Explaining Clausal Exclamatives

advertisement
Johann Wolfgang Goethe-Universität Frankfurt am Main
7. November 2006
Explaining Clausal Exclamatives
Kjell Johan Sæbø
University of Oslo
•
Long-term task: Learn more about the relation between sentence types and Speech acts
–
Because: Searle used an indiscriminate notion of Propositional Content; but:
Sentences used as utterances can have various logical types, and not every type
is appropriate for every act
(Ex.: Questions (erotetics) are normally done with interrogative sentences,
of type <<s,t>,t> (Karttunen-style) or <s,<s,t>> (Groenendijk-Stokhof-style);
with some interesting exceptions (Gunlogson 2003))
+
Recent renewed interest in these issues, inspired by Krifka (2001), Zaefferer (2001),
projects at the Department of Cognitive Linguistics (Frankfurt) and the ZAS (Berlin)
•
Short-term task:
Answer the question "What about sentences of type <s,t>, denoting propositions, as
opposed to sentences of type t, normally used for assertions?"
*
Claim
*
Such utterances are normally used as Expressives:
Exclamatives or Optatives
*
Hypothesis
*
Utterances of necessarily or ostensively true <s,t> sentences are used as Exclamatives –
and predictably so:
Whenever a true proposition denoting sentence is uttered, the natural way to make sense of it
is to supplement an exclamative speech act function; the default modal attitude towards a fact
at the speech act origo (I, now), typically astonishment, but occasionally emotionally flavoured
as annoyance, joy, or marvel (similarly Rexach 1996 and Zaefferer 2001). Particularly – contra
e.g. Rexach (1996), Zanuttini and Portner (2003), and Rett (2006) – there is no (need for an)
exclamative syntax or semantics.
2
2
Varieties of type <s,t> sentence utterances – mono- and crosslinguistically
2.1
"That" clauses (as ostensively true <s,t> sentences)
English barely makes use of "that" clauses as independent utterances.
French has "que" – but with the indicative, this is a wh- or relative "que" (see section 2.2.1);
and with the (here covert) subjunctive, "que" clauses encode counterfactual wish (optative):
(1)
Que la foudre tombe sur une pareille maison!
Wenn doch der Blitz in so ein Haus einschlagen würde!
I wish lightning would strike that house!
(attested translation)
(attested translation)
(attested translation)
Delimit also from cases of ellipsis (contextual binding), as in (2) (attested translations):
(2)
"I hear you know a great deal about Stine and me. That we live like a married couple!"
"J’me suis laissé dire que Niels en sait un bout sur la vie qu’on mène, Stine et moi.
Qu’on est comme qui dirait mari et femme!"
German (and Scandinavian), however, fairly freely uses "dass" clauses to express facts:
(3)
Dass die U-Bahn noch fährt!
‘Well, I never, the tube is still running!’
(Schwabe 2004)
(4)
Dass du dich daran noch erinnerst...!
‘It’s amazing that you still remember!’
(attested)
The theory of "that" ("que", "dass", "at") is that it presupposes and preserves a proposition:1
(D2)
that* =
λϕ<s,t> ϕ
Anyway, the result is a proposition. Now the assertion operator is usually taken to operate on
propositions (Krifka 2001: 21); but "that" clauses are inappropriate as assertion utterances. !?
Proposal: The assertion function is a function from i.a. type t, truth value denoting sentences.
2.2
Indirect Questions (as necessarily true <s,t> sentences)
Standard case:
(5)
How cold it is!
Wie kalt es ist!
Combien il fait froid!
(rare; cf. below)
Derivation of "how cold it is", according to Groenendijk and Stokhof (1997 and earlier)
equivalent to "that it is (at least) as cold as it is" (simplified) (in two-sorted type theory,
with possible-world variables w and an actual-world variable v:
1
Cf. Fabricius-Hansen and Sæbø 2004; assuming, with Heim and Kratzer (1997: 308), a composition principle
"Intensional Functional Application" yielding a proposition if none there be:
ƒ<<s,t>,a>(g<t>) = ƒ(λv g)
3
(5D)
λw t°w ≤ t°v
how cold
λw t°w ≤ @(t°w)
C
t°v ≤ @(t°v)
λϕ<s,t> ϕ
it is
Ø
t°v ≤ @(t°v)
how
λα α ≥ @(α)
cold
t°v
More complex cases will be more difficult, of course. But this illustrates the general plot:
• The wh- word is assumed to introduce an equation between two values where one is bound
to the actual world through the actuality operator @ – for any w, @ζ = ζ[w/v]
• The raising to Spec,CP is assumed to trigger intensionalization, by making C visible;
a visible C, like a subjunction, introduces the identity function over propositions.
That C is made visible is argued by examples like:
(6) Whan that Aprill with his shoures soote ...
(Chaucer)
There are many variations on this theme and points where exclamatives deviate from "normal"
(embedded) indirect questions, syntactically as well as semantically. I will consider such
deviations in two separate subsections, one for syntax and one for semantics.
4
2.2.1
Syntactic Specialties
For one thing, in French the customary way to form the exclamative is not as in (5), but as in
(7) (note the stranded adjective in both cases). Swedish has a similar pattern.
(7)
Comme il fait froid!2 / ((Qu’est-)Ce) Qu’il fait froid!
Norwegian has a special "wh- word" reflecting the equative question semantics directly, "så":
(8)
Så lite (som) han forstår!
so little that he understands
How little he knows!
Wie wenig er versteht!
(Corpus original)
(Corpus translation)
(Corpus translation)
The forms in (7) and (8) cannot be embedded under predicates like "ask" or "wonder". But
that is no wonder, since clauses embedded under those predicates have a higher logical type
(in the theory of Groenendijk and Stokhof: <s,<s,t>>) (cannot embed "that" clauses).
The forms in (7) and (8) can to a certain extent be embedded under predicates like "know":
(9)
Elle sait comme il fait froid dehors.
and they can to a great extent be embedded under predicates like "amazing":
(10)
C’est fou comme elle est belle.
C’est fou ce que j’aime cette femme quand elle rit.
(Laurent Réval)
That is not amazing – after all, these predicates seem to mean approximately the same as the
exclamative speech act function.
German has adjective stranding + finite verb raising (V2) as an alternative to (5):
(11)
Heimatliche Natur! Wie bist du treu mir geblieben!
homely
nature how are you faithful me remained
(Hölderlin: Der Wanderer)
There is also the option of "was" (what) instead of "wie" (how):
(12)
Was bist du groß geworden!
what are you big become
This V2 pattern cannot occur embedded. No way.
(13) * Irre, was/wie bist du groß geworden.
crazy what how are you big become
Suggestion: The syntactic peculiarities of exclamatively used
indirect questions are signs that the clause cannot be embedded
2
Mais le septième trouva Blanche-Neige sur son lit et appela les autres pour la leur montrer;
– Oh! comme elle est belle! dirent-ils tous.
5
2.2.2
Semantic Specialties
• Not every IQ has the same interpretation as an exclamative as as an embedded question.
• Not every IQ is appropriate as an exclamative (IQ = Indirect Question).
2.2.2.1
Scalar Interpretations
First •: As noted by Elliott (1974), as an exclamative, a wh- word has a scalar interpretation:3
(14)
He may be a genius, but Jesus, how he eats.
(about Duke Ellington)
vs.:
..., but have you noticed how he eats? (nonscalar interpretation possible)
or
..., but do you realize how he eats?
(nonscalar interpretation possible)4
(15)
a.
b.
Quelle voix elle a!
Tu ne sais pas quelle voix elle a.
(only scalar interpretation possible)
(nonscalar interpretation possible)
(15a) seems to mean "that the voice she has is as A as it is" for an underspecified adjective A.
The same sentence in (15b) can have this interpretation, but it can also have a nonscalar one.
(Compare, On sait combien il fait has only a "nonscalar" reading: …
λw t°w = t°v , cf. (5).)
Suggestion:
If a scalar interpretation is available, it is selected because
the utterance communicates that the fact is remarkable
Zanuttini and Portner (2003) encode scalarity in a context change operator Rwidening
(which is supposed to be interpreted into the clause on the basis of pragmatic reasoning).
The IQ is supposed to denote a set of propositions, the set of true answers (Karttunen-style).
Rwidening has a superset condition (i) and an scale condition (ii); jointly they express extremity.
To be precise, let us try to apply these two conditions to the simple case (5). Suppose that "how cold it is" wrt. w and
[0,-10] denotes the set {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is ≤ -9}. Then "R(how cold it is)" wrt. w and [0,-10] must denote a superset,
say, {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is ≤ -11}. But it cannot, because it is in fact only -9. So the superset condition cannot be met.
Suppose now that "how cold it is" wrt. w and [0,-10] denotes {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is ≤ -10}. Then the exclamative can
denote {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is ≤ -11}. But then the sentence "John knows how cold it is" cannot be true, because it is in
fact -11 and John only knows that it is -10. The problem is that both with and without R, the IQ is to denote the whole
set of true answers, still the exclamative is to denote something more extreme than the interrogative.
Thus the theory is incoherent. Generally, I believe it is misguided to try to encode extremity.
It is unnecessary and it seems impossible.
3
4
Milner (1978: 252): Les énoncés exclamatifs expriment "un haut degré dans l’ordre de la quantité ou de la qualité".
Cf. "It’s how I eat, Sir!" (Beggar in Chicago)
6
2.2.2.2
Plurality and Habituality
2nd •: First, the observation that a floating universal quantifier can be necessary (German):
(16)
Geilo mit wem ich ?(alles) getanzt hab!
Geilo with whom I all danced have
(attested)
This seems to be related to the preference for a scalar reading: The universal indicates a scale.
But there may be more to it than that: Note that when the wh- value is clearly outlined and
thus easily describable, attitudes of the “astonishing” sort are not appropriate:
(17)
a.
b.
c.
d.
It’s Amazing who won ...
(only Google hit "amazing who won")
# It’s amazing who won.
√ It’s amazing that Bush won.
Isn’t it amazing who wins those damn things?
(attested – habitual!)
It might be that invoking a plurality or habituality is a means to evade competition from "that".
In (17d) there is a scale involved, but merely one of likelihood, which should be easy to read
into (17b). What distinguishes (17d) from (17b) is evidently the difficulty of naming the who.
True, an exclamative remains bad. But in German it is ok; cf. (18a). Even (18b) is accepted:
(18)
a.
b.
•
Also ich weis warum ich den Eurovision Song Contest nicht mag.
Das hatt doch alles nix mit Musik zu tun! Wer da alles gewinnt!
Wer da wieder gewonnen hat!
who there all wins
who there again won
has
Let us say that IQs used as exclamatives or under predicates like "incroyable", as
opposed to predicates like "sait", are super-factive: the speaker knows the proposition
Suggestion:
Preferences for habitual or plural interpretations of super-factive IQs
can be explained as effects of a competition with a more specific clause
Nowhere is the competition from "that" clauses stronger than with indirect polarity questions –
a stronger (more specific) presupposition is to be preferred if only it is justified:5
(19)
a.
b.
# Ob die U-Bahn noch fährt!
# It’s incredible whether the tube is still running.
The denotation of the IQ is ‘that the tube is still running iff it is in fact still running’, and since
the speaker knows the proposition that the tube is still running or the proposition that it is not,
the corresponding sentence with "that" has a nonvacuous presupposition and is preferred.6
Conversely, nowhere is the competition from a "that" clause weaker than with degree IQs
where there is no standard scale ("how beautiful", etc.).
5
6
Note a parallel to David Lewis’ "Whether report": # John believes whether it is raining.
This can be made precise in Bidirectional Optimality Theory (BOT) (e.g. Blutner 2000).
7
3
Apparent type t exclamatives
A common form of exclamatives is the declarative (root) "so" ("si", "so", "så") sentence:
(20)
C’est si bon!
Zum Augenblicke dürft’ ich sagen: Verweile doch, du bist so schön!
(Hornez)
(Goethe)
These are type t sentences. Still, they can evidently be used alongside <s,t> sentences:
(21)
a.
Så kaldt det er!
so cold it is
b.
Det er så kaldt!
it is so cold
(Norwegian)
(21b) can serve the same function as (21a), beside ellipsis:
(21)
c.
– Pourquoi tu as mis ton pull?
– Il fait si froid!
(# – Comme il fait froid!)
(22)
— Å, jeg er så glad for min skjønnhet, å så glad, så glad jeg er!
"Ach, ich bin so froh, weil ich so schön bin, o so froh, so froh bin ich!"
"Oh, I’m so happy about my beauty; oh so happy, so happy am I!"
"Ah! Comme j’aime ma beauté, comme je l’aime, comme je l’aime!"
(Norwegian)
(corpus transl.)
(corpus transl.)
(corpus transl.)
Suggestion:
These sentences generally mean the same as the corresponding IQs
minus the intensionalization.
That is, (21b) denotes the same as the sentence "it is as cold as it actually is"; "so" translates
as λα α ≥ @(α), just like "how", but because it remains in situ and Spec,CP is thus not filled,
the denotation is not a proposition but a truth value – in fact, 1 regardless of the actual world.
This makes the sentence inappropriate as an assertion. So it is lifted to <s,t> by the principle
Intensional Functional Application (cf. footnote. 1), and digested by the exclamative function.
This explains the contrast in (21c): Ellipsis (implicit parce que) contributes intensionalization
and cannot digest a type <s,t> sentence.
4 Conclusions
This is a weak theory of (clausal) exclamatives, postulating nothing, ascribing no more to the
clauses than what we know about them in advance. I seek to attribute the speech act to the
logical type <s,t> assuming only reasonable general conditions of communication; you utter
something because it is worth mentioning, – and calling attention to a true proposition only
makes sense if that proposition is to the speaker’s mind remarkable.7 In a sense, this is what
Rexach (1996) and Zanuttini and Portner (2003) purport to do; – but they do posit something
(EXC as a semantic function, Rwidening as something contained in a clause). In my picture, there
is no direct link between syntax and exclamative speech acts, and the only direct semantic link
is the logical type; the special interpretational properties of exclamative clauses are strategies
designed to enhance remarkability and to evade competition from more specific sentences.
7
Quite literally!
8
References
Blutner, Reinhard (2000) "Some Aspects of Optimality in Natural Language Interpretation", in
Journal of Semantics 17, 189-216.
Castroviejo Miró, Elena (2006) "Though exclamatives are not extremely amazing, how amazing
they are!", Sinn und Bedeutung 11, Barcelona.
Elliott, Dale (1974) "Towards a Grammar of Exclamations", in Foundations of Language 11,
231-246.
Fabricius-Hansen, Cathrine and Kjell Johan Sæbø (2004) "In a Mediative Mood: The Semantics
of the German Reportive Subjunctive", in Natural Language Semantics 12, 213-257.
Groenendijk, Jeroen and Martin Stokhof (1997) "Questions", in Johan van Benthem and Alice
ter Meulen (eds.), Handbook of Logic and Language, Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1055-1124.
Gunlogson, Christine (2003) True to Form: Rising and Falling Declaratives as Questions in
English. New York: Routledge.
Heim, Irene & Angelika Kratzer (1997) Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.
Karttunen, Lauri (1977) "Syntax and Semantics of Questions", in Linguistics and Philosophy 1,
3-44.
Krifka, Manfred (2001) "Quantifying into Question Acts", in Natural Language Semantics 9, 140.
Michaelis, Laura (2001) "Exclamative Constructions", in Martin Haspelmath et al. (eds.),
Language Typology and Universals: An International Handbook of Contemporary Research,
Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1038-1058.
Milner, Jean-Claude (1978) De la Syntaxe à l’interprétation: Quantités, Insultes, Exclamations.
Éditions du Seuil: Paris.
Munaro, Nicola and Hans-Georg Obenauer (2002) "On the semantic widening of underspecified
wh-elements", in Manuel Leonetti, Olga Fernàndez Soriano and Victoria Escandell Vidal
(eds.) Current Issues in Generative Grammar, Universidad Alcalà de Henares - Servicio de
Publicaciones, Madrid, 165-194.
Reis, Marga (1999) "On sentence types in German: an enquiry into the relationship between
grammar and pragmatics", in Interdisciplinary Journal for Germanic Linguistics and
Semiotic Analysis 4, 195-236.
Rett, Jessica (2006) "Exclamatives are Degree Constructions", Rutgers Linguistics Conference
(RULing) 1.
Rexach, Javier Gutiérrez (1996) "The Semantics of Exclamatives", in Edward Garrett and
Felicia Lee (eds.), Syntax at Sunset (= UCLA Working Papers in Linguistics), 146-162.
Schwabe, Kerstin (2004) "German root declaratives and independently used dass complement
clauses", to appear in Valerie Molnár and Susanne Winkler (eds.) Architecture of Focus,
Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Searle, John R. (1976) "A classification of illocutionary acts", in Language in Society 5, 1-23.
Zaefferer, Dietmar (1983) "The Semantics of Non-Declaratives: Investigating German
Exclamatories", in Rainer Bäuerle, Christoph Schwarze, and Arnim von Stechow (eds.),
Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language, Berlin: de Gruyter, 466-490.
Zaefferer, Dietmar (2001) "Deconstructing a classical classification. A typological look at
Searle’s concept of illocution type", in Revue Internationale de Philosophie 216, 209-225.
Zanuttini, Raffaella and Paul Portner (2003) "Exclamative Clauses: at the Syntax-Semantics
Interface", in Language 79, 39-81.
9
("En fait je ne sais même pas quelle voix elle a car elle n'a pas parlé de tout le repas")
λw t°w ≥ t°v
By contrast, I barely have a theory; I do not encode scalarity at all but simply appeal to it as a
general interpretational strategy. (Of course, there is more to be said about the details of
scalar interpretations of apparently nonscalar IQs.)
To be precise, let us try to apply these two conditions to the simple case (5). Suppose that "how cold it is" wrt. w and
[0,-10] denotes the set {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is ≤ -9}. Then "R(how cold it is)" wrt. w and [0,-10] must denote (the same
as "how cold it is" wrt. w and, say, [0,-11], namely) a proper superset, say, {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is ≤ -11}. But it cannot,
because it is in fact only -9 in w. So the exclamative is impossible, the extremity condition
cannot be satisfied. Suppose that "how cold it is" wrt. w and [0,-10] denotes {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is
≤ -10}. Then the exclamative can denote {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is ≤ -11}. But then the sentence
"John knows how cold it is" cannot be true. Because it is in fact -11 in w and the denotation of "how cold it is" stops at
-10. Suppose, for the sake of completeness, that "how cold it is" wrt. w and [0,-10] denotes the set {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is
≤ -11}. Then the exclamative must denote {it is ≤ 0, ..., it is ≤ -12}, which again it cannot, since it is only -11 in w.
The problem is that both with and without R, the IQ is to denote the complete set of true answers, still the exclamative
is to denote something more extreme than the interrogative.
Recall the general scheme on p. 1. It predicts that it should be possible to lift an indirect to a
direct question, i.e. for the question function to digest a type <s,t> sentence. Do you know a
language (or a dialect) where this is attested? (Remember anecdote from ZAS, Berlin)
Download