General equilibrium analysis: Welfare results in pure exchange Lectures in Microeconomic Theory Fall 2010, Part 12 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 Pareto efficiency Edgeworth box The initial endowment is not Pareto-efficient, since both consumers can be b made d b better off ff by moving to x (x1 , x 2 ) 21 x (x1 , x 2 ) 22 x ( x , x ) 1 2 (1 , 2 ) 12 1 is Paretoefficient, since no consumer can be made better off without making the other worse off. 11 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 2 1 Illustrating the first welfare theorem First welfare theorem: Assume that Any Walrasian equilibriumxis (x1 , x 2 ) Pareto-efficient. is a Walrasian x2 x2 x1 p ( p1 , p2 ) x1 equilibrium. Then it is not feasible to make b h consumers both better off. Why? 07.07.2010 3 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 Illustrating the second welfare theorem Assume that Second welfare theorem: x (x1 , x 2 ) Any Pareto-efficient Pareto efficient allocation is Pareto efficient. can be implemented as a If utility functions Walrasian equilibrium. x are quasi-concave, then x can be implemented as a Walrasian equilibrium How? 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 4 2 Why is quasi-concavity assumed in the second welfare theorem? x (x1 , x 2 ) is still Pareto efficient, but the allocation cannot be implemented as a Walrasian equilibrium because of consumer 1’s nonconvex preferences. x Kinks — no problem. 07.07.2010 5 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 Weak and strong Pareto efficiency A feasible allocation ( x 1 , x 2 ) is weakly Pareto - efficient u2 if there is no other feasible allocation ( x 1 , x 2 ) such that u i ( x i ) u i ( x i ) for both i . A feasible allocation ( x 1 , x 2 ) is strongly Pareto - efficient (u(1u(1x(1x),1 ), u 2u(2x(2x))2 )) (u1 (x1 ), u 2 (x 2 )) if there is no other feasible u1 allocation ( x 1 , x 2 ) such that u i ( x i ) u i ( x i ) for both i , and u i ( x i ) u i ( x i ) for one i . 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 6 3 Equivalence of weak and strong PE Assumption : For each i , u i is (1) continuous (2) strictly quasi - concave, and ((3)) monotone ((i.e.,, x x implies p u i ( x ) u i ( x ) )). Result. Under the assumption on the utility functions, an allocation is weakly Pareto efficient if and only if it is strongly Pareto efficient. Proof. If ( x 1 , x 2 ) is strongly PE, then ( x 1 , x 2 ) is weakly PE. If ( x 1 , x 2 ) is not strongly PE, then there is ( x 1 , x 2 ) s.t. u i ( x i ) u i ( x i ) for both i , and u i ( x i ) u i ( x i ) for one i . By transferri ng from i , both can be made better off. 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 7 First welfare theorem Result. If ( x 1 , x 2 , p ) is a Walrasian equilibr., then ( x 1 , x 2 ) is weakly Pareto efficient. Proof. Suppose ( x 1 , x 2 , p ) is a Walrasian equilibr., where ( x 1 , x 2 ) is not weakly Pareto efficient. Then there is a feasible allocation ( x 1 , x 2 ) such that u i ( x i ) u i ( x i ) for both i . Hence, 1 2 x 1 x 2 and p x i p i for both i . This leads to a contradict ion : p 1 2 p x 1 x 2 p x 1 p x 2 p 1 p 2 . 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 8 4 Second welfare theorem Result. Suppose the assumption on the utility functions holds. If the feasible allocation ( x 1 , x 2 ) is PE, then there is a p such that ( x 1 , x 2 , p ) is a Walrasian equilibr. x12 x22 Set of aggregate consumption vectors that lead to a Pareto improvement. P x1 x2 p ( p1 , p2 ) x11 x12 07.07.2010 9 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 Second welfare theorem — sketch of proof The set P is convex since the utility functions are quasi-concave. x12 x22 The monotonicity of utility functions combined with strict quasi-concavity leads to the existence of p 0 such that px p x 1 x 2 for all x P . The continuity of utility functions leads to px p x 1 x 2 for all x P . P x1 x2 p ( p1 , p2 ) x11 x12 Suppose ( x 1 , x 2 , p ) is not a Walrasian equilibrium with ( x 1 , x 2 ) as initial endowments. Then there exists i and x i such that u i ( x i ) u i ( x i ) and px i px i . Contradiction: p x i x i p x i x i and x i x i P . 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 10 5 Welfare maximization Pareto efficiency does not yield a specific allocation. This can be resolved by assuming the existence of a social welfare function, W ( u1 , u 2 ) , that is increasing in each of its arguments. Result. If ( x 1 , x 2 ) maximizes a social welfare function, then ( x 1 , x 2 ) is strongly Pareto efficient. P f If it Proof. i would ld have h b been possible ibl to increase i ui without decreasing the utility of the other consumer, then it would have been possible to increase W ( u1 , u 2 ). 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 11 Supporting a strongly PE allocation u2 (u1 (x1 ), u 2 (x2 )) U (a1 , a2 ) u1 07.07.2010 Question: If ( x 1 , x 2 ) is strongly PE, does there exists a social welfare func func tion a1 u1 ( x 1 ) a 2 u 2 ( x 2 ) such that maximization of this social welfare function leads to ( x 1 , x 2 ) ? Answer: The utility possipossi bility set U must be convex. Concave utility functions ensure this in pure exchange. G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 12 6 Determining the supporting welfare weights a i 1 i 1 v i ( p , px i ) m i u2 v 2 (p , m 2 ) a m 2 slope : v1 ( p , m1 ) a m1 1 2 a1 07.07.2010 (u1 ( x1 ), u 2 ( x 2 )) U ( a1 , a2 ) 2 1 v1 ( p , m1 ) m1 a 2 u1 Intuition? v 2 (p , m 2 ) m 2 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 13 To recapitulate: Competitive equilibria are always Pareto efficient. Pareto efficient allocations are competitive equilibria with quasi-concave u-functions & endowm. redistrib. Welfare maxima are always Pareto efficient. Pareto efficient allocations are welfare maxima with concave u-functions for some choice of welfare weights. 07.07.2010 G.B. Asheim, ECON4230-35, #12 14 7