24 Two To be reckoned among nations A nation is a group of people united by a common error about their ancestry and a common dislike of their neighbors. 1 A nalytically, we may distinguish between three concepts of the nation: The nation as a political community, more or less coterminous with a sovereign state; the nation as a subjective community; and the nation as a cultural community, with emphasis on language or other "objective" factors. Varieties of all three are in contemporary use. This ambiguity is deeply rooted in history, and indicates how the path to nationhood has been far from uniform. Today's nation concept is far removed from the original Latin natio (from nasci, to be born), which designated groups of people that were foreign, i.e. different from the Romans by birth, race, or origin. The elusiveness of our contemporary nation concept is the result of a series of semantic changes over the centuries in different parts of Europe, from a community of origin (geographically and/or linguistically) among university students, via a community of opinion, a political, cultural and social elite, to a sovereign people, and finally a unique people.2 Historically, the criteria that must be filled in order for an entity to be reckoned among nations have varied, as have indeed the criteria for inclusion in one particular nation. Varying features of nationhood have been emphasized; among the most prominent of these have been national character (expressed through shared values, customs and traditions); a connection to a territory; a common government and common laws; shared history, religion, language and origins.The idea that people belonging to certain nations share a national character, certain features and ways of behaving that are more or less objectively given, can be dated back to the Middle Ages, and had become widely accepted in Europe by the mid 18th century.3 For obvious reasons, the habit of equating nation with race largely went out of fashion after the Second World War, as did the notion of national character. It gave way to the notion of "national identity", which is perceived as subjectively defined rather than objectively given, flexible rather than unchangeable, varying according to context rather than permanent. 1 European saying, quoted in Robert King: Minorities under communism (1973:5). 2 Leah Greenfeld: Nationalism (1992:4–9). See also Louis L. Snyder: Encyclopedia of nationalism (1990), Aira Kemiläinen: Nationalism (1964); John Hutchinson & Anthony D. Smith: Nationalism (1994); Walker Connor: Ethnonationalism (1994). 3 Anthony D. Smith: National identity (1991:85–86). 25 Roughly speaking, there were two main paths to nationhood in Europe. One path was the familiar nationalist, where a national movement helped form, or in their own eyes, reawakened the nation. The other path was the path of the "first-born"4 West European nations, where a nation was formed within the borders of an existing state. In the nationalist version, the nation was a cultural community, while the "first-born" nations were first and foremost civic nations. This distinction should, however, not be exaggerated. Before the French Revolution, the features of nation in France had been a connection to a territory (or a land), including common laws and government, and a national character. In the course of the Revolution, "nation" got the additional meaning of a whole people and a sovereign people, thereby strengthening the political conception of nationhood. This also implied that nation was a community of will, not just any people living within the territory of a state. Among the Germans, nation acquired ethno-cultural rather than political connotations. The attributes of the nation were common (racial) origins and country, often associated with common language, laws and customs. This idea of nationhood was much more closed and differential than the French. Aira Kemaläinen argues that the Holy Roman Empire of the German nation (as a loose confederation rather than a state), was essential in shaping the original German conception of nation as a community of descent and language. Another important factor was the zone of ethno-culturally mixed populations in Eastern Europe, where German identity was defined ethno-culturally in relation to the Slavs.5 The philosophers of German Romanticism elaborated on this ethno-cultural conception of nationhood, perceiving nations as historically rooted, organic entities, regulated by natural laws rather than human will, and imbued with a specific, unique spirit, a Volksgeist. The role of the state was to provide shelter for this cultural organism, whose true spirit found expression through the native language.6 A nation is a state ... None of the conventional meanings of nation are "wrong." On the other hand, one of them should be avoided for the sake of clarity: namely, the all-too-common equation of the word "nation" with state (or also nation-state) – cf. the United Nations. In this meaning "nationality" equals "citizenship", with no questions asked about the subjective identity or cultural attributes of the population. For our purposes, a definition along these lines would be unsatisfactory and confusing, chiefly because the lack of congruence between nation and state is often a major point of contention for national movements: The classic nationalist goal is to secure "a state of its own" for the nation. Hence, for the study of nationalism, the nation cannot be any group of people living within an existing state framework. 4 5 6 The term was coined by Leah Greenfeld (1992). See Kemiläinen (1964:39) and Rogers Brubaker: Citizenship and nationhood in France and Germany (1992:5–7). A different German tradition evolved in Prussia, where the meaning of nation came to be understood more along (French) political lines. See Brubaker (1992: pp. 9 ff.) for more on this. 26 The rest of this discussion will focus on two other rivaling nation concepts. These may conveniently be labeled voluntarist and cultural nation concepts, since they focus, respectively, on voluntary adherence and on certain shared objective features, such as language, religion, ethnicity and shared history. These are of course not mutually exclusive notions. ... is a "daily plebiscite" ... In a lecture held at the Sorbonne in 1882, which appeared in print the same year under the title Qu’est-ce qu’une nation?, the French historian Ernest Renan spoke of the nation as "a daily plebiscite" (un plébiscite de tous les jours) – perhaps one of the most quoted phrases in the literature on nationalism even today. Renan regarded a nation as a spiritual human community, endowed with a past, but also with a desire to uphold it through a day-to-day vote of confidence. According to Renan, not only does the nation share common memories, it also shares an amnesia, a collective forgetfulness that enables the members to forget past differences, while concentrating on the things that link them together. Renan's concept of the nation owes much to Rousseau, and conveys a close relationship between the nation idea and the idea of rule by the sovereign people. The nation, according to Rousseau, was the sovereign people. Yet, Rousseau thought of a society whose members shared common customs as the best foundation for a political society: The people that are fit for legislation – the people that should be sovereign – should already be "united by some common bond of origin, interest or convention."7 Here the voluntary aspect becomes blurred. The nation in Renan's scheme was an entity united by the same political institutions, the same rules and regulations, the same rights and obligations, which made membership in the nation more a matter of voluntary choice than a matter of birth or blood. His insistence that it would be wrong to attribute to nations racial, religious, linguistic, or physiographical connotations must be seen in light of the French experience, what the French were and what they were not at that time. They were certainly not a homogeneous cultural community. The transition from peasants to Frenchmen was not completed until the early 20th century, according to a muchquoted study by Eugen Weber.8 Later on "French-ness" acquired an additional cultural meaning, including food, beverage, language, customs and traditions. This culturally French identity permeated the masses only after compulsory education was introduced during the 1880s.9 The notion of an ancestry of blood never entered the French national idea; the French nation was thus inclusive where the German was exclusive. 7 Jean-Jacques Rousseau: The social contract (1762), quoted in Anthony H. Birch: Nationalism and national integration (1989:15). 8 Eugen Weber: Peasants into Frenchmen (1976), referred in Connor (1994); Geoff Eley & Ronald Grigor Suny (eds.): Becoming national (1996:7). 9 Douglas Johnson: The making of the French nation, in: Mikuláš Teich/Roy Porter (eds): The national question in Europe in historical context (1993:52). 27 The merit of a voluntarist nation concept is the idea of an identity inherent in it – and, even more important, an identity that may to a certain extent be chosen. A nation is not a fixed entity that we are born into, but a community of people with a mutual feeling of belonging together. The existence of a nation presupposes a subjective identity, which is acquired; hence, nations are capable of change, incorporating new members, expanding and declining. A nation concept like this allows for the fact that at times there may be groups of people with dual or no distinct feeling of national identity at all. It also allows for the fact that people occasionally change national denomination, if not in the course of one generation, as least in two or three. This is especially important for understanding the processes that led to the formation of nations, and in accounting for the fact that nations have a beginning, and possibly also an end. Second, a voluntarist nation concept includes only those who are aware of belonging to the nation. This enables us to distinguish between a situation where nobody feel that they belong together in a national community, a situation where some feel that they belong together and a situation where all have this feeling. This allows us to distinguish between stages in the evolution of national awareness, and to describe nation forming as a gradual process. Nations exist not by virtue of some common objective feature, like skin color, language, or religion, but by virtue of our identification with people that are like us: they are in the famous phrase of Benedict Anderson "imagined communities."10 Hence, where no documentation can be found proving that such sentiments were very common, no nation can be said to have existed. And nothing of the kind can be proven for the Middle Ages or the ancient world.11 Most pre-modern communities are then ruled out, as well quite a few of the present-day entities that claim to be nations. One the other hand, an exclusively voluntarist nation concept makes it impossible to distinguish between a situation where only some feel that they belong together and a situation where all have this feeling, because separating "some" from "all" implies using a criterion other than voluntary adherence. This would mean that even the smallest elite starting to define itself as a nation must be considered a nation. We need to be able to distinguish between state populations and nations, between ethnic groups and nations, and between national movements and nations. A strictly voluntarist nation concept does not permit any of this. Finally, to perceive the nation as something entirely voluntary would be to understate both the stability of national identities and the amount of coercion involved. For one thing, national identities have been known to persist for years under foreign oppression. This suggests a stability outside the domain of will alone. Second, even the French model nation is not quite as voluntary as it may seem. France was made into a unit by conquest, and the incorporation processes that led to a common identity were certainly not without coercive elements. 10 11 Benedict Anderson: Imagined communities (1991:6-7). Even if it did exist, we would not be able to prove the existence of an all-encompassing national sentiment in the Middle Ages, since the available sources are at the most reliable for the literate strata. (See Chapter One, page 14). 28 ... is a community of culture In his 1913 manifesto on Marxism and the national question, Josef Stalin defined the nation as a historically constituted, stable community of people, formed on the basis of a common language, territory, economic life and psychological make-up, manifested in a common culture.12 This is entirely in line with Otto Bauer's nation concept. It is often quoted in the literature on nationalism as an example of a purely cultural definition, since it leaves out the notion of an subjective awareness altogether. Where the voluntarist nation concept is rooted in the experience of the French and the British, the cultural nation concept has deep roots in German and East European soil. The nation in the German meaning is not some accidental group of people, but a people bound together by culture, by language, by birth, by history. This is a culturally distinct entity, an organic whole, something to be born into, rather than a matter of choice by a sovereign people. German romantic philosophers like Herder and Fichte added the conception of language as the soul of the nation and the main differentiating principle. Their influence has been profound and lasting. Even today some scholars, not to mention nationalists, see language as the main constituting feature of nations. Other candidates are ethnicity, religion and a shared history. A cultural nation concept has some obvious merits. By emphasizing culture and language, we exclude heterogeneous state populations from the concept, and the entities we normally think of as nations do have certain cultural features in common. Moreover, an identity, separating us from the others, presupposes that we have something in common that they do not have, a certain "sameness" in cultural values and attributes that can be recognized. It does not imply that this sameness has existed from time immemorial. On the contrary, common features may be more or less recently "construed" or "invented",13 and they may have spread from an original elite to the masses. That does not make them any less real. Today most scholars of nationalism reject an exclusively cultural or objective nation concept, and rightly so in my opinion, mainly because objective criteria claiming general validity are hard to come by. A closer look at the main candidate – language – may serve to illustrate the problem. First, although the differences between literary languages may be easily observable, dialect boundaries tend to be fuzzy rather than sharp. In Europe, the Magyars and the Basques are probably the only people who beyond doubt are linguistically different from all their neighbors. Second, nation is not always coterminous with language. There are people who speak different languages and see themselves as one nation – notably the Swiss. There are numerous other people who speak the same language, but regard themselves as different nations, like the Germans and the Austrians, or the British, the Australians and the Americans. Likewise, the Serbs, the Croats and the Muslims of former Yugoslavia speak basically the same language, albeit with some nuances in dialect that criss-cross the national divide. 12 Quotation in Teich & Porter (1993: xvii). 13 I will return to this debate in the next chapter. 29 The same exercise could be applied to other criteria. Upon reviewing the main alleged criteria (language, religion, ethnicity, holy icons), Eric Hobsbawm concludes that no single criterion is applicable to all cases, and consequently, that no feature is indispensable for the formation of national identities.14 He does, however, concede that when such common features exist, they make the job of national movements easier, as they serve as a foundation for mobilizing the masses. This indicates that it is not the differentiating feature per se that is important, but the fact that it sets "us" apart from "the others." Another problem is of course that, regardless of what kind of features we see as constituting nationhood, a cultural concept of nation means that we would not be able to distinguish between what Anthony D. Smith calls ethnic categories (people who have certain cultural attributes in common but do not define themselves as a group), ethnie, (where some people are aware of their common attributes), and nations, (where most people are aware that they "belong together").15 Again, we are deprived of the possibility of describing the forming of nations as a process. Cultural sameness is obviously not enough either. National identity – a combined notion Our conception of "nation" should include both a certain cultural sameness (it may include language, and in most cases it will) and a feeling of belonging to a community. A nation may then be defined as a historically constituted community of people who share a common culture, including one or more differentiating cultural features, created and recreated by people with a mutual feeling of belonging together. National identities thus exist in our minds as ideas of who we are and with whom we belong. This subjective identification thrives on a certain sameness, some cultural features that are seen as constituting the national community. It is this sameness that enables the members of a community to recognize each other as belonging to the same community, and by the same token recognize non-members as outsiders or foreigners. The ability of a nation to incorporate new members depends both on the willingness of newcomers to change their identity, and on the willingness of the host nation to accept them as conationals. A corollary is that nations are more or less open to newcomers, depending on what the constituting features are believed to be. A national identity that is tied to residence and adherence to certain political institutions is open to newcomers, an identity tied to ancestry is typically closed, while a national identity that is first and foremost based on language is neither completely open nor completely closed. Finally, while any cultural feature may be acquired in the course of a few generations, assimilation may still be barred if one's physical features remain outside the bounds of "normal appearance" in the national community. 14 See Eric Hobsbawm: Nations and nationalism since 1780 (1992), Chapter 2. 15 Anthony D. Smith: National identity (1991).