Constraints on Lexical NP Selection Referential NP generation is the task of building a description for an object that is known to the generator, under the assumption that hte hearer wants to know who the referent is. The received wisdom is that there is a hierarchy of NPs that one could use for this task starting with the local pronouns and the reflexive and reciprocal pronouns, going down through third person pronouns, demonstrative pronouns, names, demonstrative lexical NPs, definite descriptions down to indefinite descrptions. The task is a question of walking down the hierarchy and to see whether the NP type in question is appropriate: if it works, the choice is right. If it does not work, one takes a step down in the hierarchy. The hierarchy is related to the quality of the identification, the ease of identification and to the power supplied to the hearer by the identification. The quality can be described as the reliability of the identification, ease as the amount of effort that the hearer needs to put into the identification and power as the handle that the hearer will get on the referent. Local pronouns give a very high degree of all three properties: for singular local pronouns, identification is almost guaranteed, the referents are higly activated, and the referents are given in the speech situation where the hearer is observing them, address them or carry out other action. For indefinites the three dimensions are low: effort is high since the referent is new, it is only the full clause that gives a unique description, and that description is not guaranteed to enable any action on the referent. The whole hierarchy guarantees identification. Certain uses of definite descriptions do not have the uniqueness property but they share with referential indefinite descriptions the property that a unique description is provided by the nominal material together with the rest of the clause (the Evans property). The talk is about the lexical NPs and explores the hypothesis that the same three concerns give the preferences in the choice of lexical material and the choice for the article. The speaker chooses the material and the article, guided by his take on the hearer strategy and resources. Non-unique descriptions with the definite article would be prefered over other descriptions because of ease and power. They are evaluated by direct association to elements in the common ground which serve as antecedent, as origin of a bridge or as indirect indicator of the referent. This requires little effort and the antecedent offers the best possible handle on the referent. Bridging does not guarantee uniqueness. Non-unique definite descriptions are not able to accommodate in the strict sense. Unique descriptions require the definite article, and freely allow accommodation. Accommodating descriptions are distinguished from indefinite descriptions in giving more power by allowing at least two full strategies of identification: from the main eventuality in the clause and from the description itself. The hypothesis predicts a preference for nonunique descriptions that identify the referent directly over bridging uses by ease. And of bridging uses over unique descriptions. The Evans property entails that in choosing lexical material for an indefinite reference, identity is still a consideration. The full clause must yield a unique description of the referent. But bridging is also central for the choice of the description in indefinites. A bridge or a subsection increases the power of the hearer on the referent and if possible should have preference over descriptions that do not have one. Both givenness and uniqueness are obligatory marked by a definte article and while they often coincide, they need not. 1