distinguishing between rigorous argument and rhetorical persuasion is as all-pervasive as I have suggested, then these mid-spectrum questions apply to all texts which are concerned with philosophical issues, and one of the leading criteria for distinguishing between mid-spectrum and properly 15 philosophical texts collapses. So, too, does any bar to philosophical probing of the rhetorical power of literary texts with their own persuasive designs upon us, and exploration of the relations between rational and poetic force. Reason and imagination, it may begin to appear, are interdependent both in imaginative literature and in philosophy. And this is increasingly being recognised. A number of contemporary philosophers have brought to philosophical prominence the capacity of literature rationally to illuminate experience in such ways as to properly modify our ways of seeing the world. Bernard Harrison argues for the capacity of literature ‘to unhinge and destabilise ... Great Truths’9 , Tristram Shandy being a notable example. Stanley Cavell takes seriously the categories developed by literary criticism to help us grasp and assess the capacities of imaginative literature to transform our understanding and sensibility, playing (for example) Coleridge’s ‘Rime of the Ancient Mariner’ off Kant’s account of the noumenal, and Shakespeare against scepticism.10 Martha Nussbaum argues more specifically for an interdependence between literature and moral philosophy, maintaining that each needs the other, from concerns with the fragility of goodness engaged by the great Greek philosophers and tragedians to the twentieth-century explorations of the texture of human relationships found in the novels of Henry James.11 Exposure to such philosophers’ sensitive and attentive handling of literary and philosophical texts, together with consideration of the conceptions of philosophising such handling presupposes, endorses and serves to develop, may help students to grasp the variety of modes of seeking clarity and precision, and also of subversion, that may be legitimate within philosophy, and to see the point of Bernard Williams’s claim that serious philosophical works are themselves imaginative achievements, that failure to achieve what is required may well show itself in failings which attract the kinds of criticism applicable to imaginative literature, not only those familiar from the standard range of philosophical criticisms: ‘Philosophy needs virtues of literature and should fear failing in ways that literature can fail.’12 Behind the Republic’s exclusion of the poets lies a certain model of philosophy as dialectic which alone can yield knowledge, conveyed in language which contains only 16 terms that are perfect images of realities; and the relations between these terms, relations embedded in the logic of this form of discourse, must precisely mirror those that hold between the elements of reality itself. The analogies with the linguistic model of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus are not accidental, and the philosophical pull of such an idealisation seems to be perennial, often associated with the concern for clarity, precision and rigour. Given it, the poets in their pretensions to understand and teach about the most important things in life are indeed ‘liars by profession’ or - as the logical positivists would have it - purveyors of nonsense. But Plato himself recognised some of the problems with this ideal; if no image is identical with that whose image it is, perhaps the notion of a perfect image is ultimately devoid of sense; and since dialectic is dependent on language the dialectical ideal is itself problematic. One notes that he himself wrote in dialogue form, incorporating the ‘Socratic’, subversive, element as well as the ‘Aristotelian’ quest for rational ordering. In the Phaedrus we are presented by Plato’s Socrates with a vision that unites the philosopher, the lover of wisdom, with the lover of beauty under the sign of devotion to the Muses - though that devotion, we find, still involves engaging in a form of dialectic as well as an idealised rhetoric. Whether that represents his final vision is controversial, as is whether it should be ours. Ancient enmities still run deep. But the sorts of philosophical pedagogic engagement with literature that I have sketched may so help in the formation of our students’ paideia that if, ultimately, they decide that rapprochement is not possible, that aspiration to common content remains subverted by irreducible differences of method, their judgement will be informed, understanding and respect will reach across the battle-lines, and we may be spared the melancholy spectacle that characteristically ensues when ‘ignorant armies clash by night’.13 17 Notes W.B. Yeats, ‘What Then?’, from Last Poems (1936-39), in his Collected Poems, London: Macmillan, 1961. 1 See for example, Jacques Derrida, ‘La mythologie blanche’, Poétique 5, 1971; English translation as ‘White mythology’ in his Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass, Brighton: Harvester Press, 1982. 2 F.R. Leavis, ‘Literary criticism and philosophy’, Scrutiny 6, 1937; reprinted in his The Common Pursuit, Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin 1962. See also his ‘“Thought” and emotional quality’, Scrutiny 13, 1945; reprinted in his A Selection from Scrutiny, vol. 1, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968. 3 4 Frank Kermode, An Appetite for Poetry: Essays in Literary Interpretation, London: Collins 1989; see especially the prologue and first chapter. 5 William Righter, Logic and Criticism, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963, p. 84. 6 See, for example, John Casey, The Language of Criticism, London: Methuen, 1966, chap. 8, especially sect. 2. John Wisdom, ‘Other minds IV’, Mind 50, 1941, p 215; reprinted in his Other Minds, Oxford: Blackwell, 1952, p. 86. 7 8 Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press & Blackwell, 1980. 9 Bernard Harrison, Inconvenient Fictions: Literature and the Limits of Theory, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991, p. 11. 10 Stanley Cavell, In Quest of the Ordinary: Lines of Skepticism and Romanticism, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988, chaps. 2-4; Disowning Knowledge: In Six Plays of Shakespeare, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987; see also The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979, especially part 4. 11 Martha C. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986; Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990. Bernard Williams, ‘Philosophy and the imagination’; paper presented to the conference After the Revolution: The Future of Analytic Philosophy at the University of Warwick, March 1996. 12 13 Closing words of ‘Dover Beach’ by Matthew Arnold, first published 1867. 18