PhD Course Voting and Political Debate Lecture 7 Francesco Squintani University of Warwick email: f.squintani@warwick.ac.uk 1 Information Aggregation and Optimal Structure of the Executive Model • There is a set K = {1, ..., K} of politicians and of policy choices. • Each agent i ∈ K has ideology bi ; b = {b1 , ..., bn }, b1 ≤ ... ≤ bn . • Decision making is assigned according to a : K → K. ai is the number of choices assigned to agent i. • In the common-state model, the state θk is common across k and equals θ, uniformly distributed on [0, 1]. • In the policy-specific information model, θk are i.i.d. across k and uniformly distributed on [0, 1]. 2 • Each politician k receives a private signal sk ∈ {0, 1} about θk , with Pr(sk = 1|θk ) = θk . • If conversations are private, each politician i sends a possibly different message m̂ij ∈ {0, 1} to any other politician j. • If meetings are public, any player i sends a public message m̂i . • After communication, policies ŷk ∈ ℜ chosen by politicians a(k). • The payoff of politician i facing action profile ŷ and states θk is ∑ ui (ŷ, θ) = − (ŷk − θk − bi )2 k∈K Politicians are ideological about all policy choices. 3 • A pure communication strategy is mi (si ) = {miN }N ∈Ni (g) . When miN (si ) = si , i communicates truthfully to audience N . • A communication strategy profile is m = {m1 , ..., mn }, where mi : {0, 1} → {0, 1}|Ni | . • The strategy m defines the equilibrium communication network c(m): • A policy strategy by i is yk : {0, 1}|N̄i | × {0, 1} → [0, 1] for all k = a−1 (i), where N̄i is the set of players communicating with i. 4 • Our solution concept is pure-strategy Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium. • A pure strategy mij : {0, 1} → {0, 1} is either truthful, if mij (si ) = si , or babbling, if mij (si ) is independent of si . Given the strategy profile m, define the factional network c with cij = 1 if and only if mij is truthful — and cii = 1. • By sequential rationality, the equilibrium decisions are: yk = ba(k) + E[θk |da(k),k (c), la(k),k (c)] 1. di,k (c) is i’s equilibrium information on θk : the number of signals on θk held by i, including her own; 2. li,k (c) is the equlibrium number of realizations equal to one. 5 • Because of Beta-binomial updating: li,k + 1 E[θk |di,k , li,k ] = di,k + 2 • Our welfare function is ex-ante weighted Utilitarian ∑ ∑ − γi E[(yk − θk − bi )2 ] i∈K k∈K where γi is the weight of player i. • We let politician j ’s moderation be the distance between bj and the average ideology ∑I i=1 γi bi . 6 Two Forces • By a mean-variance decomposition, the ex-ante welfare is: [ ] ∑ ∑ 1 2 − γi (bi − ba(k) ) + 6[da(k),k (c) + 2] k∈K i∈K • The first term in the square parenthesis is the aggregate ideological loss, the second term is the residual variance. Proposition 1. The optimal selection of the assignemnt a involves considering two forces: politicians’ moderation and information. • Intuitively, moderate policiticians lower the aggregate ideological loss, whereas informed politicians lower the residual variance. 7 Factional Network: Private Conversations Lemma 1 (GGS, 2010). Suppose that the state θ is common, and communication private. The profile m is an equilibrium if and only if, whenever i is truthful to j, 1 |bi − bj | ≤ 2[dj (c) + 2] • i’s capability to communicate is independent across players. • i’s capability to communicate with j declines with: – their bias difference and, – how many other players communicate truthfully with j . 8 Optimal Executive – Private Conversations Proposition 2. For generic biases b, any optimal assignment is centralized to a single leader j, i.e., a(k) = j for all k. • Intuition: ∈ a(K), the maximal equilibrium in-degree dj (c) is independent of the set of tasks assigned to player j. – For any j – Maximizing the welfare function is equivalent to finding the index j that minimizes I ∑ i=1 1 γi (bj − bi ) + . 6(dj (c) + 2) 2 9 Factional Network: Public Meetings Lemma 2 (GGS, 2010). Suppose that the θ is common, and communication is public.The strategy m is equilibrium if and only if for all i communicating truthfully ∑ ∑ γj (c) bi − , bj γj (c) ≤ j∈K\{i} 2[dj (c) + 2] j∈K\{i} where aj /[dj (c) + 2] γj (c) = ∑ j ′ ∈K\{i} aj ′ /[dj ′ (c) + 2] • i’s capability to communicate depends on a weighted average of all the biases of the players. 10 Optimal Executive – Public Meetings Consider a simple example: There are 4 players, with b1 = −β, b2 = ε, b3 = β, and b4 = 2β, where ε is small. For β < 1/24 or β > 1/18, it is optimal to select 2 as the leader. For β ∈ (1/24, 1/21), 3 decisions are optimally given to 2 and one to 3. For β ∈ (1/21, 1/18), 2 decisions are given to 2 and 3 each. • In fact, for β < 1/24, all players are fully informed; • for β > 1/8, there is no truthful communication; • for β ∈ (1/24, 1/18), player 4 is willing to talk to 2 and 3 publicly, and not to 2 privately; • for β ∈ (1/24, 1/21), player 4 talks even if 2 is assigned 3 tasks. 11 Private Conversations vs. Public Meetings Proposition 4. For generic ideologies b, the optimal assignment with public meetings dominates all assignments with private conversations. Intuition: • Under the conditions of Proposition 2, the optimal assignment with private conversations selects a single leader. • When a single leader is selected, private conversations and public meetings coincide. • Hence, public meetings cover private conversations. 12 Optimal Executive – Public Meetings: Large Governments The key result is that, as the number of politicians becomes large, the fraction of decisions assigned to politicians close to the most moderate politician becomes one. Proposition 5 Suppose that biases bj , j = 1, ..., I are i.i.d. and drawn from a distribution with connected support. For every small δ > 0, there exists a possibly large Iδ > 0 so that for all I > Iδ , the fraction of decisions in the optimal assignment that are not concentrated to politicians with biases b such that |b − mI | < δ is smaller than δ, ∑I 1 b where mI = arg mini=1...I bi − I j=1 j . 13 Intuition: • We first prove that, as the number of politicians becomes large, allocating all decisions to the most moderate politician aggregates all information. • We then show that any possible informational gain is dominated by an ideological loss, if assigning decisions to politicians significantly distant from the most moderate one. Note that this does not necessarily imply that all decisions are assigned to the most moderate politician, as the number of politicians explodes. There may still be informational gains at small ideological loss, when assigning decisions to politicians close to the most moderate one. 14 Public Meetings – Small Government: Numerical Simulations We ran simulations with I = 7 politicians, and biases b drawn i.i.d. from skew normal distributions of variance σ 2 and skewness γ . Authority is highly concentrated to the leader: at least 5.51 decisions out of 7 are given to the leader. Cabinet executive significantly improves upon Ministerial government. The fraction of draws for which all decisions is allocated to the leader may be as low as 36 %. Both quantities are U-shaped in the variance of the bias distribution. The skewness seems not to have a major effect. 15 γ=0 γ = 1/4 γ = 1/2 γ = 3/4 γ=1 σ 2 = 10 7.00 7.00 7.00 6.99 7.00 σ2 = 1 6.91 6.93 6.89 6.91 6.88 σ 2 = 0.1 6.17 6.21 6.18 6.16 6.21 σ 2 = 0.01 5.58 5.51 5.53 5.68 5.67 σ 2 = 0.001 6.35 6.35 6.37 6.49 6.35 σ 2 = 0.0001 7.00 7.00 7.00 7.00 7.00 Average number of decisions assigned to the leader. 16 γ=0 γ = 1/4 γ = 1/2 γ = 3/4 γ=1 σ 2 = 10 1.00 1.00 1.00 0.99 1.00 σ2 = 1 0.95 0.96 0.93 0.95 0.92 σ 2 = 0.1 0.57 0.60 0.58 0.61 0.62 σ 2 = 0.01 0.40 0.36 0.36 0.41 0.45 σ 2 = 0.001 0.70 0.70 0.74 0.78 0.69 σ 2 = 0.0001 1.00 1.00 1.00 1.00 1.00 Fraction of draws where all decisions are assigned to the leader. 17 Factional Network – Policy Specific Knowledge Proposition 5. Suppose that θk are i.i.d. across k. The profile (m, y) is an equilibrium if and only if, whenever i is truthful to j = a(i), |bi − bj | ≤ 1/6 • Intuition: – Independently of the form of communication, there is only one signal to communicate to a single player. – Hence there is no communication congestion. – Nor the average bias in the audience matters. 18 Optimal Executive – Policy Specific Knowledge Corollary 2. With policy specific knowledge, private and public communication coincide. Proposition 6. When knowledge is policy specific, each decision k is assigned to either the most moderate politician m∗ or to m(k), the most moderate politician with bias within 1/6 of bi , depending on whether ( )2 ∑I 2 ∗ [ b − b ]/I − [(b − b ) ]/I < (>)1/36. i i m m(k) i=1 i=1 ∑I The tradeoff is between the most moderate politician m∗ and the most moderate informed politician m(k). 19 Proposition 7. Despite policy specific knowledge, full decentralization is never optimal for generic ideologies b. A leadership of the few naturally arises even in the presence of policy specific information. ∑I ∗ Proposition 8. If there is a politician m with bm∗ = i=1 bi /I, then each decision k such that |bk − bm∗ | ∈ (0, 1/6] ∪ [1/3, ∞] is optimally assigned to m∗ . This result uncovers an interesting non-monotonicity, that suggests that the most moderate politician makes a large fraction of decisions. 20 Policy Specific Knowledge – Simulations γ=0 γ = 1/4 γ = 1/2 γ = 3/4 γ=1 σ 2 = 10 6.96 6.95 6.97 6.97 6.97 σ2 = 1 6.70 6.73 6.69 6.81 6.74 σ 2 = 0.1 5.97 5.90 5.90 5.86 5.75 σ 2 = 0.01 6.59 6.54 6.53 6.57 6.55 σ 2 = 0.001 7.00 7.00 7.00 7.00 7.00 σ 2 = 0.0001 7.00 7.00 7.00 7.00 7.00 The average number of decisions assigned to the leader is not smaller than in the common state model. 21