Are Science and Society Going in the Same Direction? Leo Marx Science, Technology, & Human Values, Vol. 8, No. 4. (Autumn, 1983), pp. 6-9. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0162-2439%28198323%298%3A4%3C6%3AASASGI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-C Science, Technology, & Human Values is currently published by Sage Publications, Inc.. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/sage.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Sat Jun 23 16:03:32 2007 Are Science and Society Going in the Same Direction? Leo Marx O n 4 and 5 April 1983 the Chicago Museum o f Science and Industry celebrated its 50th anniversary with an invited conference titled, "Where Are W e Going!-Critical Issues i n Science and Technology. " This article is a slightly revised version o f Professor Marx's talk given there.-Ed. I first took the "we" in the title of this conference ("Where are W e Going?") to refer to our society or perhaps even to humanity, but the agenda indicates that the "we" most specifically refers to science and technology. The implication is that society (or humanity) is going where science and technology are going and that the activities of scientists and engineers in large measure will determine where all of us are going. As a cultural historian concerned about the interplay between science and technology on the one hand and society (and culture) on the other, I want to call that assumption into question. It is a dangerous mistake, I believe, to assume that what scientists and engineers do necessarily will be the primary determinant of where we go as a society. That assumption is the legacy of an old, outmoded conception of history, and I believe that scientists have an obligation to help us get rid of it as quickly as possible. Professor Marx i s the William R. Kenan Professor of American Cultural History, Program i n Science, Technology, and Society, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, C a mbridge, M A 02139. If the agenda of the Conference were limited to the question "where are science and technology going?" the answer would be obvious enough. We have little reason to doubt that science and technology will continue to advance from triumph to triumph as they have done at an accelerating rate for some 400 years now. Scientists and engineers will gain ever greater knowledge of natural processes, ever greater capacity to understand, control, manipulate, imitate, transform, and, in general, use the various elements of the bio-physicalchemical environment. In an impressively lucid paper describing some of the recent achievements of molecular science, one of the other participants in this conference, Roald Hoffmann of Cornell University, illustrates the remarkable expansion of human knowledge and power which results when scientists bring their collaborative intelligence and ingenuity to bear upon the natural environment. The tenor of Professor Hoffmann's remarks exemplifies the justifiably proud, selfassured, optimistic spirit of modern science, and the promise it holds forth of yet more impressive achievements in the future. However, contrary to popular belief, there is little reason to assume that such future achievements necessarily will lead to the resolution of the most urgent human problems. So far as scientific and technological progress encourages the still widespread public tendency to trust in a scientific-technological so- "Chemistry in 1983," presented at the 50th Anniversary Conference of the Chicago Museum of Science and Industry, 4 April 1983. O 1983 by the Massachusetts Inst~tuteof Technology and the President and Fellows of Hanard College. Published by John Wlley & Sons CCC 01 62-2439/83/040006-04$01.80 Science, Technology, el Human Values, Volume 8, Issue 4, pp. 6-9 [Fall 1983) Marx: Science and Society lution or "fix," thereby deflecting attention from the real character of our gravest problems, the future promise of science and technology could seriously impede their resolution. To dismiss the possibility of a scientific or technological "fix" is a commonplace of contemporary intellectual discourse, but too often the idea is treated as if it were a single, discrete, isolable, vulgar error-a tiny speck of bad thmking easily removed from the public eye. Unfortunately, the dangerous idea of a technical fix is embedded deeply in what was, and probably still is, our culture's dominant conception of history. Let me convey the spirit of this compelling ideology by citing an example from its heyday in the mid-19th century. This is an excerpt from the peroration of an address delivered by Daniel Webster, U.S. Senator from Massachusetts and spokesman for the industrial interests of New England. Widely esteemed as the nation's leading orator, Webster was speaking at the opening of a new railroad in New Hampshire in 1847: It is an extraordinary era in which we live. It is altogether new. The world has seen nothing like it before. I will not pretend, no one can pretend, to discern the end; but every body knows that the age is remarkable for scientific research into the heavens, the earth, and what is beneath the earth; and perhaps more remarkable still for the application of this scientific research to the pursuits of life. The ancients saw nothing like it. The moderns have seen nothing like it till the present generation. . . . We see the ocean navigated and the solid land traversed by steam power, and intelligence communicated by electricity. Truly this is almost a miraculous era. What is before us no one can say, what is upon us no one can hardly realize. The progress of the age has almost outstripped human belief; the future is known only to Omniscience.' The key word here is, of course, "progress." At the time the new railroad was for Americans the most popular embodiment of that Enlightenment idea, and Webster, like the general public then and now, ignored the fine distinction-so dear to sophisticated historians-between science and technology. So far as he and his audience were concerned, the scientdic and industrial revolutions were twin aspects of the same grand enterprise: research into the nature of nature and the application of that knowledge to the pursuits of life. That these activities were the primary driving force of modern history seemed obvious. And, by 7 simple extrapolation, that inference led to the belief that progress is the essence of the collective human enterprise; or, put differently, it led to the belief that history is characterized above all by the steady, cumulative, inevitable or perhaps preordained (or at least irreversible) expansion of human knowledge and power, and that such an expansion may be expected to produce improvements across the entire range of human endeavor: material, political, moral, aesthetic, and spiritual. Although the full-blown idea of progress, as it had been formulated by Condorcet and other Enlightenment thinkers, often had been couched in purely secular language, Webster's capitalized "Omniscience" ("the future is known only to Omniscience") added a touch of &vine providence; his tribute to science-based progress resonated with the strain of millenial optimism characteristic of evangelical Protestantism, the most influential American religion of the time. Thus, the secular belief in progress and the religious faith in the imminence of the earthly kingdom of God, or millenium, reinforced each other and often converged. The treacherous legacy of t h s grand, quasitheological myth of history is the lingering belief that a causal nexus exists between progress within science and technology and the general progress of humanity. The assumption is that the achievements of scientists and engineers translate more or less naturally and predictably-in the ordinary course of events-into solutions of such grave problems as material scarcity, the protection of the natural environment, the extension of social justice, and the avoidance of a catastrophic nuclear war. But why, one might well ask, should we bother to rehearse this well-known story at t h s late date? We know that the high water mark of the Victorian faith in progress is well behind us. In the United States it may have occurred as early as the eve of World War I, but since Hiroshima the tide of that faith manifestly has been ebbing. In 1933, the year the Chicago Museum of Science and Industry was founded, the tide was still running strong. That was the year of the Chicago "Century of Progress" International Exposition, whose theme was "progress through the application of science to industry." In the Exposition's Hall of Science stood a large sculpture: A man and woman, nearly lifesized, stretched out their hands, "as if in fear or ignorance." Between them stood "a huge angular robot nearly twice their size, bending low over them, with an angular me- 8 Science, Technology, eJ Human Values-Fall 1983 tallic arm thrown reassuringly around each." In the official Guidebook of the Fair appeared the sobering motto "SCIENCE FINDS-INDUSTRY APPLIES-MAN CONFORMS."~But after World War 11, to repeat, this simple faith began to ebb more rapidly. The change is often revealed in the writings of scientists, and it is poignantly revealed in the paper by Roald Hoffmann referred to above. Until the final three-sentence paragraph, the tone of the paper-as Professor Hoffmann confidently predicts the future triumphs of molecular science in understanding chemical mechanisms, in freeing us from dependence upon fossil fuels, etc.-is almost as exultant as Daniel Webster's. The paper exudes trust in progress-but only progress within science. When he turns to the crucial nexus between science and society, however, Professor Hoffmann's tone becomes rueful, tentative, questioning, uncertain. "And in the process of attaining all that knowledge," he asks, "will we do it without destroying our environment, our cultural heritage, and ourselves? Will we be able to use our better understanding of the universe to improve our life and yet keep feeling, as man must, the eternal forces of nature? I think we must." Judging by these sad rhetorical questions, it is clear that Professor Hoffmann, like most of us, no .longer shares the old faith. But I submit that its ghost hovers over his paper, as it does over much of contemporary discourse about the relations among science, technology, and society. If one devotes more than eight pages to the inspiring advances to be expected from molecular science and then, in conclusion, abruptly leaps to the need, in the process, to avoid "destroying our environment, our cultural heritage, and ourselves," then the connection between the two parts-the body of the paper and its conclusion-unavoidably becomes problematic. What is the tacit rationale behind that extraordinary transition? I suggest that it is an unspoken tribute to the logical abyss in our thinking created by the receding faith in progress. The missing connection is a vestige of the old expectation, no longer tenable but not yet repudiated, that in the natural course of events thk achievements of molecular science will be translated into social progress, ~h~~~ is a sense in which the rhetorical structure Of Professor Hoffmann's argument, for all his manifest lack of faith, derives from the generous but unwarranted of a natural, tO-be-ex~ected of scientific progress to social progress. I do not wish to detract from the achievements of molecular science. But I am suggesting that there is much less significant connection than adherents of the progressive faith would have us believe between our new chemical knowledge and our ability, say, to clean up toxic waste dumps in the United States. New knowledge of chemical processes, like all advances in science and technology, is a potential source of power but is useless in answering the two questions that will determine whether we pollute our environment: Who controls the power? To what end? If the EPA is controlled by persons who attach a low priority to the protection of the environment, then none of the advances predicted by Professor Hoffmann is likely to help to protect it. A banality, to be sure, but a great many Americans cling to the old faith. They continue to cherish the hope, for example, that scientists and engineers will discover a solution to the nuclear dilemma-that they may yet come up with the "ultimate" defense against nuclear attack. President Reagan himself illustrated t h s widely held belief when, on 23 March 1983, he announced that he was initiating a program aimed at "eliminating the threat posed by nuclear missiles." He called upon "the scientific community who [sic] gave us nuclear weapons to turn their great talents to the cause of mankind and world peace: to give us the means of rendering these nuclear weapons impotent and ~ b s o l e t e . "The ~ approach described in what the press quickly named President Reagan's "Star Wars" speech was an all-or-nothing reliance upon scientific progress as the means of ending the arms race. The President advocated a vast new build-up of nuclear armaments until such time as scientists and engineers devised a sure-fire technological defense against nuclear attack. The only people who will have much success in persuading the public that such a resolution of the arms race is extremely unlikely are the scientists and engineers themselves. They should be the ones to say, loudly and clearly, that they have almost no hope of devising an absolutely Let me emphasize that the locus of the dlfficulty is a rhetorical structure which embodies the vestiges of the old progressive faith. Since writing this commentary I have had an extended discussion of the issues with Roald Hoffmann, and it seems evident that his concluding sentences had less of the aspect of a considered judgment than a conventionalized, almost ritual statement. As a cultural historian, however, I would argue that this rhetorical convention embodies the residue o r a widely held belief system or world view Marx: Science and Society reliable defense against nuclear weapons. AS the heroes of the old myth, scientists and engineers have a responsibility to repudiate that sometimes pleasurable if misleading role. Few arguments could be more useful today than one aimed at persuadmg the world that science and technology, essential as they are, cannot save us. It is not enough, in other words, for scientists and engineers to be skeptical about the old progressive myth. They have an obligation to help us rid our thinking entirely of its obfuscating influence. Our ability to understand and control the natural environment is of crucial importance, yet it has only marginal value in the enhancement of our ability to understand and control the social environment. That discrepancy helps to explain why we have made so little headway in closing the famous gap between the "two cultures." The diffusion of scientific and technological knowledge is a necessary but not sufficient basis for genuine progress. The most urgent problems on the human 9 agenda inhere in the man-made, not the natural, environment. They are political, not scientific, and thus scientific progress cannot be the basis for their resolution. Notes 1. "Opening of the Northern Railroad," remarks made at Grafton and Lebanon, NH, The Writings and Speeches of Daniel Webster, Volume N (1903):105117. For a detailed analysis of Webster's speech and his reaction to the new machine technology, see Leo Marx, The Machine i n the Garden: Technology and the Pastoral Ideal in America (NewYork: Oxford University Press, 19641, pp. 209-220. 2. This sculpture is described in Lowell Tozer, "A Century of Progress, 1833-1 933: Technology's Triumph Over Man," American Quarterly, Volume 4, Number 78 (1952). 3. The N e w York Times (24 March 1983):A20.