8000 P E L

advertisement
8000
PUBLIC ENFORCEMENT OF LAW
A. Mitchell Polinsky
Stanford University
Steven Shavell
Harvard University
© Copyright 1999 A. Mitchell Polinsky and Steven Shavell
Abstract
This chapter discusses the theory of the public enforcement of law - the use of
public agents (inspectors, tax auditors, police, prosecutors) to detect and to
sanction violators of legal rules. We first present the basic elements of the
theory, focusing on the probability of imposition of sanctions, the magnitude
and form of sanctions, and the rule of liability. We then examine a variety of
extensions of the central theory, including accidental harms, costs of imposing
fines, mistake, marginal deterrence, settlement, self-reporting, repeat offenses
and incapacitation.
JEL classification: K14, K42
Keywords: Law Enforcement, Crime, Deterrence
1. Introduction
In this chapter we consider the theory of the public enforcement of law - the use
of public agents (inspectors, tax auditors, police, prosecutors) to detect and to
sanction violators of legal rules. Of course, private parties also play an
important role in law enforcement, by providing information to public
authorities and also by initiating their own legal actions (notably, tort suits), but
to maintain focus we restrict attention here to public enforcement activity. (On
private enforcement, see generally Landes and Posner, 1987, and Shavell,
1987c; and on private versus public enforcement, see Becker and Stigler, 1974;
Landes and Posner, 1975, and Polinsky, 1980a.)
In Sections 2 through 4, we present the basic elements of the theory of
public enforcement of law. Our concern is with the probability of imposition of
sanctions, the magnitude and form of sanctions, and the rule of liability. In
Sections 5 through 16 we then examine a variety of extensions of the central
theory, including accidental harms, costs of imposing fines, mistake, marginal
deterrence, settlement, self-reporting, repeat offenses and incapacitation.
307
308
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Before proceeding, we note that economically-oriented analysis of public
law enforcement dates from the eighteenth century contributions of
Montesquieu (1748), Beccaria (1770), and, especially, Bentham (1789), whose
analysis of deterrence was sophisticated and expansive. But, curiously, after
Bentham (1789), the subject of enforcement lay essentially dormant in
economic scholarship until the late 1960s, when Becker (1968) published a
highly influential article, which has led to a voluminous literature.
2. The Basic Framework
An individual (or a firm) chooses whether to commit an act that for simplicity
is assumed to cause harm with certainty (see Section 5 on uncertain harm). If
he commits the act, he obtains some gain, and also faces the risk of being
caught, found liable and sanctioned. The rule of liability could be either strict under which the individual is definitely sanctioned - or fault-based - under
which he is sanctioned only if his behavior fell below a fault standard. The
sanction that he suffers could be a monetary fine, a prison term, or a
combination of the two.
Whether an individual commits a harmful act is determined by an expected
utility calculation. He will commit the act if that would raise his expected
utility, taking into account the gain he would derive and the probability, form,
and level of sanction that he would then face. We will usually first examine the
assumption that individuals are risk neutral with respect to sanctions, that is,
that they treat an uncertain sanction as equivalent to its expected value; but we
will also consider alternative assumptions.
Social welfare generally is presumed to equal the sum of individuals’
expected utilities. An individual’s expected utility depends on whether he
commits a harmful act, on whether he is a victim of someone else’s harmful
act, and on his tax payment, which will reflect the costs of law enforcement,
less any fine revenue collected. If individuals are risk neutral, social welfare
can be expressed simply as the gains individuals obtain from committing their
acts, less the harms caused, and less the costs of law enforcement. (The
assumption that individuals’ gains always are credited in social welfare could
be relaxed without affecting most of our conclusions. The principal difference
that altering the assumption would make is that more acts would be treated as
socially undesirable and that optimal sanctions and enforcement effort would
increase.)
We assume, as is conventional, that fines are socially costless to employ
because they are mere transfers of money (but in Section 6 we consider fines
that are costly to impose), whereas imprisonment involves positive social costs
because of the expense associated with the operation of prisons and the
disutility due to imprisonment (which is not naturally balanced by gains to
others).
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
309
The enforcement authority’s problem is to maximize social welfare by
choosing enforcement expenditures or, equivalently, a probability of detection,
the level of sanctions and their form (a fine, prison term, or combination), and
the rule of liability (strict or fault-based).
3. Optimal Enforcement Given the Probability of Detection
We consider here optimal enforcement given the assumption that the
probability of detection is fixed (the probability will be treated as a policy
instrument in the next section). Thus, we ask about the optimal form and level
of sanctions under strict and fault-based liability, and about how the two
liability rules compare.
Strict Liability
Assume initially that fines are the form of sanction and that individuals are risk
neutral. Then the optimal fine is the harm h divided by the probability of
detection p, that is, h/p; for then the expected fine equals the harm (observe that
p(h/p) = h). If, for example, the harm is $1,000 and the probability of detection
is 25 percent, the optimal fine is $4,000, and the expected fine is $1,000. This
fine is optimal because, when the expected fine equals the harm, an individual
will commit a harmful act if, but only if, the gain he would derive from it
exceeds the harm he would cause. Essentially this basic and fundamental
formula was noted by Bentham (1789, p. 173) and it has been observed by
many others since.
If individuals are risk averse with regard to fines, one would expect the
optimal fine to be lower than in the risk-neutral case for two reasons. First, this
reduces the bearing of risk by individuals who commit the harmful act. Second,
because risk-averse individuals are more easily deterred than risk-neutral
individuals, the fine does not need to be as high as before to achieve any desired
degree of deterrence. (However, for subtle reasons that we will not address here,
the optimal fine could, in principle, be higher when individuals are risk averse.)
Next assume that imprisonment is the form of sanction, with social costs
incurred in imposing sanctions. In this case, there is not a simple formula for
the optimal imprisonment term (see Polinsky and Shavell, 1984). The optimal
term could be such that there is either underdeterrence or overdeterrence,
compared to socially ideal behavior. On one hand, a relatively low
imprisonment term, implying underdeterrence, might be socially desirable
because it means that imprisonment costs are reduced for those individuals who
commit harmful acts. On the other hand, a relatively high term, implying
overdeterrence, might be socially desirable because it means that imprisonment
costs are reduced due to fewer individuals committing harmful acts, even if
310
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
some of these deterred individuals would have obtained gains exceeding the
harm. (The possible optimality of overdeterrence strikes us as more theoretical
than real, however.)
Now consider the combined use of fines and imprisonment. Here, the main
point is that fines should be employed to the maximum extent feasible before
resort is made to imprisonment. In other words, it is not optimal to impose a
positive imprisonment term unless the fine is maximal. (The maximal fine
might be interpreted as the wealth of an individual.) The rationale for this
conclusion is that fines are socially costless to impose, whereas imprisonment
is socially costly, so deterrence should be achieved through the cheaper form
of sanction first. This point is noted by Bentham (1789, p. 183) and Becker
(1968, p. 193); see also Polinsky and Shavell (1984). To amplify, suppose that
the fine f is less than the maximal fine fm and that a positive prison term t is
employed. Raise f toward fm and lower t so as to keep the disutility of the
combined sanctions constant. Then deterrence and the amount of harm will not
change, but the cost of imposing the imprisonment sanction will fall, raising
social welfare. Hence, it must be optimal for the fine to be maximal before
imprisonment is used. (Observe that this argument holds regardless of
individuals’ attitudes toward risk of either fines or imprisonment.)
Fault-Based Liability
Assume again that fines are the form of liability. Then the same formula for the
fine that we said was optimal under strict liability - namely, h/p, the harm
divided by the probability of detection - will lead to compliance with the fault
standard (assuming that the fault standard is optimally selected). For example,
suppose that the harm is $1,000, and that an individual would be found at fault
if he failed to take a precaution costing less than $1,000 that could have
prevented the harm. Furthermore, suppose such a precaution exists that costs
$700. If the probability of detection is 25 percent, then a fine of $4,000 for
being at fault would induce the individual to take a precaution costing less than
$1,000; in particular, he would prefer to spend $700 on the precaution and
escape liability than not to take the precaution and bear an expected fine of
$1,000.
Observe that the optimal fine of $4,000 in the preceding example is not
unique. Any higher fine also would induce compliance with the fault standard,
as would some lower fines (as long as the expected value of the fine exceeds
$700, or whatever is the expense of the precaution that costs less than $1,000).
Note that higher fines do not lead to a problem of overdeterrence because
parties can escape fines by complying with the fault standard. (However, if
mistakes occur in the legal process, they might be induced to spend excessively
on precautions; see Section 8 below).
If individuals are risk averse, they are more easily deterred than if they are
risk neutral, so the fine does not need to be as high to induce compliance with
the fault standard. Moreover, assuming that compliance occurs, no one actually
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
311
is sanctioned because no one is found at fault (assuming, as we do here, that
there are no mistakes). Thus, fault-based liability has the attractive feature that
it can accomplish desired deterrence of harm-creating conduct without
imposing risk on risk-averse individuals (Shavell, 1982).
Next, consider imprisonment as the sanction; see Shavell (1987a). Here, for
essentially the reasons given in the case of fines, any sanction above a threshold
level will ensure compliance with the fault standard, and the minimum sanction
necessary to induce compliance is higher the lower is the probability of
detection. Also (Shavell, 1985), fault-based liability again can accomplish
deterrence without the actual imposition of sanctions, which would be socially
costly.
Finally, consider the joint use of fines and imprisonment. In this case, it
does not matter what the combination of sanctions is, provided that the
sanctions achieve compliance with the fault standard. In particular, it is not
advantageous for society to employ maximal fines before resorting to
imprisonment because compliance means that sanctions are never imposed.
Comparison of Liability Rules
Because sanctions are not imposed under fault-based liability (in the absence
of mistakes), this form of liability has an advantage over strict liability when
the sanction is the fine and individuals are risk-averse, or when the sanction is
imprisonment. However, fault-based liability is more difficult to administer.
Namely, to apply fault-based liability, the enforcement authority must have
more information than under strict liability: it must be able to calculate optimal
behavior to determine the fault standard and it must ascertain whether the fault
standard was met. Under strict liability, the authority need only ascertain harm.
(Moreover, for reasons we discuss in Section 7 below, strict liability encourages
better decisions by injurers regarding their level of participation in
harm-creating activities.)
4. Optimal Enforcement Including the Probability of Detection
We now consider the optimal system of enforcement when expenditures on
enforcement, and hence the probability of detection, are allowed to vary.
Consideration of this issue originated with Becker (1968); the early writers on
enforcement (including Bentham, 1789) did not examine the issue of the choice
of enforcement effort.
Strict Liability
Assume first that the sanction is a fine and that individuals are risk neutral.
Then the optimal level of the fine is maximal and the optimal probability is low
312
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
(in a sense to be described). The basic explanation for this conclusion is that if
the fine were not maximal, society could save enforcement costs by
simultaneously raising the fine and lowering the probability without affecting
the level of deterrence. Suppose, for example, that the fine initially is $4,000
and that the probability of detection is 25 percent. Now raise the fine to
$10,000, presuming that the maximal fine is at least this high, and lower the
probability of detection to 10 percent. Then the expected fine remains equal to
$1,000, so that deterrence is maintained, but expenditures on enforcement are
significantly reduced, implying that social welfare rises. This process can be
continued, and social welfare augmented, as long as the fine is below the
maximal level fm. Becker (1968) suggested this result (although much of his
analysis implicitly presumes that the fine is not maximal); Carr-Hill and Stern
(1979, pp. 280-309) and Polinsky and Shavell (1979) note it explicitly.
The optimal probability is low in that there is some underdeterrence; that
is, the optimal p is such that the expected fine pfm is less than the harm h
(Polinsky and Shavell, 1984). The reason for this result is that if pfm equals h,
behavior will be ideal, meaning that the individuals who are just deterred
obtain gains essentially equal to the harm. These are the individuals who would
be led to commit the harmful act if p were lowered slightly. That in turn must
be socially beneficial because these individuals cause no net social losses
(because their gains essentially equal the harm), but reducing p saves
enforcement costs. How much pfm should be lowered below h depends on the
saving in enforcement costs from reducing p compared to the net social costs
of underdeterrence that will result if p is lowered non-trivially.
If individuals are risk averse, the optimal fine generally is less than
maximal, as first shown in Polinsky and Shavell (1979) (and elaborated upon
in Kaplow, 1992). This is because the use of a very high fine would impose a
substantial risk-bearing cost on individuals who commit the harmful act.
Another more particular explanation involves reconsidering the argument that
we used in the risk-neutral case. If the fine f is less than fm, it is still true that
f can be raised and p lowered so as to maintain deterrence, but because of risk
aversion, this implies that pf falls, meaning that fine revenue falls. The
reduction in fine revenue reflects the disutility caused by imposing greater risk
on risk-averse individuals. If individuals are sufficiently risk averse, the decline
in fine revenue associated with greater risk-bearing could more than offset the
savings in enforcement expenditures from reducing the probability of detection,
implying that social welfare would be lower.
Next, assume that the sanction is imprisonment and that individuals are risk
neutral in imprisonment, that is, the disutility of imprisonment is the same for
each additional year. (We did not discuss individuals’ attitudes toward the risk
of imprisonment in Section 3 because the points we made there did not depend
on this consideration.) Then the optimal imprisonment term is maximal
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
313
(Shavell, 1991b). The reasoning behind this result parallels that used to show
that the optimal fine is maximal when individuals are risk neutral in fines.
Specifically, if the imprisonment term is raised and the probability of detection
lowered so as to keep the expected sanction constant, neither individual
behavior nor the costs of imposing imprisonment are affected (by construction,
the expected prison term is the same), but enforcement expenditures fall.
Suppose instead that individuals are risk averse in imprisonment. In other
words, the disutility of each year of imprisonment grows with the number of
years in prison, perhaps because imprisonment becomes increasingly difficult
to tolerate. In this case there is a stronger argument for setting the
imprisonment sanction maximally than when individuals are risk neutral
(Polinsky and Shavell, 1997). This is because, when the imprisonment term is
raised, the probability of detection can be lowered even more than in the
risk-neutral case without reducing deterrence. Thus, not only are there greater
savings in enforcement expenditures, but also the social costs of imposing
imprisonment sanctions decline because the expected prison term falls.
Last, suppose that individuals are risk preferring in imprisonment, that is,
the disutility of each year of imprisonment falls with the number of years in
prison. This assumption seems particularly important: the first years of
imprisonment may create special disutility, due to brutalization of the prisoner,
or due to the stigma effect of having been imprisoned at all. Additionally, the
fact that individuals discount the future disutility of imprisonment makes
earlier years of imprisonment more important than later ones. If individuals are
risk preferring in imprisonment, the optimal sanction may well be less than
maximal (Polinsky and Shavell, 1997). In particular, the type of argument used
above does not necessarily apply. When the sanction is raised, the probability
that maintains deterrence cannot be lowered proportionally, implying that the
expected prison term rises. Because the resulting increased cost of imposing
imprisonment sanctions might exceed the savings in enforcement expenditures
from lowering the probability, the optimal prison term might not be maximal.
When the probability of detection is set optimally, together with the
imprisonment term, underdeterrence may well result, not only to save
enforcement expenditures, but also to reduce the costs of imposing
imprisonment sanctions. (In theory, however, overdeterrence could be optimal
for the reason mentioned in Section 3 - that overdeterrence could reduce the
costs of imprisonment.)
Now consider the situation when both fines and imprisonment are employed
as sanctions. Recall that under the optimal enforcement policy, the fine must
be maximal, for otherwise it cannot be desirable to employ imprisonment. The
main point we wish to make is that, unlike when imprisonment is used alone,
the optimal imprisonment term may not be maximal even if individuals are risk
neutral or risk averse in imprisonment. Suppose that individuals are risk
314
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
neutral in imprisonment and fines. Then if the imprisonment term is raised and
the probability of detection is lowered so as to keep the expected imprisonment
term constant, deterrence declines because the expected fine falls (due to the
reduction in the probability). Hence, to maintain deterrence, the probability
cannot fall proportionally. But this implies that the expected prison term, and
the costs of imposing imprisonment, are higher than previously. Only if the
savings in enforcement costs are sufficiently large, therefore, is it socially
desirable to raise the imprisonment sanction.
Fault-Based Liability
The least expensive way to accomplish compliance with the fault standard is
to use the highest possible sanction and, given this sanction, the lowest
probability of detection that deters individuals who would be at fault. The
reason is that, if all individuals who would be at fault are deterred, the only cost
incurred is associated with the setting of the probability; this cost is minimized
by using the maximal sanction and a correspondingly low probability. Note that
this is true regardless of whether the sanction is a fine or imprisonment and
regardless of individuals’ attitudes toward the risk of fines or of imprisonment.
Comparison of Rules
As we emphasized earlier, under fault-based liability sanctions are not actually
imposed (in the absence of mistakes), which is an advantage over strict liability
when the sanction is a fine and individuals are risk averse, and is always an
advantage when the sanction is imprisonment. Moreover, this advantage of
fault-based liability implies a second advantage: it may allow a further savings
in enforcement expenditures over that under strict liability. For example,
suppose that the sanction is a fine and that injurers are risk averse. Then, as we
have emphasized, the optimal fine under strict liability generally is not
maximal, due to risk-bearing by injurers. This implies that the probability of
detection needed to achieve any given level of deterrence is higher than if the
fine were maximal. Under fault-based liability, however, the optimal fine is
maximal despite the risk aversion of injurers (because the fine is not actually
imposed), meaning that a lower probability can be employed. However, to
decide which liability rule is preferable, these advantages of fault-based liability
would have to be weighed against the disadvantages of this rule relative to strict
liability that we mentioned at the end of Section 3 (one of which, as noted, will
be discussed in Section 7).
This concludes the presentation of the basic theory of public enforcement of
law. We now turn to various extensions and refinements of the analysis.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
315
5. Accidental Harms
As we noted at the outset, we assumed that individuals decide whether or not
to commit acts that cause harm with certainty, that is, they decide whether or
not to cause intentional harms. In many circumstances, however, harms are
accidental - they occur only with a probability. For instance, if a driver speeds,
he only creates a likelihood of a collision; or if a firm stores toxic chemicals in
a substandard tank, the firm only creates the probability of a harmful spill.
Essentially all that we have said above applies in a straightforward way
when harms are accidental. If individuals are risk neutral, sanctions are
monetary, and the expected sanction equals harm, then induced behavior will
be socially optimal; further, the optimal magnitude of sanctions is maximal if
individuals are risk neutral because this allows enforcement costs to be saved;
and so forth. Our general conclusions from above can thus be interpreted to
apply both when harms are intentional and cause harm for sure, as well as
when actions alter the risk of harm.
There is, however, an additional issue that arises when harm is uncertain:
a sanction can be imposed either on the basis of the commission of a dangerous
act that increases the chance of harm - storing chemicals in a substandard tank
- or on the basis of the actual occurrence of harm - only if the tank ruptures
and results in a spill. In principle, either approach can achieve optimal
deterrence. To illustrate, suppose that the substandard tank has a 10 percent
chance of rupturing, in which case the harm would be $10 million; the expected
harm from using the tank therefore is $1 million. If injurers are risk neutral and
sanctions are imposed only when harm occurs, deterrence will be optimal if, as
usual, the expected sanction equals the harm of $10 million. Alternatively, if
sanctions are imposed on the basis of the dangerous act of using the
substandard tank, deterrence will be optimal if the owner of the tank faces an
expected sanction equal to the expected harm due to his use of the substandard
tank, $1 million.
Several factors are relevant to the choice between act-based and harm-based
sanctions (Shavell, 1993). First, act-based sanctions need not be as high to
accomplish a given level of deterrence, and thus offer an underlying advantage
over harm-based sanctions because of limitations in parties’ assets. In the
example in the preceding paragraph, the owner of the storage tank might be
able to pay the $1 million required if sanctions are act-based but not the
$10 million required if sanctions are harm-based. Second, and closely related,
because act-based sanctions need not be as high to accomplish deterrence, they
offer an advantage over harm-based sanctions when parties are risk averse.
Third, act-based sanctions and harm-based sanctions may differ in the ease
with which they can be applied. In some circumstances, act-based sanctions
may be simpler to impose (it might be less difficult to determine whether an oil
shipper properly maintains its vessels’ holding tanks than to detect whether one
316
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
of the vessels leaked oil into the ocean); in other circumstances, harm-based
sanctions may be easier (a driver who causes harm might be caught without
difficulty, but not one who speeds). Fourth, it may be hard to calculate the
expected harm due to an act, but relatively easy to ascertain the actual harm if
it eventuates; if so, this constitutes an advantage of harm-based liability.
6. Costs of Imposing Fines
We inquire in this section about the implications of costs borne by enforcement
authorities in imposing fines. Our principal observation is that such costs
should raise the level of the fine.
We assume for simplicity that the probability of detection is fixed, that
liability is strict, and that individuals are risk neutral. In this setting, recall
from Section 3 that the optimal fine is h/p, the harm divided by the probability
of detection.
Now let there be a public cost k of imposing a fine. The optimal fine then
becomes h/p + k; the cost k should be added to the fine that would otherwise be
desirable (Becker, 1968, p. 192 and Polinsky and Shavell, 1992). The intuition
behind this result is that, if an individual commits a harmful act, he causes
society to bear not only the immediate harm h, but also, with probability p, the
cost k of imposing the fine - that is, his act results in an expected total social
cost of h + pk. If the fine is h/p + k, the individual’s expected fine is p[(h/p) +
k] = h + pk, leading him to commit the harmful act if and only if his gain
exceeds the expected total social cost of his act.
For example, suppose the harm is $1,000, the probability of detection is 25
percent, and the cost of imposing the fine is $500. An individual’s harmful act
causes society to bear expected total social costs of $1,125 - the harm of $1,000
plus a 25 percent chance of the $500 cost of imposing a fine. If the fine is set
equal to $4,500, the individual’s expected fine also will equal $1,125.
Additionally, observe that, not only does the state bear costs when fines are
imposed, so do individuals who pay the fines (such as legal defense expenses).
The costs borne by individuals, however, do not affect the formula for the
optimal fine. Individuals properly take these costs into account, because they
bear them.
7. Level of Activity
We have been assuming that the sole decision that an individual makes is
whether to act in a way that causes harm when engaging in some activity. In
many contexts, however, an individual also makes a choice about his activity
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
317
level - that is, not only does he choose whether to commit a harmful act when
engaging in an activity, he also chooses whether to engage in that activity or,
more generally, at what level to do so. For example, besides deciding how to
behave when driving (whether to exercise care in changing lanes), an
individual also chooses how many miles to drive; the number of miles driven
is the individual’s level of activity. Similarly, not only does a firm decide how
to conduct its operations during production (whether to pollute), it also chooses
its level of production; the output of the firm is its level of activity.
The socially optimal activity level is such that the individual’s marginal
utility from the activity just equals the marginal expected harm caused by the
activity. Thus, the optimal number of miles driven is the level at which the
marginal utility of driving an extra mile just equals the marginal expected harm
per mile driven. The determination of the optimal level of activity presumes
that individuals act optimally when engaging in the activity - for example, that
they drive with appropriate care. Thus, in determining the optimal level of
activity, an individual’s marginal utility from the activity is compared to the
expected harm that results when he acts appropriately when engaging in the
activity. Often this expected harm is positive even when a party acts optimally,
because the cost of precautions (or, equivalently, the gain or savings from not
taking precautions) exceeds the expected reduction in harm that taking the
precautions would bring about.
Will parties’ choices about their activity levels be socially correct under the
two major forms of liability? The answer is that under strict liability, their
choices about activity levels will be correct, but under fault-based liability, they
generally will participate in activities to a socially excessive extent. Under strict
liability, parties will choose the optimal level of activity because they will pay
for all harm done. They will choose the optimal number of miles to drive
because they will pay for all harm per mile driven. Under fault-based liability,
however, parties generally do not pay for the harm they cause because, as we
have discussed, they will be induced to behave so as not to be found at fault.
Consequently, when deciding on their level of activity, they will choose an
excessive level. They will not take into account the harm that each additional
mile of driving causes, and therefore they will drive too much.
The interpretation of the preceding points in relation to firms is that under
strict liability the product price will reflect the expected harm caused by
production, so that the price will reflect the full social cost of production.
Hence, the amount purchased, and thus the level of production, will tend to be
socially optimal. However, under fault-based liability, the product price will not
reflect harm, but only the cost of precautions; thus, the amount sold, and the
level of production, will be excessive.
A related comment is that safety regulations and other regulatory
requirements are often framed as standards of care that have to be met, but
318
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
which, if met, free the regulated party from liability. Hence, regulations of this
character are subject to the criticism that they lead to excessive levels of the
regulated activity. Making parties strictly liable for harm would be superior to
safety regulation with respect to inducing socially correct activity levels.
The tendency of parties to choose an excessive level of activity under
fault-based liability, but not under strict liability, constitutes a fundamental
advantage of strict liability; it was first emphasized in Shavell (1980) and
Polinsky (1980b). This advantage, note, is stronger the greater is the harm
engendered by engaging in the activity (given that behavior is optimal when
engaging in the activity). Thus, for activities for which expected harm is likely
to be substantial, the disadvantage of fault-based liability will be significant.
8. Mistakes
Errors of the two classic types can occur in public enforcement of law. First, an
individual who should be found liable might mistakenly not be found liable - a
Type I error. Second, an individual who should not be found liable might
mistakenly be found liable - a Type II error. For an individual who has been
detected, let the probabilities of these errors be 01 and 02, respectively.
Given the probability of detection p and the chances of Type I and Type II
errors, an individual will commit the wrongful act if and only if his gain g net
of his expected fine if he does commit it exceeds his expected fine if he does not
commit it, namely, when g ! p(1 ! 01)f > ! p02f, or, equivalently, when g > (1
! 01 ! 02)pf.
The first point to note is that, as emphasized in Png (1986), both types of
error reduce deterrence: the term (1 ! 01 ! 02)pf is declining in both 01 and 02.
The first type of error diminishes deterrence because it lowers the expected fine
if an individual violates the law. The second type of error, when an individual
is mistakenly found liable, also lowers deterrence because it reduces the
difference between the expected fine from violating the law and not violating
it. In other words, the greater is 02, the smaller the increase in the expected fine
if one violates the law, making a violation less costly to the individual.
Because mistakes dilute deterrence, they reduce social welfare (see generally
Kaplow and Shavell, 1994a). Specifically, to achieve any level of deterrence,
the probability p must be higher to offset the effect of errors. It should also be
noted that, were one to take into account an individual’s decision whether to
engage in an activity (like driving), Type II errors have the additional effect of
discouraging socially desirable participation in the activity.
Now consider the optimal choice of the fine. Given any probability of
detection, the dilution in deterrence caused by errors requires a higher fine to
restore deterrence. If the probability and the fine are variable, then, as
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
319
explained in Section 4, the optimal fine is maximal. Somewhat surprisingly, the
optimal fine remains maximal despite mistakes, by essentially the argument
used previously: if the fine f were less than maximal, then f could be raised and
the probability p lowered so as to keep deterrence constant, but saving
enforcement costs.
Now consider the possible risk aversion of individuals. As we emphasized
in Section 4, the optimal fine under strict liability generally is less than
maximal when individuals are risk averse, because lowering the fine from the
maximum level reduces the bearing of risk. Introducing the possibility of
mistakes may increase the desirability of lowering the fine because, due to
Type II errors, individuals who do not violate the law are subject to the risk of
having to pay a fine (Block and Sidak, 1980). Indeed, because the number of
persons who do not violate the law often would far exceed the number who do,
the desire to avoid imposing risk on the former group can lead to a substantial
reduction in the optimal fine.
Next, consider imprisonment and mistake. In this regard, our conclusions
parallel those with respect to fines in several respects. Notably, mistakes of both
types dilute the deterrent effects of imprisonment; and the optimal
imprisonment term is maximal if individuals are risk neutral or risk averse in
imprisonment but generally is not maximal if they are risk preferring in
imprisonment.
We have not yet commented on fault-based liability. Here, an important
implication of mistake is that some individuals will bear sanctions even if they
comply with the fault standard. Hence, the results regarding the optimal
probability of detection and the sanction under strict liability apply to some
extent under fault-based liability as well. Moreover, as stressed by Craswell and
Calfee (1986), individuals will often have a motive to take excessive
precautions in order to reduce the chance of being found erroneously at fault.
Finally, observe that, although we have treated the probabilities of error as
fixed, they can be influenced by procedural choices. For example, prosecutorial
resources can be increased in order to reduce the probability of a Type I error,
or the standard of proof can be raised to reduce the chance of a Type II error
(although this presumably increases Type I errors). Because the reduction of
both types of error increase deterrence, expenditures made to reduce errors may
be socially beneficial (Kaplow and Shavell, 1994a).
9. General Enforcement
In many settings, enforcement may be said to be general in the sense that
several different types of violations will be detected by an enforcement agent’s
activity. For example, a police officer waiting at the roadside may notice a
driver who litters as well as one who goes through a red light or who speeds,
and a tax auditor may detect a variety of infractions when he examines a tax
320
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
return. To investigate such situations, suppose that a single probability of
detection applies uniformly to all harmful acts, regardless of the magnitude of
the harm. (The contrasting assumption is that enforcement is specific, meaning
that the probability is chosen independently for each type of harmful act.)
The main point that we want to make is that in contexts in which
enforcement is general, the optimal sanction rises with the severity of the harm
and is maximal only for relatively high harms; this point was first made in
Shavell (1991b) (Mookherjee and Png, 1992a is closely related). To see this,
assume that liability is strict, the sanction is a fine, and injurers are risk neutral.
Let f(h) be the fine given harm h. Then, for any given general probability of
detection p, the optimal fine schedule is h/p, provided that h/p is feasible;
otherwise - for high h (all h such that h/p > fm) - the optimal fine is maximal.
This schedule is obviously optimal given p because it implies that the expected
fine equals harm, thereby inducing ideal behavior, whenever that is possible.
The question remains whether it would be desirable to lower p and raise
fines to the maximal level for the low-harm acts for which h/p is less than
maximal. The answer is that if p is reduced for the relatively low-harm acts
(and the fine raised for them), then p - being general - is also reduced for the
high-harm acts for which the fine is already maximal, resulting in lower
deterrence of these acts. The decline in deterrence of high-harm acts may cause
a greater social loss than the savings in enforcement costs from lowering p. To
express this point differently, p must be sufficiently high to avoid significant
underdeterrence of high-harm acts (for which fines are maximal). But since this
p also applies to less harmful acts, the fines for them do not need to be maximal
in order to appropriately deter them.
The result that, when enforcement is general, sanctions should rise with the
severity of harm up to a maximum also holds if the sanction is imprisonment
and if liability is fault-based. The underlying reasoning is the same as that
given above.
10. Marginal Deterrence
In many circumstances, a person may consider which of several harmful acts
to commit, for example, whether to release only a small amount of a pollutant
into a river or a large amount, or whether to kidnap a person or also to kill the
kidnap victim. In such contexts, the threat of sanctions plays a role in addition
to the usual one of attempting to deter individuals from committing harmful
acts: for individuals who are not deterred, sanctions influence which harmful
acts individuals choose to commit. Notably, such individuals will have a reason
to commit less harmful rather than more harmful acts if expected sanctions rise
with harm. Deterrence of a more harmful act because its sanction exceeds that
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
321
for a less harmful act is sometimes referred to as marginal deterrence (it
apparently was so named by Stigler, 1970).
Other things being equal, as observed by Beccaria (1770, p. 32) and
Bentham (1789, p. 171), it is socially desirable that enforcement policy creates
marginal deterrence, so that those who are not deterred from committing
harmful acts have a reason to moderate the amount of harm that they cause.
This suggests that sanctions should rise with the magnitude of harm and,
therefore, that sanctions should not generally be maximal. However, fostering
marginal deterrence may conflict with achieving deterrence generally: in order
for the schedule of sanctions to rise steeply enough to accomplish marginal
deterrence, sanctions for less harmful acts may have to be so low that
individuals are not deterred from committing some harmful act.
We have two additional observations to make about marginal deterrence.
First, marginal deterrence can be promoted by increasing the probability of
detection as well as the magnitude of sanctions. For example, kidnappers can
be better deterred from killing their victims if more police resources are devoted
to apprehending kidnappers who murder their victims than to those who do not.
(But in circumstances in which enforcement is general, the probability of
detection cannot be independently altered for acts that cause different degrees
of harm.) Second, marginal deterrence is naturally accomplished if the expected
sanction equals harm for all levels of harm; for if a person is paying for harm
done, he will have to pay appropriately more if he does greater harm. Thus, for
instance, if a polluter’s expected fine would rise from $100 to $500 if he dumps
five gallons instead of one gallon of waste into a lake, where each gallon causes
$100 of harm, his marginal incentives to pollute will be correct. For formal
analyses of marginal deterrence, see Shavell (1992), Wilde (1992), and
Mookherjee and Png (1994).
11. Principal-Agent Relationship
Although we have assumed that an injurer is a single actor, injurers often are
more appropriately characterized as collective entities, and specifically as a
principal and the principal’s agent. For example, the principal could be a firm
and the agent an employee; or the principal could be a contractor and the agent
a subcontractor.
When harm is caused by the behavior of principals and agents, many of the
conclusions of our prior analysis are not fundamentally altered; they simply
carry over to the sanctioning of principals. Notably, if a risk-neutral principal
faces an expected fine equal to harm done, he will in effect be in the same
position vis-à-vis his agent as society is vis-à-vis a single potential violator of
law (see Newman and Wright, 1990 on a closely related point). Consequently,
322
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
the principal will behave socially optimally in controlling his agents, and in
particular will contract with them and monitor them in ways that will give the
agents socially appropriate incentives to reduce harm (but see Arlen, 1994).
Another result that carries over to the principal-agent context is that it often
will be desirable for society to tolerate some degree of underdeterrence in order
to conserve enforcement resources.
A question about enforcement that arises when there are principals and
agents is the allocation of financial sanctions between the two parties. It is
apparent, however, that the particular allocation of sanctions does not matter
when, as would be the natural presumption, the parties can reallocate the
sanctions through their own contract. For example, if the agent finds that he
faces a large fine but is more risk averse than the principal, the principal can
assume it; conversely, if the fine is imposed on the principal, he will retain it
and not impose an internal sanction on the agent. Thus, the post-contract
sanctions that the agent bears are not affected by the particular division of
sanctions initially selected by the enforcement authority.
The allocation of monetary sanctions between principals and agents would
matter, however, if some allocations allow the pair to reduce their total burden.
An important example is when a fine is imposed only on the agent and he is
unable to pay it because his assets are less than the fine (see Sykes, 1981, and
Kornhauser, 1982). Then, he and the principal (who often would have higher
assets) would jointly escape part of the fine, diluting deterrence. The fine
therefore should be imposed on the principal rather than on the agent (or at
least the part of the fine that the agent cannot pay).
A closely related point is that the imposition of imprisonment sanctions on
agents may be desirable when their assets are less than the harm that they can
cause, even if the principal’s assets are sufficient to pay the optimal fine (see
Polinsky and Shavell, 1993). The fact that an agent’s assets are limited means
that the principal may be unable to control him adequately through use of
contractually-determined penalties, which can only be monetary. For example,
a firm may not be able, despite the threat of salary reduction or dismissal, to
induce its employees never to rig bids. In such circumstances, it may be socially
valuable to use the threat of personal criminal liability and a jail sentence to
better control agents’ misconduct.
12. Settlements
Although we have thus far assumed that when a liable injurer is discovered he
is sanctioned in some automatic fashion, in practice he must be found civilly
or criminally liable in a trial, and before this occurs, he commonly settles in
lieu of trial. (In the criminal context, the settlement usually takes the form of
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
323
a plea bargain, an agreement in which the injurer pleads guilty to a reduced
charge.) Given the prevalence of settlements, it is important to consider how
they affect deterrence and the optimal system of public enforcement, and
whether settlements are socially desirable.
There are two general reasons why parties might prefer an out-of-court
settlement to a trial (see generally the survey by Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1989;
and for some recent discussions of plea bargaining, see, for example,
Reinganum, 1988, and Miceli, 1996). First, a trial is costly to the parties in
terms of time and/or money. Second, settlements eliminate the risks inherent
in the trial outcome, a benefit to parties who are averse to such risks. These
advantages of settlement to the parties suggest that settlement is socially
valuable, but the effect of settlement on deterrence is a complicating factor.
Specifically, settlements dilute deterrence: for if injurers desire to settle, it
must be because the expected disutility of sanctions is lowered for them (see
generally Polinsky and Rubinfeld, 1988). The state may be able to offset this
settlement-related reduction in deterrence by increasing the level of sanctions;
if so, settlements need not compromise the overall level of deterrence.
Settlements may have other socially undesirable consequences. First, they
may result in sanctions that are not as well tailored to harmful acts as would be
true of court-determined sanctions. For example, if injurers have private
information about the harm that they have caused, settlements will tend to
reflect the average harm caused, whereas trial outcomes may better
approximate the actual harm. Thus, the distribution of sanctions meted out
through settlements will not be as good in terms of inducing injurers to take
proper precautions (high-harm injurers will be underdeterred, and vice versa).
Second, settlements hinder the amplification and development of the law
through the setting of precedents, a factor of occasional relevance; and
settlements also sometimes allow defendants to keep aspects of their behavior
secret, which can reduce deterrence. Third, settlements for prison terms can
result in increases in public expenditures on jail if defendants are risk averse
in imprisonment. On the social desirability of settlement, see, for example,
Shavell (1997a) and Spier (1997).
13. Self-Reporting
We have assumed that individuals are subject to sanctions only if they are
detected by an enforcement agent, but in fact parties sometimes disclose their
own violations to enforcement authorities. For example, firms often report
violations of environmental and safety regulations, individuals usually notify
police of their involvement in traffic accidents, and even criminals occasionally
turn themselves in.
324
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
We explain here why it is generally socially desirable for the structure of
enforcement to be such as to encourage self-reporting (see Kaplow and Shavell,
1994b). Self-reporting can be induced by lowering the sanction for individuals
who disclose their own infractions. Moreover, the reward for self-reporting can
be made small enough that deterrence is only negligibly reduced.
To amplify, assume for simplicity that the sanction is a fine f, that the
probability of detection is p, and that individuals are risk neutral. If an
individual commits a violation and does not self report, his expected fine is pf.
Suppose the fine if an individual self-reports is set just below pf, say at pf ! 0,
where 0 > 0 is arbitrarily small. Then the individual will want to self-report but
the deterrent effect of the sanction will be (approximately) the same as if he did
not self-report. For example, suppose that the fine if an individual does not self
report is $1,000 and that the probability of detection is 10 percent, so the
expected fine is $100. If the fine for self-reporting is slightly below $100, such
as $95, or even $99, individuals will self-report but deterrence will barely be
reduced.
Given that self-reporting can be induced essentially without compromising
deterrence, why is self-reporting socially advantageous? There are two basic
reasons. First, self-reporting reduces enforcement costs because, when it occurs,
the enforcement authority does not have to identify and prove who the violator
was. If a company reports that it caused pollution, environmental enforcers do
not need to spend as much effort trying to detect pollution and establishing its
source. Second, self-reporting reduces risk, and thus is advantageous if injurers
are risk averse. Drivers bear less risk because they know that if they cause an
accident, they can (and will be led to) report this to the police and suffer a
lower and certain sanction, rather than face a substantially higher sanction (for
hit and run driving) imposed only with some probability.
14. Repeat Offenders
In practice, the law often sanctions repeat offenders more severely than
first-time offenders. We explain here why such a policy may be socially
desirable.
Note first that sanctioning repeat offenders more severely cannot be socially
advantageous if deterrence always induces first-best behavior. If the sanction
for polluting and causing a $1,000 harm is $1,000, then any person who
pollutes and pays $1,000 is a person whose gain from polluting (say the savings
from not installing pollution control equipment) must have exceeded $1,000.
Social welfare therefore is higher as a result of his polluting. If such an
individual polluted and was sanctioned in the past, that only means that it was
socially desirable for him to have polluted previously. Raising the current
sanction because of his having a record of sanctions would overdeter him now.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
325
Accordingly, only if deterrence is inadequate is it possibly desirable to
condition sanctions on offense history to increase deterrence. But deterrence
often will be inadequate because, as we emphasized in Section 4, it will usually
be worthwhile for the state to tolerate some underdeterrence in order to reduce
enforcement expenses.
Given that there is underdeterrence, making sanctions depend on offense
history may be beneficial for two reasons. First, as developed in Polinsky and
Shavell (1996), the use of offense history may create an additional incentive not
to violate the law: if getting caught violating the law implies not only an
immediate sanction, but also a higher sanction for any future violation, an
individual will be more deterred from committing a violation presently. Second,
as studied, for example, in Rubinstein (1979) and Polinsky and Rubinfeld
(1991), making sanctions depend on offense history allows society to take
advantage of information about the dangerousness of individuals and the need
to deter them: individuals with offense histories may be more likely than
average to commit future violations, which might make it desirable for
purposes of deterrence to impose higher sanctions on them.
There is also an incapacitation-based (see Section 16) reason for making
sanctions depend on offense history. Repeat offenders are more likely to have
higher propensities to commit violations in the future and thus more likely to
be worth incapacitating by imprisonment.
15. Imperfect Knowledge about the Probability and Magnitude of
Sanctions
Although we have implicitly assumed that injurers know the probability and
magnitude of sanctions, this is not always the case. Individuals frequently have
imperfect knowledge of these variables; that is, they have estimates, or more
likely, subjective probability distributions, describing the true probability of a
sanction and its true magnitude. They might not know the true probability of
a sanction for several reasons: because the enforcement authority refrains from
publishing information about the probability (perhaps hoping that individuals
will believe it to be higher than it is in fact); because the probability is variable,
depending on factors that individuals do not fully understand (the probability
of a tax audit, for example, is influenced by a large number of considerations);
and because probabilities seem to be difficult for individuals to assess. Also,
individuals may have incomplete knowledge of the true magnitude of sanctions,
particularly if the magnitudes of sanctions are not fixed by law, but are to some
degree discretionary.
The implications of injurers’ imperfect knowledge are straightforward.
First, to predict how individuals behave, what is relevant, of course, is not the
326
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
actual probability and magnitude of a sanction, but the perceived levels or
distributions of these variables.
Second, to determine the optimal probability and magnitude of a sanction,
account must be taken of the relationship between the actual and the perceived
variables (on which, see, for instance, Bebchuk and Kaplow, 1992, and see
Kaplow, 1990b, on learning about sanctions). For example, suppose that there
is a delay of at least a year before individuals fully comprehend a change in the
probability of enforcement. Then if enforcement resources are increased so as
to make the probability, say, 15 percent rather than 10 percent, there might not
be a significant increase in deterrence for some time, making such an
investment less worthwhile. Or, for instance, suppose that the sanction for some
act, such as robbery, is variable (say from one month of jail time to 10 years),
and that individuals’ perceptions are quite rough, not based on true averages
but more on the possible range. Then increasing the average sentence might
have very little effect on deterrence, but increasing the probability substantially
might still augment deterrence. The psychology and learning process (see Sah,
1991) by which individuals assimilate and formulate perceived probabilities of
sanctions and their magnitude are important, therefore, to determining how
deterrence works and what optimal policy is.
16. Incapacitation
Our discussion of public enforcement has presumed that the threat of sanctions
reduces harm by discouraging individuals from causing harm - that is, by
deterring them. However, an entirely different way for society to reduce harm
is by imposing sanctions that remove parties from positions in which they are
able to cause harm - that is, by incapacitating them. Imprisonment is the
primary incapacitative sanction, although there are other examples: individuals
can lose their drivers licenses, preventing them from doing harm while driving;
businesses can lose their right to operate in certain domains, and the like. We
focus here on imprisonment, but what we say applies to incapacitative sanctions
generally; on the economic theory of incapacitation, see Shavell (1987b).
To better understand the role of public enforcement when sanctions are
incapacitative, suppose that the sole function of sanctions is to incapacitate; that
is, sanctions do not deter. (Deterrence might not occur if, for instance,
individuals’ gains from harmful acts exceed the expected sanctions, given the
relevant range of the probabilities and magnitudes of the sanctions.) We assume
that the social goal is as before, to maximize gains from acts less harm, and less
the costs of enforcement and sanctions, including the costs of keeping
individuals in prison.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
327
The optimal sanction to impose on an individual who is apprehended is
determined by comparing the expected harm, net of gains, he would cause if
not in prison to the private and public costs of imprisonment. If the expected
net harm exceeds the costs of imprisonment, he should be put in prison and
kept there as long as this condition holds. Thus, the optimal sanction as a
function of expected net harm is zero up to a threshold - the point at which
expected net harm equals the costs of imprisonment - and then rises
discontinuously to the length of time during which the person’s net expected
harm exceeds imprisonment costs. Jail should only be used to incapacitate
individuals whose net harm is relatively high.
Two points about the incapacitative rationale are worth making. First, there
is evidence that suggests that the expected harm caused by individuals declines
with their age. Thus, from the incapacitative standpoint, individuals should be
released from jail when their dangerousness falls below the cost of
incapacitation. Second, as a matter of logic, the incapacitative rationale might
imply that a person should be put in jail even if he has not committed a crime
- because his danger to society makes incapacitating him worthwhile. This
would be true, for example, if there were some means accurately to predict a
person’s dangerousness independently of his actual behavior. In practice,
however, the fact that a person has committed a harmful act may be the best
basis for predicting his future behavior, in which case the incapacitation
rationale would suggest imposing a jail term only if the individual has
committed an especially harmful act.
Last, we comment on the relationship between optimal enforcement when
incapacitation is the goal versus when deterrence is the goal. First, when
incapacitation is the goal, the optimal magnitude of the sanction is independent
of the probability of apprehension. In contrast, when deterrence is the goal, the
optimal sanction depends on the probability - the sanction generally is higher
the lower is the probability. Second, when incapacitation is the goal, the
sanction rises discontinuously with the magnitude of harm (from zero to a
positive amount), but when deterrence is the goal the sanction rises
continuously with harm. Third, when deterrence is the goal, the probability and
magnitude of sanctions depend on the ability to deter, and if this ability is
limited (as, for instance, with the enraged), a low expected sanction may be
optimal. However, a high expected sanction still might be called for to
incapacitate.
328
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
17. Conclusion
It may be worthwhile summarizing the main points that we have made in this
chapter:
(a) When the probability of detection is for some reason fixed, the
benchmark level of the optimal fine is the harm divided by the probability of
detection, for this results in an expected fine equal to the harm. However, costs
incurred by the public in collecting the fine should be added to the benchmark
level of the fine, and risk aversion of injurers should usually lower the level of
the fine.
(b) When the probability of detection may be varied, high sanctions may
be optimal, for this allows a relatively low probability to be employed and
thereby saves enforcement costs. Indeed, the optimal fine is in principle
maximal for this reason if individuals are risk neutral in wealth, and the
optimal imprisonment term is maximal if individuals are risk neutral or risk
averse in imprisonment. More realistically, optimal sanctions are not maximal
when individuals are risk averse in wealth or risk preferring in imprisonment
(as well as for the general enforcement reasons discussed in Section 9),
although the motive to set sanctions at relatively high levels in order to reduce
enforcement costs still applies.
(c) Optimal enforcement tends to be characterized by some degree of
underdeterrence relative to first-best behavior, because this conserves
enforcement resources. More precisely, by lowering the probability of detection
from a level that would lead to first-best behavior, the state reduces
enforcement costs, and although more individuals commit the harmful act,
these individuals do not cause social welfare to decline substantially because
their gains are nearly equal to the harm.
(d) The use of fines should be exhausted before resort is made to costlier
sanctions, notably imprisonment.
(e) An advantage of fault-based liability over strict liability is that costly
sanctions - fines when individuals are risk averse, and imprisonment - are
imposed less often: under fault-based liability, injurers generally are induced
(in the absence of mistakes) to obey fault standards, and therefore ordinarily do
not bear sanctions. Under strict liability, however, injurers are sanctioned
whenever they are caught.
(f) An advantage of strict liability over fault-based liability is that it is
easier to apply. Another advantage is that injurers’ activity-level decisions
generally will be better: under strict liability, injurers’ activity levels will tend
to be optimal because injurers will pay for harm that they cause. But under
fault-based liability, their activity levels will tend to be excessive because they
generally will not pay for harm that they cause (because they will be led to
behave without fault).
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
329
These and other basic conclusions about the public enforcement of law that
we have described in this essay are now, for the most part, well-established in
the economic literature on enforcement. However, an important aspect of this
subject that has received relatively little attention is the behavior of public
enforcers themselves. Because our focus was on deriving socially optimal public
enforcement policies, we assumed, as is conventional, that public enforcers act
so as to maximize social welfare. A logical step to take next would be to
re-examine optimal enforcement policies when public enforcers behave in a
self-interested manner. Although some effort already has been devoted to this
inquiry, much remains to be done.
Acknowledgments
Polinsky’s research was supported by the Center for Advanced Study in the
Behavioral Sciences (through National Science Foundation grant
#SBR-960123) and the John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics at
Stanford Law School. Shavell’s research was supported by the John M. Olin
Center for Law, Economics, and Business at Harvard Law School. This essay
previously appeared with a less comprehensive bibliography in Peter Newman
(ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and The Law, London,
Macmillan Reference Ltd. (1998).
Bibliography on Public Enforcement of Law (8000)
Adelstein, Richard and Miceli, Thomas J. (1997), ‘Toward a Comparative Economics of Plea
Bargaining’, Manuscript.
Allingham, Michael G. and Sandmo, Agnar (1972), ‘Income Tax Evasion: A Theoretical Analysis’,
1 Journal of Public Economics, 323-338.
Altrogge, Phyllis and Shughart, William F. (1984), ‘The Regressive Nature of Civil Penalties’, 4
International Review of Law and Economics, 55-66.
Andenaes, Johannes (1966), ‘The General Preventive Effects of Punishment’, 114 University of
Pennsylvania Law Review, 949-983.
Andenaes, Johannes (1971), ‘Deterrence and Specific Offenses’, 38 University of Chicago Law
Review, 537-553.
Andenaes, Johannes (1974), Punishment and Deterrence, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press.
Anderson, Lee G. and Lee, Dwight R. (1986), ‘Optimal Governing Instrument, Operation Level, and
Enforcement in Natural Resource Regulation: The Case of the Fishery’, 68 American Journal of
Agricultural Economics, 678-690.
Andreoni, James (1991), ‘Reasonable Doubt and the Optimal Magnitude of Fines: Should the Penalty
Fit the Crime?’, 22 RAND Journal of Economics, 385-395.
330
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Andreoni, James, Erard, Brian and Feinstein, Jonathan (1998), ‘Tax Compliance’, Journal of
Economic Literature, forthcoming.
Arlen, Jennifer A. (1994), ‘The Potentially Perverse Effects of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 23
Journal of Legal Studies, 833-867.
Arlen, Jennifer. (1997), ‘Corporate Crime and Its Control’, U.S.C. Law School Working Paper Series,
Working Paper No. 97-2, forthcoming in The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the
Law.
Arlen, Jennifer and Kraakman, Reinier (1997), ‘Controlling Corporate Misconduct: An Analysis of
Corporate Liability Regimes’, 72 New York University Law Review, 687-779.
Avio, Kenneth L. (1975), ‘Recidivism in the Economic Model of Crime’, 13 Economic Inquiry,
450-456.
Avio, Kenneth L. (1987), ‘Clemency in Economic and Retributive Models of Punishment’, 7
International Review of Law and Economics, 79-88.
Avio, Kenneth L. and Clark, C. Scott (1976), Property Crime in Canada: An Econometric Study,
Toronto, University of Toronto Press.
Ayres, Ian and Levitt, Steven D. (1998), ‘Measuring the Positive Externalities from Unobservable
Victim Precaution: An Empirical Analysis of Lojack’, Quarterly Journal of Economics,
forthcoming.
Baldry, Jonathan C. (1980), ‘Crimes Punishable by Imprisonment: A Note’, 9 Journal of Legal
Studies, 617-619.
Baldry, J.C. (1984), ‘The Enforcement of Income Tax Laws: Efficiency Implications’, 60 Economic
Record, 156-159.
Basu, Kaushik, Bhattacharya, Sudipto and Mishra, Ajit (1992), ‘Notes on Bribery and the Control of
Corruption’, 48 Journal of Public Economics, 349-359.
Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Kaplow, Louis (1992), ‘Optimal Sanctions When Individuals Are
Imperfectly Informed About the Probability of Apprehension’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies,
365-370.
Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘Optimal Sanctions and Differences in Individuals’
Likelihood of Avoiding Detection’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 217-224.
Beccaria, Cesare (1770), On Crimes and Punishments, and Other Writings. Bellamy, Richard (ed.),
Davies, Richard, et al. (trans.), New York, Cambridge University Press, 1995.
Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political
Economy, 169-217.
Becker, Gary S. and Landes, William M. (eds) (1974), Essays in the Economics of Crime and
Punishment, New York, Columbia University Press.
Becker, Gary S. and Stigler, George J. (1974), ‘Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of
Enforcers’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-18.
Ben-Shahar, Omri (1997), ‘Playing Without a Rulebook: Optimal Enforcement When Individuals
Learn the Penalty Only by Committing the Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and
Economics, 409-421.
Ben-Shahar, Omri and Harel, Alon (1995), ‘Blaming the Victim: Optimal Incentives for Private
Precautions Against Crime’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 434-455.
Ben-Shahar, Omri and Harel, Alon (1996), ‘The Economics of the Law of Criminal Attempts: A
Victim-Centered Perspective’, 145 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 299-351.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
331
Benson, Bruce L. and Baden, John (1985), ‘The Political Economy of Government Corruption: The
Logic of Underground Government’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 391-410.
Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong and Rasmussen, David W. (1994), ‘Estimating Deterrence Effects: A
Public Choice Perspective on the Economics of Crime Literature’,61 Southern Economic Journal,
161-168.
Bentham, Jeremy (1789), ‘An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation’, in The
Utilitarians, Rept. Garden City, NY, Anchor Books, 1973.
Besanko, David and Spulber, Daniel F. (1989), ‘Delegated Law Enforcement and Noncooperative
Behavior’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 25-52.
Block, Michael K. (1991), ‘Optimal Penalties, Criminal Law and the Control of Corporate Behavior’,
71 Boston University Law Review, 395-419.
Block, Michael K. and Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1986), ‘The Spillover Effect of Antitrust Enforcement’,
68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 122-131.
Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975a), ‘Crime and Punishment Reconsidered’, 4 Journal of
Legal Studies, 241-247.
Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975b), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crimes Punishable by
Imprisonment’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 479-492.
Block, Michael K. and Sidak, Joseph Gregory (1980), ‘The Cost of Antitrust Deterrence: Why Not
Hang a Price Fixer Now and Then?’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1131-1139.
Block, Michael Kent, Nold, Frederick Carl and Sidak, Joseph Gregory (1981), ‘The Deterrent Effect
of Antitrust Enforcement’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 429-445.
Bone, John (1985), ‘On Substituting a Socially Costless Penalty for Costly Crime’, 5 International
Review of Law and Economics, 239-246.
Bose, Pinaki (1995a), ‘Anticipatory Compliance and Effective Regulatory Activity’, 15 International
Review of Law and Economics, 151-159.
Bose, Pinaki (1995b), ‘Regulatory Errors, Optimal Fines, and the Level of Compliance’, 56 Journal
of Public Economics, 475-484.
Bowles, Roger and Garoupa, Nuno (1997), ‘Casual Police Corruption and the Economics of Crime’,
17 International Review of Law and Economics, 75-87.
Brown, William W. and Reynolds, Morgan O. (1973), ‘Crime and “Punishment”: Risk Implications’,
6 Journal of Economic Theory, 508-514.
Burnovski, Moshe and Safra, Zvi (1994), ‘Deterrence Effects of Sequential Punishment Policies:
Should Repeat Offenders be More Severely Punished?’, 14 International Review of Law and
Economics, 341-350.
Cadot, Olivier (1987), ‘Corruption as a Gamble’, 33 Journal of Public Economics, 223-244.
Cameron, Samuel (1988), ‘The Economics of Crime Deterrence: A Survey of Theory and Evidence’,
41 Kyklos, 301-323.
Cameron, Samuel (1989), ‘On the Welfare Economics of Capital Punishment’, 28 Australian
Economic Papers, 253-266.
Campbell, Donald T. and Ross, H. Laurence (1988), ‘The Connecticut Crackdown on Speeding:
Time-Series Data in Quasi-experimental Analysis’, in Overman, E. Samuel (ed.), Methodology
and Epistemology of Social Science: Selected Papers, Chicago and London, University of
Chicago Press, 222-237.
Carlin, Paul and Sandy, Robert (1990), ‘The Value of Time and the Effect of Fines on Child Car Safety
Seat Usage’, 22 Applied Economics, 463-476.
332
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Carr-Hill, R.A. and Stern, N.H. (1979), Crime, the Police and Criminal Statistics: An Analysis of
Official Statistics for England and Wales Using Econometric Methods, London, Academic Press.
Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1979), ‘Crime and Punishment with Possible Post-Offense Compromise’, 17
Academia Economic Papers, 131-167.
Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1990), ‘Plea Bargaining with the IRS’, 41 Journal of Public Economics, 319-333.
Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Proceedings in Civil-Law Countries’,
11 International Review of Law and Economics, 111-116.
Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1993), ‘Oscillatory vs. Stationary Enforcement of Law’, 13 International Review
of Law and Economics, 303-315.
Chu, C.Y. Cyrus and Jiang, Neville (1993), ‘Are Fines More Efficient than Imprisonment?’, 51
Journal of Public Economics, 391-413.
Chu, C.Y. Cyrus, Hu, Sheng-cheng and Huang, Ting-yuan (1997), ‘Punishing Repeat Offenders More
Severely!’, Manuscript.
Chwe, Michael Suk-Young (1990), ‘Why Were Workers Whipped? Pain in a Principal-Agent Model’,
100 Economic Journal, 1109-1121.
Clotfelter, Charles T. (1977), ‘Public Services, Private Substitutes, and the Demand for Protection
Against Crime’, 67 American Economic Review, 867-877.
Clotfelter, Charles T. (1983), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Rates: An Analysis of Individual Returns’, 65
Review of Economics and Statistics, 363-373.
Coffee, John C., Jr (1980), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: A Non-Chicago View of the Economics
of Criminal Sanctions’, 17 American Criminal Law Review, 419-476.
Cohen, Mark A. (1986), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Oil Spill Prevention and Enforcement’, 13 Journal
of Environmental Economics and Management, 167-188.
Cohen, Mark A. (1987), ‘Optimal Enforcement Strategy to Prevent Oil Spills: An Application of a
Principal-Agent Model with Moral Hazard’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 23-51.
Cohen, Mark A. (1989a), ‘The Role of Criminal Sanctions in Antitrust Enforcement’, 7 Contemporary
Policy Issues, 36-46.
Cohen, Mark A. (1989b), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: A Study of Social Harm and Sentencing
Practice in the Federal Courts, 1984-1987’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 605-660.
Cohen, Mark A. (1992), ‘Environmental Crime and Punishment: Legal/Economic Theory and
Empirical Evidence on Enforcement of Federal Environmental Statutes’, 82 Journal of Criminal
Law and Criminology, 1054-1108.
Cook, Philip J. (1977), ‘Punishment and Crime: A Critique of Current Findings Concerning the
Preventative Effects of Punishment’, 41 Law and Contemporary Problems, 164-209.
Cook, Philip J. (1980), ‘Research in Criminal Deterrence: Laying the Groundwork for the Second
Decade’, in Morris, Norval and Tonry, Michael (eds), 2 Crime and Justice: An Annual Review
of Research, University of Chicago Press, 211-268.
Cook, Philip J. (1983), ‘Costs of Crime’, in Kadish, Sanford H. (ed.), 1 Encyclopedia of Crime and
Justice, New York, The Free Press, 373-378.
Cook, Philip J. (1986), ‘The Relationship Between Victim Resistance and Injury in Noncommercial
Robbery’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 405-416.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
333
Cook, Philip J. (1987), ‘The Economics of Criminal Sanctions’, in Friedland, M.L. (ed.), Sanctions
and Rewards in the Legal System: A Multidisciplinary Approach, Toronto, University of Toronto
Press, 50-78.
Cook, Philip J., Molliconi, Stephanie and Cole, Thomas B. (1995), ‘Regulating Gun Markets’, 86
Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 59-92.
Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their
Resolution’, 27 Journal of Economic Literature, 1067-1097.
Cox, Gary W. (1994), ‘A Note on Crime and Punishment’, 78 Public Choice, 115-124.
Craswell, Richard and Calfee, John E. (1986), ‘Deterrence and Uncertain Legal Standards’, 2 Journal
of Law, Economics, and Organization, 279-303.
Daniel, Kermit, and Lott, John R., Jr (1995), ‘Should Criminal Penalties Include Third-Party
Avoidance Costs?’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 523-534.
Das-Gupta, Arindam and Mookherjee, Dilip (1995), ‘Tax Amnesties in India: An Empirical
Evaluation’, Institute for Economic Development, Boston University, Discussion Paper No. 53.
Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Law as a Preference-Shaping
Policy’, Duke Law Journal, 1-38.
Davis, Michael L. (1988), ‘Time and Punishment: An Intertemporal Model of Crime’, 96 Journal of
Political Economy, 383-390.
Dickens, William T. (1986), ‘Crime and Punishment Again: The Economic Approach with a
Psychological Twist’, 30 Journal of Public Economics, 97-107.
Diver, Colin S. (1980), ‘A Theory of Regulatory Enforcement’, 28 Public Policy, 257-299.
Dye, Ronald A. (1986), ‘Optimal Monitoring Policies in Agencies’, 17 RAND Journal of Economics,
339-350.
Earnhart, Dietrich (1997), ‘Enforcement of Environmental Protection Laws Under Communism and
Democracy’, 40 Journal of Law and Economics, 377-402.
Ehrlich, Isaac (1972a), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Criminal Law Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Legal
Studies, 259-276.
Ehrlich, Isaac (1972b), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities: A Theoretical and Empirical
Investigation’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 521-565.
Ehrlich, Isaac (1975), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Question of Life and Death’, 65
American Economic Review, 397-417.
Ehrlich, Isaac (1981), ‘On the Usefulness of Controlling Individuals: An Economic Analysis of
Rehabilitation, Incapacitation and Deterrence’, 71 American Economic Review, 307-332.
Ehrlich, Isaac (1982), ‘The Optimum Enforcement of Laws and the Concept of Justice: A Positive
Analysis’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27.
Ehrlich, Isaac (1996), ‘Crime, Punishment, and the Market for Offenses’, 10 Journal of Economic
Perspectives, 43-67.
Ehrlich, Isaac and Brower, George D. (1987), ‘On the Issue of Causality in the Economic Model of
Crime and Law Enforcement: Some Theoretical Considerations and Experimental Evidence’, 77
AEA Papers and Proceedings, 99-106
Eide, Erling (1994), Economics of Crime: Deterrence and the Rational Offender, Amsterdam,
Elsevier.
Eide, Erling (1995), ‘RDEU Models of Crime’, University of Oslo Working Papers, WP No. C1.
334
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Eide, Erling (1997), ‘Economics of Criminal Behavior: Survey and Bibliography’, University of Oslo
Working Papers, WP No. C5.
Elzinga, Kenneth G. and Breit, William (1976), The Antitrust Penalties: A Study in Law and
Economics, New Haven, Yale University Press.
Epple, Dennis and Visscher, Michael (1984), ‘Environmental Pollution: Modeling Occurrence,
Detection, and Deterrence’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 29-60.
Evans, William N., Neville, Doreen and Graham, John D. (1991), ‘General Deterrence of Drunk
Driving: Evaluation of Recent American Policies’, 11 Risk Analysis, 279-289.
Faith, Roger L. and Tollison, Robert D. (1983), ‘The Pricing of Surrogate Crime and Law
Enforcement’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 401-411.
Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1990), ‘Detection Controlled Estimation’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics,
233-276.
Fenn, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (1988), ‘A Positive Economic Theory of Regulatory
Enforcement’, 98 Economic Journal, 1055-1070.
Forst, Brian and Brosi, Kathleen B. (1977), ‘A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis of the Prosecutor’,
6 Journal of Legal Studies, 177-191.
Fowles, Richard and Loeb, Peter D. (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55-MPH Limit:
Comment’, 79 American Economic Review, 916-921.
Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1995), ‘Negotiated Enforcement and Criminal Deterrence’, University of
Bologna, Manuscript.
Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1997a), ‘Amnesties, Settlements and Optimal Tax Enforcement’, University
of Bologna, Manuscript.
Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1997b), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance’, preliminary version, forthcoming
in International Encyclopedia of Law and Economics.
Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (forthcoming), ‘Punishment and Grace: On the Economics of Permanent
Amnesties’, Public Finance/Finances Publiques.
Friedman, David D. (1981), ‘Reflections on Optimal Punishment, or: Should the Rich Pay Higher
Fines?’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 185-205.
Friedman, David and Sjostrom, William (1993), ‘Hanged for a Sheep - The Economics of Marginal
Deterrence’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 345-366.
Furlong, William J. (1987), ‘A General Equilibrium Model of Crime Commission and Prevention’, 34
Journal of Public Economics, 87-103.
Garoupa, Nuno (1995), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement and Imperfect Information’, University of York,
Discussion Paper 95/96.
Garoupa, Nuno (1997a), ‘The Theory of Optimal Law Enforcement’, 11 Journal of Economic
Surveys, 267-295.
Garoupa, Nuno (1997b), ‘The Economics of Organized Crime and Optimal Law Enforcement: the Urge
for a Tougher Policy’, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Manuscript.
Garoupa, Nuno (1997c), ‘The Role of Moral Values in the Economic Analysis of Crime: A General
Equilibrium Approach’, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Manuscript.
Garoupa, Nuno (forthcoming), ‘Prison, Parole and the Criminal Justice Act 1991', 18 Research in Law
and Economics.
Gibbons, Thomas (1982), ‘The Utility of Economic Analysis of Crime’, 2 International Review of Law
and Economics, 173-191.
Gibbs, Jack P. (1975), Crime, Punishment and Deterrence, New York, Elsevier.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
335
Goel, Rajeev K. and Rich, Daniel P. (1989), ‘On the Economic Incentives for Taking Bribes’, 61
Public Choice, 269-275.
Graetz, Michael J., Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘The Tax Compliance Game:
Toward an Interactive Theory of Law Enforcement’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and
Organization, 1-32.
Graves, Philip E., Lee, Dwight R. and Sexton, Robert L. (1989), ‘Statutes Versus Enforcement: The
Case of the Optimal Speed Limit’, 79 American Economic Review, 932-936.
Graves, Philip E., Lee, Dwight R. and Sexton, Robert L. (1990), ‘A Note on Drinking, Driving and
Enforcement Costs’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 793-796.
Greenberg, Joseph (1984), ‘Avoiding Tax Avoidance: A (Repeated) Game Theoretic Approach’, 32
Journal of Economic Theory, 1-13.
Grieson, Ronald E. and Singh, Nirvikar (1990), ‘Regulating Externalities Through Testing’, 41
Journal of Public Economics, 369-387.
Grossman, Gene M. and Katz, Michael L. (1983), ‘Plea Bargaining and Social Welfare’, 73 American
Economic Review, 749-757.
Gyapong, Anthony O. and Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1988), ‘Factor Substitution, Price Elasticity
of Factor Demand and Returns to Scale in Police Production: Evidence from Michigan’, 54
Southern Economic Journal, 863-878.
Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1987), ‘Economies of Scale in Municipal Police Departments: The Case
of Florida’, 69 Review of Economics and Statistics, 352-356.
Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1989), ‘Functional Substitution Among Crimes: Some Evidence’, 15
Eastern Economic Journal, 129-140.
Hannan, Timothy H. (1982), ‘Bank Robberies and Bank Security Precautions’, 11 Journal of Legal
Studies, 83-92.
Harel, Alon (1994), ‘Efficiency and Fairness in Criminal Law: The Case for a Criminal Law Principle
of Comparative Fault’, 82 California Law Review, 1181-1229.
Harris, Milton and Raviv, Artur (1978), ‘Some Results on Incentive Contracts with Applications to
Education and Employment, Health Insurance, and Law Enforcement’, 68 American Economic
Review, 20-30.
Hawkins, Gordon (1969), ‘Punishment and Deterrence: The Educative, Moralizing, and Habituative
Effects’, 1969 Wisconsin Law Review, 550-565.
Hawkins, Keith O. (1982), Environment and Enforcement, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Hellman, Daryl A. (1980), The Economics of Crime, New York, St. Martin’s Press.
Hellman, Daryl A. and Alper, Neil O. (1990), Economics of Crime: Theory and Practice, Needham
Heights, Simon and Schuster, Ginn Press.
Henszey, Benjamin N. and Roadarmel, Richard L. (1981), ‘A Comparative Analysis of State Individual
Income Tax Enforcement Procedures’, 34 National Tax Journal, 207-216.
Hui-Wen, Koo and Png, I.P.L. (1994), ‘Private Security: Deterrent or Diversion?’, 14 International
Review of Law and Economics, 87-101.
Hylton, Keith N. (1996), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement and Victim Precaution’, 27 RAND Journal of
Economics, 197-206.
Jacob, Herbert (1980), ‘Deterrent Effects of Formal and Informal Sanctions’, 2 Law and Policy
Quarterly, 61-80.
Jones, Carol Adaire (1989), ‘Standard Setting with Incomplete Enforcement Revisited’, 8 Journal of
Policy Analysis and Management, 72-87.
336
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Kahan, Dan M. (1997), ‘Social Influence, Social Meaning, and Deterrence’, 83 Virginia Law Review,
349-395.
Kambhu, John (1989), ‘Regulatory Standards, Noncompliance and Enforcement’, 1 Journal of
Regulatory Economics, 103-114.
Kan, Steven S. (1996), ‘Corporal Punishments and Optimal Incapacitation’, 25 Journal of Legal
Studies, 121-130.
Kaplow, Louis (1990a), ‘A Note on the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions,’ 42 Journal of Public
Economics, 245-247.
Kaplow, Louis (1990b), ‘Optimal Deterrence, Uninformed Individuals, and Acquiring Information
about Whether Acts are Subject to Sanctions’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization,
93-128.
Kaplow, Louis (1990c), ‘Optimal Taxation with Costly Enforcement and Evasion’, 43 Journal of
Public Economics, 221-236.
Kaplow, Louis (1992), ‘The Optimal Probability and Magnitude of Fines for Acts that Definitely are
Undesirable’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-11.
Kaplow, Louis (1994), ‘The Value of Accuracy in Adjudication: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal
of Legal Studies, 307-401.
Kaplow, Louis (1996), ‘How Tax Complexity and Enforcement Affect the Equity and Efficiency of the
Income Tax’, 49 National Tax Journal, 135-149.
Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994a), ‘Accuracy in the Determination of Liability’, 37 Journal
of Law and Economics, 1-15.
Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994b), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement with Self-Reporting of
Behavior’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 583-606.
Karpoff, Jonathan M. and Lott, John R., Jr (1993), ‘The Reputational Penalty Firms Bear from
Committing Criminal Fraud’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 757-802.
Katyal, Neal Kumar (1997), ‘Deterrence’s Difficulty’, 95 Michigan Law Review, 2385-2476.
Keeler, Theodore E. (1994), ‘Highway Safety, Economic Behavior, and Driving Environment’, 84
American Economic Review, 684-693.
Keenan, Donald C. and Rubin, Paul H. (1982), ‘Criminal Violations and Civil Violations’, 11 Journal
of Legal Studies, 365-377.
Kenkel, Donald S. (1993a), ‘Do Drunk Drivers Pay Their Way? A Note on Optimal Penalties for
Drunk Driving’, 12 Journal of Health Economics, 137-149.
Kenkel, Donald S. (1993b), ‘Drinking, Driving, and Deterrence: The Effectiveness and Social Costs
of Alternative Policies’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 877-913.
Klevorick, Alvin K. (1985a), ‘Legal Theory and the Economic Analysis of Torts and Crimes’, 85
Columbia Law Review, 905-920.
Klevorick, Alvin K. (1985b), ‘On the Economic Theory of Crime’, in Pennock, J. Roland and
Chapman, John W. (eds), Nomos XXVII: Criminal Justice, New York, New York University
Press, 289-309.
Klitgaard, Robert (1988), Controlling Corruption, Berkeley, University of California Press.
Knoeber, Charles R. (1978), ‘Penalties and Compensation for Auto Accidents’, 7 Journal of Legal
Studies, 263-278.
Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1992), ‘Deterrence with Multiple Defendants’,23 RAND Journal of Economics,
507-517.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
337
Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1992), ‘Low-Probability-High-Penalty Enforcement
Strategies and the Efficient Operation of the Plea-Bargaining System’, 12 International Review
of Law and Economics, 69-77.
Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1996), ‘In Defense of Criminal Defense Expenditures and
Plea Bargaining’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 397-416.
Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1982), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Choice Between Enterprise and Personal
Liability for Accidents’, 70 California Law Review, 1345-1392.
Kraakman, Reinier (1986), ‘Gatekeepers: The Anatomy of a Third-Party Enforcement Strategy’, 2
Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 53-104.
Kramer, Samuel (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of Criminal Attempt: Marginal Deterrence and the
Optimal Structure of Sanctions’, 81 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 398-417.
Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics,
61-107.
Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1975), ‘The Private Enforcement of Law’, 4 Journal of
Legal Studies, 1-46.
Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge,
MA, Harvard University Press.
Landsberger, Michael and Meilijson, Isaac (1982), ‘Incentive Generating State Dependent Penalty
System: The Case of Income Tax Evasion’, 19 Journal of Public Economics, 333-352.
Lave, Charles A. (1985), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit’, 75 American Economic
Review, 1159-1164.
Lave, Charles A. (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit: Reply’, 79 American
Economic Review, 926-931.
Layton, Allan P. (1983), ‘The Impact of Increased Penalties on Australian Drink/Driving Behaviour’,
19 Logistics and Transportation Review, 261-266.
Layton, Allan P. (1984), ‘The Impact of Increased Penalties on Australian Drink/Driving Behavior - A
Procedural Note’, 20 Logistics and Transportation Review, 187-189.
Lee, Dwight R. (1983), ‘On Substituting a Socially Costless Penalty for Costly Detection’, 3
International Review of Law and Economics, 179-185.
Lee, Dwight R. (1985), ‘Policing Cost, Evasion Cost, and the Optimal Speed Limit’, 52 Southern
Economic Journal, 34-45.
Leung, Siu Fai (1991), ‘How to Make the Fine Fit the Corporate Crime? An Analysis of Static and
Dynamical Optimal Punishment Theories’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 243-256.
Leung, Siu Fai (1995), ‘Dynamic Deterrence Theory’, 62 Economica, 65-87.
Levitt, Steven D. (1997a), ‘Private Information as an Explanation for the Use of Jail Sentences Instead
of Fines’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 179-192.
Levitt, Steven D. (1997b), ‘Using Electoral Cycles in Police Hiring to Estimate the Effect of Police on
Crime’, 87 American Economic Review, 270-290.
Levitt, Steven D. (forthcoming a), ‘Juvenile Crime and Punishment’, Journal of Political Economy.
Levitt, Steven D. (forthcoming b), ‘Why do Increased Arrest Rates Appear to Reduce Crime:
Deterrence, Incapacitation, or Measurement Error?’, Economic Inquiry.
338
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Levy, David T. and Asch, Peter (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit: Comment’,
79 American Economic Review, 913-915.
Lewin, Jeff L. and Trumbull, William N. (1990), ‘The Social Value of Crime?’, 10 International
Review of Law and Economics, 271-284.
Linder, Stephen H. and McBride, Mark E. (1984), ‘Enforcement Costs and Regulatory Reform: The
Agency and Firm Response’, 11 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management,
327-346.
Lott, John R., Jr (1987), ‘Should the Wealthy be Able to “Buy Justice”?’, 95 Journal of Political
Economy, 1307-1316.
Lott, John R., Jr (1990a), ‘The Effect of Conviction on the Legitimate Income of Criminals’, 34
Economics Letters, 381-385.
Lott, John R., Jr (1990b), ‘A Transaction-Costs Explanation for Why the Poor Are More Likely to
Commit Crime’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 243-245.
Lott, John R., Jr (1991), ‘When Does Learning about a Crime Produce External Benefits?’, The
Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania, Manuscript.
Lott, John R., Jr (1992a), ‘An Attempt at Measuring the Total Monetary Penalty from Drug
Convictions: The Importance of an Individual’s Reputation’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies,
159-187.
Lott, John R., Jr (1992b), ‘Do we Punish High Income Criminals too Heavily?’, 30 Economic Inquiry,
583-608.
Lott, John R., Jr and Roberts, Russell D. (1989), ‘Why Comply: One-Sided Enforcement of Price
Controls and Victimless Crime Laws’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 403-414.
Lott, John R., Jr and Roberts, Russell D. (1995), ‘The Expected Penalty for Committing a Crime: An
Analysis of Minimum Wage Violations’, 30 Journal of Human Resources, 397-408.
Lui, Francis T. (1986), ‘A Dynamic Model of Corruption Deterrence’, 31 Journal of Public
Economics, 215-236.
Luksetich, William and White, Michael (1982), Crime and Public Policy: An Economic Approach,
Boston, Little, Brown.
McChesney, Fred S. (1980), ‘On the Economics of Antitrust Enforcement’, 68 Georgetown Law
Journal, 1103-1111.
McPheters, Lee R. and Stronge, William B. (eds) (1976), The Economics of Crime and Law
Enforcement, Springfield, IL, Thomas.
Malik, Arun S. (1990), ‘Avoidance, Screening and Optimum Enforcement’, 21 RAND Journal of
Economics, 341-353.
Malik, Arun S. (1992), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Choice of Policy Instruments for Controlling
Pollution’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 714-720.
Melumad, Nahum D. and Mookherjee, Dilip (1989), ‘Delegation as Commitment: The Case of Income
Tax Audits’, 20 RAND Journal of Economics, 139-163.
Miceli, Thomas J. (1991), ‘Optimal Criminal Procedure: Fairness and Deterrence’, 11 International
Review of Law and Economics, 3-10.
Miceli, Thomas J. (1994), ‘Prison and Parole: Minimizing the Cost of Non-monetary Sanctions as
Deterrents’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 197-211.
Miceli, Thomas J. (1996), ‘Plea Bargaining and Deterrence: An Institutional Approach’, 3 European
Journal of Law and Economics, 249-264.
Montesquieu, Charles (1748), The Spirit of the Laws, Rept. edn, Berkeley, University of California
Press, 1977.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
339
Mookherjee, Dilip (1997), ‘The Economics of Enforcement’, in Bose, Amitava, Rakshit, Mihir and
Sinha, Anup (eds), Issues in Economic Theory and Policy, Essays in Honor of Tapas Majumdar,
New Delhi, Oxford University Press, 202-249.
Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, Ivan (1989), ‘Optimal Auditing, Insurance, and Redistribution’, 104
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 399-415.
Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1990a), ‘Eliminating Corruption: An End in Itself?’, John E.
Anderson Graduate School of Management at UCLA, Business Economics Working Paper No.
90-23.
Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1990b), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Optimal Progressivity of
Income Taxes’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 411-431.
Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1992a), ‘Monitoring vis-à-vis Investigation in Enforcement of Law’,
82 American Economic Review, 556-565.
Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1992b), ‘Rights and Regulations: How and How Much to
Enforce?’, John E. Anderson Graduate School of Management at UCLA, Business Economics
Working Paper No. 92-1.
Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1994), ‘Marginal Deterrence in Enforcement of Law’, 102 Journal
of Political Economy, 1039-1066.
Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1995), ‘Corruptible Law Enforcers: How Should they be
Compensated?’, 105 Economic Journal, 145-159.
Nagin, Daniel and Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘The Effects of Criminality and Conviction on the Labor
Market Status of Young British Offenders’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics,
109-126.
Nash, John (1991), ‘To Make the Punishment Fit the Crime: The Theory and Statistical Estimation of
a Multi-Period Optimal Deterrence Model’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics,
101-110.
Newman, Harry A. and Wright, David W. (1990), ‘Strict Liability in a Principal-Agent Model’, 10
International Review of Law and Economics, 219-231.
Ordeshook, Peter C. (1990), ‘Crime and Punishment: Are One-Shot, Two-Person Games Enough?’,
84 American Political Science Review, 573-575.
Parker, Jeffrey S. (1989), ‘Criminal Sentencing Policy for Organizations: The Unifying Approach of
Optimal Penalties’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 513-593.
Pashigian, B. Peter (1975), ‘On the Control of Crime and Bribery’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies,
311-326.
Png, I.P.L. (1986), ‘Optimal Subsidies and Damages in the Presence of Judicial Error’, 6 International
Review of Law and Economics, 101-105.
Png, Ivan P.L. and Zolt, Eric (1989), ‘Efficient Deterrence and the Tax Treatment of Monetary
Sanctions’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 209-217.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980a), ‘Private versus Public Enforcement of Fines’, 9 Journal of Legal
Studies, 105-127.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980b), ‘Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting’, 70 American
Economic Review, 363-370.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1988), ‘The Deterrent Effects of Settlements and
Trials’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-116.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘A Note on Optimal Public Enforcement with
Settlements and Litigation Costs’, 12 Research in Law and Economics, 1-8.
340
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1991), ‘A Model of Optimal Fines for Repeat
Offenders’, 46 Journal of Public Economics, 291-306.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1979), ‘The Optimal Tradeoff between the Probability and
Magnitude of Fines’, 69 American Economic Review, 880-891.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘The Optimal Use of Fines and Imprisonment’, 24
Journal of Public Economics, 89-99.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1991), ‘A Note on Optimal Fines When Wealth Varies
Among Individuals’, 81 American Economic Review, 618-621.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Optimal Magnitude and
Probability of Fines’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 133-148.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘Should Employees Be Subject to Fines and
Imprisonment Given Existence of Corporate Liability?’, 13 International Review of Law and
Economics, 239-257.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1996), ‘Repeat Offenders and the Theory of Deterrence’,
John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics, and Business, Harvard Law School, Discussion Paper
No. 188; John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics, Stanford Law School, Working Paper No.
134.
Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1997), ‘On the Disutility and Discounting of Imprisonment
and the Theory of Deterrence’, John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics and Business, Harvard
Law School, Discussion Paper No. 213; John M. Olin Program in Law and Econ., Stanford Law
School, Working Paper No. 146; Forthcoming in Journal of Legal Studies.
Posner, Richard A. (1980a), ‘Optimal Sentences for White-Collar Criminals’, 17 American Criminal
Law Review, 409-418.
Posner, Richard A. (1980b), ‘Retribution and Related Concepts of Punishment’, 9 Journal of Legal
Studies, 71-92.
Posner, Richard A. (1985), ‘An Economic Theory of the Criminal Law’, 85 Columbia Law Review,
1193-1231.
Pyle, David J (1983), The Economics of Crime and Law Enforcement, London, Macmillan.
Pyle, D.J. (1995), ‘The Economic Approach to Crime and Punishment’, 6 Journal of Interdisciplinary
Economics, 1-22.
Rasmusen, Eric (1995), ‘How Optimal Penalties Change with the Amount of Harm’, 15 International
Review of Law and Economics, 101-108.
Rasmusen, Eric (1996), ‘Stigma and Self-Fulfilling Expectations of Criminality’, 39 Journal of Law
and Economics, 519-543.
Ray, Subhash C. (1989), ‘Legal Control of Drunken Driving: A Time Series Study of California Data’,
5 International Journal of Forecasting, 515-522.
Reder, M.W. (1974), ‘Citizen Rights and the Cost of Law Enforcement’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies,
435-455.
Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1988), ‘Plea Bargaining and Prosecutorial Discretion’, 78 American
Economic Review, 713-728.
Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1993), ‘The Law Enforcement Process and Criminal Choice’,13 International
Review of Law and Economics, 115-134.
Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1984), ‘An Equilibrium Model of Tax Compliance with
a Bayesian Auditor and Some “Honest” Taxpayers’, California Institute of Technology, Social
Science Working Paper.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
341
Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1985), ‘Income Tax Compliance in a Principal-Agent
Framework’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 1-18.
Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1988), ‘A Note on Enforcement Uncertainty and
Taxpayer Compliance’, 103 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 793-798.
Reynolds, Robert J. (1980), ‘The Economics of Antitrust Enforcement: Theory and Measurement’, 68
Georgetown Law Journal, 1121-1130.
Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1975), ‘The Economics of Corruption’, 4 Journal of Public Economics,
187-203.
Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1978), Corruption: A Study in Political Economy, New York, Academic
Press.
Ross, H. Laurence (1975), ‘The Scandinavian Myth: The Effectiveness of Drinking-and-Driving
Legislating in Sweden and Norway’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 285-310.
Ross, H. Laurence (1977), ‘Deterrence Regained: The Cheshire Constabulary’s “Breathalyser Blitz”’,
6 Journal of Legal Studies, 241-249.
Ross, H. Laurence (1984), ‘Social Control Through Deterrence: Drinking-and-Driving Laws’, 10
American Review of Sociology, 21-35.
Ross, H. Laurence (1992), ‘The Law and Drunk Driving’, 26 Law and Society Review, 219-230.
Ross, H. Laurence and Blumenthal, Murray (1974), ‘Sanctions for the Drinking Driver: An
Experimental Study’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 53-61.
Rottenberg, Simon (ed.) (1973), The Economics of Crime and Punishment, Washington, American
Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research.
Rubin, Paul H. and Zwirb, Robert (1987), ‘The Economics of Civil RICO’, 20 U.C. Davis Law
Review, 883-912.
Rubinstein, Ariel (1979), ‘An Optimal Conviction Policy for Offenses that May Have Been Committed
by Accident’, in Brams, S.J., Schotter, A. and Schwödiauer, G. (eds), Applied Game Theory,
Wurzburg, Physica-Verlag, 406-413.
Rubinstein, Ariel (1980), ‘On an Anomaly of the Deterrent Effect of Punishment’, 6 Economics
Letters, 89-94.
Russell, Clifford S., Harrington, Winston and Vaughan, William J. (1986), Enforcing Pollution
Control Laws, Washington, DC, Resources for the Future.
Sah, Raaj K. (1991), ‘Social Osmosis and Patterns of Crime’, 99 Journal of Political Economy ,
1272-1295.
Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1984), An Economic Analysis of Crime and Justice: Theory,
Methods, and Applications, New York, Academic Press.
Schroyen, Fred (1997), ‘Pareto Efficient Income Taxation Under Costly Monitoring’, 65 Journal of
Public Economics, 343-366.
Schwartz, Warren F. (1980), ‘An Overview of the Economics of Antitrust Enforcement’, 68
Georgetown Law Journal, 1075-1102.
Scotchmer, Suzanne (1987), ‘Audit Classes and Tax Enforcement Policy’, 77 American Economic
Review, 229-233.
Scotchmer, Suzanne and Slemrod, Joel (1987), ‘Optimal Obfuscation in Tax Enforcement’, Graduate
School of Public Policy, University of California, Berkeley, Working Paper.
Segerson, Kathleen and Tietenberg, Tom (1992a), ‘Defining Efficient Sanctions’, in Tietenberg, T.H.
(ed.), Innovation in Environmental Policy, Aldershot, Edward Elgar, 53-73.
342
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Segerson, Kathleen and Tietenberg, Tom (1992b), ‘The Structure of Penalties in Environmental
Enforcement: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Environmental Economics and
Management, 179-200.
Seidman, Louis Michael (1984), ‘Soldiers, Martyrs, and Criminals: Utilitarian Theory and the Problem
of Crime Control’, 94 Yale Law Journal, 315-349.
Shapiro, Perry and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1984), ‘Deterrence and Subjective Probabilities of Arrest:
Modeling Individual Decisions to Drink and Drive in Sweden’, 18 Law and Society Review,
583-604.
Shavell, Steven (1980), ‘Strict Liability versus Negligence’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-25.
Shavell, Steven (1982), ‘On Liability and Insurance’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 120-132.
Shavell, Steven (1985), ‘Criminal Law and the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’,
85 Columbia Law Review, 1232-1262.
Shavell, Steven (1987a), ‘The Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 77 American
Economic Review, 584-592.
Shavell, Steven (1987b), ‘A Model of Optimal Incapacitation’, 77 American Economic Review ,
107-110.
Shavell, Steven (1987c), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University
Press.
Shavell, Steven (1990), ‘Deterrence and the Punishment of Attempts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies,
435-466.
Shavell, Steven (1991a), ‘Individual Precautions to Prevent Theft: Private versus Socially Optimal
Behavior’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 123-132.
Shavell, Steven (1991b), ‘Specific versus General Enforcement of Law’, 99 Journal of Political
Economy, 1088-1108.
Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘A Note on Marginal Deterrence’, 12 International Review of Law and
Economics, 345-355.
Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘The Optimal Structure of Law Enforcement’, 36 Journal of Law and
Economics, 255-287.
Shavell, Steven (1997a), ‘The Fundamental Divergence between the Private and the Social Motive to
Use the Legal System’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 575-612.
Shavell, Steven (1997b), ‘The Optimal Level of Corporate Liability Given the Limited Ability of
Corporations to Penalize Their Employees’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics,
203-213.
Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1993), ‘Corruption’, 108 Quarterly Journal of Economics,
599-617.
Sigman, Hilary (1995), ‘Midnight Dumping: An Empirical Analysis of Illegal Waste Oil Disposal’,
Department of Economics, UCLA, Manuscript.
Skogh, Göran (1973), ‘A Note on Gary Becker’s “Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach”’,
75 Swedish Journal of Economics, 305-311.
Skogh, Göran and Stuart, Charles (1982a), ‘A Contractarian Theory of Property Rights and Crime’,
84 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 27-40.
Skogh, Göran and Stuart, Charles (1982b), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crime Rates, Punishment, and
the Social Consequences of Crime’, 38 Public Choice, 171-179.
Slemrod, Joel and Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1987), ‘The Optimal Size of a Tax Collection Agency’, 89
Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 183-192.
8000
Public Enforcement of Law
343
Sloan, Frank A., Reilly, Bridget A. and Schenzler, Christoph M. (1994), ‘Tort Liability versus Other
Approaches for Deterring Careless Driving’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics,
53-71.
Snyder, Donald (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55-MPH Limit: Comment’, 79 American
Economic Review, 922-925.
Snyder, Edward A. (1990), ‘The Effect of Higher Criminal Penalties on Antitrust Enforcement’, 33
Journal of Law and Economics, 439-462.
Spier, Kathryn E. (1997), ‘A Note on the Divergence between the Private and the Social Motive to
Settle under a Negligence Rule’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 613-621.
Stigler, George J. (1970), ‘The Optimum Enforcement of Laws’, 78 Journal of Political Economy,
526-536.
Swanson, Timothy M. (1991), ‘Enforcement of Environmental Regulation’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.),
Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer
Wirtschaftsverlag, 67-78.
Sykes, Alan O. (1981), ‘An Efficiency Analysis of Vicarious Liability under the Law of Agency’, 91
Yale Law Journal, 168-206.
Tauchen, Helen, Witte, Ann Dryden and Griesinger, Harriet (1994), ‘Criminal Deterrence: Revisiting
the Issue with a Birth Cohort’, 76 Review of Economics and Statistics, 399-412.
Thurow, Lester (1970), ‘Equity vs. Efficiency in Law Enforcement’, 18 Public Policy, 451-459.
Tullock, Gordon (1967), ‘The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies and Theft’, 5 Western Economic
Review, 224-232.
Tullock, Gordon (1969), ‘An Economic Approach to Crime’, 50 Social Science Quarterly, 59-71.
Tullock, Gordon (1974), ‘Does Punishment Deter Crime?’, 36 The Public Interest, 103-11.
United States Sentencing Commission (1995), Federal Sentencing Guidelines Manual, 1995 Edition,
St. Paul, MN, West Publishing.
Usher, Dan (1987), ‘Theft as a Paradigm for Departures from Efficiency’, 39 Oxford Economic
Papers, 235-252.
van den Haag, Ernest (1982), ‘The Criminal Law as a Threat System’, 73 Journal of Criminal Law
and Criminology, 769-785.
Veljanovski, C.G. (1982), ‘The Market for Regulatory Enforcement’,Economic Journal, Supplement,
123-129.
Veljanovski, Cento G. (1983), ‘Regulatory Enforcement - An Economic Case Study of the British
Factory Inspectorate’, 5 Law and Policy Quarterly, 75-96.
Veljanovski, Cento G. (1984), ‘The Economics of Regulatory Enforcement’, in Hawkins, Keith and
Thomas, John M. (eds), Enforcing Regulation, Boston, Kluwer-Nijhoff, 171-188.
Viscusi, W. Kip (1986a), ‘Market Incentives for Criminal Behavior’, in Freeman, Richard B. and
Holzer, Harry J. (eds),The Black Youth Employment Crisis, Chicago, University of Chicago Press,
301-346.
Viscusi, W. Kip (1986b), ‘The Risks and Rewards of Criminal Activity: A Comprehensive Test of
Criminal Deterrence’, 4 Journal of Labor Economics, 317-340.
Votey, Harold L., Jr (1982), ‘Scandinavian Drinking-Driving Control: Myth or Intuition?’, 11 Journal
of Legal Studies, 93-116.
344
Public Enforcement of Law
8000
Votey, Harold L., Jr and Phillips, Llad (1972), ‘Police Effectiveness and the Production Function for
Law Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 423-436.
Waldfogel, Joel (1993), ‘Criminal Sentences as Endogenous Taxes: Are They “Just” or “Efficient”?’,
36 Journal of Law and Economics, 139-151.
Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘Are Fines and Prison Terms Used Efficiently? Evidence on Federal Fraud
Offenders’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 107-139.
Weinblatt, J., Spiegel, Uriel, Hakim, Simon and Ben-Zion, Uri (1983), ‘Crime Prevention Policies and
Externalities: A Theoretical Analysis’, 38 Public Finance, 110-131.
Wilde, Louis L. (1992), ‘Criminal Choice, Nonmonetary Sanctions, and Marginal Deterrence: A
Normative Analysis’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 333-344.
Wilkinson, James T. (1987), ‘Reducing Drunken Driving: Which Policies are Most Effective?’, 54
Southern Economic Journal, 322-334.
Wilson, James Q. (1983), Thinking About Crime, 2nd edn, New York, Basic Books.
Wilson, James Q. and Herrnstein, Richard J. (1985), Crime and Human Nature, New York, Simon and
Schuster.
Witte, Ann D. and Woodbury, Diane F. (1985), ‘The Effect of Tax Laws and Tax Administration on
Tax Compliance: The Case of the U.S. Individual Income Tax’, 38 National Tax Journal, 1-14.
Yohe, Gary W. (1982), ‘Fines as Economic Incentives - An Alternative Variable Control’, 2
International Review of Law and Economics, 95-109.
Zolt, Eric M. (1989), ‘Deterrence via Taxation: A Critical Analysis of Tax Penalty Provisions’, 37
UCLA Law Review, 343-387.
Download