1 Appendix B: Pareto dominance of unanimity when proposer has private information (Proposition 10) In this appendix we establish that there are circumstances under which both the proposer and voters prefer unanimity, even when the proposer has private information. Formally, we establish Proposition 10, stated in the main text. Existence of a pooling equilibrium under unanimity The proof requires us to work with a fixed equilibrium under unanimity. The particular equilibrium we use is of little importance, but the equilibrium utilities need to be continuous as we change preferences. The easiest equilibrium to work with is a pooling equilibrium, in which the proposer makes the same offer for all realizations of σ 0 . Our first two results establish circumstances under which such an equilibrium exists. First, we show that whenever the information quality of voters is low, the proposer’s limit expected payoff is convex in the offer x. Notationally, let vn (x, σ 0 , b, λ) denote the proposer’s expected payoff from an offer x when he has observed σ 0 , the voters attach belief b to offer x, and have preferences λ, i.e., vn (x, σ 0 , b, λ) = Eω V̄ ω (σ 0 ) + Pnω (x, b, λ, α) V ω (x, σ 0 ) − V̄ ω (σ 0 ) |σ 0 . (We used the same definition in the proof of Proposition 3 — see (A-4).) Define P ω and v as the pointwise limits of Pnω and v respectively. Lemma B-1 Fix preferences λ and suppose unanimity rule is in effect (α = 1). Then there exists ℓ such that whenever ℓ(σ) > ℓ, the proposer’s limit payoff v is convex in x over [0, min {1, xU (b, λ)}] for all σ 0 , b. As a consequence, v is maximized at min {1, xU (b, λ)}; and if xU (b, λ) < 1 the maximizer is unique. Proof of Lemma B-1: For use throughout the proof, write x̌ = min {1, xU (b, λ)}. The limit acceptance probability is identically equal to zero over [0, xH (λ)], and is increasing 2 thereafter. So to prove the result, it suffices to show that for ω = H, L there exists ℓ such that whenever ℓ(σ) > ℓ, the second derivative of P ω (x, b, λ) V ω (x, σ 0 ) − V̄ ω (σ 0 ) is positive for x ∈ (xH (λ) , x̌], for all σ 0 , b. H (x,σ,λ) b Let ℓ(σ) denote the likelihood ratio at σ. Write R(x, σ, b, λ) = − ∆ , γH = ∆L (x,σ,λ) 1−b γω ℓ(σ) and γ L = 1, so that P ω (x, b, λ) = [R(x, σ, b, λ)ℓ(σ)] 1−ℓ(σ) for x ∈ (xH (λ) , xU (b, λ)). The second derivative of P ω (x, b, λ) V ω (x, σ 0 ) − V̄ ω (σ 0 ) with respect to x is given by ∂2 ω V (x, σ 0 ) ∂x2 γω γω ∂ ∂ +2 V ω (x, σ 0 ) [R(x, σ, b, λ)ℓ(σ)] 1−ℓ(σ) −1 R(x, σ, b, λ) ∂x 1 − ℓ(σ) ∂x γω ∂2 γω [R(x, σ, b, λ)ℓ(σ)] 1−ℓ(σ) −1 2 R(x, σ, b, λ) + V ω (x, σ 0 ) − V̄ ω (σ 0 ) 1 − ℓ(σ) ∂x 2 γω γω γω ∂ −2 ω ω + V (x, σ 0 ) − V̄ (σ 0 ) ( − 1)[R(x, σ, b, λ)ℓ(σ)] 1−ℓ(σ) R(x, σ, b, λ) 1 − ℓ(σ) 1 − ℓ(σ) ∂x γω = P ω (x, b, λ) K 1 − ℓ(σ) P ω (x, b, λ) where K = 1 − ℓ(σ) ∂ 2 ω ∂ ∂ V (x, σ 0 ) + 2 V ω (x, σ 0 ) ℓ(σ)−1 ln R(x, σ, b, λ) 2 γ ω ∂x ∂x ∂x ∂2 + V ω (x, σ 0 ) − V̄ ω (σ 0 ) R(x, σ, b, λ)−1 ℓ(σ)−1 2 R(x, σ, b, λ) ∂x ∂ γ − 1 + ℓ(σ) + V ω (x, σ 0 ) − V̄ ω (σ 0 ) ω R(x, σ, b, λ)−1 ℓ(σ)−1 ln R(x, σ, b, λ). 1 − ℓ(σ) ∂x Observe that γ L − 1 + ℓ(σ) = ℓ(σ) and γ H − 1 + ℓ(σ) = 2ℓ(σ) − 1. The term V ω (x, σ 0 ) − V̄ ω (σ 0 ) is bounded away from zero over [0, x̌]. The term R(x, σ, b, λ)−1 is also bounded away from zero over (xH (λ) , x̌]. From Assumption 5, the term R(x, σ, b, λ) is strictly increasing over [0, x̌], and so ∂ ∂x ln R(x, σ, b, λ) is positive and bounded away from zero over [0, x̌]. From these observations, it is immediate that there exists ℓ such that K > 0 whenever ℓ(σ) > ℓ and x ∈ (xH (λ) , x̌], and for all σ 0 , b. This completes the proof. Lemma B-1 implies that in the limit, for any given voter beliefs the proposer prefers the offer xU (b, λ) to all lower offers, unless lower offers lead voters to hold more positive 3 beliefs (i.e., higher b). We use this observation to establish that there exists a pooling equilibrium in which the proposer offers xU b = pH , λ regardless of his information σ 0 . Lemma B-2 Fix voter preferences λ and suppose that xU (b = pH , λ) < 1. If the unanimity rule is in effect (α = 1) and voter information is sufficiently poor so that Lemma B-1 holds, then there exists N such that for all n ≥ N there is a pooling equilibrium in which the proposer’s offer is independent of σ 0 and lies within 1/n of xU (b = pH , λ). Proof of Lemma B-2: If the proposer’s signal is completely uninformative (i.e., ℓ0 (·|H) ≡ 1), the result is immediate from the uniform convergence of acceptance probabilities (Lemma 4) and the proposer payoff convexity (Lemma B-1). The remainder of the proof deals with the case in which the proposer’s signal is informative, and so b < pH < b̄. We claim that for all n large enough, there is a pooling equilibrium in which the proposer offers xU (b = pH , λ) independent of his signal σ 0 ; the voters accept with probability one; and the voters assign belief b to any downwards deviation by the proposer. If the proposer offers xU b = pH , λ and the voters hold beliefs b = pH , the acceptance probability is one for all n. So the proposer’s payoff for any finite n in the claimed equilibrium exactly equals the limit payoff v xU b = pH , λ , σ 0 , b = pH , λ , which for the remainder of the proof we write as v ∗ . Fix δ > 0. From the payoff convexity result Lemma B-1, there exists ε > 0 such that v x, σ 0 , b = pH , λ < v ∗ − ε whenever x < xU b = pH , λ − δ. A fortiori, v (x, σ 0 , b, λ) < v ∗ − ε also. By uniform convergence (Lemma 4) it follows that there exists N1 such that vn (x, σ 0 , b, λ) < v ∗ − ε whenever n ≥ N1 . It remains only to rule out downwards deviations between xU b = pH , λ − δ and xU b = pH , λ . From Lemma 3, there exists some ϕ > 0 such that the limit acceptance probabilities satisfy P ω (x, b, λ) < P ω x, b = pH , λ − ϕ 4 for offers x in this interval. So there exists ϕ̂ > 0 such that the limit proposer payoffs similarly satisfy v (x, σ 0 , b, λ) < v x, σ 0 , b = pH , λ − ϕ̂ for offers x in this same interval. By payoff convexity (Lemma B-1), v x, σ 0 , b = pH , λ < v ∗ . So by uniform convergence, it follows that there exists N2 such that vn (x, σ 0 , b, λ) < v ∗ whenever n ≥ N2 . So for all n ≥ max {N1 , N2 } the proposer has no profitable deviation, completing the proof. Pareto dominance of unanimity Given the existence of a pooling equilibrium under unanimity, we are now ready to establish our main result of this section, Proposition 10. The proof strategy is similar to that for the special case stated in Proposition 9: by changing preferences, and specifically the proposer’s status quo payoff V̄ L , by continuity we can find a set of preferences such that the voters are indifferent between majority and unanimity rules, while total surplus is higher. In more detail, the argument is as follows. Suppose preferences are such that (15) does not hold, i.e., agreement creates surplus in state L, and moreover W (·; λ, α) > 0. For these preferences, voters strictly prefer unanimity. Next, consider a change in preferences as V̄ L is decreased. If V̄ L is decreased by enough, W (·; λ, α) < 0, and the voters strictly prefer majority. Moreover, provided that the proposer’s signal is non-degenerate, the voters’ expected payoff under majority varies in a continuous way as V̄ L changes. The effect of changing preferences on the voters’ payoff under unanimity is harder to characterize, since in general there may be multiple equilibria. However, if we focus on the specific pooling equilibrium whose existence we established in Lemma B-2, the expected payoff of voters also varies in a continuous way as the proposer’s preferences are changed. It follows that there exist preferences at which the voters receive the same payoff from majority voting and unanimity voting (in the pooling equilibrium). At this indifference 5 point, when facing majority the proposer offers xH after some realizations of his own signal σ 0 , and xL after other realizations — for if instead he always offered one or the other, the voters would have a strict preference between majority and unanimity. But because the proposer offers xH to voters using majority rule with strictly positive probability, the offer is rejected by the voters with strictly positive probability also. In contrast, in the unanimity pooling equilibrium the proposer always offers xU , and the voters always except. Given these observations, one can see that at the “indifference” preferences total surplus is higher under unanimity than majority. Since by construction the voters are indifferent between the two decision rules, the proposer strictly prefers unanimity. That is, the unanimity rule Pareto dominates majority voting. Formally: Proof of Proposition 10: The proof revolves around a family of possible proposer preferences, which we select as follows. First, choose a specification of proposer preferences such that V ω and V̄ ω are independent of σ 0 , and such that pH (σ)V H (xH (λ = 0)) + pL (σ)V̄ L > E [V ω (xL (λ = 0)) |σ] . Under these preferences, W (σ 0 ) > 0 for all σ 0 and all α, for λ small enough. Write V̄0L for the proposer’s payoff from the status quo in state L under these preferences. Next, choose V̄1L sufficiently small such that pH (σ̄)V H (xH (λ = 0; α)) + pL (σ̄)V̄1L < E [V ω (xL (λ = 0)) |σ̄] . So under these alternate preferences, W (σ 0 ) > 0 for all σ 0 and all α, for λ small enough. For any η ∈ (0, 1) define V̄ηL = (1 − η) V̄0L + η V̄1L . The family of proposer preferences we consider is V= V H , V L , V̄ H , V̄ L : V̄ L = V̄ηL , some η ∈ [0, 1] . Let C be the constant whose existence is implied by Assumption 7. Since at λ = 0, U ω (xω (λ; α) , σ i , λ) = Ū ω (σ i , λ) for all σ i , and xL (λ = 0) = xL (λ = 0; α) for all α, it 6 follows from xL (λ = 0, α) < 1 and Assumptions 4 and 5 that U ω (x, σ i , λ = 0) + CV ω (x) > Ū ω (σ i , λ = 0) + C V̄ ω for all x ∈ [0, 1], σ i ∈ [σ, σ̄], and proposer preferences in the family V. So there exists some ε > 0 and some λ̌ > 0 such that for λ ≤ λ̌, U ω (x, σ i , λ) + CV ω (x) > Ū ω (σ i , λ) + C V̄ ω + ε for all x ∈ [0, 1], σ i ∈ [σ, σ̄], and proposer preferences in the family V. That is, under agreement at any offer in [0, 1] creates social surplus of at least ε relative to the status quo. For the remainder of the proof, we assume that voter information, as measured by ℓ(σ), is sufficiently poor such that Lemma B-1 holds for all preferences in the set V and λ ≤ λ̌. (Note that changing the voter information quality does not affect any of the expressions used so far in the proof.) For the remainder of the proof, fix voter preferences at λ ≤ λ̌ and a majority voting rule αM < 1. From Proposition 4, for any proposer preferences such that W (σ) > 0, the majority limit payoff of voters is Eσi ,ω Ū ω (σ i ) + pH Eσi ∆H (xH (λ; αM ) , σ i , λ) |H . Likewise, for any η such that W (σ̄) < 0, the majority limit payoff of voters is Eσi ,ω Ū ω (σ i ) + Eσi ,ω [∆ω (xL (λ; αM ) , σ i , λ)]. So as the proposer’s preferences range over V as η increases from 0 to 1, the majority limit payoff of voters varies continuously from the former expression to the latter. In contrast, the unanimity limit payoff of voters in the pooling equilibrium (Lemma B-2) is simply Eσi ,ω Ū ω (σ i ) + Eσi ,ω ∆ω xU pH , λ , σ i , λ for all proposer preferences in V. By Proposition 5, in the limit, the voters are strictly better off under the unanimity pooling equilibrium for η = 0, while since xU pH , λ < xL (λ; αM ) they strictly prefer majority equilibrium at η = 1. So by continuity, there exists η̂ ∈ (0, 1) at which they are indifferent between the majority equilibrium and the unanimity pooling equilibrium. Moreover, we know that W (σ) < 0 < W (σ̄) at η̂, so the limit rejection probability under 7 majority strictly exceeds 0. By continuity, select η̌ < η̂ such that the limit rejection probability under majority in state L equals q > 0, and the unanimity limit payoff of voters exceeds the majority limit payoff by an amount pL qε/2. At proposer preferences η̌, the sum of the voter and proposer limit payoffs is lower under majority than under unanimity by an amount of at least pL qε (that is, the efficiency loss ε multiplied by the rejection probability). Since the limit voter payoff is pL qε/2 higher under unanimity, the limit proposer payoff is at least pL qε/2 higher under unanimity also. So there exists some N such that under the preferences defined, both the proposer and voters strictly prefer unanimity to the majority rule αM whenever n ≥ N.