Justice Breyer's Mandarin Liberty Active Liberty: Interpreting Our Democratic Constitution by Stephen Breyer Review by: Ken I. Kersch The University of Chicago Law Review, Vol. 73, No. 2 (Spring, 2006), pp. 759-822 Published by: The University of Chicago Law Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4495568 . Accessed: 31/12/2013 12:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . The University of Chicago Law Review is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The University of Chicago Law Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions REVIEW Justice Breyer'sMandarinLiberty Ken I. Kerscht Active Liberty:InterpretingOurDemocraticConstitution, StephenBreyer.Alfred A. Knopf,2005.Pp ix, 161. JusticeStephenBreyer arrivedat the SupremeCourtin 1994with a broad backgroundin academia,governmentservice,and the federal judiciary,and as one of the nation'sleading scholarsof administrative and regulatorypolicy and law. At the time, Breyer, a HarvardLaw School law and economics scholar who had worked effectively as a congressionalstaffer with members of both parties and had been an architectof airlinederegulationduringthe Carteradministration,won broad supportfrom both sides of the aisle.Although extensivelypublished in his areas of expertise,he had written little or nothing about constitutionalissues,includingmattersof constitutionalinterpretation. Most of the limitedoppositionto Breyer'sappointmentcame not from Republicans,but from the left wing of the DemocraticParty,whichsaw him as a bloodless technocrattoo cozy with business interests and insufficientlycommittedto civil liberties and civil rights.He was nevertheless confirmedby a vote of 87-9.' t Assistant Professorof Politics,PrincetonUniversity;VisitingResearch Scholar,Social Philosophyand PolicyCenter,Bowling Green State University(Fall2005).Thanksto Aurelian Craiutu,Donald Downs,ClementFatovic,RonaldKahn,KeithWhittington,and the participants in the AmericanPoliticalDevelopmentWorkshopat the Universityof Wisconsin,Madison,for helpfulcommentsand suggestions.Researchassistancewas providedby TerranceWatson(Bowling Green)and EmilyZackin(Princeton). 1 See Ken I. Kersch,TheSyntheticProgressivismof StephenG. Breyer,in Earl M. Maltz, the CourtDynamic241,243-44,248-49 (Kansas2003) (dised, RehnquistJustice:Understanding cussingBreyer'sscholarlypursuits,activitiesin government,and reputationas a "techno-judge"); KennethJost, The SupremeCourtYearbook,2000-2001 335-36 (CQ 2002) (providinggeneral biographicalinformationaboutJusticeBreyer).See also Ken I. Kersch,StephenBreyer,in Melvin Urofsky,ed, The SupremeCourtJustices:A BiographicalDictionary(forthcoming2006) (noting thatfor Clinton'sfirstSupremeCourtappointment,he chose to nominateRuth BaderGinsburg insteadof Breyer because Breyer"reportedlycame acrossas too cold and technocraticfor the President'staste").Those looking for a broad overview of JusticeBreyer'sjurisprudenceand decisions as a SupremeCourt Justiceshould consult these sources.Here, I considerhis book froma broader,more theoreticalperspective. 759 This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 760 The University of Chicago Law Review [73:759 Unlike many modern constitutionalliberals,Justice Breyer has never consideredthe task of interpretingthe law to be, first and foremost, a "matterof principle."2'Accounts of Justice Breyer's jurisprudence (with whichhe would most likely agree) have typicallyended by characterizinghim as a "commonsense"moderate and judicial"pragmatist,"with a predispositionfor looking beyond the applicationof formal,a prioriprinciplesin favor of the attainmentof concrete,realworld objectives."His particulartalent has been to read technically complex regulatorycontexts and to interpret statutes being applied within them in a way that best advanceswhat he takes to be the relevant regulatoryobjective.He conceives of this task as a problemsolving endeavorin whichcourtsandjudges are only one partof a broader national-levelregulatoryapparatus.The role of the judge, in Breyer's view, is to be mindful of the regulatorysystem's purpose as a whole (and the limited institutionalcapacitiesof judges) and to work as part of a broaderteam of institutionsfocused on achievingstatutoryobjectives.4 In approachinga policy problem or a case, JusticeBreyer is characteristicallymindful that an appropriatejudgment is possible only when a wealth of empiricaldata is close at hand. For this reason,Justice Breyer is a committed empiricist.Because legislatorsand expert administratorsroutinely have a wealth of empirical information at their command that judges do not have, Justice Breyer has often reminded us they are typicallybetter situatedthanjudges to make these 2 See Ronald Dworkin, A Matterof Principle 2-3 (Harvard 1985). See also Justice Breyer'scolloquywith Dworkin,in RobertBadinterand StephenBreyer,eds,Judgesin ContemporaryDemocracy:AnInternationalConversation85 (NYU 2004): Ronnie says that judges enforce their convictionsof "politicalmorality."... [T]he basic questiona judgeasksis "Whatis fair?"... [O]ne,highlyabstract,generalquestionthat I ask about the properresultin a case [is,]"Does this interpretationmake sense?"where"sense" has a speciallegalconnotationrelatedto the basicpurposeof the provisionin question. 3 See, for example,Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 244 (cited in note 1); WalterE. Joyce, The Early Constitutional Jurisprudence of JusticeStephenG. Breyer:A Studyof the Justice'sFirstYearon the UnitedStatesSupremeCourt,7 Seton Hall ConstL J 149, 163 (1996) (describingBreyer's"moderation,technicalskill, and measuredanalysis"and "carefuland pragmatic approachto constitutionalinterpretation"); Mark Silversteinand WilliamHaltom, You Can'tAlwaysGet WhatYouWant:Reflectionson the Ginsburgand BreyerNominations,12 J L & Polit 459, 461 (1996) (describingBreyeras "a techno-judgeof substantiallegal skillsbut utterly wantingin the politicaland real-lifeexperiences[PresidentClinton]sought").ConsiderJeffreyS. Lubbers,JusticeStephenBreyer:Purveyorof CommonSensein ManyForums,8 Admin L J Am U 775, 776 (1995) (notingBreyer's"willingnessand abilityto serve as a common-sensegovernment reformer"in forumsoutsideof the Court);RichardJ.Pierce,Jr.,JusticeBreyer:Intentionalist,Pragmatist,and Empiricist,8 AdminL J Am U 747,747 (1995). 4 See Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 248-49 (cited in note 1) ("Thefirstimperativeof [Breyer's]syntheticprogressivismis thatthe judge shouldserve as a helpmeetin the formulation of wise policy."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 761 assessments."For this reason,Justice Breyer counts himself a believer in judicialrestraint. An admirer of European technocracy,Justice Breyer has been one of the most prominentadvocates for a "comparativist"approach to legal questions,'whereby lawyers and judges talk across borders and look around the world for approaches and solutions to shared policy problems.Unlike many who look abroadprimarilyto discerna moral consensus (such as, for example, on the death penalty), Justice Breyer's comparativismis primarilyan outgrowthof his empiricism. He argues that American judges should look to the ways in which their counterpartsin other countries have decided cases because, in doing so, they will find a wealth of informationthat will "cast an empirical light" on many of the same purposive policy questions that commonlycome before Americancourts.9 5 See id at 249 ("Wisepolicymakingis [to Breyer]first and foremosta matter of ... an empiricaljudgmentof the kind that a legislatureis more likely than a court to make with accuracy.")(internalquotationmarksomitted).See also UnitedStatesv Lopez, 514 US 549, 616-17 (1995) (Breyerdissenting)("Courtsmustgive Congressa degreeof leeway."). 6 LindaGreenhouse,The CompetingVisionsof the Role of the Court,NY Times C3 (July 7, 2002). See also Pierce,8 AdminL J Am U at 753-54 (cited in note 3) (describingCourtcases reversingagencyinterpretationsof statutesas "starklyinconsistentwith JusticeBreyer'sdedication to intentionalism,pragmatism,and empiricism").Some have allegedthat JusticeBreyerhas been the RehnquistCourtjusticeleast likely to void a federalstatuteon constitutionalgrounds. See PaulGewirtzand ChadGolder,So WhoAre theActivists?,NY TimesA19 (July6, 2005): We found that justicesvary widely in their inclinationto strike down Congressionallaws. JusticeClarenceThomas,appointedby PresidentGeorgeH.W.Bush,was the most inclined, voting to invalidate65.63 percent of those laws; Justice Stephen Breyer, appointed by PresidentBill Clinton,was the least,votingto invalidate28.13percent. A studyby politicalscientistChristopherZorn,however,places Breyernear the Rehnquist Court'scenter in this regard.He was more likely to void a federal statute on constitutional grounds,statisticallyspeaking,thanwere JusticesRehnquistand O'Connor,but less likely to do so thanJusticesThomas,Scalia,Kennedy,Ginsburg,and Stevens.He was approximatelyas likely to invalidatefederal statutesas was JusticeSouter.ChristopherZorn, LiberalJustices,Judicial Activism,and FederalJudicialReview:An EmpiricalPerspective9 (presentedat the LibertyFund Conferenceon Law,Liberty,andJudicialReview,June9-12, 2005). 7 I borrowthe termJusticeBreyeruses to describehimselfin this regard.StephenBreyer, KeynoteAddress,97 Am SocietyIntl L Proc 265, 266 (2003) ("I believe the 'comparativist'view that severalof us have enunciatedwill carrythe day."). 8 Thisis not the case for all the Court'sjusticesinterestedin this trend,and not exclusively the case for JusticeBreyer.See Ken I. Kersch,The SupremeCourtand InternationalRelations Theory,Albany L Rev (forthcoming2006).There,I argue that many of the justices,including JusticeBreyer,have also been influencedby a broader,"diplomatic," foreignpolicyvision.Id at 2-4 (criticizingthis vision as undertheorizedand as a concessionto popularliberalconceptions the Globalized of internationallaw). See also Ken I. Kersch,The New Legal Transnationalism, Judiciary,and the Rule of Law, 4 Wash U Global Stud L Rev 345, 354-55 (2005) ("[A]t least some of the Court'sjustices ... increasinglysee themselves as ambassadorsdoing their part, throughjudicialglobalization,to improvethe reputationof the United Statesabroad."). 9 Printz v United States,521 US 898, 977 (1997) (Breyer dissenting)(using Madison's examinationof Europeanpoliticalexperiencein TheFederalist,numbers42 and 43, to arguefor This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 762 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 With the publicationof Active Liberty:InterpretingOur Democratic Constitution,Justice Breyer has now moved to undergird his longstandingjurisprudentialvision with a foray into democratictheory.'o Formerly,Breyer, the scholar of statutes, administration,and regulation,was more or less content to take up a succession of relatively narrow questions that involved discerningthe purpose of particular statutes and constitutional provisions and principles, each viewed more or less in isolation from the other."In Active Liberty,he now argues confidentlythat the Constitutionhas a centralpurposethe promotion of "active liberty"or "the right of individualsto participate in democratic self-government"(p 21). While the Constitution's "democraticobjective"in many cases counselsjudicialrestraint, he argues,it also should serve as a "sourceof judicialauthorityand an interpretive aid to more effective protection of [both individualand community]liberty"(p 6). He contends that it is importantfor a judge to see his or her interpretivetask as involving"a quest for ... workable democraticgovernmentprotective of individualpersonal liberty" (p 34). As his use of the word "quest"suggests,this process is perpetual and provisional,always open to appropriateexperimentationand the considerationof new empiricalevidence.To the judge befalls the especially importanttask of keeping the conduits of evidence open, and the lines of discussionfree.1 Active Libertyis a short book, writtenfor (serious) general readin ers, which Breyer sets out, explains, and seeks to justify his approach to constitutional(and statutory)interpretation.JusticeBreyer understandshimself to have a modest conception of a judge's role. Consistently,he claimsonly modest ambitionsfor this book. "I am not arguing for a new theory of constitutionallaw,"he explains (p 110). "My argument[does] not rest[] upon logical or scientificallyconvincan analogouscontemporaryendeavorby the Court).ConsiderStephenBreyer,On the Uses of Statutes,65 S Cal L Rev 845,868 (1992)("[U]nlikeour country, LegislativeHistoryin Interpreting [foreign countries]have developed other institutions[such as the use of expert draftersand administrativejudges who review proposedlegislation]to bring about and maintainnecessary interpretiveconsistencyandcoherence."). 10 This process,culminatingin 2005'sActive Liberty,was launchedin Breyer'sMadison Lectureat New YorkUniversitySchool of Law School.See generallyStephenBreyer,Our DemocraticConstitution, 77 NYU L Rev 245 (2002). 11 See Breyer,65 S Cal L Rev at 845-46 (cited in note 9); StephenBreyer,JudicialReview of Questionsof Law and Policy,38 Admin L Rev 363,364-65 (1986) (advocatingjudicialreview of agencyregulationsbased on a "global,comprehensiveview of an agency'sobjectivesand its work")(emphasisadded). 12 Here, JusticeBreyer echoes a theme that has been at the center of the constitutional scholarof risk and regulation,Cass Sunstein.See Cass philosophyof anotherHarvard-educated R. Sunstein,One Caseat a Time:JudicialMinimalismon the SupremeCourt259 (Harvard1999) ("Minimalismalso maintainsflexibilityfor the future,an especiallylarge virtuewhen facts and valuesare in flux."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer's Mandarin Liberty 763 ing empiricaldemonstration"(id). It does not "presenta general theory of constitutionalinterpretation"(p 7). Rather,Active Liberty"illustrate[s] a theme" (id). Indeed, Breyer, as we have been told by scholarsof the Court no less than by the Justicehimself,does not believe that such general theories are useful (pp 19, 110-11). As such, this book touts its humility,not simply as a matter of JusticeBreyer's temperament,but also as a matterof his substantiveconvictions." Althoughit may not be fully argued,or defendedby "logicalor scientificallyconvincingempiricaldemonstration,"Active Libertyloudly trumpetsa theory of interpretation(p 110).Thattheoryconsists of two propositions.First, a judge should interpret a law in light of both its purposes (or objectives) and the consequences of that judge's interpretationfor the achievementof those purposes.Second, an approach that accords due regard to the purposes and consequences of interpretingparticularstatutoryand constitutionalprovisionswill advance the overarchingpurpose of the Constitutionas a whole, which is to promote "the people's will," or "democracy,"or "active liberty" (pp 115-16). Breyer illustratesthe usefulness of this "approach,perspective, and emphasis"by providingreaders with short discussions,in a seeminglycommonsensicalspirit,of how a focus on purposes,and the consequences of particular interpretations for the likelihood of achieving those purposes,can helpfully inform the way that judges approachstatutoryand constitutionalquestionsinvolving"contemporaryproblems"of free speech, federalism(or, as he has called it, "the 'federalist'problem"),14privacy,affirmativeaction, statutoryinterpretation, and administrativelaw (pp 7, 11). Breyer bookends these "applications"chapters with short, elegantly written chapters on democratic theory and American constitutionalhistory,grounding his approach at the book's beginningand anticipatingand meeting possible objectionsto it at its end. JusticeBreyer'sprotestationsto modesty notwithstanding,Active Liberty will be taken by many as presenting a novel and refreshing interpretiveposture, on a Court starved for intellectually ambitious 13 Sunsteinhas defined "judicialminimalism"as an approachto judging that promotes "democraticdeliberation"by avoidingabstractionsand,while acceptingagreedupon core principles in makingdecisions,hews closely to the relevantfacts of unique,individualcases to issue provisionaldecisions that are subjectto later refinement,clarification,and revision.Id at 4-5 decisionmakingrules in constitutionallaw that keep rulingsnarrowand (listing"time-honored" fact specific).See also JeffreyRosen, TwoCheersfor the RehnquistCourt,1 Nexus J Op 37, 39 (1996)(describingBreyeras "cautious,incremental,pragmatic,respectfulof historicalarguments, andsuspiciousof sweepingclaimsaboutfundamentalvalues"). 14 StephenBreyer,KeynoteAddress,Symposiumon Democracyand the Rule of Law in a ChangingWorldOrder,New YorkUniversitySchool of Law (Mar9, 2000) (notingthat physical distancefromfederaldecisionmakerstendsto alienateindividualcitizens). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 764 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 jurisprudentialliberals.Active Libertywill also be taken by many as a brief for judicial restraintand humilityin an era of highly aggressive (and, to many,frightening)conservativejudicial activism."Although there are grounds for either type of reception, neither perspective, viewed more broadly,capturesthe truth. I. PURPOSES,CONSEQUENCES,AND LIBERTY Justice Breyer begins his argument in Active Liberty by noting the genuine difficultyof the questionsof how to interpreta legal text, particularlyas that text is applied in the sorts of close cases that comprise the most prominentpart of the Supreme Court'sdocket (pp 7, 9). And he notes that, in approachingthis task, all judges,himself included, are pluralists--that is, they are eclectic.All "use similarbasic tools to help them accomplishthe task"(p 7): They read the text's language along with related language in other parts of the document.They take account of its history,including history that shows what the language likely meant to those who wrote it. They look to tradition indicating how the relevant language was, and is, used in the law. They examine precedents interpretingthe phrase, holding or suggesting what the phrasemeans and how it has been applied.They try to understand the phrase'spurposesor (in respect to many constitutional phrases)the values that it embodies,and they considerthe likely consequences of the interpretivealternatives,valued in terms of the phrase's purposes (pp 7-8).16 The differencesbetween judges in makingrecourseto these materials, he contends,is a matter of emphasis,both within a particularcase or context and more generally.Breyer argues,however,that these differences in emphasismatter(pp 8-9). "My own view,"he writes,explainingthe originsof his own general emphases in interpretinga legal text, stems from "see[ing] the [Constitution]as creatinga coherent frameworkfor a certain kind of government"(p 8): Described generally, that government is democratic;it avoids concentrationof too much power in too few hands;it protects 15 See, for example,ThomasM. Keck, TheMostActivistSupremeCourtin History2 (Chicago 2004) ("[T]he [Rehnquist]Court has developed a distinctivenew style of conservative judicialactivism."). 16 It is notable that the Court'snew chief justice,John Roberts,describedthe judge'srole in similarlypluralisticterms duringhis confirmationhearings.See Craig Green, O'Connor's Opposite,27 Natl L J 23,23 (Aug22,2005). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer's Mandarin Liberty 765 personal liberty; it insists that the law respect each individual equally; and it acts only upon the basis of law itself. The document embodies these general objectives in discrete provisions (pp 8-9). In approachingconstitutionalcases,as JusticeBreyer sees it, he is called upon to assess the implicationsof his understandingof the relationship between the Constitution's"other general objectives" and this overarching"democraticobjective"(p 9). He acknowledgesthat in difficult cases, differentjustices will assess the implicationsof this relationshipin differentways (pp 9-11). These differencesare evident not only by looking at the spectrum of emphases found among the justices of the currentSupremeCourt, but also if one surveysthe nation'spast.JusticeBreyer is somethingof an historicist.Rather than seeking to advancea timeless argumentfor an appropriatejudicialposture,Breyer the pluralistacknowledgesthat "membersof historicallydifferent Supreme Courts have emphasized different constitutionalthemes, objectives,or approachesover time" (p 9). In the early nineteenth century,the Court "helped to establish the authorityof the federal government,includingthe federal judiciary" (p 10). In the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries,the Court "overlyemphasized... the protection of private property"and "wrongly underemphasizedthe basic objectives of the Civil War amendments"(id). The New Deal and the WarrenCourts"emphasized ways in which the Constitutionprotected the citizen's 'active liberty,' i.e., the scope of the right to participatein [democratic]government" (id).." As his decision to characterizeboth the New Deal and Warren Courtsas centrallycommittedto democracyand "activeliberty"makes clear,JusticeBreyer identifieshis own constitutionalagenda with that of these earlier courts,and positions himself,in significantrespects,as a partisan of midcentury constitutional liberalism (p 11). And he commits himself to carryingthis agenda forwardinto the future (pp 11-12). At the point in historyin which he sits on the SupremeCourt, while it is importantto give due weight to "language,history,and tradition," he argues here, it is especially important to emphasize the consequencesof particularinterpretationson the advancementof "active liberty"-the "Constitution'sdemocraticobjective"(p 12). Justice Breyer argues that an approach mindful of the consequences of a particularlegal interpretationfor the achievementof the 17 For similarviews on the Lochner,New Deal, andWarrenCourts,see Akhil Reed Amar, America'sConstitution:ABiography475 (RandomHouse 2005);MortonJ.Horwitz,TheWarren Courtand thePursuitof Justice3-4, 76-78 (Hill andWang1998). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 766 The University of Chicago Law Review [73:759 Constitution'sdemocraticobjective falls squarelywithin "an interpretive tradition"that values not simplycollective rights,but also the collective duties of the people (p 17). Such an interpretivetraditionvalues "callsfor judicial restraint"in the face of decisionsmade by a majority of the people, often throughthe voice of their elected representatives (id). The authorityof these representatives"mustbe broad"(p 15). Deference to them is due not just when a judge determines for himself that, as a matter of public policy, they have decided rightly. "Thepeople must have room to decide and leeway to make mistakes," he writes (p 15).'8 This interpretive tradition,he tells us, "sees texts as driven by purposes"(p 17). "[T]hejudge, whether applyingstatute or Constitution, should 'reconstructthe past solution imaginativelyin its setting and project the purposes which inspired it upon the concrete occasions which arise for their decision"'(p 18).19And to realize these purposes in the real world,a judge must be attentive to the consequences likely to flow from his interpretation.This requiresa judge to read and map that world, taking full account of "contemporaryconditions,social, industrial,and political, of the communityto be affected" (id).20 According to Breyer,"nothingthat is logically relevant should be excluded"(id).21 Justice Breyer recognizesthat the interpretivetraditionhe seeks to advance in Active Liberty"does not expect highly general instructions themselves to determinethe outcome of difficultconcrete cases where language is open-ended and precisely defined purpose is difficult to ascertain" (id). Key constitutional provisions like the Due Process and Equal Protection clauses reflect "aspirations,"and were not designed to be rules of action (id).22When faced with these provi18 See also New StateIce Co v Liebmann,285 US 262, 286-300 (1932) (Brandeisdissenting). For Justice Breyer'sviews on Justice Brandeisas a like-mindedempiricist,see Stephen Breyer,JusticeBrandeisas LegalSeer,BrandeisLectureat the Universityof LouisvilleSchoolof Law (Feb 16, 2004), online at http://www.supremecourtus.gov/publicinfo/speeches/sp_02-1604.html(visitedApr 4, 2006) ("[Brandeis]was rightthat we mustcontinueto use facts and consequencesto distinguishpermissible,or better,from impermissibleor worse,interpretationsof the Constitutionand of law."). 19 CitingLearnedHand, The Contributionof an IndependentJudiciaryto Civilization,in IrvingDilliard,ed, TheSpiritof Liberty:PapersandAddressesof LearnedHand 155,157 (Knopf 3d ed 1960)(arguingagainsta plainlanguageapproachbecause"wordsare suchtemperamental beingsthatthe surestway to lose theiressenceis to take themat theirface"). 20 CitingLouisD. Brandeis,in SolomonGoldman,ed, TheWordsof JusticeBrandeis115(1953) or arbitrary"). (usingsocialconsensusto assesswhethera policepowerstatuteis "unreasonable 21 CitingFelix Frankfurter, Some Reflectionson the Readingof Statutes,47 ColumL Rev 527,541 (1947) ("Therigidityof the Englishcourtsin interpretinglanguagemerelyby readingit disregardsthe fact thatenactmentsare ... organismswhichexist in theirenvironment."). 22 CitingFelix Frankfurter, The SupremeCourtin the Mirrorof Justices,in PhilipB. Kurland,ed, Of Law and Life & OtherThingsThatMatter:PapersandAddressesof FelixFrankfurter, This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 767 sions, judges must not act "willful[ly],in the sense of enforcing individual views" (id).23Quoting Louis Brandeis,he reminds judges that "we must be ever on our guard,lest we erect our prejudicesinto legal principles"(p 19).24At the same time,JusticeBreyer arguesthatjudges should not rely uncriticallyand woodenly on legal formulasin an effort to steer clear of willfulness(id):25 The tradition answerswith an attitude,an attitude that hesitates to rely upon any single theory or grandview of law,of interpretation, or of the Constitution.It championsthe need to search for purposes;it calls for restraint.... And it finds in the democratic nature of our system more than simply a justificationfor judicial restraint(id). A. Purposeand the Legal Process In laying out his argumentthat legal texts are most appropriately interpretedin light of their purposes and the likely consequences of particularinterpretationsfor the achievementof those purposes,Justice Breyer forswearsany ambitionsto originality.He is right to do so. For with the publicationof Active Libertyreaders are presented with the legal process templatefor the interpretationof legal texts- a template that first rose to prominencein the heydayof managerialliberalism in the 1950s-in what surely must be the purest, most undiluted form ever proffered by a sitting Justice of the Supreme Court.The central argumentof Active Liberty--that (as Breyer puts it) the law is or ought to be goal-oriented,rational,and dynamic(pp 17-20), that it ought to be understood purposively,with an animatingfocus on the problems to be solved, with courts interpretingthe law situated, as institutionswith their own distinctive competences,within a broader frameworkof a "problemsolvinggovernment"-is all but lifted off the pages of Henry Hart and Albert Sacks's landmarklaw school text- 1956-196377, 94 (Atheneum1969) (noting that "[t]he Courtwas of course from the beginning the interpreterof the Constitution"). 23 Citingid at 95 (arguingthatjudgesmust also not act "wooden[ly],in uncriticallyresting on formulas").Justice Breyer's views, in this regard,are similar to Ronald Dworkin's.See Dworkin,Matterof Principleat 17 (cited in note 2) (distinguishingjudgeswho decide cases "on politicalgrounds"from those who eschew all externalconstraintson their decisionmakingprerogative). 24 QuotingNew StateIce, 285 US at 311 (Brandeisdissenting)(cautioningthat substantive due processcan be a meansby whichprejudiceis embodiedin law). 25 Citingid ("[Adjudication]demandsthe habit of curbingany tendencyto reach results agreeableto desireor to embracethe solutionof a problembefore exhaustingits comprehensive analysis."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 768 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 book, TheLegal Process,whichJusticeBreyerstudiedas a law student at HarvardLaw School in the early 1960s.26 To gain a deeper appreciationfor Breyer's self-described"interpretive tradition"or "attitude,"we can put Active Libertyto the side for the time being and go back to the legal process template itself. "[K]nowledge,"HenryHart wrote in 1941, consists, not in doctrine,not in propositionalstatements stored away in the brain;but in the capacity to solve problems as they are actuallypresented in life; the capacityto see all the implications ... of the action to be taken;the capacityto bringto bear in the taking of decisions the maximumof the availableexperience of mankind.2 The law, Hart explained, is instituted to solve problems by availing itself of this practicalknowledge: Law is a response to the problemswhich are intrinsicin the existence of a society.It is an effort to deal with the problems:to deal with them in a way which at the least will preservethe minimum benefits of group living and at best will increase the benefits to the currently attainable maximum. Law, therefore, is dynamic and not static. It is a doing of something,an activitywith a pur26 See WilliamN. Eskridge,Jr.,andPhilipP.Frickey,An Historicaland CriticalIntroduction to The Legal Process,in HenryM. Hart,Jr.,andAlbert M. Sacks,TheLegalProcess:BasicProblems in the MakingandApplicationof Law li, c-cii (Foundation1994) (notingthat adherentsof legal processtheorysoughtto pair this "dynamic"governmentwith "neutral"or "lawlike"principles).JusticeBreyerdoes not mention TheLegal Processin ActiveLiberty.He does,however, mentionWilliamN. Eskridge,Jr.,PhilipP.Frickey,and ElizabethGarrett'sCasesand Materials on Legislation:Statutesand the Creationof Public Policy (West3d ed 2001), a casebook that is heavily influencedby legal process approachesand that discussesextensivelythe nature and history of legal process thinking.See id at 565-67 (describingthe evolution of "the rationalist traditionin Americanlaw").See generallyid at ch 7, ? 2 (presentingcases and secondarysources that address legal process theories of interpretation).This rejectionof grand theorizingand foundationalthinkinghas a certainaffinitywith pragmatism,a majorinfluenceon early twentieth centuryprogressives.JusticeBreyer studiedpragmatismsystematically,both as an (undergraduate)philosophymajorat Stanfordand at the HarvardLaw School.Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 245 (cited in note 1) ("JusticeBreyercame by his pragmatismin the first instance As Breyerinteracts less as a by-productof la vie activethanas a matterof seriousmetaphysics."). in the comingyears with JusticesRoberts and Alito, it will be of interestto see how their own rejectionof grandtheorizingand foundationalthinking,whichseems to be rooted in a commitment to common law legal craftsmanshipand legal professionalism,is differentfrom Justice Breyer's,which is rooted in philosophicalpragmatismand a backgroundin administrativelaw and regulatorypolicy.I returnto this theme,briefly,at the end of this Review.See text accompanyingnotes 218-19. 27 Letter from HenryM. Hart,Jr.,to John H. Williams(Oct 15, 1941),quoted in Eskridge and Frickey,An Historicaland CriticalIntroductionat lxxvi (cited in note 26) (describingHart's commitmentto addressingstatutoryinterpretationthrough"realistic'problems'at a given point in time"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 2006] 769 pose. Reflecting on this purposivequality,we come to see that it infuses the whole of law and all its parts.We come to see that every legal problemis a problemof purpose,of means to an end, and needs to be approachedwith awarenessthat this is so.28 As Hart and Sacksput it in their textbook'schapter,"An Introduction to the Nature and Functionof Law": Law is a doing of something,a purposive activity,a continuous striving to solve the basic problems of social living .... Legal ar- rangements(laws) are provisionsfor the future in aid of this effort. Sane people do not make provisionsfor the futurewhich are purposeless.It can be accepted as a fixed premise,therefore,that every statute and every doctrine of unwrittenlaw developed by the decisional process has some kind of purpose or objective, however difficultit may be on occasion to ascertainit or to agree exactlyhow it should be phrased. Underlyingevery rule and standard,in other words,is at the least a policy and in most cases a principle.This principleor policy is always available to guide judgment in resolving uncertainties about the arrangement'smeaning.The uncertaintiescannot be intelligentlyresolved-indeed, in a just case they cannot be intelligibly resolved--without reference to it. If the policy is in doubt in relevant respects,that doubt must be cleared up. Always the question must be faced:What purpose--what policy or objective or underlyingprinciple--shouldbe attributedto the arrangement in question?The immediateuncertaintyabout the arrangement's meaningmust then be resolved not only so as to avoid irrational inconsistenciesin applicationbut so as to furtherthe purpose so attributed.29 Hart and Sacks add (and JusticeBreyer agrees-prominently -in Active Liberty) that: 28 HenryM. Hart,Jr.,Note on Some Essentialsof a WorkingTheoryof Law, Hart Papers, Box 18,Folder3, quotedin EskridgeandFrickey,An Historicaland CriticalIntroductionat lxxxii (cited in note 26) (notingthat Hart "posited[that]perhapsthe crucialfact about any society is the interdependenceof its members")(internalquotationmarksomitted).See ThomasL. Haskell, TheEmergenceof ProfessionalSocialScience:TheAmericanSocialScienceAssociationand Crisisof Authority15 (Illinois 1977) (describing"a major intellectual the Nineteenth-Century reorientation"at the end of the nineteenthcenturybroughtabout by social scientists'recognition of "the objectivefact of social interdependence").See also MichaelWillrich,Cityof Courts: SocializingJusticein ProgressiveEra Chicago84-85 (Cambridge2003) (describingthe Progressive Era shift from individualrights to communityrights,especially in the realm of criminal responsibility). 29 Hartand Sacks,TheLegalProcessat 148 (citedin note 26). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview 770 [73:759 Not only does every particularlegal arrangementhave its own particularpurpose but that purpose is always a subordinateone in aid of the more general and thus more nearly ultimate purposes of the law.Doubts about the purposesof particularstatutes or decisionaldoctrines,it would seem to follow,must be resolved, if possible,so as to harmonizethem with more general principles and policies.The organizingand rationalizingpower of this idea is inestimable.:o B. Democracyand the Legal Process This purposive approach,which looks towardsgovernmentoptimisticallyas a problemsolvingendeavor,was forged in the wake of the New Deal triumph(but before the WarrenEra rightsrevolution).31For many liberals at this time, the democraticbona fides of the New Deal triumphwere so self-evident that there was no felt need to elaborate any serious democratic theory on which to ground the purposive, problem-focusedapproach:the problemsolversservingin the national government in Washingtonwere experts in the science of advancing the public interestwho acted,few doubted,with only the people's best interestsat heart.3 The judicialactivismof the WarrenEra (the implicationsof which were not foreseen by Hart and Sacks when they wrote their text33), changed all that. The fact that Hart and Sacks "had an insufficiently elaborated theory of democracy,"had hardly been noticed before.34 Once the rights revolution took off, however, it suddenly became a "problem"that legal academicsneeded to solve. In subsequentyears, a successor generation of "new legal process"thinkerssupplemented Hart and Sacks'spurposive approachwith argumentsthat it was the most consistentwith "democracy."35 The majorroute by which they did so was to conceive of "lawmakingas a dialectic and evolutive process.'36 New legal process scholarsemphasized"the importanceof dia30 Id. 31 See Lucas A. Powe, Jr., The WarrenCourtand AmericanPolitics 17 (Belknap 2000) ("[T]heCourt'sprimerole was to facilitatethe policiesordainedby the electedbranches."). 32 See id at 17-18. 33 See EskridgeandFrickey, An HistoricalandCriticalIntroduction atxcviii(citedin note26). 34 Id at cxix-cxx (noting argumentsthat legislativeintent and popularwill did not match up becauseof suppressionof the minorityandmanipulationof the majority). 35 Id at cxxx-cxxxi(reconceivinglegal processtheoryto minimizethe impactof undemocratic statutes,for example, those that reflect rent-seekingby special interests);William N. Eskridge,Jr.,and PhilipP.Frickey,Casesand Materialson Legislation:Statutesand the Creation of PublicPolicy333 (West1st ed 1988)("Thenew legalprocessthinkersjustifyan activerole for judgesand administrators by rethinkingthe conceptof lawmakingin a democraticpolity."). 36 EskridgeandFrickey,Casesand Materialson Legislationat 333 (citedin note 35). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 771 logue or conversation as the means by which innovative lawmaking can be validated in a democraticpolity and by which the rule of law can best be defended against charges of unfairnessor illegitimacy." For these scholars,"[1]awmaking is a continuousprocess of discussion, the enactment and interpretationof statutes punctuated perhaps by but mainly animated by an ongoing dialogue of interested and informed observers.""Judges are only one of many participantsin this process.As such, it is incumbentupon them to work with the other institutionsof governmentas partnersin the ongoing (and, by its nature,experimental)process of solving social problemsand implementing public policy effectively. The judge's role should be modestdeferentialto the legislative and bureaucraticexpertise where appropriate, but assertive in areas in which judges possess unique institutional competence (such as, for example, cases involving the protection of civil rightsand civil liberties).If judges fulfilled this role properly,so the new legal process thinkersheld, judges would also be acting as the helpmeets of democracyeven if they voted in a countermajoritarianway.39 Active Liberty, in classic new legal process fashion, marries a broaderdemocratictheory to an articulationof Hart and Sacks'spurposive and consequentialistapproachto statutory interpretation.In doing so, however, Justice Breyer has decided to rest more prominently than most of the other new legal process scholarson the original purposive approachto statutory constructionas set out by Hart and Sacks themselves."In this book, JusticeBreyer stipulatesthat that or "activeliberty"(see pp 98-99). more generalpurposeis "democracy" Breyer argueshis way to this conclusionthrougha series of steps. The book begins with the affirmationthat "[t]he United States is a nation built upon principlesof liberty"(p 3).41 But he then explains 37 Id at 331 (describingthree commonthemesin the responsesof new legal processscholars to past criticismsof legal processtheory). 38 Id at 333 ("The legitimacyof law derivesnot from its formalsource,but ratherfromits capacityfor enlighteningus and advancingthe moralandeconomicdialecticof our society."). 39 See, for example,Sunstein,One Case at a Time at 4 (cited in note 12) ("[M]inimalist rulingsincreasethe spacefor furtherreflectionand debate at the local,state,andnationallevels, simplybecausethey do not foreclosesubsequentdecisions.").But see AlexanderM. Bickel,The LeastDangerousBranch:The SupremeCourtat the Bar of Politics20-21 (Yale 1986) (elaborating the possibilitythat, if courts' decisions reach too broadly,courts may become "a countermajoritariancheck on the legislativeand the executive [that]ha[s] a tendencyover time seriously to weaken the democraticprocess");JohnHart Ely,Democracyand Distrust:A Theoryof JudicialReview102-03 (Harvard1980) (advocatingthatjudgesinterveneonly when the political by trammelingminorityrights). process"issystemicallymalfunctioning" 40 See text accompanyingnote 30. 41 In his emphasison "liberty"ratherthan "equality"as a baseline,JusticeBreyerdeparts from the approachof the new legal processscholarhe most resembles,Cass Sunstein.See Cass R. Sunstein,The PartialConstitution141 (Harvard1993) (emphasizing,as keys to a functioning This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 772 The University of Chicago Law Review [73:759 that "libertymeans not only freedom from governmentcoercion but also the freedom to participatein the governmentitself"(id). As such, this "publicliberty"has two dimensions.In describingand elaborating upon these dimensions,Breyer returnsto a famous distinctionmade by the nineteenthcenturyFrenchpoliticalphilosopherBenjaminConstant between the "liberty of the ancients"and the "liberty of the moderns"(id).42 For Breyer,Constant'slibertyof the ancientsinvolved"a sharing of a nation's sovereign authority among that nation's citizens,"and "an active and constantparticipationin collective power"(p 4). (Constant'smodel here was the classicalGreek polis.43)Breyer writes:"This sharing of sovereign authority,Constant said, 'enlarged'the citizens' 'minds,ennobled their thoughts,'and 'establishedamong them a kind of intellectualequality which forms the glory and the power of a people"' (id). In Constant'sview, Breyer tells us-and these real virtues notwithstanding- "ancient liberty was incomplete [because it] failed to protect the individualcitizen from the tyrannyof the majority[and it] provided a dismal pretext for those who advocated new 'kinds of tyranny"'(id). (Constant'sthoughtshere were turnedboth to The Terror, which he had witnessed, and in which appeals to classical ideals played a prominentpart,and to the Napoleonic dictatorship,in which a tyranny was cemented through the withdrawalof significant segments of the people from public life.") Because of the threat of tyranny,it was essential to also recognizethe importanceof the "modern liberty,""civil liberty,"or "freedom from government,consist[ing]of the individual'sfreedom to pursue his own interests and desires free state, politicalequalityand equal opportunityto develop individualcapacities);JamesE. FlemtheSubstantiveConstitution, 72 Tex L Rev 211,213-14 (1993)(notingSunstein's ing, Constructing concernswithequality).The decisionto emphasizelibertyratherthanequalityis probablybetter attunedto the moreconservativeCourton whichJusticeBreyeris sitting,and on whichhe seeks to have influence.Thisuse of "liberty"is most likelynot a matterof mere strategyalone.Justice Breyer,afterall, was a law and economicsscholar(albeitin the generallystate-friendlyHarvard incarnationratherthan the free-marketUniversityof Chicagoguise) and had the supportof manyRepublicansfor his appointmentto the Court. 42 This distinctionwas first drawnin the early texts of Madamede Stadl,who exerted a stronginfluenceon Constant.StephenHolmes,BenjaminConstantand the Makingof Modern Liberalism38 (Yale 1984) (notingthat Constantand de Stadlelaboratedthe distinctionin their 1798 work CirconstancesActuelles).It is well known among political theorists,and has been advertedto by law professorsin an arrayof contextsover the years.Breyer'sadoptionof Constant'sdistinctionhere is remarkableless for its originalitythanfor the centralityhe accordsit in advancinga theoryregardingthe appropriateway to interpretlegal texts.See id at 19 (describing Constant'sdistinctionas applicableto the politicalprocessbut not to judicialreview). 43 See id at 19 ("[Popularself-government]was most fully actualizedin the ancientpolis, while [private independence]was the aspirationof all those inhabitingmodern, large-scale commercialsocieties."). 44 See id at 26 (describingboth Robespierreand Napoleonas "politicalhypocri[tes]""who decoratedcrueltywith democraticsymbols"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 773 of impropergovernmentinterference"(p 5). The safeguardingof each form of liberty was necessary,but not sufficient (id). Breyer informs his readers-rightly-that Constant argued for the simultaneousimportanceof both kinds of libertyin the modernworld,and that,to live well politically,we must"learnto combinethe two together"(id). Breyer calls Constant'sliberty of the ancients "activeliberty"(p And 4). Breyer, in turn, identifies active liberty with the "democratic nature"of government(p 5). He fastens the last link in this chain by arguing-dubiously, but not in any way denyingthe importanceof the liberty of the moderns-that the liberty of the ancients,or active liberty,is, and alwayswas,centralto the meaningof the Constitution,and represents its overarching"objective"(p 6). And, again, while never denyingthe significanceof negative liberty,he tells us that his primary focus here will be on active liberty,that is, on "the Constitution'sdemocraticnature"(p 5). This, of course, is not simply a matter of political theory.It has implicationsfor the way JusticeBreyer and, presumably,other judges (who mightbe persuaded)interpretlaw."Mythesis,"Breyerwrites,"is that courts should take greater account of the Constitution'sdemocratic nature when they interpretconstitutionaland statutorytexts" (p 5). A due attentivenessto "the Constitution'sdemocraticnature,"he tells us expressly,counsels a postureof judicialrestraint(pp 5, 17). But the nature of the Constitutiondoes more than that: "It finds in the Constitution'sdemocratic objective not simply restraint on judicial power or an ancient counterpartof more modern protection,but also a source of judicialauthorityand an interpretiveaid to more effective protection of ancient and modern liberty alike"(p 6). "[E]mphasizing this democraticobjective,"he contends,"canbringus closer to achieving the properbalanceto which Constantreferred"(id). C. Historyand the Legal Process The purposiveapproachas originallyforged in the New Deal Era by Hart and Sacks,which looked towards government optimistically as a problemsolvingendeavor,was not only initiallyoffhand about its theory of democracy(the solving of nationalproblemsby the national governmentwas assumedto be self-evidentlydemocratic).It was also initiallyoffhand about both the constitutionaltext itself and the text's roots in America'spolitical and constitutionalhistory (which,in many respects,advocates of the purposiveapproachfelt did not much matter in the modern era)."Hart and Sacks's"purposive"understanding 45 Thisoffhandednessmay have stemmed,in part,fromthe stronginfluenceof the progressive historiesof the FoundingduringHartand Sacks'sintellectuallyformativeyears,in whichthe This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 774 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 of the nature of law,and the judge's role in interpretingit was derived with statutes and the problem of interpretingthem in mind, and not the Constitution.46As New Deal veterans grappledwith the problems and promise of the modern administrativestate they had helped to create, the main constitutionalquestions seemed to be behind them.47 As they saw it, they now lived in a pragmaticage, in which the central questions for governmentwere practicalquestions of "what works?" (they essentiallydrew an equivalencebetween what worked and what was constitutional).In the nearly fourteen hundredpages of The Legal Process, the Constitution-and the Founders-are mentioned rarely,and only in passing.4 That being the case, it is notable that The Legal Process opens with a specific mention of the constitutionalmoment in 1789.But the use Hart and Sacksmake of the Foundingis telling: In 1789 when the American republic was established some 800 million people inhabitedthe globe. Today,there are about 2,500 millions and the numberis steadily increasing.These human beings have a greatvarietyof wants,rangingfrom the commonurge to secure the simple necessities of physicalexistence to the most subtle of desires to achieve some sense of oneness with the universe. The more basic wants are clearly apprehendedand relaFoundingitself (and the originalConstitution)was condemnedas, in many respects,undemocratic.See CharlesA. Beard,An EconomicInterpretation of the Constitutionof the UnitedStates 154 (Macmillan1944) (implyingthat the Constitutionwas supportedby "the ownersof personalty anxiousto find a foil againstthe attacksof levelingdemocracy"). 46 See Eskridgeand Frickey,An Historicaland CriticalIntroductionat cvi-cvii (cited in note 26) (noting that civil rights cases and other constitutionalmaterialsfailed to enter The Legal Processin the 1950s).For a classic articulationof the "purposive"approachto statutory interpretationas expoundedby a legal processscholar,see generallyReed Dickerson,TheInterpretationand Applicationof Statutes87-88 (Little,Brown 1975) (looking to the "ulteriorpurpose"of statutesas "thetouchstoneof statutoryinterpretation"). 47 The key battle,of course,was the New Deal constitutionalstandoffin which Roosevelt threatenedto packan uncooperativeCourtwith new justiceswho favoredNew Deal legislation. See WilliamLeuchtenburg,The SupremeCourt Reborn 132-34 (Oxford 1995) ("[Roosevelt] recommendedthatwhen a federaljudge who had servedat least ten yearswaitedmore thansix monthsafterhis seventiethbirthdayto resignor retire,a Presidentmightadd a new judge to the bench.").See also NLRB v Jones & LaughlinSteel Corp,301 US 1, 37 (1937) (expandingthe federal government'spower under the CommerceClause to includeall activitieswith "sucha close andsubstantialrelationto interstatecommercethattheircontrolis essentialor appropriate to protectthat commercefrom burdensand obstructions");WestCoastHotel Co v Parrish,300 US 379,400 (1937) (upholdingstate regulationof the numberof hourswomen could workoutside of the home). Hart servedin the Roosevelt administrationas AssociateGeneralCounselof the Office of Price Administration(OPA). WilliamN. Eskridge,Jr., and Philip P. Frickey,The Makingof The Legal Process,107 HarvL Rev 2031,2036 (1994) (notingthat"[t]heOPA experience filled Hartwith a new enthusiasmfor teachinglegislation"). 48 So far as I can tell, a constitutionalFrameris mentionedonly once:JamesMadisonis referencedbrieflyin the discussionof federalism,the book's only sustained(albeit brief) foray into a constitutionalsubject.Hartand Sacks,TheLegalProcessat 168 (cited in note 26). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 2006] 775 tively fixed. Others often are only dimly felt, and are subject to change by many complex processes both of external suggestion and of internal reflection.But whatever for the time being each individual'swants may be, human life is an unceasingprocess of fixing upon those on which time and effort are to be expended, and tryingto satisfythem.... The coexistence on the face of the same planet of these everchanging and increasingmillions of people, having these wants and such abilities to satisfy the wants under these conditions of interdependence,are the basic facts of social science,and pose its basic problems.... Among those who have succeeded in survivingfor the time being, whose wants,taken as they are at any given time, and which of them, are to be satisfied,and how? To the extent that presently existing wants are subject to change by external suggestion, which wants are to be encouragedand which discouraged?These are all questions which in some fashion or other must be answered-by events if not by consciouschoice.Law being a pervasive aspect of social science, the questions pose problems which are basic also for lawyers.49 By the WarrenEra, however,when, among liberalsand conservatives alike, cries reached a crescendo that liberal activistjudges were no longer interpretingthe Constitution,either as written or as intended by the Framers,but instead were simply writing into law the judges' own policy preferences,it was no longer politically and intellectually plausible for judges and law professorsto dispense with either the Constitutionor with argumentsfrom history.It was at this time that purposive and consequentialistnew legal process scholars supplementedtheir newly forged democratictheories with a "republican" reading of American history-a reading that first appeared in historicalliteraturein the middle of the 1960s•o-which in its own way emphasizedthe same sort of classicalrepublicanismthat Constanthad in mind when describingwhat he referredto as the liberty of the an49 Id at 1-2. Thought, 50 See,for example,J.G.A.Pocock,CivicHumanismandItsRole inAnglo-American in J.G.A.Pocock,Politics,Language,and Time:Essayson PoliticalThoughtand History80, 101 (Atheneum1971) ("Thereis in fact evidenceof a continuingattemptthroughoutthe eighteenth centuryto explainhow the individualof an urbanand commercialsocietycouldbe a citizen,free, BernardBailyn,TheIdeologicalOriginsof theAmericanRevovirtuous,andaboveall uncorrupt."); states"formed lution281 (Belknap1967)(positingthatat the time of the Revolution"[r]epublican "a new socialbasis for the middlelevel of government").See also Akhil Reed Amar,The Bill of 302 (Yale 1998) (listing"historians[who]have exploredthe Rights:Creationand Reconstruction strongrepublicanstrandsof the Founding"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 776 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 cients. The law school civic republicans,who arrivedon the scene in numbers in the 1980s,argued-as Breyer does in his book-that "the historical evidence supports the view that the republicantraditionis the dominant tradition and that public values should inform legisla"Is it reasonable from a tion (and its implementation)at all levels.""51 historicalperspective,"he asks,"to view the Constitutionas centrally focused upon active liberty,upon the rightsof individualsto participate "I believe so,"he concludes(p 21). in democraticself-government?" The reading of history Justice Breyer advances here is nothing new (though the degree to which the republicanstrainrepresentsthe dominant one in American political thought is debatable52). The real interest in Justice Breyer's historicaloverview lies at the end, where he translatesthis civic republicanreadingof Americanhistoryinto his own patented (and technocratic)legal process idiom. Justice Breyer refers to the active liberty thrust of the Constitutionas its "primary objective,"which is manifestedin three ways (p 33). First,"all citizens share the government'sauthority... in the creation of public policy" (id). Second,"theConstitution'sstructuralcomplexity"was a "respon[se] to certainpracticalneeds,for delegation,for nondestructive(and hopefully sound) public polices,and for protectionof basic individualfreedoms" (id). Third,"the Constitution'sdemocraticimperative"should be understood"as accommodating,even insistingupon, these practical needs" (pp 33-34). "In sum,"he concludes,"ourconstitutionalhistory had been a quest for workable democraticgovernment"(p 34). (This, it is worth noting,is a somewhatidiosyncraticmove, because many of 51 Eskridgeand Frickey,Casesand Materialson Legislationat 331 (cited in note 35) (describingthese scholars'claims as a "powerfulanalyticattackon pluralism"and a rejectionof interestgroupsas the principalgeneratorsof legislation).See, for example,Sunstein,ThePartial Constitutionat 23-24 (cited in note 41) ("[T]heframers'belief in deliberativedemocracydrew from traditionalrepublicanthought.");BruceA. Ackerman,TheStorrsLectures:Discoveringthe Constitution,93 Yale L J 1013,1030-31 (1984) (using The Federalistto argue that the Framers sought"a constitutionaleconomyof [republican]virtue"). 52 See, for example,Michael P. Zuckert,NaturalRightsand the New Republicanismxix (Princeton1994) ("Americawas not 'foundedin the dread of modernity,'as one of the civicrepublicanhistoriansputs it, but foundedin the embraceof modernity."); JoyceAppleby,Liberalismand Republicanismin theHistoricalImagination338 (Harvard1992) ("[B]ypresentingthis mode of politicaldiscourseas encapsulatingAmericanswithina closed ideology,the republican revisionistshave gone beyond their evidence.");Isaac Kramnick,Republicanismand Bourgeois Radicalism:Political Ideology in Late Eighteenth-Century England and America 40 (Cornell 1990) ("Liberalismthere was in late eighteenth-centuryEngland and America alongside the older ideal of republicanism,a progressiveliberalismstill subversiveof the status quo.");John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of AmericanPolitics:Virtue,Self-Interest,and Foundationsof Liberalism20 (Basic 1984) (arguingthat the key thinkersin the Revolutionaryand Constitutionaleras did not employcivicrepublicanismin theirwritings). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer's Mandarin Liberty 777 the republicantheorists themselves saw the Constitutionas, in many respects,a betrayalof, or a retreatfrom,the republicantradition.") II. ACTIVE LIBERTY AS RHETORICAND TOOL To trace the originsof JusticeBreyer's"interpretivetradition,"of his "attitude"in approachinga legal text, of course, is not the same thing as to critiqueit. There are a numberof ways,though,that we can critique Breyer's philosophy.First, we can ask if he uses Constant's understandingof "activeliberty"appropriatelyin justifyinghis stated interpretivestance.Second,we can see how JusticeBreyer'semphasis on purposes and consequencesin the service of what he understands to be active libertyinformshis reasoningand his decisions in concrete, contemporarycases.If we do so, I think that we shall see that this Justice uses "active liberty"and appeals to democracyin a chiefly rhetoricalway,and that, in many respects,this permitshim to obscurethe ways in which his "attitude"is perhaps the least "democratic"of any of the SupremeCourt'scurrentlysittingjustices. A. Active Libertyas Rhetoric JusticeBreyer'sdecisionto invoke BenjaminConstantas a touchstone is understandable,both with respect to JusticeBreyer'sown approach to law and politics and more generally.Both Breyer and Constant endeavorto be clear-eyedabout the attractionsand dangersof a belief in human progress,on the one hand, and conservatism,on the other.Like JusticeBreyer,Constantbelievedthat a sensibleliberalpolitics is best conceivedof, not as a deductionfrom a first-factor a principle, but ratheras a sensiblemeans,given the ambientcontext,of solving pressingpoliticalproblems.54 Breyer'sdecisionto invoke Constant'sunderstandingof the nature and promiseof liberalfreedomin the modem worldis also understandable-and, in many respects,welcome--because, among modern liberals, Constantis clearlypossessed of a rare wisdom.Where others (particularlycontemporaryacademics)have derivedtheir understandingof 53 See GordonS.Wood, TheRadicalismof theAmericanRevolution253-54 (Knopf 1992) (contendingthat the Framersused the Constitutionto grantpoliticalpower to an elite groupof supposedlyvirtuousand"disinterestedgentry");GordonS.Wood,The Creationof theAmerican Republic,1776-1787606 (North Carolina1969) ("[T]heAmericansof 1787 shatteredthe classical Whigworldof 1776."). 54 "Theliberalstate is desirablenot because it mirrorshumannatureor respectseternal humanrights,but becauseit is the politicalarrangementmost adequateto solvingthe problems of European society in its current stage of economic, scientific, and moral development." Holmes, BenjaminConstantat 32 (cited in note 42) ("[Constant]deliberatelysupplantedthe contractmythwitha theoryof socialchange."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 778 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 libertyfrom almostgeometricproofs,restingon a cloud of abstractions that would bring a twinkle to the eyes of Aristophanes,Constant framedhis views as a profoundlyreflectiveparticipantin actualpolitics, as a memberof the FrenchAssembly,and, indeed, (afterhavingpreviously criticizedhim ferociously)as part of a group that helped Napoleon draft France's1815 constitution."He was engaged in public life, moreover,at a time when many of the most profoundpolitical questions,presentedin their deepest form,were on the table,and when the consequencesof varioustheories and choices became readilyapparent because these theories and choices were put swiftly into action in the actual world.56 Constant'sreflectionson politics and libertywere additionally informedby a broad and deep readingof historyand political theory,as well as by a profoundinterestin, and insightinto,humannature and individualpsychology."He was possessed of a well-rounded, deeply humanisticunderstandingof politics. That said, though,it is not at all clear of what real use Constant, and his concepts of the "libertyof the moderns"and the "libertyof the ancients"can be-other than as a rhetoricaljumping off point-to a modern Americanjudge like JusticeBreyer,faced with concrete legal cases aimed at "interpretingour democratic Constitution"(pp 5-6). Unlike Alexis de Tocqueville,Constantnever visitedAmerica and was not a lawyer.And Constantwas not a judge."Much of his writing,including his famous essay on "Ancientand Modern Liberty,"was written as he navigated his way--politically, intellectually,and personally-through the tumult in ideas and political practice that shook France from the late eighteenth century to the early nineteenth century.In this context, Constant took up the deepest questions of government, includingthose involving the relevance of classical democ- 55 See Holmes,BenjaminConstantat 12, 17-19 (cited in note 42) (notingthat "Constant's celebratedlecturecomparingancientand modernliberty"was deliveredafterhis experiencesin the TribunatandNapoleon'sgovernment). 56 For an analysisof the debates of that period, see AurelianCraiutu,Liberalismunder Siege:The PoliticalThoughtof the FrenchDoctrinaires58 (Lexington2003) (describingConstant'seffortsto develop"viablerepresentativeinstitutions"in Francewhile avoidinga "dangerous" returnto the monarchy).See also id at chs 3, 5 (describingFrenchpoliticalphilosophers' effortsto createa viablegovernmentin the wake of the 1789Revolution). 57 Holmes,BenjaminConstantat 13 (cited in note 42) (notingthat Constant'sworkoutside of the realmof the strictlyphilosophical"allow[s]us to penetratedeep to the psychologicalroots of liberalpolitics").Constantwas also a novelist,and a masterdelineatorof humanmotivation and introspection.See, for example,BenjaminConstant,Adolphe37 (Penguin1964) (L.W.Tancock,trans)("Atthat time all I wantedwas to give myselfup to the kind of primitiveand impulsive reactionswhichlift the soul out of the commonrut and make it look upon everydaythings with disdain."). 58 See Holmes,BenjaminConstantat 4 (citedin note 42). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer's Mandarin Liberty 779 racy to the modern world,and the nature and future of freedom itself withinthe modern,pluralist,capitalistnation-state.59 To be sure, Constant was deeply interested in constitutionalism. He was particularlyinterested in the role that a balance of powers played within a constitutionalsystem."Perhaps his ultimate achievement in this context was to arriveat the convictionthat (constitutionally) limited and representativegovernmentthat both protected individual rights (that is, a privatesphere), and encourageda realisticand appropriatelevel of engagementin politics,was the best form of governmentfor the modernworld.61 Whatwas Constantfor?As StephenHolmes has describedit: Constantadvocateda constitutionalsystem that stipulateddirect popular elections, integral renewal and inviolabilityof representatives,two chambers,an executive veto, the right of dissolution, a responsibleexecutive liable to dismissal,an independentjudiciary,trial by jury,a ban on retroactivelaws, absolute freedom of the press, and an institutionalbarrierbetween the army and the police. The legislaturewas to have the right to initiate new laws and repeal old ones; and it was to control the purse strings of government,voting every year on taxes and on support for the armedforces.Equallyimportant,it was to scrutinizeall executive actionssuch as treatieswith foreign governments.62 Perhaps his most significant contributionis his vigorous defense of governmentby elected representatives.' In arriving at these views, Constant looked admiringlyto the handiworkof the American Founders.64He evinced a strong affinity 59 See id at 19-20. 60 See BenjaminConstant,Principlesof PoliticsApplicableto All Governments35 (Liberty Fund 2003) (Etienne Hofmann,ed) (Dennis O'Keeffe,trans) ("The mutualsupervisionof diverse sections of the governmentis useful only in preventingone of them from aggrandizing itself.").In this, though,he emphasizedthe role that the King would play as a neutralpower standingabove all politicalpartiesand groups.See id at 51 ("Whenhereditarymonarchyrested on divine right,the very mysterywhich sanctionedthis theocraticinstitutionwas able to invest the monarchwith superiorenlightenment.").See also id at 151 ("[W]ebelieve ... that the indispensableconditionsfor makingjudicialpower the safeguardof citizensare the same under all forms of government.").It bearsconsideringwhetherJusticeBreyerhas come to see judges as replacingkingsin this role. 61 See Holmes,BenjaminConstantat 2-3 (cited in note 42) (noting that Constant'sphilosophyreflectedhis experiencesduring"theRevolution,the Restoration,and the Empire"). 62 Id at 131 (elaboratingalso the need for checks and balancesbetween branchesof government).The liberalside of Constantis emphasizedin AurelianCraiutu,The Battlefor Legiti28 HistoricalReflections471 (2002). macy:Guizotand Constanton Sovereignty, 63 See Holmes,BenjaminConstantat 132 (citedin note 42). 64 See id at 49. See also GarryWills,ExplainingAmerica:The Federalist265 (Doubleday 1981) ("Wehave been told that Madisonpitted interestagainstinterestin a constructiveprocess This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 780 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 for Scottish Enlightenment thought, including that of David Hume, Adam Smith,and Adam Ferguson--thoughtthat itself had had a profound influence on the American Founders.(Indeed, Constant had spent a formativeyear in Edinburgh.65)The Constitutionhad already settled most of these matters:the Constitution,for example, and the American people, were fully committed to government by elected representatives,an independentjudiciary,separationof powers more generally,and trial by jury,thanks in large part to the influentialwritings of another liberal French thinker,Montesquieu.This being the case, it is not clear what Justice Breyer's appeal to Constant adds.In interpretingour own Constitution,why not cut out the middleman, and go straightto the Foundersthemselves?It is not at all clear that an originalist approach to constitutional interpretation,of the sort advocated by JusticesThomas and Scalia, is any less faithful to the spirit of "active liberty"as delineated by Constant and the Constitution, than is JusticeBreyer'sprogressivelyinflected,"purposive"legal process approach. If we move beyond Constant'sdefense of representativegovernment (in the face of claims of Rousseau,Robespierre,and the appeal to many of a revival of the classicalGreek polis) to his advocacyof a politics for the modern world that sagely combined"the liberty of the ancients"with the "libertyof the moderns,"the same considerations arise.To be sure,there are,and have been, Americanswho believe that citizens should focus on private concerns alone, and not bother themselves with questions of the public good as advancedthroughparticipation in public life. And to be sure,there are, and have been, Americans who believe that the good life can be lived only through sustained, direct, and continuous (to the point of full-time) participation in government.We could doubtless find people who claim that the practice of direct democracyin service of the collective good should always trump claims made on behalf of private interest and private And the strucright.But the AmericanFoundersdid not believe this.6" ture of our governmentdoes not reflect either of those extremes:in its basic outlines, its "framework,"as Justice Breyer likes to describe it (and the justificationsthat were made to defend it) (p 110), it repreof self-correction[,but Madisonreally said] that interestis to be eliminatedfrom the political arena,distilledout of the process."). 65 See Holmes,BenjaminConstantat 183 (cited in note 42). See also GertrudeHimmelfarb, The Roads to Modernity:The British,French,and AmericanEnlightenments94, 200-01 (Knopf 2004) (findingthe influenceof the ScottishEnlightenmenton earlyAmericanpolitical thinkersboth FederalistandAntifederalist). 66 See, for example,Amar,TheBill of Rightsat xii (cited in note 50) ("A close look at the Bill [of Rights]revealsstructuralideas tightlyinterconnectedwith a languageof rights;states' rightsandmajorityrightsalongsideindividualandminorityrights."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 781 sents a sage combination of both.67 It accepts what Constant, in his times,in his country,was forced to argue at length:that liberalismand democracywere not opposites,but rather,ultimately,mutuallysupportive."The American Founders(as Constanthimselfclearly saw) knew this."And, for that reason, we already have a system of government that looks to both ancientand modernlibertyas worthyof protection. B. Active Libertyas Tool Justice Breyer's decision to remindus of all of this philosophical traditionin the first chapter of Active Libertyis all to the good-and entirely uncontroversial.He then, however,purports(in a chapterentitled "Applications")to demonstrate the way in which an attitude mindful of the importanceof Constant's"activeliberty"helps him to think through (if not ultimately decide) hard cases of contemporary constitutionallaw. It is probablynot quite fair to say that Constant's conceptionsof libertyhave nothingto do with JusticeBreyer'sapplications, because the claims of representativegovernmentacting collectively (through legislation) in the face of counterclaimsanchored in private right are common in questions coming before the Supreme Court.70 But Constant was concerned chiefly with questions involving the fundamental framework of constitutionalgovernment-such as should we have an executive,or should we have an elected legislature, or shouldcriminaldefendantsbe tried before a judge alone,or with the assistanceof a citizenjury? Constantwas not concernedwith the sorts of interpretivequestions that Breyer wishes to discuss,such as closely contested questions of the meaning of highly technical provisions of 67 Id ("Individualand minorityrightsdid constitutea motif of the Bill of Rights-but not the sole, or even the dominant,motif."). 68 Holmes,BenjaminConstantat 54,73 (cited in note 42) ("[Constant]drewthe distinction [betweenancientand modernliberty]sharplyin order to emphasizethe tight interdependence of public influenceand privatesecurity.").AurelianCraiutuargues,however (in disagreement with Holmes), that Constant'sthought emphasizesliberalismmore than democracy.Craiutu arguesthat Holmes tends to gloss over the attendanttensions between liberalismand democracy.See AurelianCraiutu,Liberalismunder Siege at 17 (cited in note 56) ("[T]he historyof nineteenth-centuryFrenchliberalisminvitesus to reflecton the uneasyalliancebetweenliberalism anddemocracy."). 69 Holmes,BenjaminConstantat 49 (cited in note 42) (describingConstant'sattractionto the AmericanRevolutionariesbecause they did not requirethat individualssubordinatetheir desiresto the needs of the state). 70 See, for example,MinersvilleSchoolDistrictv Gobitis,310 US 586,591 (1940) ("A grave responsibilityconfrontsthis Courtwheneverin courseof litigationit mustreconcilethe conflictSee also WestVirginiaStateBoardof Educationv Barnette, ing claimsof libertyand authority."). 319 US 624, 646-47 (1943) (Frankfurterdissenting)(notingthat the conflictbetween individual rightsandstate powercreatesverypersonalstakes,even for the justicesdecidingthe case). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 782 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 the McCain-FeingoldAct." As Justice Breyer recognizes,moreover, Constant arguedfor the importance(as Breyer himself does) of both the liberty of the modernsand the liberty of the ancients.As such,appealing to Constant's concepts-other than rhetorically,which is, really, what Justice Breyer does in this book-is of little help to a judge in calibratingwhat particularblend and balance of them is appropriatein arrivingat a decisionin each particularcase. There is little obvious harm done by JusticeBreyer's call for an animatingfocus on purposesand consequencesin the service of active liberty when he applies them to the sorts of legal problems that for many people, specialists aside, will matter least.72Most prominent amongst these are the sorts of complex and seeminglyapoliticalregulatory cases that most interested the original legal process scholars and-not coincidentally-Justice Breyer himself.73The inadequacyand, indeed, the harm-of JusticeBreyer'sfocus on purposesand consequences,by contrast,is thrown into high relief the moment he ventures into the contentious territoryof high profile constitutionallaw that, for many people, will mattermost. 1. Affirmativeaction. Justice Breyer's efforts in this book to situate affirmativeaction withinhis "activeliberty"frameworkare particularlyrevealingand will serve as my main illustration.In the twin decisionscoming out of disputes over the University of Michigan'saffirmativeaction programs, Justice Breyer aligned himself with Justice O'Connor at the Court's ostensibly"moderate"center.74If we look at "activism"as a numerical proposition-did the justice vote to void a governmentallaw or practice, or did he or she "defer"to the govemment?-he was 50 percent 71 See McConnellv FEC, 540 US 93, 233-34 (2003) (addressingthree highly technical provisionsof a statute regulatingelection advertisingin an opinion so long that four justices collaboratedto writepartsof the majority). 72 See Peter M. Haas,Introduction: EpistemicCommunitiesand InternationalPolicy Coordination,46 Intl Org 1,5 (Winter1992) (notingthatepistemicagreementamongpolicyexpertsis "possibleonly in those areasremovedfrom the politicalwhirl").This is not to say that there is not a good deal of nonobviousharmin these cases inherentin a "purposive"approach.These statutes typicallyhave many,often conflicting,purposes.The decision to identify one as paramount and overridingis commonlya highlypoliticalact. Where an overridingpurposecan be identified,it can be at such a high level of abstractionas to be useless in resolvingwith any definitivenessany concretelegal question.R. ShepMelnick,Betweenthe Lines:Interpreting Welfare Rights53-54,84-92,207-16 (Brookings1994). 73 Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 247-48 (cited in note 1). 74 Breyerjoined O'Connor'smajorityopinionand Ginsburg'sconcurringopinionin Grutter v Bollinger,539 US 306, 310 (2003).He also concurredin the Court'sjudgmentin Gratzv Bollinger,539 US 244 (2003),wherehe joined O'Connor'sopinionexceptwhereit joined thatof the Court.See id at 281-82 (2003)(Breyerconcurring). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Mandarin JusticeBreyer's Liberty 2006] 783 activist and 50 percent restrainedin the Michigancases. Breyer and O'Connor both voted to strike down the affirmative action plan adopted by the undergraduateadmissionsoffice, which awardednumericalbonus pointsto applicantsfromspecifiedminorityraces,"but to uphold the affirmativeaction plan adopted by the law school's admissions office,whichtook race into accountas a more nebulous"plusfactor.""Both admissions offices sought to justify their plans on the groundsthat they were aimed at the "compellingstate interest"of creating a racially diverse campus environment.Justices O'Connor and Breyerboth acceptedthis rationale.77 In his discussionapplyingan attitudemindfulof the claimsof active liberty to affirmative action programs,Justice Breyer draws a clear line between JusticeThomas's"color-blind"approachto interpreting the FourteenthAmendment's Equal Protection Clause, as it applied to these admissions schemes, and his own "more narrowly purposive"interpretationof the same constitutionalclause (p 77). As JusticeThomassees it, "the equal protectionprinciplereflects our Nation's understandingthat such classificationsultimately have a destructiveimpact on the individualand our society.""7 Breyer's own apfocused on the achieveand more narrowly proach is less categorical, ment of a sensible result (p 77). When one approachesthe question from such a perspective,he argues,one is freer to draw a practicaldistinction between the classificationsaimed at achieving a socially desirable result, and classificationsaimed at thwartingone (pp 78-79). The decision of governmentsto classifypersonson the basisof race,he tells us,may be undertakenin some cases with "malign"purposes-that is, with the objective of "exclusion"rather than "inclu[sion]"(p 83). This "malign"purposewould be impermissiblebecause it is not aimed at achieving the right result.The decision of governmentsto classify persons on the basis of race in other circumstances,however, has a "benign"purpose (pp 78-79)-that is, it is aimed at the objective of "inclu[sion]"ratherthan "exclusion."This is constitutionallypermissible (if narrowlytailored in service of a compellinggovernmentinterest) because it is aimed at a desirableresult (pp 83-84). Breyer lays out two possible justificationsfor holding racial classificationspermissiblein cases involvingbenign discriminationaimed at achieving the right result (both of which are offered by Supreme 75 Gratz,539 US at 276-79 (invalidatingan affirmativeaction programbecause the setasidesandbonusstructureswere rigid,not flexible). 76 Grutter,539 US at 338 (upholdingan affirmativeaction plan that considereda "broad rangeof qualitiesandexperiences"). 77 See id at 325. 78 Id at 353 (Thomasdissenting). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 784 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 Court justices in earlier rulings on affirmativeaction). He then, in turn, offers his own "activeliberty"justificationfor this and touts his own approach'sspecial virtues.The first justification-a staple of Justice Brennan's (that is traced back here to earlier rulings by federal JudgeJohn MinorWisdom)-would be to hold that, under a principle of equality,the "Constitutionis color consciousto prevent discrimination being perpetuatedand to undo the effects of past discrimination" (pp 79-80).79 The second justification-the groundingof Justice Powell's opinion (speakingfor himself only) in Regentsof the Universityof Californiav Bakke?-is to hold that, under a principleof liberty,"the Constitution grants universities especially broad authority to determine for themselves the compositionof their student bodies" (p 80).0' Justice Breyer argues,however,that a close readingof the University of Michigancases demonstratesthat neither of these considerations-but insteadhis own-were determinative(pp 80-81). The Rehnquist Court's decisions, he argues--quoting Justice O'Connor'sopinion at length-are grounded not primarilyin either liberty or equalityprinciples,but, instead,in "practicalconsiderations" (p 81). In Gratz v Bollinger"and Grutterv Bollinger,"the meaningof the Equal ProtectionClause,as applied,derived chiefly from the fact that: [H]igh rankingretired officers and civilianleaders of the United States military assert that "based on [their] decades of experience," a "highlyqualified,raciallydiverse officer corps ... is essential to the military'sability to fulfill its principalmission to provide nationalsecurity."... Studentbody diversity... better preparesstudentsfor an increasingly diverse workforceand society,and better preparesthem as professionals.... [E]ducation[is] pivotal to sustainingour political and culturalheritage [and plays] a fundamentalrole in maintainingthe fabricof society.... [N]owhere is the importanceof ... openness more acute than in the context of higher education.Effective participationby members of all racialand ethnic groups in the civic life of our Nation is essential if the dream of one Nation, indivisible,is to be real79 Citing UnitedStatesv JeffersonCountyBoard of Education,372 F2d 836, 876 (5th Cir 1966)("Thecriterionis the relevancyof color to a legitimategovernmentalpurpose."). 80so438 US 265 (1978). 81 Id at 271-72 (strikingdown a medicalschool'squota-basedaffirmativeactionplan but allowingraceto be used as a factorin admissions). 82 539 US 244 (2003). 83 539 US 306 (2003). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 785 ized.... [Indeed,]the path to leadership[must]be visiblyopen to talented and qualifiedindividualsof every race and ethnicity.All members of our heterogeneous society must have confidence in the openness and integrity of the educational institutions that provide this training.... [And] all [must]participate(pp 81-82).8 This evidence and these argumentscount for a great deal. But Justice Breyer is apparentlynot content to leave these argumentsto rest on foundationsof practicalityalone. "Whatare these arguments," he asks in turn,"but an appeal [not to liberty,not to equality,but] to principlesof solidarity,to principlesof fraternity?"(p 82).8 But, to be fair, Justice Breyer doesn't rest his constitutionalapproval of racial preference programstoo deeply on the principle of fraternity.86For,immediatelyafter that, he adds "to principlesof active liberty"(p 82). But he doesn't rely too deeply on "activeliberty"either (id). Immediatelyafter that (on the road, we might say,from Paris to Port Huron) he adds, "[or] to maintain a well-functioningparticipatory democracy"(id). The ease with which Breyer moves with equivalence between these terms is troubling.For it suggeststhat the bottom line in these cases for this Justiceis that affirmativeaction is constitutional because a lot of people say it "work[s]"and is "helpful"(p 83). And if they say it is helpful, he seems to imply,there must be some useful principle to justify it. It seems not to matter,really,to Justice 84 Citingid at 330-32. Some readersmay find JusticeBreyer'sappealto the principlesof the FrenchRevolution, ratherthan our own, to be jarring,and possiblyinadvertent.It is far fromunprecedentedin his writings,though.In encouragingan increasingengagementby Americanlawyersandjudges with the case law,legal concepts,and politicaland institutionalarrangementsof other countries, Breyer has cited Wordsworth'spaean to the FrenchRevolution.See StephenBreyer,Keynote Address,Symposiumon Democracy(cited in note 14) ("[W]hatcould be more excitingfor an academic,practitioner,or judge,than the 'global'legal enterprisethat is now upon us? Wordsworth'swords,writtenabout the FrenchRevolution,will, I hope, still ring true:'Bliss was it in that dawnto be alive/Butto be youngwas very heaven.'").And he has expresslyconsideredthe relevanceof the principleof fraternityto contemporaryAmericanjurisprudence. In light of this, his referenceshere to fraternitycould be read as a subtle gesture towardsincreasingtransnational dialogue or deliberationin American law. See Stephen Breyer,Riflexions Relativesau RemarksAddressedto the TroisiemeCongresde l'Associationdes Cours Principede Fraternitg, ConstitutionnellesAyanten Partagel'Usage du Franqais,Ottawa,Canada(June20, 2003),online at http://www.supremecourtus.gov/publicinfo/speeches/sp_06-20-03.html (visitedApr 4, 2006) (stating that judges everywhereface the same types of problemsand have the same types of legal instrumentsto fix them, and that to solve these problems,the differencesin languagedo not matter). 86 I would note here that,in a failed opportunityfor some useful cosmopolitanism,Justice Breyerneglectsto note that Franceitself (untilvery recently)strenuouslyrejectedracialpreference programsas the necessaryimplicationof these very same principles(appliedmore appropriatelyin that case). See ThomasSowell,AffirmativeAction aroundthe World167 (Yale 2004) ("Francehas passed a law [around2001] requiringpoliticalpartiesto have equal numbersof male andfemalecandidates."). 85 This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 786 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 Breyer whether we call that principlefraternity,participatorydemocracy,or active liberty. So how does Justice Breyer know that racial preferences are helpful,or that they work?Here, looking to the "butterflyeffect"logic that Justice Breyer deployed most famously in his dissent in United Statesv Lopez"might prove unexpectedlyilluminating."There,Justice Breyer arrived at the conclusion that the possession of a gun in a school zone had a "significanteffect"on interstatecommercebecause the possession of guns in school zones is upsetting to kids in school, which throws off their concentration,which hurts their grades,which affects theirjob prospects,which lowers their productivity,which hurts the economy's total productivity,which lowers GNP,which depresses commerce,both domesticallyand internationally,which puts Americans at a distinct economic disadvantage,vis-a-vis the Japanese.8 If 87 514 US 549 (1995). 88 See id at 616 (Breyerdissenting)("[I]ndeterminingwhethera local activitywill likely have a significanteffect upon interstatecommerce,a court must consider,not the effect of an individualact (a singleinstanceof gun possession),but ratherthe cumulativeeffect of all similar instances."). 89 See id at 618-25 (claimingthatallowingthe law to stand"wouldnot expandthe scope of [the Commerce]Clause"but"simplywouldapplypre-existinglaw to changingeconomiccircumstances").JusticeBreyer,of course,did not introducethese sorts of argumentsinto American constitutionallaw.Theywere a definingfeatureof New Deal constitutionalthought,andwere,in many respects,the consequenceof the insinuationinto constitutionalreasoningof the social sciences,which emphasizethe significanceof the interconnectednessof a broadarrayof social phenonena.See Willrich,City of Courtsat 86 (cited in note 28) (noting that social scientists' somewhatundertheorizedclaimsof interconnectednessblended"hereditarianand environmentalist explanations"while soundly rejecting"formalistconception[s]");Haskell, Emergenceof ProfessionalSocial Scienceat 252-53 (cited in note 28) (notingthat by the early twentiethcentury,politicians,philosophers,sociologists,and economistshad all employedthemesof interconnectednessin their work). See also Wickardv Filburn,317 US 111, 125 (1942) (drawingwheat productionfor personalconsumptionunderthe CommerceClausebecauseit exertsa "'direct'or 'indirect"'"economiceffect on interstatecommerce");NLRB v Jones& LaughlinSteelCorp,301 US 1, 37 (1937) (expandingthe federal government'spower under the CommerceClause to includeall activitieswith"sucha close and substantialrelationto interstatecommercethat their control is essentialor appropriateto protect that commercefrom burdensand obstructions"). JusticeBreyer,however,in holdingthat,for all intentsand purposes,there are no limitsto interconnectivityarguments,and,hence (so long as a fundamentalrightis not trenchedupon),there are no limitsto the police powerof the nationalcentralstate that drawsupon them,citingostensibly collective purposes,follows an approachthat is common among contemporaryconstitutional liberals.See, for example,Lopez, 514 US at 618-25 (Breyer dissenting).For this reason, Cass SunsteinclassifiesBreyeras being withinthe mainstreamof moderate,minimalistconstitutional thought.CassR. Sunstein,Radicalsin Robes:WhyExtremeRight-WingCourtsAre Wrong for America237, 239 (Basic 2005).On the rise and spreadinginfluenceof the social sciencesin the United States in the late nineteenthand early twentiethcenturies,see Daniel T. Rodgers, Atlantic Crossings97 (Belknap 1998) (describingthe flow of social science knowledge from European-trainedAmerican students to America);Dorothy Ross, The Origins of American Social Science xiii (Cambridge1991) ("[The] liberal values,practicalbent, shallow historical vision, and technocraticconfidence [of social science] are recognizablefeaturesof twentiethcenturyAmerica.").JusticeBreyerplaysthis same game,incidentally,in his applicationconcern- This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 787 patternsof logic like this are acceptablein determiningconstitutionality, then, of course,it should be no trouble at all to argue,in line with the butterflyeffect, that racialpreferenceshave a significanteffect on the achievementof participatorydemocracyand active liberty.Justice O'Connordrawsthese connectionsin Grutterwith no great difficulty." And JusticeBreyer breezilyassents. Justice Breyer was able to defend himself against charges of importing butterflyeffect logic into the marrowof constitutionallaw by arguingthat these relevantfactualfindingsand extendedlogicalchains, however fanciful,were not his, but the legislature's,and, as such, were arrivedat after extensive study and the collection of vast amounts of testimony and empiricalevidence after extensive public hearingsand debates." But this was certainly not the case in the University of Michigancases.There, the empiricalevidence, such as it was, was offered not by the legislature(as had been true in the New Deal cases using similarlogic92),but by the defendant and the "manyknowledgeable groups"that submitted amicus briefs to the Supreme Court (p 83). What did this "evidence" show? Without granting admissions preferenceson the basis of race: Too many individualsof all races would lack experience with a racially diverse educational environment helpful for their later effective participationin today's diverse civil society.Too many individualsof minorityrace would find the doors of higher education closed; those closed doors would shut them out of positions of leadershipin the armed forces, in business,and in government as well; and too many would conclude that the nation and its governmentalprocessesare theirs,not ours (id). "If these are the likely consequences,"Justice Breyer asks earnestly, "as many knowledgeable groups told the Court they werecould our democraticform of governmentthen function as the Framing the constitutionalityof campaignfinanceregulationschallengedon the groundsof the freedom of speech.There,he arguesthat if the regulationswere invalidatedon the groundsof the freedom of speech, the nation'scommitmentto democracycould be called into question as a matterof appearance,underminingconfidencein the politicalsystem,and, hence, undermining our actualdemocracyin fact (that is,appearancewouldbecome reality).See McConnell,540 US at 237 (Breyer).If the regulationsare well-intentionedand helpful,there must be a principleto explainwhy this is the case (let's say "activeliberty").And if it is helpfuland principled,it must be constitutional. 90 See Grutter,539 US at 331 (noting that the Court has "repeatedlyacknowledgedthe overridingimportanceof preparingstudentsfor work and citizenship,describingeducationas pivotalto 'sustainingour politicaland culturalheritage'with a fundamentalrole in maintaining the fabricof society"). 91 See, for example,Jones & LaughlinSteel,301 US at 22-23, 23 n 2 (describingand quotthe ing government'sempiricalfindingson the NationalLaborRelationsAct). 92 See Grutter,539 US at 310-14;Gratz,539 US at 248-51. This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 788 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 ers intended?" (id). Justice Breyer's more criticallyminded readers will note that this empiricallyminded Justice,with a deep and longstandinginterestin rigorouseconomic analysisand complex questions of the relationshipof science and the law,93seems here to have a great deal of difficultyin distinguishingbetween genuine data and multiculturalistcant.The notion that,today,in the absenceof racialpreference schemes, "[t]oo many individuals of minority race would find the doors of higher education closed," and be barred from positions of leadership is, of course, not a fact at all (p 83). It is an assertion, wrappedin a highly politicizednormativeassessment,that no amount of rhetoricalappeal to empiricismcan conceal.How many,after all, is "too many"? JusticeBreyer has been consistentlypraisedfor stickingclosely to facts the and refusingto make unwarrantedgeneralizationsand logical leaps.But here, as he writes about affirmativeaction in Active Liberty,he does not trouble to distinguishthe effects of racialpreferences at a tiny sliver of elite schools from those at the great mass of other colleges and universities,from whichfew,blackor white,are excluded.94 For those who parse things more carefully,however, the most likely effect of racial preferenceschemes in universityadmissionsis to trigger a "pervasiveshiftingeffect,"in which blacks (and other preferred groups receiving preferences in admissions) are simply bumped up one or two or three levels from the schools to which they would normally be admitted.The likely consequenceof this being that those who avail themselves of these preferences-understandably,under the circumstances-are put in a position where they feel (and, in many respects, are) underqualified,and desperatelystrugglingto catch up, to demonstrate that they "deserve"to be there.95 To be sure, there has 93 See Stephen Breyer, The Interdependenceof Science and Law, 82 Judicature24, 27 (1998). 94 StephanThernstromand AbigailThernstrom,Americain Blackand White:One Nation, Indivisible421 (Simonand Schuster1997)("Signup [forcollege] and you can go. And if you do well, even at virtuallyunknownplaces,the doors to jobs and furthereducationwill have been opened.").See also Sowell,AffirmativeAction at 155 (cited in note 86) (notingthat the University of Coloradoat Denver admits68 percentof black applicantsand 82 percentof white applicants,and both applicantgroupshave similartest scoresandsix-yearcollege graduationrates). 95 See Sowell,AffirmativeAction at 145-50 (cited in note 86) ("[P]referentialadmissions, beginningat the top elite institutions,would create a nationwidemismatchingof minoritystudentsand the institutionsthey attended,all up and downthe academicpeckingorder.").See also Ron Suskind,A Hope in the Unseen:An AmericanOdysseyfrom theInnerCityto theIvy League 362-65 (Broadway1998) (narratingthe academicand social tribulationsof a black man who attendedhighschoolin inner-cityWashington,D.C.,and then matriculatedat BrownUniversity). There is a live disputeover whether,in specificempiricalcontexts(such as undergraduates, graduate,and law schools) affirmativeaction actuallyleads minoritystudentsto either fail to graduateor to fail key professionalqualifyingexams.I make no such claim here. Compare,for example, Richard H. Sander,A SystematicAnalysis of AffirmativeAction in AmericanLaw This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 789 been intense debate amongst scholars about whether increasing the numberof blacks at the very highestreachesof the elite universitiesis helpful to their careerprospects.(If a "credentialing"effect exists,and they graduate after having been shoehorned into an especially difficult environmentit is, indeed, likely to be effective,but such an effect would apply to whites as well.9) But there is no evidence presented here that in the absence of these preferences,blacks would be largely shut out of American higher education and potential leadershippositions in society,as JusticeBreyer boldly asserts. The more devastatingthe consequences that "manyknowledgeable groups"allege will flow from the elimination of racial preferences in universityadmissions,the more the advocates of those preferences are forced to acknowledgethat,far from being a "plusfactor" that simply tips the scales, the more the applicant'srace must have been decisive in the admissionsdecision (see pp 76, 83). And, if this is the case, then the distinction that Justice Breyer (and other liberal "radicalsin robes"97)draws between "benign"and "malign"discrimination becomes all the shakier.The logic here is tight enough, and recourse to butterflyeffects are unnecessary.The number of students admittedto a university'sentering class constitutes100 percent of the students admitted to the entering class.When a student is admitted because he is black,anotherstudent is denied admissionbecause he is not. When universities celebrate their accomplishmentof increasing the percentageof students who are black in their incomingclass,they are simultaneouslycelebratingtheir accomplishmentin reducing the percentage of students who are not black in that class. (When they celebrate their success in increasing the percentage of students of Schools,57 StanL Rev 367,481 (2004) ("Theprogramsset blacksup for failurein school,aggravate attritionrates,turn the bar exam into a majorhurdle,disadvantagemost blacksin the job market,and depressthe overallproductionof black lawyers."),with David L. Chambers,et al, The Real Impactof EliminatingAffirmativeAction in AmericanLaw Schools:An Empirical Critiqueof RichardSander'sStudy,57 Stan L Rev 1855,1857 (2005) (arguingthat Sander"has significantlyoverestimatedthe costs of affirmativeaction and failed to demonstratebenefits from ending it"). See also Stephen Cole and Elinor Barber,IncreasingFacultyDiversity:The OccupationalChoicesof High-AchievingMinorityStudents236-37 (Harvard2003) ("[H]aving low levels of academicachievement[even when coupledwith high levels of undergraduateadmission]will keep downthe numberof studentswho decideto becomecollege professors."). 96 See William G. Bowen and Derek Bok, The Shape of the River:Long-TermConsequencesof ConsideringRacein Collegeand UniversityAdmissions276 (Princeton1998) ("[O]ur datashow that the overallrecordof accomplishmentby blackstudentsaftergraduationhas been impressive.").ConsiderThernstromandThernstrom,Americain Blackand Whiteat 422 (cited in note 94) ("[N]othingunderthe sun except hardworkwill bringabout thatparity[in educational andeconomicopportunities]."). 97 ConsiderSunstein,Radicalsin Robes at xiii-xiv (cited in note 89) (portrayingthe subjects of the book's title as rigidand ideologicallyresolute-a categorizationthat could fit Breyer as well as the conservativejudgesthatSunsteindescribes). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 790 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 color, they celebrate their success in reducingthe percentage of students who are white.) It would be interestingto have universitypresidents pledged to the use of racialpreferencesin universityadmissions spend a year publicly advocating their position by speaking frankly about this from the flip side, that is, by celebrating their sustained campaignto reducethe percentageof white (or, in some cases,Asian) students in their incoming class. But, of course, they could never do that. For that would be "malign"discrimination.If they do the exact same thing,for the exact same reason, and talk about it instead as increasingthe percentageof black studentsin their incomingclass,that, however,is "benign"discrimination.In light of that, it is worth taking Justice Breyer's assertions that he looks to "substance,"and not "forms,"and to "real world"consequences,as opposed to verbal labels, in deciding cases-a constant refrain of this "pragmatist"-with more than a grainof salt. It is worth noting that Justice Breyer'sjurisprudencein affirmative action cases is thus,in its fundamentals,not that differentfrom the judicial maximalistJustice Brennan's.What is different about Justice Brennanis that he was an open advocate of a government-sponsored, group-basedredistributionscheme justified by a (general) history of The humble, minimalistJustice Breyer, by contrast- as oppression.9" his split vote in the Michigan cases shows-insists that universities conceal what they are doing by calling it a "plus factor"rather than being so d6class6 as to attach a number to it in public (even if, as a practical matter, the real world consequences between the two approachesare all but indistinguishable).99 Which bringsus to the depths of JusticeBreyer'scommitmentto democracy.The virtue--and drawback--ofJusticeBrennan'sapproach to affirmativeactionis that,becauseit is that of a maximalistwith clear ideological views, it is obvious what the Court is doing.This,in turn, can sparkdemocraticdeliberationof a very unruly,and even combusIt can motivate candidatesand political parties,and turn tible, kind.m" congressionaland presidentialelections.It can even lead presidentsto pledge that, if elected, they will appointthe sort of judges who will reject JusticeBrennan'sapproachand in the processinvite the charge of "radical""fundamentalism"from the academic tribunes of judicial 98 See Bakke,438 US at 335-38 (Brennan,White,Marshall,and Blackmunconcurringin part and dissentingin part) (arguingthat the Constitutionand the Congressthat enacted the 1964 Civil RightsAct intended for institutionsto take positive action to mitigate prior racial discrimination). 99 See Gratz,539 US at 295;Grutter,539 US at 337. 86 (Harvard2001). 100 See ChristopherL. Eisgruber,Constitutional Self-Government This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 791 Justice Breyer's "minimalist"approach--which (like "minimalism."'o' that of most otherjustices of the RehnquistCourt)upholds and works to institutionalizethe "maximalism"of the Warren(and,in many cases, Burger)eras,and (unlikethat of manyof the RehnquistCourt'sconservatives) endeavorsto extend itl•--by contrast,encouragesopacity and duplicityby governmentalinstitutionslike the Universityof Michigan.It abandonsBrennan'sapproachin favor of activelyaccordingnew constitutionalrecognitionto a novel governmentpurpose--"diversity"-which Breyer holds to be compelling,under the guise of humility.Its modus operandi,as illustratedby these cases, is to permit the worldview of an insulated elite to trump a clear constitutionalvalue. This policymakingelite knows exactly what is going on but-crucially, as a matter of law-has no obligation to tell us what that is. This may be consistentwith "activeliberty"as JusticeBreyer sees it. It is not, however, consistentwith basicprinciplesof Americandemocracy. Justice Breyer then reads this newly compellingpurpose-"diversity"-back not only into the Constitutionbut also into the nation's civil rights statutes.For, in addition to the FourteenthAmendment's Equal ProtectionClause,affirmativeactionschemesalso commonlyimplicatethe CivilRightsAct of 1964.10And JusticeBreyersaysa good deal in ActiveLibertyabouthis approachto statutoryinterpretation, which,as a Hart and Sacksprot6ge,is his naturalintellectualhome (pp 86-87).'1 Breyerspends a considerableamountof time in this book thoughtfully explainingthe way in which statutesare best interpretedby the Court, andprovideshelpfuldemonstrationsof the way he has approacheddifficult interpretivequestionsarisingout of the ForeignSovereignImmuni101 See Sunstein,Radicalsin Robes at xiv-xv (cited in note 89) ("It is not at all pleasantto challenge,as wrong,dangerous,radical,and occasionallyhypocritical,the manypeople of honor andgood faithwho have come to embracefundamentalism."). 102 For this reason,if historymatters(as indeed it does), we can see that minimalismand perfectionismare not functionallyseparatecategories.In their substance,they are better viewed as a tag team.See id at 33 (acknowledgingthat the WarrenCourtbehavedas perfectionistsand were succeededby the presentminimalistCourt).On the extension,see Lawrencev Texas,539 US 558, 564-66 (2003) (invalidatinga Texascriminalstatute criminalizinghomosexualsodomy, based on WarrenCourtand BurgerCourtprecedents);Stenbergv Carhart,530 US 914, 920-21 (2000) ("Weshall not revisitthose legal principles[thatgrantthe rightto an abortion].Rather, we applythem to the circumstancesof the case."). 103 Paul Frymerand John D. Skrentny,The Rise of Instrumental AffirmativeAction:Law and the New Significanceof Race in America,36 Conn L Rev 677, 683-84 (2004) (noting that affirmativeactionboth stemsfromand can be a violationof TitleVII). 104 As an administrative law scholar,JusticeBreyer'sfirstinterestwas in questionsof statutory construction.His interestin constitutionalconstructioncame later.It seems that he rather transferredthe "purposive"approachhe followedin the formerunchangedto straightforwardly the latter.See Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 257 (cited in note 1) (notingBreyer'sreticence to engage constitutionalissues withoutwell-developed"empiricalevidence relied on by legislatures"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 792 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 ties Act, the FederalArbitrationAct, and the federalhabeascorpusstatute (pp 88-98). In these discussions,JusticeBreyerexplainsthat "the interpretiveprocess [in statutorycases is] an effort to locate,and remain faithfulto, the humanpurposesembodiedin a statute"(p 95).The pragmatist JusticeBreyer sees statutesas aimed at solvingparticularproblems.And he understandsthe effortto solve thatproblemas the statute's underlyingpurpose.In discerninga statute's purpose,Justice Breyer (unlike,for example,JusticeScalia),is willingto availhimselfof all "logically relevant"materials,includinglegislativehistory(pp 18, 87-88). In approachingthe FederalArbitrationAct, for example,he looks around, and finds"[t]heonly directevidenceavailable-I wouldsay the only evidence available--indicatesthat, at the time of the statute'senactment, membersof Congresssaw a problem... [and t]hey tried to attackthat problemwitha statutetailoredto the problem'sscope"(p 95). Justice Breyer does not bring up the 1964 Civil Rights Act (or other civil rights statutes) in his discussion of racial preference schemes.By refusingto apply the law to bar these schemes,of course, JusticeBreyer is able to sidestep an inquiryinto its "purpose."•0o The "purpose"of that Act was to end the prevailingsystem of racial segregation and subordinationin America.'"'Such a "purpose" (like Ronald Dworkin'sunderstandingof constitutional"concepts"-in contradistinctionfrom the more narrowlydefined "conceptions")is potentially quite broad.' But Congress specifically set out certain means that it had voted were appropriatefor achieving those purposes-namely, the categoricalprohibitionson the forms of racialdiscriminationthat were stipulated in the Civil Right Act's text. Moreover, as both the text itself and the legislativehistoryof the text--that, in other contexts,JusticeBreyer has held to be important-made very clear, Congressprecludedthe use of racialpreferencesto achieve the Civil Rights Act's purpose, to the point of opining that such preferences were not only not envisaged as appropriateinstrumentsfor the achievement of the statute's goals, but amounted to violations of the 105 Justice O'Connor,whose opinion JusticeBreyer joins, mentions,but dismissesout of hand,and withoutdiscussion,the statutoryargumentappealingto Title VII of the Civil Rights Act. See Grutter,539 US at 343. 106 ConsiderThernstromandThernstrom,Americain Blackand Whiteat 138 (cited in note 94) ("Thegreat principleat stake was that every Americanshould be able 'to enjoy the privileges of beingan Americanwithoutregardfor his race or color."'). 107 Ronald Dworkin,Law's Empire71 (Belknap 1986) ("At the [level of concept,]agreement collectsarounddiscreteideas that are uncontroversially at employedin all interpretations; the [level of conception,]the controversylatentin this abstractionis identifiedand takenup."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 793 core provisions of the Act itself, which barred discriminationon account of race.08 The Congress that enacted the Civil Rights Act of 1964 certainly (to borrow Justice Breyer's words) "attack[ed]that problem with a statute tailored to the problem'sscope" (p 95): it banned all forms of race discrimination,includingthose stemmingfrom racialpreferences. To avoid these difficulties,however,JusticeBreyer is driven to, in effect, argue that the enacting Congress did not fully understandthe nature of the problem,or its scope.And for that reason,their prohibition on certain instrumentalmeans of addressingthat problem is no longer bindingon him as a results-oriented,problemsolvingjudge. By the time of the University of Michigan cases, the problem has been newly defined in part as involving the creation of a racially diverse polity,where all feel welcome (pp 78-79). The only way to fulfill this "purpos[e]"or achieve this "objective,"is to give governmentbodies wide latitude to engage in racial discrimination,when it is said to be benign,to achieve the desiredconsequencesin service of the objective (id). The racial preferencesplan adopted by the University of Michigan Law School "works"in this regard.And, because it works,it must be legal (see id). By the lights of some common definitionsof "judicialactivism"-whether a judge votes to uphold or strike down a law (or, as here, a practice)'"--JusticeBreyer's vote in Grutterand other such cases can be read as a textbook case of judicial restraint.By more thoughtful standards,however,it is a textbook case of activistjudging,a case, that is, in which a judge has clearly substitutedhis own understandingof what the statute's purpose was, what its scope should be, and what 108 See Sowell, AffirmativeAction at 126 (cited in note 86) (citing legislative history to demonstratethat legislatorsintended the Civil Rights Act of 1964 to be colorblind);John D. Skrentny,TheMinorityRightsRevolution88 (Belknap2002) ("Congresscreateda weak EEOC to makeTitleVII palatableenoughfor [withenforcementpowersbasedon difference-blindness] passage.");AndrewKull,TheColor-BlindConstitution200 (Harvard1992)("Theinitiativeof the civil rights agencies would have been substantiallyfrustratedhad the courts ... enforced the Civil RightsAct of 1964 as written.");Hugh Davis Graham,The Civil RightsEra:Originsand Developmentof National Policy, 1960-1972 140 (Oxford 1990) (observingthat an AFL-CIO lobbyist "insisted"that the 1964 Civil Rights Act not include quotas);Thomas Sowell, Civil Rights:Rhetoricor Reality?37 (Morrow1984) ("Initially,civil rightsmeant,quite simply,that all individualsshould be treated the same under the law,regardlessof their race,religion,sex or othersuchsocialcategories."). 109 See, for exampleKeck,TheMostActivistSupremeCourtat 1 (cited in note 15) (defining "judicialrestraint"as "a relative unwillingnessto declare constitutionallimitationson government");Gewirtzand Golder,So WhoAre theActivists?,NY Timesat A19 (cited in note 6) ("[A] markedpatternof invalidatingCongressionallawscertainlyseems like one reasonabledefinition of judicialactivism."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 794 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 instrumentsare appropriate(that is, legal) for the achievementof that objective.110 Thisspeaksdirectlyto the democraticbonafides of JusticeBreyer's interpretive"attitude"(p 19).Althoughthereis a fairamountof evidence that the "color-blind"interpretationof the FourteenthAmendment's Equal ProtectionClause held by JusticesScalia and Thomasis not, in fact, a reflection of the clause's originalmeaning (p 77),"'there is no doubt whatsoever that colorblindnesswas part of the original intent, original understanding,and original meaning of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. Public opinion polls ever since, moreover,have continued to Under these circumstances,can Justice support that understanding."112 Breyer plausiblyargue that an interpretationof the 1964 Civil Rights Act rejectinga "colorblind"understandingis more "democratic"than a more faithfulreadingof the Act's meaning(pp 77-83)? Well, sure he can. People do this all the time. But doing so would require that they engage in some elaborate and highly creative democratictheorizing.One could similarlyargue,for example,that abortion rightsare indispensiblein a truly"democratic"polity,for, without them, women cannot be full participantsin the polity's public life.113 Craftingsuch theories is the stock and trade of our more venturesome political philosophers.It is not-and should not be-the stock and trade of Article III judges. Justice Breyer's discussion of affirmativeaction also provides a useful perspectiveon the ostensible narrownessof his rulings.114A key part of JusticeBreyer'sjudicial toolkit in many cases is the emphasis 110For a critiqueof this kind of willful"purposivism," see Eskridge,DynamicStatutoryInThe terpretationat 25-34 (cited in note 72). See also R. Shep Melnick,StatutoryReconstruction: 84 GeorgetownL J 91,97 (1995). Politicsof Eskridge'sInterpretation, 111 See, for example,Kull,The Color-BlindConstitution at 5 (cited in note 108) ("[T]heidea of color blindnessstandsin radicalcontradistinctionto a constitutionalorthodoxythat at every stage of our historyhas permittedthe governmentto classifyby race so long as-by contemporarystandards-it classifiedreasonably."). 112 See id at 1 ("Themoraland politicalattractivenessof a rule of nondiscrimination made it for approximately125 years the ultimatelegal objectiveof the Americancivil rightsmovement.").On publicopinionregardingthese matters,see, for example,Melnick,84 GeorgetownL J at 108 (cited in note 110). 113 See PlannedParenthoodof SoutheasternPennsylvaniav Casey,505 US 833, 856 (1992) ("The abilityof women to participateequallyin the economicand social life of the Nation has been facilitatedby theirabilityto controltheirreproductivelives."). 114 See Sunstein,One Case at a Timeat xiv (cited in note 12) ("[C]ertainminimaliststeps promoteratherthan underminedemocraticprocessesand catalyzeratherthanpreemptdemocraticdeliberation.").See also Sunstein,Radicalsin Robesat 27 (cited in note 89) ("[M]inimalists do not want to take sides in large-scalesocialcontroversies."). Thereare manyaffinitiesbetween Breyer'sthoughtand Sunstein'sin a whole arrayof areas,includingtheir interestin risk assessment, democratictheory,and minimalism.See id at 237 (approvingof Breyer's deference to legislativeexpertisein areasof regulationsuchas gun control). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer's Mandarin Liberty 795 he places on the fit between the asserted government purpose that implicates a constitutional right, and the least restrictive means of achieving that purpose (pp 97-98). But Breyer never actually insists upon a meaningful least restrictivemeans test in affirmativeaction cases.Instead,he simplyredefines the scope of the purpose to expand the scope of the permissiblemeans. This is a failing, incidentally,that is not shared by Justices Clarence Thomas and Antonin Scalia, who insist in affirmative action cases on a close fit between ends and means (see p 77). The Court's "fundamentalist"conservatives,for instance,argue that racial preference schemes (which Breyer,like other liberals,concedes trench on a fundamentalright), are permissibleonly when they are narrowlytailored to the objective of making up for past discrimination."•For them, the paradigmaticcase holding such preferences constitutional would involve remedial racial preference plans adopted by particular institutionswith a demonstrablehistory of impermissible,intentional discrimination."6These ostensibly formalistjudges,who insist, so it is said, on broad,sweeping rules,would not accept the grantingof racial preferences to Aleuts and Pacific Islandersby an institutionwith no history of racialdiscriminationat all, or a historyof racialdiscrimination that targeted only blacks."'These are highly relevant distinctions. JusticeBreyer,however,does not drawthem. This is not simplythe case when we compareJusticeBreyer'sapproach to that of anti-affirmativeaction conservatives.The same is true when we comparehim to liberalswith a penchantfor issuingrulings groundedin sweeping articulationsof principle,like JusticeBrennan. As Justice Breyer notes in Active Liberty,Justice Brennan repeatedly justified the constitutionalityof racial preference plans on the socially transformativegrounds that they are legitimate,societywide responsesto the legacy of slavery(pp 79-80)."'To be sure,Justice Brennan was never wholly consistent about this-he upheld racial preference schemes as a matter of course no matter what (minority) 115 But see p 79 (approvingGrutterbecause the law school's affirmativeaction plan was "narrowlytailored"). 116 See City of Richmondv J.A. Croson Co, 488 US 469, 520 (1989) (Scalia concurring) ("The benign purpose of compensatingfor social disadvantages,whether they have been acquiredby reasonof priordiscriminationor otherwise,can no more be pursuedby the illegitimate means of racial discriminationthan can other assertedlybenign purposeswe have repeatedly rejected."). 117 See, for example,id at 498-99 ("[A] generalizedassertionthat there has been past discriminationin an entire industryprovidesno guidancefor a legislativebody to determinethe precisescope of the injuryit seeks to remedy."). 118 Citing Wygantv JacksonBoard of Education,476 US 267, 278 n 5 (1986) (criticizing Marshall'sdissentingopinionthat groundsaffirmativeactionprogramsin an amorphous"legitimate factualpredicate"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 796 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 racial group (or majoritysex) was involved,without botheringto distinguish the members of those groups from those who were the deBut Brennan'sformulationwas at least, in thescendants of slaves.119 took it seriously,it invited some ory,potentiallylimiting:to those who 120 form of least restrictivemeans test. Justice Breyer, however, makes a least restrictive means test pointless in affirmativeaction cases through the sleight of hand of holding a view that was once held by a single SupremeCourtjustice in Bakke (and a view that was foisted upon him chiefly by an appeal to the authorityof the Harvardadmissionsoffice), that is, as a matter of bindingconstitutionallaw,"diversity"is a "compellingstate interest.121 For if "diversity"is now the interest (or, to adopt Justice'sBreyer's preferred nomenclature,the "purpose"or "objective"),a sweeping range of racial groups is now covered automaticallyby the terms of the formulaitself.This was not the case under the approachesof Jus- ticesScalia,Thomas- or Brennan.122 119 See Metro Broadcastingv FCC,497 US 547,593 (1990) (Brennan)(upholding"minority ownershippolicies [that]are aimed directlyat the barriersthat minoritiesface in enteringthe broadcastindustry");UnitedSteelworkers ofAmericav Weber,443 US 193,197 (1989)(Brennan) (holdingthat Congress"left employersand unionsin the privatesector free to take such raceconscious steps to eliminatemanifestracial imbalancesin traditionallysegregatedjob categories").See also Croson,588 US at 539 (Marshalldissenting)(arguingthat a municipality'sfinding that it discriminatedin the past-making affirmativeaction programsremedial-should be acceptedby the Court).On the tendencyof racialpreferenceplansaroundthe worldtargetedat particulargroupsto expand,as a matterof politicaland institutionaldynamics,almostineluctably to othergroups,see Sowell,AffirmativeAction at 10-11 (in Indiaand the United States),121 (in the United States),132-38 (generally)(cited in note 86) ("Thespreadof benefitsfromgroup to group not only dilutes those benefits ... it can also make the initial beneficiariesworse off afterthe termsof the competitionare altered."). 120 MetroBroadcasting,497 US at 594 (Brennan)("The [FCC's]choice of minorityownership policies thus addressedthe very factorsit had isolated as being responsiblefor minority in the broadcastindustry."). underrepresentation 121 See ThomasM. Keck,FromBakketo Grutter:TheRiseof Rights-BasedConservatism, in Ronald Kahn and Ken I. Kersch,eds, The SupremeCourtand AmericanPoliticalDevelopment (forthcoming2006).See also Bakke,438 US at 311-12 (plurality)(stating,in a sectionjoined by no other justice,that "the attainmentof a diversestudentbody ... is clearlya constitutionally permissiblegoal"). 122 Indeed,if we add to these quietshiftsof categoriesthe resolutelyahistoricalcharacterof Cass Sunstein'sjudicial minimalism(it, for example, defends the continued viability of past maximalistholdings,such as those of the WarrenCourt,on the groundsof contemporaryminimalism;it is also quite easy, on the other side of the political spectrum,to imagine Clarence Thomasas an earlynineteenthcenturyminimalist;Sunstein'smimimalismis reallynothingmore than a brief againsthistoricaltransitions),we can see how the idea of minimalismworks as a clever shell game aimed at institutionalizingthe agenda of mid-twentiethcenturyAmerican constitutionalliberalism.But see Sunstein, The Partial Constitutionat 68 (cited in note 41) ("Muchof modernconstitutionallaw is basedon statusquo neutrality,and indeedon the understandingsof the pre-New Deal period."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 797 A better name for JusticeBreyer'sapproachin these cases would be the "leasttransparentmeans"test.12'Namely,he permitsthe state to redefine the purposeof its conductin a way that has the broadestpossible effect, deems that purposenewly "compelling,"and then, in turn, insists that the means the state uses to achieve that purpose be veiled from public view.This is not minimalist.It is not transparent.It is not democratic.And (as I see it) it is not constitutionaleither. 2. Privacy. Formore than a generationnow,the most heated controversyin all of constitutionallaw has been about whetherthe Constitutionguarantees a "right[to] privacy."124Although its antecedentsare said to trace back to a seminal 1890law review articleby SamuelWarrenand Louis Brandeis,12 the Court counted the "rightto privacy"as a fundamental constitutionalright only in the mid 1960s in a case striking down a Connecticutlaw banningthe use of birthcontrol by marriedcouples.126 The right was quicklyexpandedto apply,first,to the use of birth control by unmarriedcouples,and subsequently,to a woman'sdecision to have an abortion.127These decisions ignited controversy on a broad arrayof fronts.Politically,the Court'sdecision to declare abortion to be a national right served as a catalyst for the Right to Life movement. That movement, in turn, played a major role in realigningthe party loyalties of millions of Americans,with, over time, the Democrats becomingRoe v Wade's128chief champions,and the Republicansits most ardent critics.129Many have alleged that the Court's decision in 123 For a comparativeperspective,see Sowell,Affirmative Action at 50-51 (cited in note 86) ("Wherecourts or officials have balked at various double standards,those double standards have often gone underground,ratherthan going away.Objectivestandardshave been offset by an increase in non-objectivestandards,used clearly as counterweightsto produce the same grouprepresentationresultsproducedby explicitdoublestandards."). 124 See, for example,Roe v Wade,410 US 113 (1973) (findinga "rightof privacy... founded in the FourteenthAmendment'sconceptof personallibertyandrestrictionsupon state action"). 125 See SamuelD. Warrenand Louis D. Brandeis,The RightTo Privacy,4 Harv L Rev 193 (1890). But see Ken I. Kersch,ConstructingCivil Liberties57 (Cambridge2004) ("Warrenand Brandeiscertainlywere strainingtowarda sortof privacyin penningtheirfamousarticle,but the civil libertarianimplicationsof thatsortof privacywere dubiousat best."). 126 See Griswoldv Connecticut,381 US 479,485-86 (1965) (holdingthat doctorsdispensing birthcontrolfall withina constitutionallyprotected"zoneof privacy"). 127 See Eisenstadtv Baird,405 US 438,443 (1972) (abrogatinga statutebanningthe distribution of birth control by nondoctorson equal protectiongrounds);Roe, 410 US at 152-53 ("Thisrightof privacy... is broadenough to encompassa woman'sdecisionwhetheror not to terminateher pregnancy."). 128 410 US 113 (1973). 129 See Greg D. Adams,Abortion:Evidenceof Issue Evolution,41 Am J Pol Sci 718, 727, 733-35 (1997). See also Ruth Bader Ginsburg,Some Thoughtson Autonomyand Equalityin Relationto Roe v.Wade,63 NC L Rev 375,381 (1984-85). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 798 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 Roe-in conjunctionwith issues of crime,race,the campusrevolts,and the often anti-American,anti-VietnamWar movement-precipitated the movement of large swathes of the workingclasses out of the DemocraticPartyand into the armsof the Republicans.1o The Court'sidentificationof a "rightto privacy"also stirredup a hornet's nest among constitutionaltheorists.To liberal and conservative theoristsalike,the newly declaredprivacyrightlooked very much like the sort of nontextual"substantivedue process"rightsthat,it was thought,had been largelydiscreditedafter the Lochnerera"'-a maniantidemofestation of judicialpower run amok-and paradigmatically As their divergentviews on Roe came to split the country'stwo cratic.'32 political parties, appointmentsto the Supreme Court itself came to turn, in significantpart,on the nominee's position on whether a constitutional right to privacy existed. When one of President Reagan's nominees to the Court,Robert Bork, franklyrejected the notion that the Constitutioncontained any "rightto privacy"(Bork had made it clear that he saw the right,and the ruling,as a new form of Lochnerism),"'it set off a political firestorm,and Bork's appointmentwas re- 130 For a contemporaneousidentificationof this,see Peter Skerry,The Class Conflictover Abortion,Pub Int 69,70 (Summer1978) ("Abortionis part of a largerculturalconflictbetween certainstrataof the upper-middleclass ... and the massof Americanswho comprisethe working and lower-middleclasses.").See also ThomasFrank,What'sthe MatterwithKansas?:How ConservativesWontheHeartof America199 (Metropolitan2004) ("[Roe]cementedforevera stereotype of liberalismas a doctrineof a tiny clique of experts,an unholycombinationof doctorsand lawyers,of bureaucratsand professionals,securingtheir 'reforms'by judicialcommandrather than by democraticconsensus.").The claim that Roe split the workingclass from the uppermiddle class, and drove the former into the RepublicanParty,is now becoming subjectedto increasingempiricaldispute,however.See, for example,LarryM. Bartels,What'sthe Matterwith What's the Matterwith Kansas?,Presentedat the Annual Meeting of the AmericanPolitical ScienceAssociation30 (Sept 1-4, 2005),onlineat http://www.princeton.edu/%7ebartels/kansas.pdf (visitedApr 4, 2006) ("[T]heresult [of the politicalshift motivatedby Roe] is not (certainlynot yet) the new 'dominantpolitical coalition' conjured up by Frank and other liberal handwringers."). 131 See Lochnerv New York,198 US 45 (1905) (declaringa state maximum-hours statute unconstitutionalunderthe FourteenthAmendment). 132 See JohnHart Ely, TheWagesof CryingWolf A Commenton Roe v.Wade,82 Yale L J 920,920 (1973);Louis B. Boudin,1 Governmentby Judiciaryvi (WilliamGodwin1932) (writing that "[t]he actual practiceof the courts is to declare any law unconstitutionalof which they WilliamG. Ross,A MutedFury:Populists,Progressives,and Labor Unions stronglydisapprove"); Confrontthe Courts,1890-193720 (Princeton1994) ("Whiledecisionssuch as Lochnerv. New Yorkin 1905 created only limited and temporarysetbacksfor advocatesof reformlegislation, they became symbolsof judicialintransigenceand providedlightningrods for progressivecriticismof the courts.").In ActiveLiberty,JusticeBreyerhimselfwarnsof the lessonshe has learned from a studyof the willfulactivistjudgingof the Lochnerera. See p 10 (describingthe Lochner Court as having "overlyemphasizedthe Constitution'sprotectionof private property"at the expenseof "thebasicobjectivesof the CivilWaramendments"). 133 See, for example,Robert H. Bork, The TemptingofAmerica:The PoliticalSeductionof the Law 290-91 (Free 1990). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 799 jected by the Senate.134No nominee to the Court since Bork has ever been so frank.Today,the SupremeCourt appointmentprocess is, to a large extent, centered on the question of whether the judge believes the Constitution contains a right to privacy,and whether the judge believes that right applies to a woman's decision to terminate her 135 pregnancy. Justice Breyer's progenitors,Hart and Sacks, never mentioned the most importantand politicallyconBrown v Board of Education,"6 tentious case of their time, in The Legal Process, though both men were liberals who supportedthe decision."'And, in his own contemporaryreiterationof their purposive approachto legal interpretation, Justice Breyer, true to the spirit of the original textbook itself, never once mentions Roe. This omission is all the more strikingbecause Justice Breyer has specificallyincluded an extended discussionin his applications section on "privacy."He begins that portion of the book, however, by announcingto his readers that "[b]y privacy,I mean a person'spower to controlwhat others can come to know about him or her" (p 66). He then reduces this definitionto questions raised by the "uncertaintybrought about by rapid changes in technology" (id). "[M]ostof our privacy-relatedlegal challenges,"he writes,"lie at the intersectionof a legal circumstanceand a technologicalcircumstance" (p 67)."138 Needless to say,as a regulatoryscholarwith a longstandinginterest in the relationshipbetween science,technology,and the law,this is the sort of territoryon which Justice Breyer feels most at home. His examples here involve the collection of data by businesses to create detailed customerprofiles,the privacyof medical records,and the interception of cell-phone conversations(pp 69-70). Today,the critical questionsconcerningprivacy,he tells us, are the following: 134 MortonJ. Horwitz,The Meaningof the Bork Nominationin AmericanConstitutional History,50 U Pitt L Rev 655, 656 (1989) (citingBork's"positivistattackon modernrightstheory"as the factorthat"eventuallyled to his defeat"). 135 See Green,27 Natl L J at 23 (citedin note 16) (listingabortionfirstamongcriticalissues on whichJohnRobertswas to be evaluatedduringhis confirmationhearings). 136 347 US 483 (1954).See Powe, TheWarrenCourtat 50-51 (cited in note 31) (describing Brownas creatinga revolutionin doctrineand a crisisin implementation). 137 Eskridgeand Frickey,An Historicaland CriticalIntroductionat cvii (cited in note 26) ("The co-authors'neglect of issues involvingracialjustice not only deprivedtheir materialsof potentiallyfascinatingproblemsbut madethe processof updatingincreasinglyintractable."). 138 It is, of course,possiblethatBreyerdoes not see abortionas a privacyissue,but ratheras an issue of personalautonomy(liberty) or equalitythat cannot be explainedfully on privacy grounds.Nonetheless,he has upheldthe righton privacygroundsas a matterof precedent.See Stenbergv Carhart,530 US 914,920 (2000) (Breyer)("Weshall not revisitthose legal principles [set out in Roe].Rather,we applythem to the circumstancesof this case."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 800 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 Should the law require programmingvideo cameras on public streets to turn off at certain times? When? Should the law require softwarethat instructscomputersto delete certainkinds of information? Which? Should the law require encrypted cell phones? Should the law impose upon certain Web sites a requirementthat they permitusers with certainprivacypreferences to negotiate access-relatedprivacyconditions?How? When will the softwarebe available(p 70)? These are all very importantmatters,and are likely to become even more importantin the future."9But they are distinctivein being very difficult to discuss other than on fine-tuned empirical grounds (pp 66-67).140They are essentiallyregulatoryquestions. Interestingly,it is this cascade of highly technicalregulatoryquestions that spursJusticeBreyer to one of his most spiritedarticulations of his understandingof the role of the Courtin a democracy."It is difficult even to begin to understandthe legal, technological,and valuebalancingcomplexityinvolved in tryingto resolve the legal aspects of the personalprivacyproblem,"he writes (p 70): I cannot offer solutions. But I can suggest how twenty-firstcenturyAmericansgo about findingsolutions.... Ideally,in America,the lawmakingprocessdoes not involve legislators,administrators,or judges imposinglaw from above.Rather, it involves changes that bubble up from below. Serious complex legal change is often made in the context of a nationalconversation involving, among others, scientists,engineers, businessmen and women, the media, along with legislators,judges, and many ordinarycitizens whose lives the new technologywill affect.That conversationtakes place throughmeetings,symposia,and discussions, throughjournal articlesand media reports,throughadministrative and legislative hearings,and through court cases. Lawyers participatein this discussion,translatingspecialized knowl139 See, for example,Jeffrey Rosen, The UnwantedGaze: The Destructionof Privacy in America7 (RandomHouse 2000) (describinghow advancesin technologymake people's personal lives less secure from intrusions);JeffreyRosen, TotalInformationAwareness,NY Times El16-17 (Dec 15,2002) (describinga "sweeping"Departmentof Defense effort to "monitorthe activityof Americans");JeffreyRosen, SiliconValley'sSpy Game,NY TimesF46 (Apr 14,2002) (describinghow the CIA investedmillionsin dot-comstartupsin order to develop new spying technologies). 140 See JeffreyRosen, Robertsv. The Future,NY Times sec 6 at 24 (Aug 28, 2005) (noting the FourthAmendmentproblemsthat new surveillancetechnologymay generate).Although Breyer mentions the FourthAmendmentin passing on the chapter'slast full page, the lion's share of the discussionproceedssolely underthe (nontextual)guise of addressing"theprivacyrelatedlegal problem"(pp 66,73). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 801 edge into ordinary English, defining issues, often creating consensus. Typically administratorsand legislators make decisions only after the conversationis well underway.Courts participate later in the process, determining whether, say, the legal result reached through this "bubblingup" is consistent with basic constitutionalnorms (pp 70-71). The way this happens, Justice Breyer opines-in a remarkable characterizationof a process that is akin to a publicpolicy seminar--is "best described as a form of participatorydemocracy"(p 70). "This conversation,"he continues,"is the 'tumult,'the 'clamor ... raised on all sides' that,Tocquevillesaid,'you find yourselfin the midst of when 'you descend ... on the soil of America.'It is the democraticprocessin action"(p 71). Justice Breyer's argumenthere is that, in a changing regulatoryenvironmentcharacterizedby complex questions of technological change,judges should be relativelydeferentialto "scientists, engineers"and others who are in the process of workingout a sensible regulatoryregime (pp 70-71).141 In this context, it is best to rule narrowly in these cases, "focus[ing]upon the particularcircumstances present in the case"(p 72). He explains: The narrownessof the holding itself serves a constitutionalpurpose. The democratic"conversation"about privacyis ongoing.In those circumstances,a Court decision that mentions its concerns without creating a binding rule could lead Congress to rewrite eavesdroppingstatutes,tailoringthem to take account of current technological facts, such as the widespread availabilityof scanners and the possibility of protectingconversationsthrough encryption.A broader constitutionalrule might itself limit legislative options in ways now unforeseeable(p 72). Whatever the merits of this approachin this type of case--and they are considerable-to identify this managed,elite-inflectedopenness with the more unrulyforms of democracyassociatedwith democform, and that Tocquevillewas describingin racy in its "participatory" his accountof JacksonianAmerica,is quite an audaciousmove.142 In passages like this,JusticeBreyer betrayshis deep-indeed, his deepest--intellectual roots in pre-New Deal, early twentieth century progressivism,an outlook with an animatingfaith in government by Deexpert, acting as stand-insfor the (uninformed)people at large.143 141 Note that"manyordinarycitizens"come last in Breyer'slist (p 71). 142 See Amar, The Bill of Rights at 88 (cited in note 50) (noting that Tocquevillefound Americaninstitutions,suchas the jurysystem,to be "fundamentally populistand majoritarian"). 143 See Eldon J.Eisenach,TheLost Promiseof Progressivism46 (Kansas1994) (describing the authorityof the Progressivesas resting on "the languageof social science, social control, This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 802 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 spite his appeals to "participatorydemocracy"(p 70), anyone with a passing familiaritywith the history of democraticpolitics in America will see much more the "attitude"of ClarkKerr than Tom Hayden in the "democratic"processas limnedby JusticeBreyer.'" All of this discussion about the challenges to privacy in a constantly changing technological environment,of course, usefully distracts the reader from the question of the "rightto privacy"as found by the Court in Roe. This is a good thing, because if Justice Breyer were to actuallytake that up in his book, where "purposiveness"and "activeliberty"are the essentialtouchstones,he would be forced to tie the Court'srulingin Roe to the "purpose"of the Due Process Clause of the FourteenthAmendment,and to the cause of "participatorydemocracy"(see p 18). In the butterfly-effectworld of contemporary constitutionalliberalism(as noted in the discussionof JusticeBreyer's take on racialpreferencesabove), that would be far from impossible.'45 But it would force Justice Breyer to engage nakedly in the sort of highly creative democratictheorizingthat would be much more difficult for him to conceal than it was for him in the affirmativeaction [and] systemsof knowledge");Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 248 (cited in note 1) (noting Breyer's"affinitywith rationalist,scientific,antiformalistsystems-regarding progressivismof the early twentieth century").See also Karl N. Llewellyn, The Constitutionas an Institution,34 ColumL Rev 1, 22 (1934) (arguingthat constitutional"amendmentoccurstypicallyby actionof the relevant[administrative] specialistsalone")(emphasisomitted). 144 See ThePortHuronStatement,in JamesMiller,"DemocracyIs in theStreets":FromPort Huronto the Siegeof Chicago329,336 (Simonand Schuster1987) (criticizingthose who see the "nationaldoldrumsas a sign of healthyapprovalof the establishedorder,"and who "thinkthe nationalquietudeis a necessaryconsequenceof the need for elites to resolvecomplexand specializedproblemsof modernindustrialsociety").See also Miller,"DemocracyIs in the Streets"at 16 (findingthe cruxof earlyNew Left politicsin the PortHuronStatement'sDeweyanvision of participatorydemocracy).ClarkKerr,the Presidentof the Universityof Californiasystemfrom 1958to 1967,was a liberallaboreconomistand exemplarof the postwar,managerialand technocratic"newadministrativeliberalism"thatwas targetedin The PortHuronStatement.Jeff Lustig wrote: For despiteits claimsof opennessand tolerance[it was liberal,andnot conservative],it was, and remains,ill equippedfor real argumentand debate.It is not set up for such things.It requiresstandardizedproceduresand coded phrasesfor its operation,and regardsthe acceptanceof such proceduresand newspeakas the preconditionfor its functioning,not the outcomeof debate. Jeff Lustig,The Mixed Legacy of ClarkKerr:A PersonalView,90 Academe 51, 52 (July-Aug 2004).Accordingto Lustig,Kerrwas "the chief prophetand ornament"of postwarmanagerialism.As Kerrcame to see, his approachworkedbetter in the consensusfifties than in the subsequent period of fundamentaldisagreement.See id at 51 (notingKerr's"late recognitionof the growingcrisis"of the free speechmovementat Berkeley). 145 See, for example,Casey,505 US at 844-46 (invalidatinga statuterestrictingabortionby expansivelyreadingRoe); Ruth Bader Ginsburg,Speakingin a JudicialVoice,67 NYU L Rev 1185,1198-99(1992) (arguingthat"[d]octrinallimbstoo swiftlyshaped... may prove unstable" and criticizingRoe as one such"limb");Ginsburg,63 NC L Rev at 385 (cited in note 129) ("Roe, I believe, would have been more acceptableas a judicialdecision if it had not gone beyond a rulingon the extremestatutebeforethe Court."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 803 cases.Here, he simplyputs the purposeto the side,helps himselfto the maximalistactivismof the late 1960s and early 1970s,in the form of stare decisis, and decides that (in his "Applications"section on privacy) it is more prudent to turn to something completely different (pp 73-74).46 III. THE LIMITSOF PURPOSE In their earlierincarnations,"purposive"legal process approaches to interpretationof the sort JusticeBreyer seeks to reintroducein Active Libertyhave already been extensively critiqued.In commenting on Hart and Sacks,Eskridgeand Frickeyhave summarizedthe virtues and drawbacksof the purposivelegal posture: The strengthsof the legal process vision were its insistence that law is accountableto reason and not just fiat, its claim that institutional architectureand procedureare both criticalto law's operation and can be analyzed systematically,and its consideration of legal doctrinein light of law's purposesand the polity's underlying principles.Its main weaknesses were its polarized categorizations (e.g., substance/procedure),its undue optimismabout the competence and public-spiritednessof state institutions,and its failure to recognize the ideological and non-neutralnature of its own positions.'47 Indeed, the pretense by practitionersof the purposive approach that they were neutraland nonideologicalprofessionals(forged in the spirit of the consensus,managerial1950s) was, in its earlier incarnation, critiquedmost extensivelyfrom the Left, by CriticalLegal Scholars,who were shaped by the New Left of the 1960s.148The superimposing of a rhetorical appeal to "active liberty" does not make any of these criticismsless valid today than they were then. Although Hart and Sacks said it, today it is Justice Breyer who argues (adding a few humble caveats to signal our movement beyond 146 See Stenberg,530 US at 929-30 (invalidatingas unconstitutionalon the basis of Roe a Nebraskastatuterestrictingabortion). 147 Eskridgeand Frickey,An Historicaland CriticalIntroductionat civ (cited in note 26) (noting that these strengthsand weaknessesreflect the intellectualinfluenceof WarrenCourt jurisprudence). 148 See Eskridge,Frickey,and Garrett,Casesand Materialson Legislationat 728 (cited in note 26) ("Criticalscholars argue that legal process judges are making unarticulatedvalue choices underthe auspicesof neutralcraft.").See also MarkTushnet,Darknesson the Edge of Town:TheContributions Theory,89 Yale L J 1037,1038(1980) of JohnHartEly to Constitutional (criticizingJohn Hart Ely's new legal process approachas incoherentand destructiveof other preexistingtheories). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 804 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 the unalloyedconfidenceof the liberalheyday of the 1950s) (see p 85) that: Because "every statute and every doctrine of unwrittenlaw developed by the decisional process has some kind of purpose or objective" ambiguities can be objectively and predictably resolved, first by identifyingthat purpose and the policy or principle it embodies and, then, by deducingwhich result is most consistent with that principleor policy.'49 Today,the main challengeto this interpretiveposture,as Eskridge and Frickeydescribeit, comes from"formalists"like JusticeScalia: The formalist doctrine was that when interpretinga statute all the Court is doing is diviningthe historical"will"of the legislature-the answer it "intended"to create the day it passed the statute.... The legal process insight is that statutes change over time, and an interpretationwhich might be defensible enough when made can become severely out-of-placeyears later.There ought to be greaterjudicial flexibilityto fine-tune its interpretations by looking at related legal developmentsand re-examining prior decisions.'' The dangerwith this insightis, of course,that judges will take the part of the processinvolvingthe identificationof purposesand principles, and wield it creativelyand aggressivelyin light of their own ideologies and policy preferences.Eskridge and Frickeynote that a purposive approach to interpretationproved no barrier to the highly creative and activistjudgingof the Warrenera.They tell us that "[t]he [Warren]Court seized upon the law-as-purposefeaturesof legal process" and "deemphasiz[ed]the philosophy's attention to rule-of-law values,proceduralregularity,and the limited institutionalcompetence of courts" in order to "liberalize [a wide array of areas of law]."'"' "Mostof these opinions,"they note, "wereextraordinarilydynamicinterpretationsof the statutes they were construing(often going against as well as beyondoriginallegislativeexpectations)."'52 Positioned as he is in time, as a Justice serving in the Warren Court'swake, in an era when its legacy has been under sustainedpo149 Eskridgeand Frickey,Casesand Materialson Legislationat 245-46 (cited in note 35) (describinglegal processtheoryas a purposiveapproachto statutory-but not necessarilyconstitutional-interpretation). 150 Id at 264. 151 EskridgeandFrickey,CriticalIntroductionat cv-cvi (citedin note 26). 152 Id at cvi (noting that"the Hart and Sacksmaterialsprovideda detaileddefense of [the WarrenCourt's]approachand probablycontributedto its general acceptabilityin the legal culture"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Justice Breyer's Mandarin Liberty 2006] 805 litical challenge,JusticeBreyer does not need to choose between seizing on the law-as-purposefeatures of legal process and its rule-of-law values emphasizing stability.He is free to seize on law-as-purpose themes when he wants to liberalizethe law (see, for example,pp 7879). But, because he is able to drawupon the liberalprecedentsof this earlier period,and sustainthem, he is freer to appeal to the ostensibly apolitical "rule of law" and stability themes--including the importance of stare decisis--to sustainthe viabilityof earlier,highly aggressive law-as-purposereadingsmade by the WarrenCourt (see p 119)."' This position in time permitsJusticeBreyer to be much more attentive (than JusticeBrennanwas,for example) to the limitsof judicialpower, the importanceof judicialhumility,and the position of the judiciaryas only one - and not necessarilythe most important--institutionof government (pp 31-32, 37). In an earlier stage of the New Deal/Warren Courtliberalconstitutionalregime,JusticeBrennanfelt that it was both important (and politically plausible) to describe the reform-minded liberalconstitutionalprojectas a commitmentto "livingconstitutionalism."As the Warrenyears receded into the background,JusticeBrennan was increasinglycalled upon to defend his livingconstitutionalism againsta set of risingintellectualand politicalchallenges.m'Today,Justice Breyer is essentiallycarryingon JusticeBrennan'slegacy by jettisoning the language of living constitutionalismin favor of a more -a process-oriented form of "dynamic constitutional construction" variantof the purposive,legal process-inspired"dynamic"approachto statutoryinterpretation,now applied not simplyto statutes,but to the interpretationof the Constitution itself (pp 118-20). One question JusticeBreyer'sbook raises is whether the spirit of an ostensibly"living constitutionalism"is any more palatablein this new guise inspired by theories of proper approachesto statutoryconstructionthan it was in its previous incarnation."'Justice Breyer's gambit here, looking to the opportunitiesand limitationsprovided in an increasinglyconservative age, is to changethe nomenclature. 153 See id at civ-cv. 154 See WilliamJ.Brennan,Jr.,TheConstitutionof the UnitedStates:Contemporary RatificaThe Debateover OriginalIntent23, 33 tion,in JackN. Rakove,ed, Interpretingthe Constitution: (Northeastern1990) ("[T]heuniqueinterpretiverole of the SupremeCourtwith respectto the Constitutiondemandssome flexibilitywith respect to the call of stare decisis.");Edwin Meese the Constitution, in Rakove,ed, Interpreting the Constitution13,20 ("[A]nactivist III,Interpreting jurisprudence,one whichanchorsthe Constitutiononly in the consciencesof jurists,is a chameleon jurisprudence."); JackN. Rakove,Mr.Meese,MeetMr.Madison,in Rakove,ed, Interpreting the Constitution179, 180-81 ("JusticeBrennan... dismissedMr.Meese's 'doctrinaire'position [on originalintent]as'arrogancecloakedin humility.'"). 155 See WilliamN. Eskridge,Jr., Dynamic StatutoryInterpretation, 135 U Pa L Rev 1479, 1481(1987). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 806 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 A. Does Active LibertySave Us? Does Justice Breyer's decision to superimposean appeal to "active liberty" on top of a classic legal process approach to statutory construction(now transferredto the projectof constitutionalinterpretation) save him from being, fundamentally,just anotherliving constitutionalist?It does not. The way that JusticeBreyer uses the concept of active liberty in this book differs not at all from the way that the ProgressiveEra progenitorsof a living,evolving Constitutionthat focused not simply on the protection of rights in their negative form (which, admittedly,Justice Breyer defends more aggressively than they did) but on the collective,democraticrightsof the people. Justice Breyer chooses to call this "active liberty"(p 6). But, at least as he describesit here, he could just as easily have called it the "New Freedom[]-a Liberty widened and deepened to match the broadened life of man in modem America, restoringto him in very truththe control of his government."'" That,after all, is whatWoodrow Wilson called it in his critique of the predominant constitutional thought of his time (and, prior to runningfor public office, in his sustained attackon the contemporaryrelevanceof the Constitutionitself, as writtenand understoodby the Founders).157 "Weare in the presence of a new organizationof society,"he wrote:". Our life has broken away from the past.... The life of the nation has grown infinitely varied. It does not centre now upon questions of governmentalstructureor of the distributionof governmental powers. It centres upon questions of the very structure and operation of society itself, of which governmentis only the instrument.Our developmenthas run so fast and so far along the lines sketched in the earlier day of constitutionaldefinition,has so crossed and interlaced those lines, has piled upon them such novel structuresof trust and combination,has elaboratedwithin them a life so manifold, so full of forces which transcend the boundariesof the countryitself and fill the eyes of the world,that a new nation seems to have been created which the old formulas do not fit or afforda vital interpretationof."59 156 WoodrowWilson,TheNew Freedom:A Callfor the Emancipationof the GenerousEnergiesofa People294 (Doubleday1913)(callingthis"NewFreedom"a "deep[er]"freedomthan that at the Founding). 157 See Haskell, The Emergenceof ProfessionalSocial Science at 252 (cited in note 28) (noting thatWilsonpremisedTheNew Freedomon ideals of interdependencethat contravened the LochnerCourt'sfocus on individualrights). 158 Wilson,TheNew Freedomat 3-5 (citedin note 156). 159 Id at 3-5. This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 807 Under these new conditions,it is wrong to overemphasize"negative"or "modern"liberty,Wilson explained: We used to think in the old-fashioned days when life was very simple that all that government had to do was to put on a policeman's uniform, and say, "Now don't anybody hurt anybody else."We used to say that the ideal of governmentwas for every man to be left alone and not interferedwith, except when he interfered with somebody else; and that the best governmentwas the governmentthat did as little governingas possible.... But we are coming now to realize that life is so complicatedthat we are not dealingwith the old conditions... underwhich we many live, the conditionswhichwill make it tolerablefor us to live,?' "Freedomto-day is somethingmore than being let alone,"Wilson emphasized."Theprogramof a governmentof freedom must in these days be positive,not negative merely."161 Although speaking specificallyhere of the Declaration of Independence,Wilsonmayjust as well have been speakingof the Constitution itself when he wrote that: The Declaration of Independence [does] not mention the questions of our day.It is of no consequenceto us unless we can translate its generaltermsinto examplesof the present day and substitute them in some vital way for the examples it itself gives, so concrete, so intimatelyinvolved in the circumstancesof the day in which it was conceived and written.It is an eminentlypractical document,meant for the use of practicalmen.... Unless we can translateit into the questions of our own day,we are not worthy of it, we are not the sons of the sires who acted in response to its challenge. [W]e are architectsin our time, and our architectsare also engineers. We could just as easily call what Justice Breyer calls "active liberty" an interpretive approach aimed at fulfilling "The Promise of American Life." That's what the progressive intellectual Herbert Croly called it.63To achieve the full promise of America, Croly called 160 Id at 19-20. 161 Id at 284. 162 Id at 48-51 (callingfor citizensto throwoff the yoke of big business). 163 Herbert Croly, The Promise of AmericanLife 1-2 (Macmillan1910) (describingthe Whiggish"Promise"of the "Landof Democracy"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions The University of Chicago Law Review 808 [73:759 on Americans to move beyond their traditionalconstitutionalunderstandings,and their overemphasison negative,private-orientedrights. Americans,Croly argued,needed to stop thinkingin their usual formalistic categories made for a bygone age, and reconceive of government as a national-levelproblemsolvingendeavor.64 Unlike Breyer, Croly argued openly that thinking about things this way would be "revolutionary," and that his proposalswould "seem fantastic and obnoxious to the great majorityof Americans,"and involve "a radicaltransformationof the traditionalnational policy and democratic creed."'65 Because Justice Breyer is a lawyer and a judge, and not a freelance political and intellectual activist,he cannot say openly, as Croly does, that "[t]he values placed upon many political ideas,tendencies,and achievements[thathe advocates]differradically from the values placed upon them either by their originatorsand partisans or in some cases by the majorityof Americanhistorians."' "The security of private property and personal liberty, and a proper distributionof activitybetween the local and the central governments [traditionally]demanded ... and within limits still demand, adequate legal guarantees,"Croly wrote. "It remains none the less true, however, that every popular governmentshould in the end, and after a necessarilyprolongeddeliberation,possess the power of taking any action, which,in the opinion of a decisive majorityof the people, is demanded by the public welfare."He added, "Suchis not the case with the government organized under the Federal Constitution."'67 "[I]t may be," he added, "that the Constitution... is itself partly responsible for some of the existing abuses,evils, and problems"facing the country.'"Again, as a judge,Breyer cannot add a similarstatement. And he doesn't. Like Breyer, Croly appeals to an ideal of democratic"solidarity," and popularsovereigntyat the nationallevel. Crolyexplained: The phrase popular Sovereignty is ... equivalent to the phrase "national Sovereignty."The people are not Sovereign as individuals.They are not Sovereignin reason and morals even when united into a majority.They become Sovereign only in so far as they succeed in reachingand expressinga collectivepurpose.169 16 See id at 274. 165 Idat24-25. 166 Id at 27. 167 Id at 35-36. 168 Id at 137. 169 Id at 280 (noting that "thereis no royal and unimpeachableroad to the attainmentof such a collectivewill"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer's Mandarin Liberty 809 This,for Croly,as for Breyer,is "democracy"(see pp 3, 6). Constitutionaltheory,as engaged in here by JusticeBreyer (and, more systematically,by contemporarylegal academics)is an odd endeavor.The task of engagingin ambitiousinterpretationsof the American past, with highly creative appeals to key figures in the American politicaltraditionsuch as Jefferson,Hamilton,and Lincoln,in discerning the meaningand futuretrajectoryof Americanfreedom,was at one time the chief provinceof intellectuals,journalists,activists,and candidates for public office.17 Today,we assumethat its leadingpractitioners will be law professors-and intellectuallyambitiousjudges like Justice Breyer.Thischangeis closely relatedto the rise of judicialsupremacyas the sustainingbuttressof WarrenEra constitutionalliberalism.17Ostensible humilityaside,the nature of the appealsJusticeBreyer makes in ActiveLibertymarkhim as very mucha partof that endeavor.12 B. The Searchfor a LiberalInterpretiveProcessThat"Works" If the process of judgingis, in part, an effort to find workablesolutions to contemporarypolitical problems, so too is contemporary constitutionaltheory.Constitutionaltheory,as practicedby contemporary law professors, exists in what we might call a "constitutional time,"in which distinctive problems ostensibly in need of solutions, existing within distinctive political regimes, present themselves, and alteringpolitical circumstancesmakes certainsolutions to those problems appearmore intellectuallyand politicallyplausiblethan others.73 In this book, JusticeBreyer alludes to the active liberty bona fides of the New Deal/WarrenEra liberal political regime (pp 10-11)."' He was appointedto the Court,however,by a Democraticpresidentduring a Republicanera, in which that form of liberalismwas-and had 170 See id at 28-29. 171 See Powe,TheWarrenCourtat 485-86 (citedin note 31). 172 See Keith E. Whittington,"To SupportThis Constitution": JudicialSupremacyin the TwentiethCentury,in Mark A. Graber and Michael Perhac, eds, Marburyversus Madison: Documentsand Commentary101,120 (CQ 2002). 173 See Kersch,ConstructingCivilLibertiesat 1 (cited in note 125).See also id at 1-27 (describing"thepathsof constitutionaldevelopment"throughthe 1960sand 1970s). 174 Recent work emphasizingthe relationshipbetween the SupremeCourt,constitutional law,and the ambientpoliticalregimeincludesPowe, The WarrenCourtat xiii (cited in note 31); MarkTushnet,TheSupremeCourtand the NationalPoliticalOrder:Collaborationand Confrontation,in Kahnand Kersch,eds, The SupremeCourt(cited in note 121);HowardGillman,Party in Kahnand Politicsand ConstitutionalChange:ThePoliticalOriginsof LiberalJudicialActivism, Kersch,eds, TheSupremeCourt(cited in note 121);CornellW.Claytonand J.MitchellPickerill, GuessWhatHappenedon the Wayto Revolution?:Precursorsto the SupremeCourt'sFederalism Revolution,34 Publius85,87 (Summer2004). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 810 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 long been-under challenge."'This was true both as a general matter and as a matterof constitutionalinterpretation.The RepublicanParty, and the Reagan Revolution,rose to power in part throughmountinga sustained criticismof the WarrenCourt and its activistjudges,who, it was argued, acted as if they were writing a constitution rather than interpretingone.17 Before the legal academyhad fully assimilatedthe reality of Republicanrule,many constitutionaltheoristswere content to argue blissfullythat the Constitution'smeaningwas radicallyindeterminate.Noninterpretivistsexplained that, in approachingconstitutional questions,judges were not in any real way tied to the provisions of the constitutionaltext."77Some continued to argue that, in light of this, the text should be interpretedin a way that transformedsociety in a radically egalitariandirection. Rejecting originalism,and often textualism, others celebrated the Constitution as a "living" document."1By the time JusticeBreyer was appointedto the Courtin 1994, by a "triangulating"President seeking the "thirdway" to return the Democrats to power,however,the legal academyhad belatedlybegun to assimilate the reality of an altered political context, and these approaches-at least in their less cautious forms-were understood to be a weak grounding,in this altered context, on which to sustain(and, perhaps,develop) New Deal and WarrenCourt liberalism,in the face of sustainedpolitical challenge.'79Since that time, constitutionalliberals have set themselvesto the task of buildingnew foundationsto sustain this beleagueredpoliticalregime."o Broadly speaking, there have been several contenders for preeminence in this problemsolvingendeavor.The firstjoins conservative originalismby veneratingthe Founders.But it then goes on, as many conservative originalistsdo not, to take up the whole of American history sequentially,multiplying the number of "foundings"in the American constitutionaltradition,and arguingthat the contemporary SupremeCourtmust interpretthe Constitutionin light of some sort of 175 See Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 241 (cited in note 1) ("Breyer'snominationcame in the immediatewake of a successionof bitter politicalstrugglesbetween ideologicallypolarized politicalparties."). 176 See Kersch,ConstructingCivil Libertiesat 7 (cited in note 125) (describinghow the ReaganRevolutionchallenged"statistliberalism"in the federaljudiciary,amongotherplaces). 177 See, for example,ThomasGrey,Do WeHave an UnwrittenConstitution?27 Stan L Rev 703,705 (1975);MichaelPerry,TheConstitution,the Courts,and HumanRights(Yale 1982).See also Ely,Democracyand Distrust73-75 (citedin note 39). 178 See Horwitz,TheWarrenCourtat 112-13 (cited in note 17) (describingthreadsof Warren Court"activism"that survivedinto the BurgerandRehnquisteras). 179 See Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 241 (cited in note 1) (positingthat this political climatemade Breyera viablenominationfor Clintonto make). 180 See, for example,Sunstein,One Caseat a Timeat xi (cited in note 12) (disavowing"theory"in favorof "closeencounterswith particularcases"wheninterpretingthe Constitution). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 811 synthesis of these multiple foundings,which are tied to the theme of democracy as an expression (like the original Founding) of popular sovereignty as exercised by "We the People."1''Akhil Amar's version of this approachforges a second line of commonalitywith conservatives by supplementingits originalismwith a consistenttextualism.In his firstbook-lengthiteration,Amar emphasizedwhat were essentially two foundings:one in 1789 and one brought about by the Civil War Amendments.182 As he has recentlydevelopedthis,while still placingthe lion's share of the emphasis on these two foundings,he reinforceda constitutionaltext by a focus on theme of an ever-more-democratizing the subsequentadditionof the ProgressiveEra and Kennedy-Johnson Era amendments."' BruceAckerman'sversionof this approachemphasizes the same first two foundings as Amar, but adds a nontextual third Foundingto the mix-that of FranklinRoosevelt's New Deal."4 We might call these theorists"multipleoriginsoriginalists." A second major category of argumentson behalf of sustaining (and,perhaps,expanding)New Deal and WarrenCourt liberalismin a conservativepolitical and constitutionalage are those groundedin socalled "welfare"or "positive rights" constitutionalism.These scholars-who are also (in their way) originalists--have argued for a sweeping scope of governmentalpowers (and, indeed, governmental duties and responsibilities)to pursue (and enforce) the collective social good in the face of countervailing,more "formalistic"arguments 181 See Bruce Ackerman,1 We the People:Foundations5 (Belknap 1991) (urgingthat "a rediscoveredConstitution[be] the subjectof an ongoingdialogueamongstscholars,profession418-19 (Belknap als, and people at large");BruceAckerman,2 Wethe People:Transformations Bruce 1991) (urgingjudges to abandonpure legal realismfor a more principledjurisprudence); Ackerman,TheFailureof the FoundingFathers:Jefferson,Marshall,and the Rise of Presidential Democracy3 (Belknap2005). 182 See Amar, TheBill of Rightsat xii-xiii (cited in note 50) (arguingthat each "founding" dictatesa differentmode of constitutionalinterpretation). 183 See id at xv (elaboratinga theory of the Founders'understandingof the Bill of Rights and examiningthe effects of the FourteenthAmendmenton the Bill);Amar,America'sConstitution at 433 (citedin note 17) (findingconstitutionalchangeduringthe ProgressiveEra,the Great years"that increasedindividuals'"rightsof Depression,and the "Kennedy-Johnson-Vietnam democraticparticipation"). 184 See Ackerman,2 Wethe People:Foundationsat 6-7 (cited in note 181) (arguingthat the Constitutionprovidesfor two levels of lawmaking,a lowerlevel comprisedof the threebranches of governmentand a higherlevel comprisedof the people actingas a deliberativebody). In his latest book, Ackerman-apoplectic,it seems,over any constitutionalsystem that could lead to the election of George W. Bush-seems considerablyless enamoredof the eighteenth-century Founders.He has also added the election of 1800 as, in effect, a new constitutionalmoment. Ackerman,The Failureof the FoundingFathersat 247-49 (cited in note 181) ("Wehave never recoveredfrom the early republic'sfailure [in 1800] to undertakea thoroughgoingredesignof presidentialselection."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 812 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 about textuallystipulatedpowers and their limitations.'8Welfareconstitutionaliststypicallyemphasizethe Constitution'scharacteras a charAs was the case ter of not only "negative"but also of "positive"rights.'86 with multipleoriginsoriginalism,welfareor positiverightsconstitutionalism comes in more- and less-textualistversions.The more-textualist welfare constitutionalists,like Sotirios Barber, derive their understandingsfrom readings of the Constitution'sbroadly worded provisions,like the Preamble,and its assertionthat the text was designed to "promotethe general welfare"(along with similarstatementsfrom an array of Founders and subsequent touchstone figures acceptable to conservatives,such as Abraham Lincoln-but not Franklin Roosevelt)." Barber argues that the particularprovisions of the Constitution must be interpretedin light of the document'soverarchingobjective, which is to promote "the generalWelfare"or to advancethe collective public good.'"Other welfare constitutionalists,like Cass Sunstein, are less fully textualistin placing emphasison the (nontextual) New Deal transformation.Sunstein, for example, has argued for a positive rightsvision by appealingto FDR's "FourFreedoms"speech as a significantconstitutionaltouchstone.'89In a relativelycreative bid to turn constitutionalreasoning in a new (or old) direction for the twenty-firstcentury,some welfare constitutionalists-including Sunstein-have added a "globalist"argument to increase its appeal to liberals, who tend to see the United States, and its underdeveloped welfare state, as perpetuallylaggingbehind the welfare states of Western Europe. Sunstein specificallylinked FDR's positive rights vision to an understandingof a just political order simultaneouslybeing developed in European social welfare states and elaboratedin interna185 See SotiriosA. Barber,Welfareand the Constitution1-2 (Princeton2003) (advocating"a forthrightlysubstantivetheoryof 'the generalwelfare"'). 186 See id at xiv. 187 See id at 3 (citingLincoln'sstatementthat governmentshould"elevatethe conditionof men"). 188 See id at 1 (arguingthat the recognitionof positive rightscomprisesa criticalpart of constitutionalfidelity).See also StephenHolmes and CassR. Sunstein,The Costof Rights:Why LibertyDependson Taxes15 (Norton1999) ("Whenstructuredconstitutionallyand made (relativelyspeaking)democraticallyresponsive,governmentis an indispensabledevice for mobilizing and channelingeffectivelythe diffuseresourcesof the community."). 189 See generallyCassR. Sunstein,TheSecondBill of Rights:FDR's UnfinishedRevolution and WhyWeNeed It More than Ever (Basic 2004).The bcte noire of "positiverights"constitutionalistsis less Lochnerv New Yorkthan the RehnquistCourt'sdecisionin DeShaneyv Winnebago CountyDepartmentof SocialServices,489 US 189 (1989) (holdinga countynot liable to a boy repeatedlybeaten by his fatherwhen county social serviceprovidersknew of the beatings but failed to respond),whichis anathematizedin this literature.See also Ruth Bader Ginsburg and Deborah Jones Merritt,AffirmativeAction:An InternationalHuman RightsDialogue,21 CardozoL Rev 253,256-57 (1999)("[Not]all will shareequally,but ... there are minimumlevels of employment,education,and subsistenceall shouldhave."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer's Mandarin Liberty 813 The appeal of this turn has been entional treaties and declarations.'" hanced only in recent years,as the Democrats have argued on behalf of a revived multilateralismin the face of the ostensibly disastrous "unilateralism"of the much despisedBush Administration.'9' A third category of argumentson behalf of preservingconstitutional liberalism(but not expandingit) are argumentsfor minimalism and judicial restraint,most prominently advanced by Sunstein and discussed above.This approach,of course, appropriatesnot conservative originalism,but rather the conservative critique of the Warren Court'sjudicial activismwith the aim of preservingthe outcomes arrived at by that activismby restraint.92Needless to say,Active Liberty will strikemany liberalconstitutionaltheoristsas a brilliant,shortsynthesis of many of these themes, and, as such, as a possible answer to justices like Thomasand Scalia,and a plausiblehope for the future of constitutionalliberalism. C. How DemocraticIs JusticeBreyer? It is becomingsomethingof a rallyingcry for liberals,in response to conservativescomplainingabout liberal activistjudges,that Justice Breyer is actually the most restrained,and, by implication,the most democraticjustice on the SupremeCourt.'93 Although a much-alludedto op-ed in the New YorkTimesreportedthis,it may neverthelessnot be true. But we can at least meet the Timesop-ed half way and concede that JusticeBreyer was at least near the middle of the Rehnquist Courtin this score:he is clearly no WilliamBrennan,a frankideologically liberaldefenderof a highly aggressiveCourt. For many of these desperate liberals,this book will arrivein the nick of time. In it, JusticeBreyer--positioning himself against"activist"conservativeslike ClarenceThomasand Antonin Scalia--explains at length how he came to believe in judicialrestraint,and his core con- 190 Sunstein,TheSecondBill of Rightsat 129-30 (cited in note 189) (notingthat European "self-styledsocialistmovementshave often not been radical"but instead"in line with ... the [American]politicalleft"). 191 See Ken I. Kersch,Multilateralism Comes to the Courts,Pub Int 3, 4-5 (Winter2004) represents"a vast and ongoing intellectual (arguingthat the Court'suse of "multilateralism" project"to internationalizethe Constitution). 192 See Sunstein,One Caseat a Timeat 4-5 (cited in note 12) (describing"judicialminimalism"as stayingclose to precedentwithouthewingtoo closely to its weight).On David Souteras embodyingthis Harlan-esqueapproach,see TinsleyE. Yarbrough,David HackettSouter:TraditionalRepublicanon the RehnquistCourt130 (Oxford2005). 193 See Gewirtzand Golder,So WhoAre theActivists?,NY Times at A19 (cited in note 6) (allegingthat Breyerinvalidatesless than three-quartersas manystatutesas the next most "activist"judge). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 814 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 victions about the centralityof democracyto the American political tradition. But for anyone who has read through the corpus of Justice Breyer'swork-and the substantiveand theoreticalmattersthat seem (before this book) to most spark his interest-his bid in the past few years to seize the mantleof "thepeople themselves"will seem veryodd indeed.94For JusticeBreyeris, at heart,not a tribuneof the people,but a mandarin:he is self-evidentlymost at home (and most illuminating) when parsing arcane scientific and regulatoryquestions,especially in the company of academics,scientists,bureaucrats,and (transnational) judicialand regulatoryelites (see, for example,pp 85-101). Statisticallyspeaking,and given the distinctivesorts of statutory provisionsthat happen to have come before the Court in the past fifteen years,Justice Breyer may be less likely to void a federal statute than JusticesThomas and Scalia.We might say that this "proves"that today's judicial liberals like Breyer are the country'strue democrats. But recent empiricalwork on the Court has shown that this incessant back and forth in the law reviews about whether liberalsor conservatives are the "true"believersin judicialrestraintis somethingof a parlor game. Both liberals and conservativeshave evinced skewed affinities vis-a-vistheir ideologicaladversariesfor voidingfederal (and state) laws on constitutionalgroundsin different historicalperiods.'95Moreover, politicalscientistChristopherZorn has shown that "the more extreme the Court'saggregateideology-either liberalor conservativethe more willingit is to strikedownacts of Congress."' The rather simple equations between statisticsof this sort and a commitmentto "democracy"that remainsin common currencytoday were forged in the late nineteenth and early twentiethcenturieswhen the Court'sdecision to void a large numberof federal (and state) laws, such as minimum-wageand maximum-hourslaws, stood at the very heart of the politics of its day (see pp 10-11). This was the period in which scholarslike JamesBradleyThayerwere able to argue that the decision by the Court to void a law on constitutionalgroundsoutside of very clear cases representeda serious affrontto democracy.In that time, and in that context, that argumentwas quite plausible and, to 194 See LarryKramer,The People Themselves:PopularConstitutionalism and JudicialReview 8 (Oxford2004) (discerninga "popularconstitutionalism" "overmost of Americanhistory" that gave "[f]inalinterpretiveauthority[to] the people themselves")(internalquotationmarks omitted). 195 See Sunstein,Radicalsin Robes at xii-xiii (cited in note 89) (describingfour different traditionsin judicialdecisionmakingand aligningeach traditionwith particularpoliticalideologies and time periods). 196 ChristopherZorn, LiberalJusticesat 4 (cited in note 6) (noting peaks of "activism" duringthe WarrenandRehnquistCourts). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 815 many, understandablyconvincing.19 As Justice Breyer explicitly acknowledges, however, in a post-Carolene Products,198post-Warren Courtera, we no longer,in the last analysis,assessjudges by their willingness,except in the clearest of cases,to defer to legislatures(p 101). We insist, rather,that they defer where deference is appropriate,and not defer where it isn't (id). JusticeBreyer argueshere that he is being democratic-that he looks to active liberty-both when he votes to void statutes, and when he does not (pp 98-99). The test, then, is whetherhe was rightto do so in either case. Active Libertydoes not reallycontainthe sort of rigorousanalysis from principle-leading to precise results in concrete cases about when a law should be voided and when it should not-that we find in Rather,Breyer uses concrete examfully developed scholarlyworks.'99 ples illustrativleyin this book.As such,the book comes acrossin many respects as a brief for an "attitude"or a "mood"with which to confront the interpretationof legal texts (pp 18-19). It seems to me that JusticeBreyer is really only as democraticin attitude as the statistics about his willingnessto defer to the legislative branch (and administrative agencies) suggest.Key aspects of the substanceof his thought reinforcehis status as our nation'sleadingjurisprudentialmandarin. General readers,I think, will sense this right away the moment JusticeBreyerbegins discussinghis applications,which (and very much in contrastto JusticeScalia'sessay in A Matterof Interpretation?)will come across,in choice of topics to be studiedand in style of exposition, 197 See JamesB. Thayer,The Originand Scope of theAmericanDoctrineof Constitutional Law, 7 Harv L Rev 129, 132 (1893) (noting that even soon after Marbury,judicialreview"was not universallyassentedto");Boudin,Governmentby Judiciaryat 24 (cited in note 132) (claiming that if the courts have judicial review,a power "implied"by the Constitution,Congress shouldalso be able to claimexpansive,implicitpowers).See also Ross,A MutedFuryat 1 (cited in note 132) ("Between1890 and 1937,populists,progressives,and laborleaderssubjectedboth state and federal courts to vigorousand persistentcriticismand proposednumerousplans to abridgejudicialpower."). 198 UnitedStatesv CaroleneProductsCo, 304 US 144 (1938) (expandingthe Commerce Clauseto coverdairyproduction). 199 See Ely,Democracyand Distrustat 181 (cited in note 39) ("elaborat[ing]a representation-reinforcingtheory of judicial review"that representsonly one possible solution among many).But see Bickel, TheLeastDangerousBranchat 244 (cited in note 39) ("I have suggested that principle that the rule of principlein our society is neitherprecipitatenor uncompromising, to is that but not a universal universal be a constraint, leeway provided expediency guide may along the path to, and alongsidethe path of, principle.");Ronald Dworkin,TakingRightsSeriously xiv (Harvard1978)("Itis no partof my theory... that any mechanicalprocedureexistsfor demonstratingwhat political rights,either backgroundor legal, a particularindividualhas.... [T]hereare hardcases,both in politicsand law,in whichreasonablelawyerswill disagreeabout rights,andneitherwill have availableany argumentthatmustnecessarilyconvincethe other."). 200 Antonin Scalia, Common-LawCourtsin a Civil-LawSystem:The Role of the United the Constitutionand Laws,in Amy Gutmann,ed, A Matterof StatesFederalCourtsin Interpreting 3, 44-47 (Princeton1997). Interpretation This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 816 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 as highly technocraticand dry. General readers looking over Justice Breyer's shoulder as he thinks through legal cases will begin to suspect rather quicklythat his real devotion is less to the people, in any broad sense, than to high-levelconversationsand consultationstaking place among policy intellectuals(see, for example,pp 102-08). There are very strongpremonitionsof this throughoutthe broadercorpusof his work. Breyer first came to academic prominenceby arguingthat the people are not particularlyrational in the way that they think about risk, and, accordingly,that decisions about risk regulation are best placed in the hands of administrativeexperts (as they are, he noted, in continentalEuropean social welfare states).201JusticeBreyer is also the Court's most sophisticated and influential proponent of greatertransnationalconsultationamongstthe world'sjudges-a consultation that he has encouragedwith a hope that internationalcontact will provide judges ruling within their domestic constitutional systems with the knowledge and empiricaldata they need to solve the problemsat home raisedby statutoryand constitutionalquestions.202 It is notable that Breyer barely discusses his "comparativist"inclinations in Active Libertybecause, elsewhere, he has described the move by American lawyers and judges in a "comparativist"direction as representing"a modem revolution in the law."Indeed, in an effort to situate this "modernrevolution,"Breyer has asked that we "think of the MarshallCourt [andissues of] constitutionalstructure;the Warren Court and the protection of fundamentalhuman liberty;Labor law in the 1930s and again in the 1960s;Civil procedureand the Federal Rules. [Then] think of ... the role of judges in a globalized legal system."A key part of this revolution will involve an aggressive"interchangeof substantivelegal views,not simplyamong academicsand practitioners,but also among judges from the courts of different nations."203The typicallyunderstatedJusticeBreyer,the judicialminimalist, seems quite excited by the prospectof this interchange.Indeed,he has ended severalspeeches on this topic with these words: [W]hat could be more exciting for an academic,practitioner,or judge, than the "global"legal enterprise that is now upon us? Wordsworth'swords,written about the FrenchRevolution,will, I 201 See StephenBreyer,Breakingthe ViciousCircle:TowardEffectiveRisk Regulation5556, 70 (Harvard1993)(describing"theregulatorylink"as the problemin informingthe publicof risks,andcitingFranceas a countrythat has a "powerfulcoordinatingmechanism[]"). 202 See, for example,Kersch,SyntheticProgressivismat 266 (cited in note 1) (describing Breyer'sjudicialphilosophyas "thejurisprudential adjunctto... elite progressiveglobalism"). 203 Breyer, KeynoteAddress,Symposiumon Democracy (cited in note 14) (noting that judges "increasinglyturnto the experienceof other nationswhen decidingdifficultopen questions of substantivelaw"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 817 hope, still ring true: "Bliss was it in that dawn to be alive/ But to be young was very heaven."'"2 How are we to reconcilethis outsizedenthusiasmfor transnational consultationwith JusticeBreyer'sprofile as an unassumingand measuredminimalist?The key is that,as he sees it, this impendingrevolution represents the prospect that the "national conversation involving, amongothers,scientists,engineers,businessmenand women,the media, along with legislators,judges,and many ordinarycitizens"that Justice Breyer defended in Active Libertyas the essence of "participatorydemocracy... bubbl[ing]up from below"(p 70-71) is on the verge of being taken up at the worldwidelevel. If this is right,we would do very well to stop and reflect about what it says about JusticeBreyer's democratic"attitude"(p 19).To be sure,in this vision"noweveryone,or at least potentiallyeveryone,is [ ] seen as a participantin the collective This may seem democratic,until we realize decision-makingprocess."205 that there is no essential link in it between this conversationand the polity itself:it is a conversationamongstproblemsolvers-more on the model of a seminarthan a demos.206 Active Libertycontainsa few tantalizing-but subtle-gestures towards this expanding"global conversation"-though Breyer is much more explicitabout these things elsewhere.One such gesture-lest we overlookwhat is in plain view-is Breyer'sdecisionto anchorhis jurisprudentialvision in the thoughtof a Frenchman(pp 3-5). Another,as mentionedabove,is his appealto principlesof fraternit6in the affirmative actionexample.Yet anotheris his ratherodd decisionto describethe Americanconstitutionalsystemseveraltimes in Active Libertyas a system of "delegateddemocracy"(pp 23, 24, 85). Because by this he seems prettyclearlyto mean what ordinaryAmericanscall "representativedemocracy,"one explanationfor adoptingthis locutionmightbe to afford him an opportunityto extenda handin friendship(withthe hope of fruitful furtherdialogue?)to the Chief Justiceof the IsraeliSupremeCourt, AharonBarak,who has himselfprominentlyemployedthatlocution.207 204 Id (contending"thatthere is more than a generation'sworth of fundamentallegal and institutionalworkto be done"). 205 Martin Shapiro,AdministrativeLaw Unbounded:Reflectionson Governmentand Governance,8 Ind J Global Legal Stud 369, 369 (2001) ("Thischangein vocabulary[from'government' to 'governance']announcesa significanterosion of the boundariesseparatingwhat lies insidea government... andwhatlies outside."). 206 See id at 369-70(listingthewidearrayof specialinterestgroupsthatparticipate in contempoandnongovernmental"). betweengovernmental rarygovernanceandblur"theverydistinction 207 JusticeBreyer cites Barak twice in this book (see pp 139 n 2, 146 n 1). Like Breyer, has also recentlypublisheda book advocatinga "purposive"approachto the Barak,significantly, interpretationof legal texts. See generally Aharon Barak, Purposive Interpretationin Law (Princeton2005) (SariBashi,trans). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 818 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 But JusticeBreyer'sdecision to adopt a focus on "delegation"as opposed to "representation"is potentiallyof even deeper conceptual significancethan that.The cognoscenti will recognize that the preference for conceptualizingan increasingarrayof dynamicsas involving "delegation"as opposed to "representation"is one of the touchstones of the movement by contemporary cosmopolitan academics away from discussing"governments"in preference for discussing"governance."208 A choice to turn to delegation over representation,of course, retains the functionalaspect of the relationshipbetween principaland agent, while severing the connection between that relationship and Indeed,JusticeBreyer any normativeclaim to democraticlegitimacy.2"9 himself seems to acknowledge this.210 Partisansof governance argue 208 See Gerry Stoker, Governanceas Theory:Five Propositions,155 Intl Soc Sci J 17, 19 (1998) (noting that "governance"refers to a broaderweb of institutionalactors);Shapiro,AdministrativeLaw Unbounded,8 Ind J Global Legal Stud at 369-70 (cited in note 205) (arguing that participationin the governmentaldecisionmakingprocessis broad and crosses traditional publicand privatelines). 209 See Stoker, Governanceas Theoryat 21 (cited in note 208) ("Governancelacks the simplifyinglegitimating'myths'of traditional[constitutional]perspectives,such as the British WestminsterModel.").On delegationgenerally,see Alberto Alesina and GuidoTabellini,Why Do PoliticiansDelegate?2-3 (HarvardInstituteof EconomicResearchDiscussionPaper 2079, (visited Apr 4, July 2005), online at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=764430 2006) (enumeratingthree situationsin which elected politiciansshouldwant to delegate to administrativebureaucrats).Justice Ginsburg'snomenclaturehas also been affected by global dynamicsin odd but subtle ways.In her appeal to internationalstandardsin Grutter,Ginsburg (or someoneworkingfor her),possiblyinadvertently,slippeda foreignlocutioninto the opinion, writing that a race-consciouseffort of the sort adopted by the Universityof MichiganLaw School"accordswith the internationalunderstandingof the office of affirmativeaction."539 US at 344 (Ginsburgconcurring)(citing the InternationalConventionon the Eliminationof All Forms of Racial Discrimination,which endorses positive means to end discrimination).In a subsequentspeech in which she quoted this portionof her opinionin Grutter,she replacedthe foreign idiom ("the internationalunderstandingof the office of affirmativeaction")with "the internationalunderstandingof the [purposeand propriety]of affirmativeaction"(the brackets are hers).Readerswill note that she substitutedan approachsimilarto JusticeBreyer'sfocus on purposesand consequencesfor the foreign locution.Ruth Bader Ginsburg,Speech, "ADecent Respectto the Opinionsof [Human]Kind":TheValueof a ComparativePerspectivein ConstitutionalAdjudication(Apr 1, 2005),online at http://www.asil.org/events/AM05/ginsburg050401.html (visitedApr 4, 2006) (using Grutteras an example of the Court's"attentivenessto legal developmentsin the rest of the world"). 210 In his debatewithAntoninScaliaon the SupremeCourt'scitationof foreignprecedents and practices,Breyerobserved:"It'ssometimesvery hardfor-say for Europeans,to understand why Americanssometimes react negatively,so negatively to the thought that some foreign judgeswouldbe able to tell Americanswhat to do.... [T]hereis somethingdeep in this reaction, and not entirelybad.And it comes back to our being a democracy." ConstitutionalRelevanceof ForeignCourtDecisions,Transcriptof DiscussionbetweenU.S.SupremeCourtJusticesAntonin Scaliaand StephenBreyer,AmericanUniversityWashingtonCollegeof Law(Jan13,2005),online at http://domino.american.edu/AU/media/mediarel.nsf/1D265343BDC2189785256B810071F238/ (visited Apr 4, 2006) ("At bottom, 1F2F7DC4757FD01E85256F890068E6E0?OpenDocument there is reflecteda very strongAmericanbelief that all power has to flow from the people and we have to maintaina check.That'sa good thing."). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer'sMandarinLiberty 819 that to improve our is, to solve our problems--we governance--that and authorityin the place most conduciveto need to lodge the power yielding the right solution.21And who "we"is doesn't really matter all that much.What matters,ultimately,is that there is "governance,"and that the problemgets solved. What are we to make of all this? Well, in Active Liberty,Justice Breyer certainly avoids the snare for judges identified by Justice Brandeis,that "we must be ever on our guard,lest we erect our prejuIt is far from clear,however,that the crux dices into legal principles."212 of the problem is avoided by enacting prejudicesinstead into a set of stipulated "purposes"and "objectives"informed by extensive, and transnational,consultationwith members of an elite political class.13 The one function that a focus on purposes and objectives serves, though, is-as the affirmativeaction illustrationmakes clear-to obscure these prejudices behind a cloud of empirical policy-speak (in which Justice Breyer, who rarely simply defers to legislatures and agencies without "undertak[ing]a detailed reevaluationand reweighing of the factorsthat produced[another'sjudgment],"is proficient).214 Let's be clear:JusticeBreyer'sunderstandingof regulatorypolicy and administrativelaw still probablybests any currentmember of the SupremeCourt.But his efforts to startfrom that thinkingand forge it into a palatable"attitude"towardsconstitutionalinterpretationfail to convince.There is too much of the spiritof the elite regulator--with a new, governance-beyond-borderstwist-in Justice Breyer the consti211 See Stoker,Governanceas Theoryat 21 (cited in note 208) ("Thegovernanceperspec- tive [entails]a steppingback of the state and a concernto push responsibilitiesonto the private andvoluntarysectorsand,morebroadly,the citizen."). 212 New StateIce Co v Liebmann,285 US 262,311 (1932). 213 For an apt criticismof the way thatJusticeBreyer'sprejudices,obscuredby the language of "purposes"and "consequences," trumpethis ostensiblecommitmentto policy experimenta536 US 639 (2002),see RichardA. tion in the school voucherscase, Zelmanv Simmons-Harris, Posner,A PoliticalCourt,119 Harv L Rev 31, 90-92, 99-102 (2005). See also, for example,pp 120-22. JusticeBreyer gave a remarkabledescriptionof how law is created in his debate with JusticeScaliaat AmericanUniversity: [L]awis not really handed down from on high, even from the SupremeCourt.Rather,it emerges.And we're part of it, the clerks are part of it, but only part.And what really survives every time is the result, I tend to think of a conversation[:a] conversationamong judges,among professors,among law students,among membersof the bar, because you need people to put thingstogether,you need people to decidecases,you need people to tell you how it worksout in practice.And out of this giant,messy,unbelievablymessyconversation emergeslaw. Relevanceof ForeignCourtDecisions(cited in note 210). Constitutional 214 See LillianR. BeVier, The FirstAmendmenton the Tracks:ShouldJusticeBreyerBe at the Switch?,89 Minn L Rev 1280, 1312 (2005) (claimingthat "JusticeBreyer'sproportionality approachappearson its face to be the opposite of a genuine commitmentto defer to other branches"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 820 The Universityof ChicagoLaw Review [73:759 tutionalist.Part of that elitist spirit consists of failing to recognize the deep nature of the ideological assumptions,be they in mattersof substance or process, upon which his ostensibly purely technical judgments and proceduralaffinitiesseem to rest.Appeals to a vague rhetoric of "activeliberty"or "participatorydemocracy,"in the end, do not concealthis spirit. Appeals to findingcommonsensicalor "sound"resultswhen faced with practicalproblems,and appealsto the problemsolvingpayoffs(and the authority)of colloquiesamongstpolicyprofessionals,are most convincing in eras,and in areas,where there are few ideologicaldivisions, and the main problemsof law are taken to be technicalproblems.We do not live in such an era.215 JusticeBreyer'scommonsensepragmatism is suffused,self-evidently,by currentpolitical conditions,with a manifestly liberal(and cosmopolitanliberal)ideology. To date, Justice Scalia has been the most effective Justice on the Court at unmasking the ideological assumptions of the Supreme Court'sliberals,JusticeBreyer included.Given that Scalia and Breyer both relish a lively intellectualgive and take,we might assumethat the intellectual challenge to the plausibilityof JusticeBreyer's purposive and consequentialistpragmatismis most likely to continue to come from JusticeScalia.216 One wonders,however, if the next step in the deconstructionof constitutional liberalism as a political ideology may come less from the more (and more uniformly)categorical,rules-basedconservatives than from conservatives like Chief Justice John Roberts, and (perhaps) Justice Samuel Alito. Justice Scalia doubtless will continue to unmask liberal political ideology wherever he finds it and hoist the banner of a hard-edgedconstitutionaloriginalism.But, althoughthey will no doubt side with JusticesScalia and Thomas in many disputes, JusticesRoberts andAlito -so far as we can tell at this relativelyearly stage of their careerson the SupremeCourt-are also, in their general approach,nonformalistand nonoriginalisteclectic pluralists.It is quite likely that, in cases where they find it appropriate,they will also end up reasoning,to a fair extent, from purposes and consequences.They are likely to do so, however,startingnot from a backgroundin regulatory policy,with an itch for transnationalism,but from the perspective of legal craftsmanship(both have noted their admirationfor the second JusticeJohn MarshallHarlan),and a commitmentto popularsov- 215 See Sunstein,Radicalsin Robes at xi-xv (cited in note 89) (describingfour ideological divisionsin today'sjudiciaryand denigratingthosejudicialideologiesthatlook to createpolicy). 216 See, for example,Scalia,Common-LawCourtsat 3 (citedin note 200). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2006] JusticeBreyer's Mandarin Liberty 821 ereignty.217As Roberts and Alito look to the purposes and conse- quences in statutes and constitutionalprovisions,they are likely to do so in ways newly free of the ideological baggage that Breyer,with his reflexive ideologicalcommitmentto mid-twentiethcenturyliberalism, and his enthusiasm for a globetrotting cosmopolitanism,inevitably brings to the task. Justices Roberts and Alito, for instance, are less likely to reflexivelyraise the specter of the outbreak of religiouswar in EstablishmentClause cases, a specter that, for a variety of timebound reasons,assumed a privilegedplace in the mid-twentieth century liberal constitutional imagination.21 Because they are less beholden to the statist-managerialistworldviewthat became an important strain of post-New Deal administrativeliberalism,JusticesRoberts and Alito may be less inclined to dispatchwith free speech concerns when presented with the "purposive"applicationof that vision in speech-restrictivecampaignfinance regulations.2• Similarly,Justices Roberts and Alito may be more inclined to draw the sorts of fine, craftsmanlikedistinctionsin affirmativeaction cases--distinguishing, for instance,a compelling interest in having a raciallydiverse police force in the context of a raciallydiverse city of neighborhoods,from the desire of the administratorsof a very small set of elite universities to use race discriminationto serve the cause of "diversity"more generally-that Justice Breyer, a quintessential Cambridge,Massachusetts, liberal ("minimalism"notwithstanding)-would not even think to draw.220And JusticeRoberts and Alito will likely be less awestruck by the prospects of turning the task of constitutionalinterpretation 217 See CopleyNews Service,EditorialWeeklyFeature(Nov 15, 2005) (describingRoberts and Alito as eschewing"judicialoverreaching"in a way similarto the second JusticeHarlan). JusticeScaliaalso came to the Courtfrom a backgroundin administrativelaw.But his approach to the subject,in starkcontradistinctionto JusticeBreyer'spolicy-orientedvision,is thoroughly Textand Tradition constitutional.See generallyRalphA. Rossum,AntoninScalia'sJurisprudence: (Kansas2006). 218 See Simmons-Harris, 536 US at 728-29 (Breyerdissenting)(arguingfor school vouchers becausethey do not threatenthe EstablishmentClause'spurposeto foster"socialconcord");pp 46-50; pp 120-22. See also Kersch,ConstructingCivil Libertiesat 235-325 (cited in note 125) (discussingthe intellectualoriginsof the SupremeCourt'smid-twentiethcentury's"strictseparationism"in EstablishmentClausecases). 219 On the links between the defense of speech-restrictivecampaignfinance regulations with the broaderNew Deal managerialism(particularlyas it involved labor law), see Ken I. Kersch,How ConductBecame Speechand SpeechBecame Conduct:A PoliticalDevelopment Case Studyin Labor Law and the Freedomof Speech,U Penn J Const L (forthcoming2006) (discussingthe originsof contemporaryregulationsof politicalspeech duringelectionsin managerialapproachesto laborunionelectionsforgedin the 1930sand 1940s). 220 See, for example,Antol v Perry,82 F3d 1291,1303 (3d Circuit1996) (Alito concurring) (holdingthatevidencethat an employerviolatedan affirmativeactionplan sufficedto createan issue of materialfact but acknowledgingthat such evidencehas "verylittle probativevalue for the purposeof provingintentionaldiscrimination"). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 822 TheUniversity of ChicagoLawReview [73:759 towards a model anchored in deracinated,functionalist theories of "governance"and more firmly committed to the traditionalunderstandings of popular sovereignty on which the American constitutional "government"is based. As such, if constitutionalliberalismcontinues its decline,the real interpretive debate may end up being between conservatives Scalia and Thomas,on the one hand, and Roberts and Alito on the other (just as, in an earlierliberalera, it was between fellow New Deal liberals Frankfurterand Black). Justice Breyer'sdecision in this book to recycle Hart and Sacks's approach to the interpretationof statutes and to repackage it as an approachto construingthe Constitution,when marriedto his advoin constitutionalinterpretationand cacy for a greater"comparativism" the consolidationof a networked"globalcommunityof courts,"a subject he took up (as a matter of substanceand practice)in his previous book-co-edited with the former president of the French Conseil Constitutionnel- certainlymarks a significantcontributionto liberal constitutional thought.The ways in which these two sides of Justice Breyer's outlook may be mutuallyconstitutiveare especiallyinterestThat American democracy would be advanced-and, for that ing.221 matter,the power of judges properlycabined-should JusticeBreyer's mandarinvision prevail, though, seems exceedingly doubtful indeed. Far from evincinga commitmentto "participatorydemocracy"as that concept has been understood in American political life, Justice Breyer'svision will doubtlessappeal to a certainsort of contemporary liberal-a sort many have argued is too predominantin the Democratic Partyfor its own good. Whetherthis mandarinspiritwill fare any better as law than it has in politics is an open question. 221 ConsiderAnne-MarieSlaughter,A Global Communityof Courts,44 Harv Intl L J 191, 192 (2003) ("Thiscommunityof courtsis constitutedabove all by the self-awarenessof the nationaland internationaljudgeswho play a part.");Anne-MarieSlaughter,A New WorldOrder34 (Princeton2004) ("Suppos[ing]sovereigntyitself couldbe disaggregated...,the core characteristic of sovereigntywould shift from autonomyfrom outside interferenceto the capacity to networksof all types.... [D]isaggregatedsovereigntywould participatein transgovernmental empowergovernmentinstitutionsaroundthe worldto engagewith each other in networksthat would strengthenthem.");Badinterand Breyer,eds,Judgesin Contemporary Democracyat 4-5 (cited in note 2) (discussingjudicialactivism,the "secularpapacy"of the judiciary,judicialintervention into the politicalprocess,internationalcriminaljustice,the judiciaryand the media,and judges'conceptionsof theirown socialroles). This content downloaded from 136.167.3.36 on Tue, 31 Dec 2013 12:38:20 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions