Scoping Recursivity A Comment on Franklin and Napier Martin Holbraad, University College London Commenting on two papers that have appealed to the notion of ‘recursivity’ to articulate new directions for anthropological thinking, this piece seeks to clarify the scope of a recursive turn in contemporary anthropology, distinguishing it from elements of recursivity that have always been present in the discipline’s epistemic procedures. Keywords: immunology, knowledge, the native’s point of view, paternity, recursivity Two articles in Cambridge Anthropology recently (Franklin [2013] in the last issue and Napier [2013] in this issue) have masterfully illustrated that there is a profound affinity between anthropology and recursivity. Take as a starting point, on the one hand, Malinowski’s notion that anthropology is par excellence in the business of ‘grasp[ing] the native’s point of view’ (1961: 25); and on the other, Franklin’s characterization of recursivity as a form of ‘attention to the properties of the equipment you are using to determine, or manage, the properties of something else’ (2013: 21). Now, as bits of equipment for determining or managing the properties of anthropology and recursivity respectively, such attempts at definition are nothing if not recursive themselves – the attention I propose we pay to them here merely proves the point. In fact, understood in the broadest sense, all knowledge is recursive, inasmuch as it always involves calibrating the means of knowledge (empirical and analytical procedures, experimental protocols and tools, scales of measurement, assumptions, concepts – in short, its ‘equipment’) with the object of knowledge. Knowledge, one might even say, just is such a process of calibration: to know something is recursively to adjust one’s body of knowledge to it (an immunological procedure, to be sure, following Napier – a point to which I shall return). Still, Malinowski’s by now intuitive definition demonstrates a sense in which the recursive character of anthropological knowledge is exemplary, or at least heightened. It does so in two steps. First, it turns the analogy between means and objects of knowledge, implied by Franklin’s characterization, into an explicit homology. In anthropology means and objects do not only have ‘properties’ in common, to use Franklin’s language, but are, more strictly, versions of the same thing, namely ‘points of view’. To gain anthropological knowledge is to take a point of view on a point of view Cambridge Anthropology 31(2), Autumn 2013: 123–127 © Cambridge Anthropology doi:10.3167/ca.2013.310208 Martin Holbraad – a recursive locution if ever there was one. Based on this mirror-like premise, then, the second and more argonautical step completes the exemplary image of recursivity: if what anthropology strives to ‘grasp’ is itself another way of grasping (taking a point of view on a ‘native’ point of view), then the anthropologists’ attempts can only take the form of a shift of perspective: to grasp the native’s point of view involves allowing it to change one’s own. So while all knowledge involves adjusting means to objects in some sense, anthropology presents a limit case insofar as it involves, in one way or other (cf. Viveiros de Castro 2002; Strathern 1992, 2005: 135–62), an exchange of one viewpoint for the other. The content of anthropological knowledge (the native’s point of view) becomes its form (the anthropologist’s epistemic grasp of it). From which the converse also follows: knowing anthropologically involves calibrating the properties of that transformation itself, turning the form of anthropological knowledge into the content of one’s attention once more. (Hence, arguably, the doggedly constitutive role that ‘theory’ plays in anthropological inquiry, which colleagues from other disciplines often notice and sometimes lament.) As suggested by Franklin’s account of the trajectory of recursive arguments in the history of anthropological debates about (debates about concepts of) conception, this way of articulating the recursivity of anthropology is rather blunt. After all, the premise of Franklin’s article is that the prospect of ‘a recursive anthropology’ is, if not itself wholly new, then at least one that ‘prefigures[s] our current moment’, as Corsín Jimenez (in press: 3) puts it in a commentary on the recursive properties of prototyping. So how does this advertised sense of originality tally with the claim that the rudiments of recursivity can be found in someone like Malinowski (or indeed Barnes, as Franklin herself shows)? Certainly, having myself pinned a flag on recursive analysis as a significant and distinctive move in contemporary anthropological theorizing (Holbraad 2012), I frequently encounter critical queries about just how new all this really is. Franklin offers a sophisticated account of how in vitro reproductive techniques can provide a platform (or ‘stem’) for rendering anthropology’s recursive horizon as open as the recursive redefinitions of anthropos that these practices precipitate. Here I shall draw rather (and recursively, of course!) on Napier’s marvellous biopolitical allegory of contemporary immunology in order to sharpen the idea of recursivity in a way that may clarify how its ‘current moment’ is rather different from the more generic sense in which all anthropology (indeed all knowledge) is recursive. In doing so, I seek merely to make explicit a core implication of Napier’s argument. The form of recursivity he articulates for contemporary immunology loops recursively back onto the practice of anthropology itself: the reconfiguration of Self and Other that immunology performs becomes, in the very act of its anthropological analysis, a reconfiguration of Self and Other in the practice of anthropology too – or, putting it in Malinowskian terminology, a reconfiguration of the relationship between the analyst’s point of view (self) and the native’s (other). Napier’s allegory turns on a core distinction: the xenophobic body, in which the immune system’s role is taken as a search-and-destroy mission to defend the sovereignty of the body (self) from viral attack (other); and the xenophilic body, whose immune system acts as a search engine of sorts, engaging viral information by generating a sufficiently varied repertoire of cell mutations (the antibodies) to be able to anticipate 124 • Cambridge Anthropology A Comment on Franklin and Napier viral structures in a way that allows it to form symbiotic relationships with them. Now, it would be quite unfair to characterize anthropology as xenophobic in the stark way Napier makes the claim for immunology. As Malinowski’s profoundly empathic message indicates so emblematically, the best traditions of anthropological research have well-nigh defined themselves in terms of their respect for the alterity of other societies and cultures. Certainly, it would be absurd to suggest that anthropologists’ mission, like foot soldiers in a classically construed immune system for modern science and society, has been somehow to destroy social and cultural others – quite the contrary (e.g., Lévi-Strauss 1952). Still, there is one significant sense in which anthropology has maintained a xenophobic premise of sorts, in its epistemic strategies in particular. Modelling itself on Enlightenment images of science as humans’ ever-widening epistemic sovereignty over the world they inhabit, anthropology has tended to present its empathic engagements with others as an exercise in the collective human effort to understand the world. However, this lends a very specific configuration to the activity of grasping the native’s point of view. For if they are to be imagined as helping to expand a body of knowledge that has logical (as well as epistemic) priority, the recursive shifts of perspective that Malinowski recommended must also be understood in irreducibly hierarchical terms: ‘grasping’ the native’s point of view is an act of affirming one’s epistemic sovereignty over it. Take as an illustration the famed ‘virgin birth’ debate that, as Franklin shows, was so foundational to the development of social anthropology as a field of knowledge. Supposedly, non-modern people of various kinds (including the usual suspects in such debates –Australian Aborigines and Melanesians) underplay, or altogether lack, knowledge of the facts of paternity in human reproduction. According to Malinowski (1932, 1954), Trobriand islanders in the early twentieth century held human conception to be the result of matrilineal ancestor spirits entering women through their bodily orifices (men’s contribution is confined mainly to ‘opening the way’ for the spirit-foetus and subsequently feeding it with their semen during intercourse). This set of ‘beliefs’, as Malinowski calls them, is related to focal elements of Trobriand cosmology, which in turn play a major role in making sense of Trobriand social organization, to which the institution of matrilineages is fundamental. Grasping the native’s point of view, then, involves seeing how its perplexing character (here expressed rather crassly as a case of native ignorance or confusion) can be overcome when understood in relation to how a totality of native beliefs and practices hang together. While Malinowski’s work is admittedly dated as an exemplar of anthropological analysis, it demonstrates in stark terms an order of recursivity that remains characteristic of (what I’m calling) the ‘mainstream’ of anthropology to this day. In particular, it demonstrates the two crucial moves of argument that anthropologists have made in order to engage with the alterity of their objects of study without allowing it to threaten the premises upon which their epistemic sovereignty is based. The first move is to gloss native alterity in terms of the notion of ‘belief ’. Even as it delineates the bases of native conceptions and practices as objects of study, this notion immediately neuters their potential recursively to modify the bases of the anthropological conceptions and practices that are brought to bear on them. Beliefs are things to which everyone Cambridge Anthropology • 125 Martin Holbraad is entitled, anthropologist and native alike, each to their own. Facilitated by this conceptual apartheid, the second move assimilates native belief to anthropological knowledge by showing the latter’s epistemic sovereignty over the former. Malinowski’s particular manner of doing this involved a combination of ‘holism’ and ‘functionalism’ – but a whole roll-call of ‘theoretical positions’ in the discipline’s history can be imagined as competing ways of delimiting the scope of the recursive effects of the native’s point of view by trumping it analytically with our own (Holbraad 2010, 2012: 18–53). Notwithstanding their otherwise divergent theoretical orientations, what these approaches share is a basic tendency to delimit recursivity as a matter of adjusting to the native’s point of view a body of knowledge that that is imagined as having logical/ epistemic priority over it. By contrast, the kind of recursivity Franklin and Napier’s articles instantiate implies a wholesale reversal of the logical/epistemic priority of anthropological knowledge. By analogy with the ‘new immunology’, Napier discusses this ‘new recursivity’ as a basic epistemic xenophilia: Others are accorded logical priority over the terms of analysis that are brought to bear on them, insofar as it is admitted that the latter may well be inadequate to the former (indeed, this would make the native points of view in question properly Other, constitutively lying beyond the analytical tools with which one is equipped in trying to ‘grasp’ them). In such a case, note, grasping the native’s point of view must involve a loss rather than an extension of the analyst’s epistemic sovereignty, since here alterity features not just as an object of anthropological knowledge, but also as its irreducible source. Without going into the detail of how this epistemic reversal might operate in practice (see Holbraad 2012: 237–65), we may use the analogy with immunology to show how it inverts each of the two ‘xenophobic’ moves of argument I identified earlier in relation to Malinowski and the mainstream approaches he, well, fathered. First, just as, according to Napier, the new immunology depicts immune responses as the body’s manner of engaging in symbiotic relations with viral information, so construing Others as a source (rather than just an object) of anthropological knowledge implies rendering relations between the two internal, in the philosophical sense (e.g., Moore 1922). Far from logically separate sets of beliefs or bodies of knowledge, the native’s and the analyst’s point of view stand in a relationship of mutual constitution, in which the native’s perspective is constituted as an artefact of anthropological knowledge, and thereby (recursively) provides the terms with which that knowledge itself is composed. Secondly, this internal relationship also implies a reversal of the flow of knowledge (sensu Wagner 1977 and Corsín Jiménez 2011). Instead of construing the production of knowledge as a matter of subjecting native beliefs to anthropological analysis, extending the dominion of anthropological understanding and theorization to include them also, knowledge is now imagined in reverse: the native’s point of view provides the basis on which the very infrastructure of anthropological understanding and theorization are transformed. So, much as with Napier’s new immunology, in this form of anthropological engagement the Self becomes Other to itself, in order better to engage with the Others that precipitate this transformation in the first place. Just as Napier describes for the body’s production of antibodies, anthropology’s capacity to engage with alterity emerges as a function of its capacity freely to transform its own 126 • Cambridge Anthropology A Comment on Franklin and Napier analytical wherewithal. So the structural equivalents of antibodies in this analogy are anthropologists’ acts of imagination, in which novel anthropological forms (analytical concepts and procedures, methodological operations, etc.) are creatively generated to match the novelty of the native points of view that precipitate them. Certainly, as Napier emphasizes, this kind of operation is risky – Selves constituted by their vulnerability to Others. And the risk, we might add, must also include itself in its own scope: to the extent that the novel notions of recursivity articulated by Franklin and Napier in their texts, or in my recursive commentary upon them, are generated recursively, they too are constitutively on the line, subject to future transformation in directions as yet unanticipated. The fun of the risk. References Corsín Jiménez, A. 2011. Daribi Kinship at Perpendicular Angles: A Trompe l’Oeil Anthropology. HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 1, no. 1: 141–57. Corsín Jiménez, A. in press. The Prototype: More than Many and Less than One. Journal of Cultural Economy. Franklin, S. 2013. In Vitro Anthropos: New Conception Models for a Recursive Anthropology? Cambridge Anthropology 31, no. 1: 3–32. Holbraad, M. 2010. Ontology is Just Another Word for Culture: Against the Motion. Debate and Discussion from GDAT 2008, (ed.) S. Venkatesan. Critique of Anthropology 30, no. 2: 179–85. Holbraad, M. 2012. Truth in Motion: The Recursive Anthropology of Cuban Divination. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lévi-Strauss, C. 1952. Race and History. Paris: UNESCO. Malinowski, B. 1932. The Sexual Life of Savages in North-western Melanesia. London: George Routledge and Sons, Ltd. Malinowski, B. 1954. Baloma: Spirits of the Dead in the Trobriand Islands. In Magic, Science and Religion. New York: Doubleday Anchor Books. Malinowski, B. 1961. Argonauts of the Western Pacific. New York: E.P. Dutton. Moore, G. E. 1922. External and Internal Relations. In Philosophical Studies, 276–309. New York: Harcourt, Brace. Napier, D. 2013. A New Sociobiology: Immunity, Alterity, and the Social Repertoire. Cambridge Anthropology 31, no. 2: 20–43. Strathern, M. 1992. After Nature: English Kinship in the Late Twentieth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Strathern, M. 2005. Kinship, Law and the Unexpected: Relatives are Always a Surprise. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Viveiros de Castro, E. 2002. O nativo relativo. Mana 8, no. 1: 113–48. Wagner, R. 1977. Analogic Kinship: A Daribi Example. American Ethnologist 4: 623–42. Martin Holbraad teaches in the Anthropology Department of University College London, where he co-runs the Cosmology, Religion, Ontology and Culture Research Group (CROC). He co-edited Thinking through Things: Theorising Artefacts Ethnographically (2007) and Technologies of the Imagination (Special Issue of Ethnos, 2009), and is author of Truth in Motion: The Recursive Anthropology of Cuban Divination (2012). Cambridge Anthropology • 127