Capital & Class

advertisement
Capital
& Class
http://cnc.sagepub.com/
The monetary exception: Labour, distribution and money in capitalism
Geoff Mann
Capital & Class 2013 37: 197
DOI: 10.1177/0309816813481654
The online version of this article can be found at:
http://cnc.sagepub.com/content/37/2/197
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
On behalf of:
Conference of Socialist Economics
Additional services and information for Capital & Class can be found at:
Email Alerts: http://cnc.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts
Subscriptions: http://cnc.sagepub.com/subscriptions
Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav
Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
Citations: http://cnc.sagepub.com/content/37/2/197.refs.html
>> Version of Record - Jun 18, 2013
What is This?
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
481654
2013
CNC37210.1177/0309816813481654Capital & ClassMann
The monetary exception:
Labour, distribution and
money in capitalism
Capital & Class
37(2) 197­–216
© The Author(s) 2013
Reprints and permissions:
sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/0309816813481654
c&c.sagepub.com
Geoff Mann
Simon Fraser University, Canada
Abstract
Contemporary monetary institutions posit money as an ‘exceptional’ domain,
outside of democratic sovereign authority in modern capitalist states, on the
basis of the claim that without it, liberal democracy would fall apart. Labour’s
distributional critique of capitalism and the state must wrestle with the possibility
that money in modern capitalism is anti-democratic by definition, and that as
such, any social-democratic project of radical redistribution, implicit in labour’s
critique of capitalist distribution, will require not merely a different allocation of
existing money, but a radically different monetary relation.
Keywords
Labour, distribution, money
Introduction
Samuel Gompers is well known for lots of reasons, but one of them is certainly his
famous response to the question, ‘What does labour want?’– to which he replied, ‘More’.
His answer leaves considerable room for interpretation, of course, but certainly one of
the messages is, ‘We want more of what they have’. Whether Gompers thought it was a
zero-sum game or not is unclear (he may very well have thought so), but it makes perfect
sense either way: it is more than possible for ‘us’ to have more without depriving ‘them’
of anything more than the distance between us. The point was merely that the things
capital enjoys – wealth, power, dignity, security, freedom – should also be enjoyed by
labour. These ‘things’ have, ultimately, always been the stakes in the struggle between
capital and labour. One of them, however, has usually been a priority, since it is generally
considered the means to the others: money. While other ‘things’, such as the length of the
Corresponding author:
Geoff Mann, Simon Fraser University, Canada.
Email: geoffm@sfu.ca
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
198
Capital & Class 37(2)
working day, gender parity or shop-floor control, have often been at stake, the division
of the surplus is the fundamental site of struggle. In modern capitalism, this boils down
to where, and to whom, the money flows, and how it accumulates.
This struggle is premised on a tacit but absolutely essential assumption: that the
stakes – income and wealth, and all the things that flow from them – can simply be
redistributed without affecting the work they do; that the form wealth takes is not a
function of its mode of distribution. It is to assume that the direction of the flow of
monetary income and wealth (at present, increasingly toward capital) is itself not part
of what makes it work as income and wealth. The idea seems to be that modern money
can be governed so as to make anyone rich – worker or boss – and rich in basically the
same way.
But this may not in fact be the case. In capitalism, money as it currently works takes
particular forms and serves particular functions that make it capital-tropic at its core
(Weber 1978: 79; Ingham 2004: 78-81). This paper concerns the implications of this
possibility and is focused, necessarily at a rather abstract, institutional scale, on how
money works in contemporary financialised neoliberal capitalism. (Below, I try to be as
precise as possible with each of these over-used terms.) I argue that much of the critique
that animates labour studies – a critique that animates labour politics broadly – has a
tendency to imagine that the main problem with capitalism is that the capitalists are in
charge. The corollary is that the distributional questions at the centre of a labour-based
critique are mostly a question of restructuring the hierarchy via something like ‘democratisation’. But significant elements of the modern capitalist political economy, regardless
of who is in the driver’s seat, are constitutively non- or anti-democratic. It is not a matter
of merely remaking them democratically, since if they were democratic, or ‘democratisable’, they literally would not be what they are. The institution on which I focus, modern capitalist money, is a case in point: it is non-democratic by definition, and it
constrains in its very being what redistribution can mean today. Money in capitalism
cannot just be redistributed to labour according to an ethical rule of thumb, ceteris paribus. The institutional and political bases of money as a social relation in contemporary
capitalism militate against this.
Money-in-capitalism thus cannot be approached as class-, geography-, or historyneutral. That may seem to state the obvious, so it bears emphasising that my point is not
aimed at the quantitative maldistribution of purchasing power and monetary wealth
across different classes, spaces and times. That is of course a crucial concern, but my
argument is more fundamental. It is that there are aspects of money as a modern social
relation that operate at a supra-distributional level, and indeed that determine how and
to whom it can be distributed, and what it can and cannot be used to do. In other words,
there are immensely powerful geographic and social forces that animate modern money
that make it capitalist in its very being, but these forces operate at an almost ephemeral
scale, and at an institutional temporality, that blur the lines between the general and the
particular, between the macro and micro scales. And it does its work unevenly, unpredictably sometimes. But, at least in capitalism, it is never anything less than enormously
important, and its very structure has seemed to put working people on the losing end
(again, to say nothing of how little they have of it).
While workers as individuals can prosper by getting hold of pools of money, and
certain groups of workers can perhaps benefit from labour-controlled stocks of money
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
199
and capital, workers as a class – and a fortiori workers as a transnational class – cannot
become wealthy by way of capitalist monetary institutions. This to say that when
Keynes argued that the class struggle was basically over, and that workers in modern
capitalism are for the most part engaged in a tussle with each other over relative wages,
he was on to something, if for the wrong reasons: like Marx, he understood that distributional struggles within modern capitalism are systematically constrained not by
individual, mean-spirited capitalists (of which there may be many), but by the very
institutional structure that defines it as modern capitalism. Labour cannot merely take
the chair of the Federal Reserve or the Bank of Canada, for example, and continue on
as if it were the decision-makers, and not the institutions themselves, that were the
problem. In its modern institutional form, capitalist money is organised so as to constrain radical redistribution.
What follows is an attempt to show how this is so. It is organised in four sections. The
first gives a brief overview of what precisely money is; the second provides a general
description of how money works in modern capitalism. The third discusses the organisation and practice of monetary governance in the capitalist global north, emphasising the
institutional structure of central banks, the principal seat of monetary authority. In section four, I consider the politics of these monetary functions and their control in modern
capitalism, focusing on the implications of the idea, generally accepted by monetary
theory and policy, that democracy has an ‘inflation bias’. I argue that the structures
described in the previous sections are consequently intended to organise money as the
decisive exception in capitalist liberal democracy. In other words, the monetary realm is
posited as the domain of absolute, non-democratic sovereign authority in modern capitalist states, and that this virtually unaccountable power is justified by the claim that
without it, liberal democracy would fall apart.
I conclude with some cautionary thoughts regarding what these monetary features
might mean for labour’s distributional critique of capitalism and the state, to suggest that
it may not be possible to restructure, in social-democratic form, institutions like money
and monetary authority, which are anti-democratic by definition. Many of the most
important distributional outcomes are determined not by policy-makers’ decisionmaking, but systemically. Redistribution cannot mean merely the same structures, with
different people behind the wheel.
What is money?
Money is usually described as serving several functions in the economy: it is a) a medium
of exchange (facilitates the exchange of qualitatively different commodities); b) a means
of payment (i.e. transaction settlement; it is the thing with which you can settle a debt,
and is usually legally defined as such); c) a store of value (you can hold it as an asset in
the form of abstract or potential purchasing power); and d) a unit of account (the standard unit by which all ‘economic’ values are calculated and compared). Classical and
neoclassical economic analysis generally suggests that all of these functions flow from an
‘original’ function, that of medium of exchange. But, as Keynes was among the first to
argue, this is based on a schematic history with no empirical basis. It assumes that capitalism and capitalist money are not specifically capitalist in any meaningful way, but
‘natural’ outgrowths of less complex barter economies. Rather, the key function of money
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
200
Capital & Class 37(2)
in capitalism is in fact as unit of account: ‘Money is the stable measure of value which
makes it possible to establish the relative prices of all commodities’ (Ingham 2008: 68;
Keynes 1930).
Money can operate as such not because it is some ‘thing’ that circulates via exchange
(currency or less material means of payment and settlement), but rather because it represents an abstract claim on or in economic relations as a whole. In other words, money
measures and stores abstract purchasing power, and in so doing transports it through
space and time. You can use money (given state territorial and customary restrictions)
‘anywhere and anytime’, and, at least in a stable state system, it will be universally
accepted. Money is an abstract claim in the sense that one can demand, or extract from,
economic exchange when and where one chooses by exercising that claim via ‘spending’
one’s money. Money is the potential claim its holder may make upon the world of
exchange, and, like all claims, it can only make sense in a social context. Claims are only
effective if they are heard.
What political function does money serve that gives these claims force? In what does
money’s political power consist? Marx’s (1973: 507) answer was that as the ‘general
equivalent’, money is a ‘highly energetic solvent’. It dissolves what once were relational
unities, the most important being the moment of exchange. Money makes possible what
is impossible in non-monetary realms: i.e. buying and selling become distinct moments
in the process of exchange. Once ‘separated in place and time, they by no means need to
coincide’ (Marx 1973: 198). In capitalist social relations, then, money becomes a necessary ‘third party’ in all exchange, producing an unending circulation of payment and
counter-payment across space and time. Indeed, as Keynes never tired of pointing out,
‘the importance of money essentially flows from its being a link between the present and future’
(1965: 293-4; emphasis in original).
Unsurprisingly, however, Keynes was blind to the coercion that forges this link. Every
individual, family, group and institution in capitalist society is constantly implicated in
a cycle of credit and debt denominated in money. I perhaps risk stating the obvious in
pointing out the extraordinarily powerful influence this bind has on the forms contemporary political agency can take. For any claim money can represent is necessarily
propped up, and in fact can only make sense in light of, the absolute certainty that claim
will be realisable at some other point in time and/or space. Money works only on the
assumption that the future will be qualitatively like the present, and each moment will
be like now.
Indeed, the political power of money resides in the fact that more than any other
social relation, it appears to guarantee the continuity of most fundamental conditions of
the existing order. This is the real meaning of the ‘neutrality’ of money in orthodox economic theory: it is not a technical but an ontological condition. If the neutral political
economic continuity guaranteed and assumed by money were untenable, or even contestable, money would not be a general equivalent. This has nothing to do with dynamics like price volatility or exchange-rate instability, which in no way suggest a challenge
to money, which remains money no matter how extraordinarily and unexpectedly prices
or exchange rates vary. They remain prices and exchange rates, denominated in money.
If qualitative transformation is impossible, then money must have massive political influence – not in the sense that those with money have influence (however true that is), but
in the sense that money’s stability as a social relation delimits the bounds of the political.
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
201
Money goes a long way to explaining why existing social formations seem such a drag on
political imagination. The uncertain future at the heart of modern capitalist markets that
so obsesses Keynesians of all stripes is not really that uncertain. It is almost certainly a
capitalist future. Generalised monetary exchange grants virtually everyone an ‘equity
position’ in the maintenance of capitalist social relations, while at the same time ensuring, as far as possible, that it is impossible to liquidate that position.
All the four ‘standard’ functions of money described above – medium of exchange,
means of payment, store of value, and unit of account – depend entirely on this political
function of money. Moreover, in so far as they very clearly point to the operation of
modern money as essentially a more or less complex economic ‘technology’, they simultaneously disavow its political function. The technical conception of money assumes and
asserts that the space of politics is, by definition, one that cannot include, and has no
overlap with, that of money. A key question, then, is how it can work like this. What
‘actually existing’ social institutions and processes endow it with this power? The easy
answer is that we have collectively decided that it has this power, which is of course true
at the most general level, but really not all that helpful. Moreover, since we did not in fact
all get together, talk it over, and decide that this is money and this is what it will do, the
details must be more specific and complex. In fact, money is constituted by a ‘social relation of credit-debt, denominated in the abstract money of account’ (Ingham 2008: 69).
Money is transferable credit or transferable debt in so far as it is issued (publicly or privately, by banks and states) as a claim upon the issuer. It is the result of one of a set of
credit-debt contracts between two parties: a bank and a borrower, the state and its contractors, the state and a bank, the state and its citizens. In other words, modern capitalist
money is predicated on the condition of indebtedness.
The steps in this continual process have been described with admirable clarity elsewhere (see in particular, Ingham 2004 and Ryan-Collins et al. 2011). For present purposes, the crucial moments can be captured as follows: when a state or bank issues money,
it does so as the essential moment in the process of debt creation. When a borrower borrows money from a bank, the money produced via the loan is issued to the borrower, who
is then indebted, and the money represents the means of settling that debt. The debt in
this case is, of course, private, but the money produced by the establishment of the creditdebt relation circulates generally in the public realm: it is literally a product of the indebtedness of the borrower, who can transfer it to whomever he or she pleases – ’transferable
debt’. Similarly, when the state creates money, via spending, ‘printing’, borrowing etc., the
money is issued as a form of state debt, a claim by the holder on the state. This state-issued
money, and all the other privately issued debt-moneys produced by bank-borrower relations, circulate throughout the community as perfectly substitutable forms of transferable debt. For instance, when you come to settle your account with the state (pay your
taxes, say), the state must accept its own credit-issue as legitimate redemption. The cocirculation – and, more importantly, the indistinguishability – of privately and publicly
issued debt-money in modern capitalism is evidence of the complex interdependence of
the state and the banking system, finance capital, and indeed of capital in general.
The pace and extent of modern economic growth and development is not a cause but
a product of this integration of private currency (issued by banks) and sovereign debt
(issued by states), a fusion made possible by the emergence of a balance of power between
capital and the state in the early modern era (what Weber called the ‘memorable alliance’).
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
202
Capital & Class 37(2)
The alliance made sense for both parties. The state recognised the importance of the fact
that the banking system can create an elastic supply of credit-money, fuelling economic
growth. Capital recognised that money could only do the work it was supposed to do
across space and time if it was secured by a strong territorial state (Weber 1978: 353;
Ingham 2004: 115-31). This partnership is essential to capitalism, however fraught it
might sometimes seem to be these days.
Controlling the process of monetary circulation in this public-private complex is, not
surprisingly, a complex and daunting task. But given the centrality of stable money to
capitalism, it must be aggressively undertaken. There is, at least in theory, little room for
error, and the ground-rules are not open for discussion. Put another way, monetary
authority in capitalism can never be ‘democratic’. Indeed, the kind of unaccountable
power necessary for this project is virtually unparalleled in modern ‘democracy’, an
authoritarianism made possible by the persistence, over more than three decades, of a
broad (if uncritical) political consensus that money is a realm of social relations exempt
from public accountability. This state of affairs produces crucially important contradictions within political economic life in capitalist liberal democracy, contradictions that
trouble any effort to ‘democratise’, or even expand the horizons of, economic governance. A brief discussion of modern capitalist monetary governance, the principal institutional sphere through which this exemption is elaborated and legitimised, shows how
this operates.
One brief definitional note: in the course of this conversation, I lean at times on the
overused and often underspecified concept of ‘neoliberalism’. Let me briefly say what I
mean. While we can focus on it as a ‘policy package’ like those associated with the
International Monetary Fund – privatisation, liberalisation, and stabilisation, as I teach
it to undergraduates – at its core, neoliberalism is the ongoing effort, in an inevitably
uneven global economic geography, to construct a regulatory and political regime in
which the movement of capital and goods is determined as much as possible by firms’
short-term returns. Because that geography is dynamic, such a project is always incomplete and uneven, sometimes taking the form of deregulation, sometimes of reregulation
– what Jamie Peck and Adam Tickell call ‘roll-out’ and ‘roll-back’ (Peck and Tickell
2002; cf. Glyn 2006). Of particular import here, though, is the mode through which the
state operates such regulatory endeavors, and the neoliberal state is characterised by its
increasing use of the nominally ‘non-state’ realm of ‘the market’ as a principal means of
governance (Krippner, 2007).
This is especially important because capitalist market function – and, therefore, the
very possibility of the neoliberal state, not to mention of the power-saturated labour geographies and histories that constitute it – are entirely dependent upon a stable measure of
value and unit of account. Stable money, and the strong form of monetary authority
through which it is maintained, is the invisible infrastructure of contemporary capitalism,
the skeleton that keeps it upright when its muscles fail. The augmented role of money as
a mode of disciplinary governance in the neoliberal era is both cause and consequence of
this dynamic: monetary stability is both the central objective of economic governance,
and allows money to do more regulatory work. The power to pursue this spatio-temporal
harmony, through which money can fix values across time and space, is necessarily vested
in institutions – central banks in particular – endowed with quasi-Hobbesian authority.
Contemporary monetary governance is punctuated dictatorship.
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
203
This institutional autonomy certainly helps explain monetary authorities’ leading role
in crisis management today – they do not have to wait for approval from MPs or
Congress, but can just get on with the ‘rescue’. But it does not explain how and why they
enjoy such extraordinary autonomy in the first place. Central banks took the lead in the
face of current crisis only because they already exercised extraordinary – I am tempted to
say ‘sovereign’ – power in the monetary realm.
If the state has not, as some predicted, withered in the face of global capital, neoliberalism has nonetheless produced a conjuncture in which the state is not exactly what it
was (however unclear what it ‘really’ was might be). If we understand neoliberalism not
as the straightforward ‘retreat of the state’ but, rather, as involving the state’s increasing
reliance on ‘the market’ as a realm and mode of governance, then it is no exaggeration to
say that neoliberalism, at least in this dimension, is the principal means through which
the modern state wrestles with what Chantal Mouffe calls the ‘democratic paradox’, i.e.
the fact that what ‘cannot be contestable in a liberal democracy is the idea that it is
legitimate to establish limits to popular sovereignty [and also, thus, to equality] in the
name of liberty’ (Mouffe 2000: 4). In neoliberalism, the turn to the market is simultaneously a surrender of state power to the market – the realm of ‘liberty’ – and an assertion
of sovereign power by the capitalist state – it is the state that allocates power to the market, an arena in which, through money, it is always an essential player. The ‘market’
allows the state to assert its sovereignty by way of liberty.
Yet there is a structuring antagonism at the core of the ‘normal’ capitalist market,
which revolves around money as a decisive exception (in the sense developed by Carl
Schmitt [2005: 5-15] and, more recently, Giorgio Agamben [2005]). Just as the modern
economic theory of money denies its political function, the modern state – a product of
the complex and conflictual interdependence and interpenetration of the capitalist state,
finance capital, and ‘the market’ – protects money and monetary governance as a space
in which democracy has no place, the space of exception whereby both the state and
finance capital realise their political power.
Since I cannot substantiate all of this here, I focus on one crucial aspect of these
dynamics: how the institutional independence of liberal democracies’ central banks
works, and the hegemonic economic theory that underwrites this resistance to popular
democratic accountability. The theory and the practice of monetary authority are premised upon money as a realm or relation in which neither democracy nor, somewhat
ironically, the market has a place. Money is necessarily a realm of pure power, normally
‘constrained’, but the true prerogative of which is laid bare in contemporary crisis.
Indeed, contemporary common sense holds that modern representative democracy is
possible if and only if monetary authority is not subject to democratic norms; but it is
not at all clear that money would ‘work’, as we understand it today, if such ‘democratisation’ were realised.
How does modern money work?
Before we get into a little detail regarding modern monetary governance, it is perhaps
worth noting, very briefly, what exactly it is supposed to accomplish. Presently, monetary
authority in capitalist nations is almost entirely in the hands of central banks. Modern
central bankers and monetary economists share what is often called a ‘new consensus’ on
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
204
Capital & Class 37(2)
the goals and operation of monetary policy. Central banks’ first, and in many cases only,
priority today is to ‘protect’ the value of the domestic unit of account by keeping inflation low and stable – 2 per cent of core CPI is a standard target. They do this, basically,
by using interest-rate operating procedures to influence the demand for money, pushing
rates up when demand is deemed ‘too high’, lowering them when it is deemed sluggish.
The reason all this is necessary, of course, is the implications for capitalism of a lack of
stability in the unit of account (McNally 2009).
These efforts are always, and have always been, geographically and historically specific. Interestingly, however, these specifics are partly a result of the effort to universalise
capitalist monetary relations, an inevitably geographically and historically particular
endeavour – any attempt to extend and homogenise the purview of capitalist money
will have to confront, and struggle to overcome, ‘local’ difference, and will thus demand
a ‘local’ strategy. One might argue that modern monetary policy is in some ways a performative effort to make a ‘national economy’ work like a macro-model, which would
be to emphasise the ‘standardisation’ of economic governance via a set of widely accepted
‘best practices’ (trade liberalisation, removal of capital controls, floating currency
exchange rates, etc.).
But in many ways, by emphasising an unfolding ‘sameness’, this focus on the sociospatial homogenising power of capital gets the causal direction wrong, and consequently
misses the particulars. Capital mobility, for example, is not a cause of capital’s ‘universalisation’, but an intended effect thereof. The same is true of the other staples of neoliberal monetary governance, not least the ultimate objective itself: low and stable inflation.
Indeed, one could argue that in its currently hegemonic, quasi-monetarist inflationtargeting form, monetary policy hopes to coax or coerce regions into fitting its model of
national policy effectivity – an undertaking that cannot rely upon ‘out-of-the-box’ politics and policies, but actually requires a sensitivity to regional specificity.
The fact that monetary policy almost always ignores this demand for geographical
and historical specificity is arguably one of the main reasons that the project to universalise so often fails. In Canada, the UK and the USA, for example, monetary authority is
confronted with radically different regional inflation and structural unemployment levels, and differential social impacts of monetary policy (Carpenter and Rogers 2005). In
so far as policy-makers, faced with the fact of substantial regional disparity, stick their
fingers in their ears and say ‘la-la-la’ – i.e. simply keep doing what orthodoxy says they
must do until we reach the promised land of economy-wide factor price equilibrium –
they risk further entrenching spatial differentiation. And indeed, the regionally specific
work is left entirely to fiscal endeavours, like those undertaken by the Canadian government’s Western Economic Diversification programme, which try to produce, among
other goals, homogenous rate-sensitivity across regions over time, which would make
monetary policy-makers’ wishes come true.
Of course, monetary authorities are aware of, and sometimes acknowledge, subnational variation. Eddie George, the governor of the Bank of England in the 1990s,
notoriously agreed that northern unemployment was ‘an acceptable price to pay for the
control of inflation’. Confronted with regional disharmony that ‘trade-offs’ like this
might elicit, many central banks have a formal institutional structure intended to ensure
regional representation. The Fed’s board of governors is partly comprised of rotating
memberships shared by eleven of the twelve regional reserve banks, and there is an
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
205
unwritten tradition at the Bank of Canada that the board of directors will be drawn
from all the provinces. In both cases, core regions are still privileged – the New York
Fed, with its tight links to Wall Street, is the only regional bank with a permanent place
on the board of governors, and Ontario and Québec each have twice the membership
of any other province on the board of directors – but regional representation is not
entirely absent.
From a geographical and distributional perspective, however, significant unevenness
persists because of the virtually complete capture of central bank control and monetary
policy decision-making by one class fraction: finance capital. With very few exceptions,
regardless of the region they ‘represent’, central bankers in the global North come to
monetary policy work from the financial sector, or, in the exceptional case (like current
Fed chair, Bernanke) from closely related fields like university economics departments or
the IMF. The Bank of Canada’s directors represent a wider occupational background
than do the Fed’s governors, but have essentially no influence on policy, which is determined by the governor and his council.
The virtually homogeneous class and occupational background of monetary policymakers is justified by claims regarding the knowledge and experience the task demands.
I believe there is little basis for this claim – there is in fact a strong argument for the idea
that an overdeveloped faith in technical expertise is precisely what sent the global financial system into a tailspin – but in any event it does nothing to diminish perhaps the
most important feature of monetary authorities in the capitalist global North: they are,
with a few exceptions, wealthy white men who share a privileged and hegemonic perspective. The literature on voting behavior in central bank governance demonstrates
conclusively that where policy-makers come from, their gender, class background, politics, education, and work experience matters in their policy stance (Greider 1987; Gildea
1990; Havrilesky and Schweitzer 1990; Bernhard, Broz and Clark 2002). The significance of these predictors must only grow with the degree of autonomy from popular
accountability the central bank enjoys.
Indeed, one of the best-known economic models of monetary policy endorses the
appointment of a ‘conservative central banker’ whose ‘inflation-aversion’ is greater than
society’s in general (Rogoff 1985). In a community of debtors, the most likely place to
find such inflation-aversion is among creditors and the rich, since one of inflation’s
principal distributional impacts is to redistribute income from finance capital and the
wealthy to debtors and relatively lower income groups. This class-biased attitude toward
inflation holds across many otherwise very different parts of the world (Jayadev 2006).
In other words, the ‘new consensus’ among monetary economists and policy-makers is
that monetary authorities must be creditors, i.e. they must represent the banks and
finance capital.
Who put them in charge?
The expanding power and reach of finance capital is, therefore, axiomatic for modern
monetary governance theory and practice (Posen 2005; Dickens 1997). The series of
breakdowns in the wake of the ‘subprime’ crisis that began in 2007 has upset the comfortable intimacy that global finance capital and the neoliberal state have enjoyed for
much of the last three decades, particularly over the possibility of financial re-regulation
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
206
Capital & Class 37(2)
but even six years of recession have done little to dent a shared commitment to strong
institutional independence for monetary authority. Both capital and the contemporary
liberal capitalist state assume these procedures and priorities a priori; current wisdom
asserts that anti-inflationary monetary policy’s effectiveness is a positive function of, first,
monetary authority’s independence from ‘political’ influence or control, especially that
of elected or fiscal authorities; and second, the predictability of central banks’ policy
actions.
This ‘current’ wisdom is of course a product of both old and new ideas. The argument
for relatively independent monetary policy first came together in an articulate form in
the post-Second World War period, when some economists and financiers were concerned that without what is now called ‘central bank independence’ or CBI, elected
politicians would manipulate monetary policy as part of an inflationary ‘political business cycle’, softening credit constraints to produce a ‘boom’ before elections or when
some public confidence was otherwise warranted (Boddy and Crotty 1975). Today, however, it is widely recognised among economists that an attempt to positively affect growth
via the double-edged sword of low interest rates – i.e. pumping money into the economy
may cause inflation, but it helps create jobs – is not just cynical self-interest on the part
of elected representatives, but is ‘optimal’, at least in the short run. But, according to the
new consensus macroeconomics, it is the very shortness of this short-run that is the real
problem: buyers and sellers of commodities, labour and capital goods come to expect
these price-driven stimuli, and start to calculate anticipated inflation into pricing decisions and contracts (Kydland and Prescott 1977; Calvo 1978; Barro and Gordon 1983;
cf. Drazen 2000).
According to modern economic orthodoxy, in a context of expansionary economic
policy these so-called ‘rational expectations’ of inflation generate ‘time-inconsistency’, an
unintended but inevitable incongruence between short- and long-run optimality. The
reasoning is as follows: since economic agents in such conditions are already anticipating
inflation, monetary expansion can only have a stimulating effect on economic activity if
it is a ‘surprise’, i.e. if inflationary pump-priming exceeds expectations. However, since
monetary policy must therefore become more and more inflationary to produce the
‘surprise’, it cannot but lead to accelerating rates of inflation. The lesson of the theory of
time-inconsistency, then, is that any positive impact of loose money policy, sincere or
cynical, is restricted to a short period that is far less important than the ‘unavoidable’
negative long-term impacts of inflation, which accelerate as prices rise.
Consequently, since inflation is the content of a Pandora’s box it will be very difficult
to close, current wisdom holds the relationship between monetary and ‘political’ authorities to be constrained by the following ‘facts’:
(a) all state powers are susceptible to inflationary myopia;
(b) all economic agents have dynamic ‘rational expectations’ of economic change;
and
(c) time-inconsistency is a particular problem for democracy, because elected decision-makers are more beholden to a short-run-oriented electorate, and thus have
a great tendency to try to push unemployment below its ‘natural rate’, or the
‘non-accelerating inflation rate of unemployment’ (NAIRU). This is known as
democracy’s ‘inflation bias’.
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
207
If so, then a central bank must be ‘independent’ enough to resist, or at least actively suppress, these temptations. Alan Blinder (1998: 58), a former member of the US Federal
Reserve board of governors, puts it in plain language:
many governments wisely try to depoliticize monetary policy by, e.g., putting it in the hands
of unelected technocrats with long terms of office and insulation from the hurly-burly of
politics. The reasoning is the same as Ulysses’: He knew he would get better long-run results
by tying himself to the mast, even though he wouldn’t always feel very good about it in the
short run!
In saying so – and, as far as I can tell, entirely unwittingly – Blinder isolates the most
glaring problem with the independent central banks of contemporary capitalist liberal
democracy: the plainly anti-democratic nature of a handful of ‘unelected technocrats
with long terms of office and insulation from the hurly-burly of politics’.
Proponents of strong independence for monetary authority argue that the nondemocratic characteristics of this institutional structure can be redeemed by monetary
policy that is ‘credible’, ‘transparent’ and ‘accountable’. These three features are supposed
to allow citizens to understand the central bank’s policy goals, and to assess the extent to
which it is reaching them. It is worth noting that even if it operates according to these
criteria, however, the bank is in no way obligated, or even encouraged, to involve any
particular group – including the public – in the determination of what those goals are,
or in initiating any changes those groups might deem necessary. The problems, both
institutional and political, to which credibility, transparency, and accountability offer
‘solutions’ – as Blinder puts it, by ‘depoliticizing’ monetary authority – are complicated
further by radical transformations in monetary policy operations over the last three
decades, in particular the adoption, across many of the most powerful capitalist economies, of so-called policy rules. This process involves the formal renunciation, on the part
of monetary authorities, of what central bankers call ‘discretion’ – i.e. flexibility with
regard to policy tools and goals – in exchange for ‘pre-commitment’ to fixed policy goals – 2
per cent nominal annual inflation, for example – that the bank makes its first, sometimes
only, priority.
Discretionary flexibility was standard monetary policy practice prior to the early
1990s. With the exception of the monetarist experiments of the late 1970s and early
1980s, central bankers have conventionally worked with a range of policy mandates,
shifting priorities as macroeconomic conditions demanded – focusing on unemployment when it appeared to be reaching unacceptable levels, for example, or realigning
exchange rates when they moved outside of preferred values (Epstein 1992). Today, this
kind flexibility is scarce, and where it does persist, it is usually only de jure; actual practice tends to accord with ‘unwritten’ policy rules (De Long 1996: 49). The Fed’s longstanding ‘dual mandate’ of full employment and monetary stability, for example, persists
not because US central bankers are opposed to inflation-targeting, but because of what
Chair Bernanke (2003: 14) once called ‘delicate issues of communication’ (code for the
inability of the public and members of Congress to understand why the Fed should drop
its statutory commitment to employment). Nevertheless, the Fed tends to operate – at
least in ‘normal’, non-meltdown times – if not with an inflation ‘target’, then at least
with a de facto inflation control rule.
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
208
Capital & Class 37(2)
Milton Friedman is the best-known advocate of policy rules. In the mid- to late1960s, he argued that to prevent inflation bias, central banks should be legislatively
constrained to increase the money supply by a fixed annual percentage, equal to the
growth rate of the economy as a whole (Friedman 1968). However, this intuition is the
foundation of monetarism, and the failure of monetarism to meet its own limited policy
goals exposed its limits; time-inconsistency and rational expectations form the basis for
policy rules today. From the contemporary perspective, discretionary policy frameworks
are especially prone to time-inconsistency, since they do not allow market participants to
properly anticipate changes in the price level. In short, discretion is one of the two criteria by which the new consensus judges effective policy: it renders monetary authority
‘unpredictable’ (or, what is worse, ‘political’).
This is important for contemporary practice because the point of setting strict policy
rules is not only just to limit excessive monetary expansion. It is also because, according
to the same rational expectations logic, the expectational spiral of time-inconsistency is
contained only when monetary policy involves a credible commitment to an explicit
nominal inflation rate (of, for example, 2 per cent):
successful monetary policy is not so much a matter of effective control of overnight interest
rates as it is of shaping market expectations of the way in which interest rates, inflation, and
income are likely to evolve over the coming year and later. … Not only do expectations about
policy matter, but, at least under current circumstances, very little else matters. (Woodford
2003: 15)
Credible commitment to a clear rule should consequently limit or even eliminate
time-inconsistency, since it makes central banks’ behaviour eminently predictable. Rules
to which monetary authorities have, over time, demonstrated a real commitment are said
to ‘anchor’ market expectations: if a rule stipulates that the central bank must do everything in its power to maintain a target rate of inflation, and the central bank has in fact
demonstrated that it will adhere to the rule, then if inflation does accelerate for a brief
period, producers’, investors’, and wage-earners’ rational expectations will be that price
increases will be minor and temporary, and they will thus refrain from pricing anticipated inflation into their contracts. Optimal policy outcomes of this sort (i.e. the realisation of the targeted inflation rate, or near to it) are expected to be general across the
nation’s space-economy, because their effects are assumed to be temporally and spatially
uniform within its territory. (This last is one of those ‘assumptions’ made by economists
that none of them in fact believes. The problem is that if it is not assumed, the model
cannot be ‘closed’, and policy is much more difficult to justify [Issing 2001].)
I want to emphasise the fact that the seemingly ‘technical’ rules vs. discretion debate
in monetary policy takes on special weight when we remind ourselves that a policy rule
is not a ‘law’ in the ‘law of motion’ sense. The rules vs. discretion debate matters
immensely because a rule is not only something we must follow, but is also, and prior,
something we get to determine. The former – follow the rule, it’s the same for everyone
everywhere – suggests a technical proceduralism compatible with liberalism generally;
the latter suggests a politics, a politics of decision and the decision-maker, or ‘sovereign’.
And as Blinder puts it so clearly, politics is the last thing that is supposed to contaminate
contemporary capitalist monetary policy.
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
209
This is nothing more than willful, and futile, disavowal. In liberal capitalist democracy, the irreducibly political nature of monetary policy rules works itself out primarily
through the capture of central bank control and monetary authority by one class fraction: finance capital. The current ‘first world debt crisis’ has rendered this dominance,
and the associated complex and complete interdependence of the modern capitalist state
and finance capital, visible in an unprecedented manner: what else could justify the
‘bailouts’?
Democracy’s (and workers’) ‘inflation bias’
All models of monetary policy-making driving contemporary practice posit a democratic
‘inflation bias’. While the current obsession with inflation above all else has really only
determined policy in the wake of the collapse of Keynesianism, anti-democratic monetary politics are not a neoliberal innovation. In no way was Keynesianism (nor Keynes’s
theory, which is not necessarily the same thing) premised upon a wider participation in
or oversight of monetary authority, and monetary policy was an effective tool of capital
back in the Fordist hey-day too. In the late-1950s, for instance, the Fed tightened monetary policy to help disable union efforts in the industrial core (Dickens 1995). Equally, in
the late-1960s, faced with unprecedented working-class power, Nixon’s crisis-management
strategy took an explicitly ‘inflationary form’, in contrast to the deflationary form it took
in the late-nineteenth century and during the Depression, when labour was less able to
mount an effective political response (Arrighi 2007: 130; Dickens 1997). Indeed, the
collapse of the Fordist labour–capital accord is usefully framed by ‘conflict’ theories of
inflation (Taylor 1991; Rowthorn 1980), i.e. as a function of capital’s reaction to Nixon’s
attempt to use monetary policy as a means to subdue distributional conflict, a reaction
that ultimately realised itself in the authoritarian organisation of global financial hardship by Volcker’s Fed in 1979 (Marglin and Schor 1990).
It is worth emphasising that these are not only the musings of a critic of modern ‘new
consensus’ monetary governance. Orthodox economists and policy-makers have often
noted how helpful monetary policy is in containing labour–capital antagonism. As one
Bank of Canada deputy governor and economist noted in an enthusiastic assessment of
Canada’s inflation-targeting rule:
many of the other benefits anticipated from low inflation, such as low and less variable interest
rates, longer terms of wage settlements, fewer cost-of-living adjustment (COLA) clauses, a
reduction in the number of workdays lost to strikes, a lengthening in the terms of financial
contracts, and well-anchored inflation expectations, have also been realized. (Freedman 2005:
186)
Given that during the period in question (the IT era), real wages in Canada have
fallen and income and wealth inequality have accelerated, we can safely presume that
labour’s relative ‘flexibility’ is not attributable to increasing satisfaction with monetary
policy, labour relations or economic dynamics in general. Since the existence of fewer
COLAs and strikes is obviously entwined with the broader decline of union power in the
Canadian political economy, a pronouncement of this sort is clearly nothing less than an
enthusiastic celebration of monetary policy’s role in managing the Canadian working
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
210
Capital & Class 37(2)
class. Similarly, monetary authority has occasionally acknowledged explicitly that ‘fiscal’
authority has sometimes helpfully repaid its assistance in the struggle against the working
class. Writing of Volcker’s anti-inflationary work in the early years of the Reagan presidency (although it is important to note that the process began under Carter), Brenner
(1998: 191) notes how much Volcker attributed to Reagan’s attack on PATCO:
The most important single action of the administration in helping the anti-inflation fight was
defeating the air traffic controllers’ strike. He thought that this action had a rather profound,
and from his standpoint, constructive effect on the climate of labour-management relations,
even though it had not been a wage issue at the time.
Frank evaluations of this sort perform the welcome task of highlighting the class
politics central to money and monetary policy. Regardless of democracy’s purported
‘inflationary bias’, finance capital’s effort to constrain the liberal-democratic state from
following a path it deems too inflationary relies, crucially, on silencing workers’ opposition. Indeed, because inflation is frequently attributed to wage structures like COLAs –
so-called ‘wage-push’ inflation – eliminating it is understood to be predicated upon
precisely that form of working-class silence that victories in confrontations like the
PATCO strike helped capital achieve. These political effects are only exacerbated by
subnational regional disparities, which determine the distributional outcomes of monetary policy, most notably in the form of negative impacts on wages and employment
levels. Studies of several nations’ monetary regimes show that the effects of independent
central banks prioritising inflation control are to reduce wage and employment levels
over time (Fortin 2003; Iversen, 1998; Cornwall and Cornwall 1998; Jackson 1998;
Palley 2006).
In other words, if the sovereign capitalist state persists despite its anticipated disappearance in the age of capital, it does so at least partly, and in not insignificant ways,
through its monetary authority. The current ‘subprime’ crisis and the preeminence of
monetary policy in the macroeconomic mix mark the degree to which the wealthy
capitalist states – and, recently, other powerful nations like China – identify their political economic priorities as irreducibly monetary – and not necessarily in the ‘make as
much of it as possible’ way. Money is a primary means of governance in itself, via its
political function – which is, as we have seen, to help ring-fence and separate the monetary realm from democratic politics – and more instrumentally, in so far as the production, supply and pricing of money, not to mention the determination of the forms it can
legitimately take, are central tools of contemporary capitalist governance. The influence
these means have on social life today are hardly exaggerated by the business pages’
obsessive worrying. ‘Quantitative easing’, international ‘liquidity swaps’, ‘reverse repurchase agreements’: these are not tools used merely to address minor fraying at the fringes
of the social order (Financial Times, 12 May 2010, 6 April 2012; Guardian, 30
November 2011; Joyce et al. 2010; Obstfeld et al. 2009; Markets Group of the Federal
Reserve Bank of New York 2012).
Monetary regulation is thus crucial to the production and reproduction of the modern state. This involves both the performative writing of economic geographies via monetary discipline – which, in the case of powerhouses like the Fed, can extend far beyond
the state’s territorial boundaries – and the ideological production of a nationalist citizenship
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
211
which, however strictly class-differentiated, remains sufficiently beholden to a shared
macroeconomic ‘national’ welfare to accept the associated class-specific discipline as necessary.
These problems bring us back to the fact that political economic regulation in contemporary capitalist liberal democracies is founded upon money as exception. In modern
capitalist democracy, money is a realm from which both capitalism and democracy are
actively excluded. The monetary regime is not in any way shaped by competitive market
forces – it is, on the contrary, structured entirely by state authority; the competitive
moneys Hayek (1976) advocated remain a libertarian pipe-dream. Neither is money
open to democratic popular critique or engagement; the same state authority that keeps
the monetary sphere free of market forces is, even in ‘democracies’, non-democratic.
Money is a space of almost ‘pure’ decision or sovereignty, and a class-specific power at
that. This gives the very structure of modern monetary governance a distinctively authoritarian quality.
Indeed, Hobbes’s original formulation of the Leviathan is a remarkably fitting descriptor: the premise behind the entire modern capitalist state is that for capitalism and its
attendant liberties to thrive, money is the one social relation in which we must contract
with the sovereign, subject ourselves to total authority, and welcome a permanent state of
exception (Mann 2010). It is not by chance that in Agamben’s State of Exception (2005),
an engagement with Hobbes and his sometime champion, the Nazi jurist Carl Schmitt –
and a text that has quickly become very influential across the social sciences – many of the
historical examples of ‘states of exception’ are a product of the sovereign’s explicit effort to
protect the domestic currency. Democracy’s ‘inflationary bias’ is the monetary analogue of
Hobbes’s justification for the Leviathan: in the ‘state of Nature’, all we end up with is the
‘Warre of all against all’. Indeed, Hobbes (1968: 300) himself named the monetary space
as exceptional: money, he writes, is the ‘Bloud’ of the state, the ‘sanguification of the
Common-wealth’, ‘nourishing (as it passeth) every part thereof ’.
More than 350 years later, this is widely considered just plain common sense. Money
is the blood of the economic body. It must not be diluted (via inflation), and its circulation must not be interrupted. Central banks and the financial system in which they are
enmeshed are, on this account, the heart of modern life: pumping credit money through
the body, regulating systole and diastole in response to the level of (capitalist) economic
activity.
Now, however tempting it is to extend the metaphor, let’s return to the concept of
money as a non-democratic space before concluding, since it is worth confronting a
couple of finer points that further establish the ways in which the exception operates. To
take one possible wrinkle: the shift from discretionary to rule-based monetary policy I
described earlier would seem to trouble my argument. Indeed, it might seem that monetary policy conducted according to the discretion of central bankers is closer to a condition of ‘pure’ decision, and that the present commitment to policy rules fits reasonably
well with a depoliticised liberal proceduralism.
There are at least two problems with such an account, however. First, the rationales
for policy rules and central bank independence are interdependent, and evolved
together. As I hopefully made somewhat clear earlier, the expectational consistency that
justifies policy rules is understood as unobtainable if monetary authority must respond
to elected authority. Independence and policy rules are two sides of the same coin, since
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
212
Capital & Class 37(2)
one cannot make a credible commitment to a rule, a ‘decision’, if that commitment is
constantly open to popular question. In other words, the age of discretionary monetary
policy was also the age in which central banks were much more accountable to parliaments and congresses, an age in which public outrage at unemployment levels, for
example, directly shaped monetary policy. In spite of what central banks claim, rules do
not establish a juridical ‘proceduralism’ at the heart of monetary authority, since they
hold in a context in which that kind of accountability is no longer attendant to the
exercise of authority.
Second, and related, to suggest that rules are more egalitarian or ‘democratic’ is to
forget the point I made above regarding rules: they are not just followed, but also made.
And monetary policy rules like Canada’s inflation-targeting programme are made by a
tiny, but enormously powerful, cadre of society. Moreover, those who set the policy rules
in this case have no intention of debating them; the rules have not only been made by a
small group enjoying vast privilege, but, if at all possible, they will stand as the rules for
all time. Unquestionable power over the monetary regime is nothing less than the optimal institutional structure against which the ‘new consensus’ indexes policy ‘efficiency’.
Robert Lucas (1986: 128), the Nobel-winning ‘new classical’ macroeconomist (and perhaps the most influential economist of the post-Second World War era, surpassing even
his teacher Friedman), makes the case plainly: for ‘efficient’ monetary policy, ‘one must
either permit an initial government to make decisions binding for all time … or restrict
available strategies [of future governments] still further’.
To put this somewhat differently, then, ‘efficient’ (i.e. transparent and credible) monetary policy can be determined in one of two ways: set policy now for all time, or make
it impossible to change policy in the future. The authoritarian presumption is in either
case identical. Modern implementations of neoliberal monetary governance thus substitute ‘credible’, ‘transparent’, and ‘accountable’ for ‘democratic’, knowing full well that
the first two have nothing to do with democracy, and the third merely describes the
central bank’s relationship to the class that holds it accountable: capital, especially its
financial fraction.
A second potential problem for my account of money as non-democratic exception
may be highlighted through a consideration of the Euro, a ‘Bloud’ that would appear to
demand the end of state sovereignty. When the Euro came into circulation, eleven
nations agreed to surrender domestic control of their money. The status and success of
the Euro are, of course, controversial subjects. The very concept of the Euro is both
politically and analytically unstable, especially now that the Greek and Irish collapses,
and the others that appear imminent, seem to have made some wonder (i.e. Germany
and France) why they ever signed on in the first place. Nevertheless, the Euro emerged
from the European conundrum not despite or contrary to money-as-necessarilyanti-democratic, but because of it (Ingham 2004: ch. 9). This is because the common
market that preceded the Euro established an economic interdependence threatened by
the instability of diverse moneys and modes of monetary governance across member
nations. The contradictory combination of commercial integration and monetary
autonomy motivated the Euro and, as such, it arose as an international solution to the
problem of time-inconsistency writ large: space-inconsistency.
Basically, the Euro and the establishment of the European Central Bank (ECB) –
which, by no accident, is also the most independent central bank on the planet – does
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
213
not so much challenge the notion of money as exception as it demonstrates that the
accession to the sovereign decision in the monetary realm is so essential to the health of
modern capitalist states that a not insignificant number of them were willing to make the
extraordinary commitment to acquiesce to a supra-national monetary Leviathan. Indeed,
if there is a more Leviathan-like institution than the ECB at work in the West, I am not
familiar with it.
Money is not neutral
To conclude, let’s return to the problems with which the discussion opened. If labour
or working-class studies are at least partly driven by a labour theory of value that is, in
effect, a theory of exploitation, then much of its normative political content boils
down to an immanent critique of distribution in capitalism. In other words, for the
most part labour history and geography are not primarily anti-capitalist endeavours
but, rather, aimed at the construction of a kinder, gentler capitalism. If so, then the
challenge I am trying to name is not how to become more radically anti-capitalist.
Instead, my concern is that the vision of a kinder, gentler capitalist is perhaps too often
developed in the shadow of a misunderstanding of the extent to which class-privileged,
capitalist institutions are in fact the basis for the stability of social relations – like
money – that we imagine will simply continue to operate in the same fashion, after
radical redistribution. In other words, it is possible that the very wealth we imagine
might be redistributed is in fact only the kind of wealth it is because of the neoliberal
capitalism in which it circulates.
Much of the monetary stability we currently enjoy in the global North – which,
although it may seem not all that stable, is in fact almost unprecedented historically – is
a result of the institutionalisation of a class-biased, elite neoliberalism that is entirely
incompatible with the basically social-democratic vision behind much of the labour critique. Space- and time-inconsistency may or may not be illusory ‘new consensus’ scare
tactics, but the expected monetary security that is the very basis of distributional schemes
like guaranteed minimum incomes is arguably a product of power relations that mitigate
against any such arrangements. ‘Democratic’ monetary governance will produce a monetary regime very different from that currently in operation, a monetary regime that,
unless things work very differently than they do today, might very well be a good argument against itself.
Stepping back from the specifics detailed above, what all this suggests is that modern
capitalist institutions may be marked by what we might call threshold values on the
democracy index. Put another way, there is a very good chance that, if we ever realise the
kind of social change that animates the social-democratic proposals with which labour
critique is often associated, the institutions we imagine ‘retaking’ or ‘transforming’ will
not actually work for our purposes. While this is more easily believed of capitalist finance,
or the prison system, it is also potentially true of those seemingly ‘neutral’ instruments of
power, like money, that we take for granted in our gut-level theories of exploitation and
distribution.
I do not want to make any of this seem simple or straightforward. It is not. If finance
capital enjoys extraordinary power and privilege at both the national and global scale,
then what exactly is the nature of that power and privilege? I am still struggling with
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
214
Capital & Class 37(2)
these questions. Moreover, in the face of this, what are our alternatives? If money is not
to be the non-democratic, non-capitalist exception that somehow ensures the persistence
of the democratic capitalist norm – then what other possibilities might withstand scrutiny? Whatever our questions, the answers must almost certainly be more ‘radical’ than
the past might lead us to expect.
Acknowledgements
This paper has benefited from discussion following talks at the University of Washington and the
University of Victoria. I am grateful to the editors and reviewers at Capital & Class, and also to
Brad Bryan and Geoffrey Ingham, whose sharp minds greatly improved the argument. The
research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (grant
number 410-2009-2812).
References
Agamben G (2005) State of Exception. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Arrighi G (2007) Adam Smith in Beijing. New York, NY: Verso.
Barro R, Gordon D (1983) Rules, discretion and reputation in a model of monetary policy outcomes. Journal of Monetary Economics 12(1): 101–21.
Bernanke B (2003) A perspective on inflation targeting: Why it seems to work. Business Economics
38(3): 7–15.
Bernhard W, Broz JL, Clark WR (2002) The political economy of monetary institutions.
International Organization 56(4): 693–723.
Blinder A (1998) Central Banking in Theory and Practice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Boddy R, Crotty J (1975) Class conflict and macro-policy: The political business cycle. Review of
Radical Political Economics 7(1): 1–19.
Brenner R (1998) The economics of global turbulence. New Left Review I/229: 1–265.
Calvo G (1978) On the time consistency of optimal policy in a monetary economy. Econometrica
46(6): 1411–28.
Carpenter S, Rodgers W (2005) The disparate labor market impacts of monetary policy. Labor
History 46(1): 57–77.
Cornwall J, Cornwall W (1998) Unemployment costs of inflation targeting. In Arestis P, Sawyer, M
(eds.) The Political Economy of Central Banking. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, pp. 49–66.
De Long JB (1996) Keynesianism, Pennsylvania Avenue style: Some economic consequences of
the Employment Act of 1946. Journal of Economic Perspectives 10(3): 41–53.
Dickens E (1995) U.S. monetary policy in the 1950s: A radical political economic approach.
Review of Radical Political Economics 27(4): 83–111.
Dickens E (1997) Tight monetary policy during the 1973–75 recession: A survey of possible interpretations. Review of Radical Political Economics 29(3): 79–91.
Drazen A (2000) Political Economy in Macroeconomics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Epstein G (1992) Political economy and comparative central banking. Review of Radical Political
Economics 24(1): 1–30.
Fortin P (2003) Can monetary policy make a difference for economic growth and inequality?
Canadian Public Policy/Analyse de Politique 29(supp.): S223–32.
Freedman C (2005) Reflections on the Bank of Canada’s monetary policy framework. In Arestis
P, Baddeley M, McCombie J (eds.) The New Monetary Policy: Implications and Relevance.
Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, pp. 172–91.
Friedman M (1968) The role of monetary policy. American Economic Review 58(1): 1–17.
Gildea J (1990) Explaining FOMC members’ votes. In Mayer T (ed.) The Political Economy of
American Monetary Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 211–27.
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Mann
215
Glyn A (2006) Capitalism Unleashed: Finance, Globalization, and Welfare. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Greider W (1987) Secrets Of The Temple: How The Federal Reserve Runs The Country. New York,
NY: Simon and Schuster.
Havrilesky T, Schweitzer R (1990) A theory of FOMC dissent voting with evidence from the
time series. In Mayer T (ed.) The Political Economy of American Monetary Policy. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 197–210.
Hayek F (1976) Denationalization of Money: An Analysis of the Theory and Practice of Competitive
Currencies. London: Institute of Economic Affairs.
Ingham G (2004) The Nature of Money. Cambridge: Polity.
Ingham G (2008) Capitalism. Cambridge: Polity.
Issing O (2001) The single monetary policy of the European Central Bank: One size fits all.
International Finance 4(3): 441–62.
Iversen T (1998) Wage bargaining, central bank independence, and the real effects of money.
International Organization 52(3): 469–504.
Jackson A (1998) The NAIRU and macro-economic policy in Canada. Canadian Labour Congress
Research Paper No. 12. Ottawa: Canadian Labour Congress.
Jayadev A (2006) Differing preferences between anti-inflation and anti-unemployment policy
among the rich and poor. Economics Letters 91(1): 67–71.
Joyce M, Lasaosa A, Stevens I, Tong M (2010) The financial market impact of quantitative easing.
Bank of England Working Paper No. 393.
Keynes JM (1930) A Treatise on Money. London: Macmillan.
Krippner G (2007) The making of US monetary policy: Central bank transparency and the neoliberal dilemma. Theory and Society 36(6): 477–513.
Kydland F, Prescott E (1977) Rules rather than discretion: The inconsistency of optimal plans.
Journal of Political Economy 85(3): 473–93.
Mann G (2010) Hobbes’ redoubt? Toward a geography of monetary policy. Progress in Human
Geography 34(5): 601–25.
Marglin S, Schor J (1990) The Golden Age of Capitalism: Reinterpreting the Postwar Experience.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Markets Group of the Federal Reserve Bank of New York (2012) Domestic open market operations during 2011. Federal Reserve Bank of New York website, online at <www.newyorkfed.
org>, March; accessed 8 April 2012.
Marx K (1973 [1858]) Grundrisse, trans. Nicolaus M. London: Penguin.
McNally D (2009) From financial crisis to world slump: Accumulation, financialization, and the
global slowdown. Historical Materialism 17(2): 35–83.
Mouffe C (2000) The Democratic Paradox. New York, NY: Verso.
Obstfeld M, Shambaugh JC, Taylor AM (2009) Financial instability, reserves, and central bank
swap lines in the panic of 2008. National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper No.
14826.
Palley TI (2006) A post-Keynesian framework for monetary policy: Why interest rate operating
procedures are not enough. In Gnos C, Rochon LP (eds.) Post-Keynesian Principles of Policy.
Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, pp. 81–101.
Peck J, Tickell A (2002) Neoliberalizing space. Antipode 34(3): 380–404.
Polity J (2010) Fed official warns of debt threat. Financial Times 12 May.
Posen A (2005) Declarations are not enough: Financial sector sources of central bank independence. NBER Macroeconomics Annual 10: 253–74.
Rogoff K (1985) The optimal degree of commitment to an intermediate monetary target. Quarterly
Journal of Economics 100(4): 1169–89.
Rowthorn B (1980) Capitalism, Conflict and Inflation. London: Lawrence & Wishart.
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
216
Capital & Class 37(2)
Ryan-Collins J, Greenham T, Werner R, Jackson A (2011) Where Does Money Come From? A Guide
to the UK Monetary and Banking System. London: New Economics Foundation.
Schmitt C (2005) Political Theology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Schmitt C (2008) Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes: Meaning and Failure of a Political
Symbol. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Shellock D (2012) Liquidity fears drive down equities. Financial Times 6 April.
Stewart H (2011) Dollar swaps. The Guardian 30 November.
Taylor L (1991) Income Distribution, Inflation, and Growth: Lectures on Structuralist Macroeconomic
Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Weber M (1978) Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology. Berkeley, CA: University
of California Press.
Woodford M (2003) Interests and Prices: Foundations of a Theory of Monetary Policy. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Author biography
Geoff Mann is the director of the Centre for Global Political Economy at Simon Fraser University,
and teaches in the Department of Geography. His book, Our Daily Bread: Wages, Workers, and the
Political Economy of the American West (Chapel Hill) appeared in 2007, and Disassembly Required:
A Field Guide to Actually Existing Capitalism (AK Press) in early 2013. He is presently completing
a book on the many lives of Keynesian political economy.
Downloaded from cnc.sagepub.com at SIMON FRASER LIBRARY on June 18, 2013
Download