LIBRARY OF THE MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium Member Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/lindahlssolutionOOfole Him .M415 no© 3 working paper department of economics Lindahl's Solution and the Core of An Econouiy with Public Goods by Duncan K. Foley Number 3 - October 1967 massachusetts institute of technology 50 memorial drive Cambridge, mass. 02139 Lindahl's Solution and the Core of An Economy with Public Goods by uuncan K. Foley Number 3 - October 1967 C^Cf^-f I This paper was supported by the National Science Foundation (grant number GS 1585 ) The views expressed in this paper are the author's sole responsibility, and do not reflect those of the National Science Foundation, the Department of Economics, nor of the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. • rvo »"5 MAY G m. i. r. 1988 LIBRARIES . LINDAHL'S SOLUTION AND THE CORE OF AN ECONOMY WITH PUBLIC GOODS Introduction I. Since Samuelson's clear statement of the theory of consumption externalities (public goods) [7], there has been substantial progress in sharpening analytical tools for tax and expenditure problems. An important part of this progress has been the rehabilitation and reconstruction of Lindahl's problem [6] quasi-demand solution to the taxation by Johansen [4] and Samuelson [8]. More recently the theory of the core of an n-person game has been applied elegantly to the problem of economic general equilibrium [9] The purpose of this paper is to state rigorously the nodern theory of resource allocation with public goods, and to study the relationship between Lindahl's solution and the core. Section II introduces assumptions and definitions, including the notion of "public competitive equilibrium 71 of [3]. Section III establishes the relation between marginal rates of transformation and marginal rates of substitution at Pareto optimal allocations of the economy. This is a reconstruction of Samuelson's first paper [7]. Section IV defines and establishes the existence of Lindahl equilibrium. Section V defines the core. Section VI consists of a proof that a Lindahl equilibrium is in the core. ) -2- Definitions and Notation II. The economy has m public goods and k private goods. of public and private goods is written (x-,...,x ; in jl A vector y-,,...,y.) = (x;y). J& There are n consumers, distinguished by superscripts. A. Consumption Each consumer chooses a point in a consumption set X , on which there is defined a complete and transitive preference ordering ^. owns an initial endowment of private goods w , and . n i A. 1 X = EX. < has a lower bound for — i=l A. 2 X and has an interior in the is closed and convex for each i, private good subspace. A. 3 If x e X there is x A. 4 For every x {x X e x.». ^ I l ' x A. 5 If A. 6 ^. x the sets {x x\ l l (x;y) >_ + bx then ax (x ;y) e ) ^ X x.^. x.} | < (x";y) and (Continuity.) . with y in X (Non-satiation. . where a,b x . then (x;y) ^. , ^. x are closed in X } There is a point (x;y A. 7 If B. X e with x X e w and a + b = > 1. (Convexity.) . for all i. Production Production is denoted by a vector (x;z) with inputs negative and The set of all technically possible production plans outputs positive. is called Y. That is, if (x;z) and (x;y) B.l Y is a closed, convex cone. a,b B.2 e > 0, for all e Y. at least one z. < 0. Y and Y. B.3 If (x;z)^ !*• As is then (ax + bx; az + bz) e Y, e customary, x j ; x 12 >_ x 12 > x 1 means x. means x 12 >_ x 2 > x. _ .. for all i; but not x 12 = x . x 2 I 2 1 > _ x means x. > x. i 3- B.4 There is (x;z) Y with x. e > 0, = l,...,m. j (Possibility of producing public goods.) B.5 If (x;z) Y and e = x. when x. x". J J then (x;z) C. when x. J < 0, 3 (No public good is necessary as a production input.) Y. e but x. = > - J Allocations C.l An allocation is a vector of public goods x and a set of n vectors of private goods (y ,...,y / (x;y i\ ,,i — with y i • X e ) *.i_ < y such that for all ) there is i i . C.2 A feasible allocation is an allocation (x;y ,...,y n i i X [x;.E (y -w )] e Y. 1 C.3 A Pareto optimum is a feasible allocation (x;y there is no other feasible allocation K 1 (x'jy ) such that ) (x^ 1 ) for all (x";"y , . . , . . ,y . . ,y such that ) with ) i. C.4 A public competitive equil ibrium is a feasible allocation (x;y , (t 1 , . . . ,...,t n. . i_ ^(y p*[x; i \ , with ) n a) price system a ), ,y i = P *w p -w i x *x = Si E,t 1=1 . p = (p and a vector of taxes ), ;p . such that: _ i ^_p-(x;z) for all (x;z) )] - t i — -r / (x;y i\) and if i ^. r ± i\ e / (x;y ), Y; — then p -y i -1 b) P c) there is no vector of public goods and taxes (x; t n — — p «x = .I,t 1=1 x _i y (x;y y ) ^. r i such that for every i there exists y (x;y ) and p »y y —< >w p - t i > p ,...,t ) -y ; with with . y Public competitive equilibrium involves profit maximization by producers, preference maximization under the after-tax budget constraint by consumers, and the impossibility of finding a new public sector with taxes to pay for it that appears to every individual to leave him better off. See Foley [3] for a discussion of this definition and a proof that . -4- a public competitive equilibrium is a Pareto optimum. III. Prices The prices of public goods in a public competitive equilibrium Samuelson are marginal rates of transformation. has shown that [7] at a Pareto optimum the marginal rates of transformation for public goods are equal to the sums of marginal rates of substitution. is the essence of the following This theorem. There is a separate public good price vector for each individual. Every individual facing his separate price vector "demands" the same The sum of the individual vector of public goods as every other. price vectors is a social price for the public goods which is the correct guide for profit-maximizing producers to follow. Notice the symmetry: in the case of private goods everyone faces the same prices and each person chooses a different bundle of goods, while in the case of public goods everyone chooses the same bundle but faces different prices. A. a Theorem If : (x price vector p = a) y ; (p for all (x,z) Proof (x;y If b) ...,Px . 1 y± (xr.y ), [ (x , . . . ,x ; z) | x F is a convex cone since if and a,b > such that > ) w 1 )] > (j^p* 1 1 - Py )'(x;i) ; Y. e X ) p ; .^(y there exists 1 p^-x + then P 1-X > Py-y x + P - y y • Let : F = , . is a Pareto optimum, ) . Py )-[x; (j^p/; ,y , 0, then (ax =...= x —1 (x = x and — rx , . . . + bx ,...,ax ,x ; — z) + bx (xrz) a and (x ; Y] e 1 , . . . ~n ,x az + bz) has " ; z) e F, -5- -1 ax , -1 -n -1 -n ~n -n =...= ax + bx because x =...= x and x =...= x *1 , + bx , (ax + bx; az + bz) Y because e (x;z) and (x;z) , and Y and Y is a convex cone. e Let D = {(x x z) ; D is convex since if (x with a + b = (ax + bx then ax 1, . , . . . z) ; . , r, ) with I z ,x + bx + w + bz az ; z = | . . and(x ) , . + bx ,ax (x;y (x . , z . ,x + w r z D and a,b > 1 z) ; ) . (x;y ) }. az + bz) will have ; by convexity of preference, and so will be in D. D and F have no points in common, since if they did (x; y ,...,y By the Minkowski separating hyperplane would not be a Pareto optimum. theorem (for one proof see Karlin [5]), there exists (p X ,...,p p ; X price vector and a scalar r such that ^ ) a J n (1) -1 -n for all (x ,...,x (2) -1 -n for all (x ,...,x ; z) e D, ; z) e i - Z,p x *x + p -z F, n i -5-iP By continuity of preference (x,...,x;z) e D, -i ,x + r; <_ and p • z >_ r. the closure of D, and is in F so that n . E i .. p • i=l*x x + p for all (x;z) Since y z = r>— n _ i _ *x + p -z .£,p~ 1=1' x *y Y, which establishes part a) e e • F, r >_ of the theorem. and if r were positive the activity (x,...,x;z) could be expanded indefinitely giving a higher profit and contradicting (1) so that r = 0. Points with very Suppose p had some negative component. large amounts of the corresponding commodity would be in D by monotonicity, but would have smaller value than (x,...,x;z) which contradicts (2). Therefore p >_ =0. Suppose, however, that p i 0. y Some p x >_ 0. Since production ) -6- of all public goods is possible with no public good input, there would be a point in F with positive profit, which contradicts (2). Therefore p -> J 0. > -h. y ) ,-h _ Suppose (x ; ' h . (x . y ) k -k k -k where y = y and x = x for k .Z.p i i=l*x -x x + p *y -[.^(y i=l w 1 L ,-1 h. ; - w The point [x . 4- -n , . . . ,x Z ,-i (y - w )]. _ . ; w i.. )] h is in D so 1 > — )] .S.p x i=lrX >x + P K . y [.E, (y 1=1 ' 1 1 Since all terms are the same on both sides except those corresponding to h, it must be true that px h -h x -h , * h p y' y - p ' >_ 0, there is another point in X Along the line between this point and (x ;y value than (x;y but near (x ;y ), preferred to (x;y another point with all private Since there is in X Suppose equality held. goods smaller and p k P y' y ' x ) ) x h -h 'X + pr This corresponds to a point in D with smaller ). -h , y -y J all points have lower by continuity there will be a point value than (x,...,x;z) which contradicts (2). p r with lower value. h > p *x -x + p »y Therefore h y and part b) of the theorem is established. n I t = p leave it to the reader to verify that p = .E,p : i=l^x *x • (w - y i and also satisfy the definition of public competitive ) equilibrium in II. C. 4. IV. Lindahl Equilibrium Corresponding to each Pareto optimum there is a total tax on each person t = p • (w - y ) which may be positive or negative. There is also a value for total -7- consumption i p r x *x + p «y i y which may be greater or smaller than endowment income. [8] Samuelson proposes to call the difference between this consumption value and endowment income a lump-sum transfer _i L = p r x i + 'x p *y i - p y *w : i . y As Johnson [4] explicated clearly, it was Lindahl's idea [6] a kind of mock competitive equilibrium in the public sector. to find On the assumption that the endowments of the society have already been redistributed to achieve an ethical optimum, this competitive equilibrium will also be the social welfare optimum. Competitive equilibrium requires that all consumers be maximizing satisfaction at the income they get from their own endowment. In other In the language of the words all the lump-sum transfers must be zero. "benefit theory," the value of public goods received by each individual is equal to the total tax he pays. A. D efinition n 1 A Lindahl equilibrium is a feasible allocation and a price system (p a) - \ o) n i -?iP v X X ( n l-- c if • r-i- (x : ; P, ,)* , [ n x ;,-?i (y X~~ y ~i\ v >. ) r y j 1 B. ...,p / (x: ; ) i\ ) _> i ^i then pr x , . . . ,y ) ( ~i *x Lp X i X~~X + i p ; ~i p *y y -- -- n - w )] y such that >_ ii X y > p (x; )-(x;z) for all (x;z) ^ > p i x -x + i p *y y i = p *w y Existence To prove the existence of a Lindahl equilibrium the following lemma, adapted trivially from Debreu Lemma: [2] Y; e v is necessary. Given the assumptions II. A. 1-5 and II. B. 1-3, there exists in a i . -8- private good economy a feasible allocation (y ,...,y such that vector p f [-^(y 1 w " > p-z a) P' b) for every i, if y Theorem )] ^ for all z Y; e then p -y y Under assumptions II. A and : and a price ) >_ = p -y p -w . there exists a Lindahl II.fi equilibrium. Proof The strategy is to construct a private good economy to which the : lemma applies and show that the quasi-equilibrium of this economy is a Lindahl equilibrium. Extend the commodity space by considering each consumer's bundle In this nm + k of public goods as a separate group of commodities. space, the set F meets the requirements of II. B. 1-3. by writing zeroes for all public good Extend the sets X components not corresponding to the consumer. i These sets meet the requirements of II. A. 1-5. From the Lemma, there will be a vector (x ,...,x prices 1 1 / (p 'x ,...,p n . p : x ' ) , _ ( if 1 P (x;z) (2) (x i P., a y in Y. -ix v -i if -i ** y ; + ) p y ) and , v ^. -y .^(y 1 w - =...= x (x -i , ,...,y y P )'tx; ; x y sucu tuat f 1 (1) ; , (x;y ) i _ > p ^ x a -x 1 )] > (j^p/; Py )'(x:i) for all = x as a consequence of the definition of F.) . len the + >y p i = p y -w i . y An argument similar to the one based on monotonicity used in section II will assure that p *" -> and n K y > - 0. -9- Part (2) implies ± (xS y )>, (xjy if (3) 1 , x x goods smaller than w and p , ). of section II) so that if (x i -i p x *x 1 1 y ; *w . y point with all private a with smaller there is a point in X 0, >_ i This will lead to a contradiction (as in the theorem value than (x;y (4) = p Since there is in X Suppose equality held. , th en ) -1 ^ i i +p-y r J —>pr x "x+p-y y y i ,-i p 1 )^ (xry . 1 then ) +p«y-i >p x i "x+p'y i , = p y y «w i . y This establishes the theorem. The Core V. A. Definitions An allocation (x; y , or coalition of consumers )> and (x; y . (x;y 1 ) ...,y ) is said to be blocked by a subset if there exists S for all i e S (x; y such that [x; ,...,y . E led (y ) with x >_ - w Y. corresponding to consumers not in Notice that the y S )] e 0, may be zero. An allocation is in the core of the economy if it cannot be If an allocation is in the core, no coalition blocked by any coalition. can do better for all its members with its own resources. VI. iW Theorem 1 : A Lindahl Equilibrium is in the Core If (x; y , . . . ,y p ; p_ x x ; p y ) is a Lindahl equilibrium it is in the core. Proof (x; y Suppose the coalition : , . . . ,y ). could block (x; y ,...,y S Since (x;y )r . (x;,y ) for all i e S, we ) by know by the -10- definition of Lindahl equilibrium that .E (1) Since pr (2) + p • .Z > y *y ±eS J n i x 'x p ieSc r x > — for all i, . . i —> Z..p 1=1 x Z„p ieS x . 1 JiP/'X + Py-ils^-w ) + *x Z,.p ieS r x > i , = n '.Z 7 *y leSc y p f «.E„w y ieS . which means that, since x ' —> 0,' 0. But the profit maximizing condition for Lindahl equilibrium asserts that (3) n .Z,p r i=l x * _ -x _ + p r -z y for all (x;z) —< e Y. This contradiction establishes the theorem. VII. Conclusion There is no reason to think that Lindahl equilibrium can be embodied by any working political process. There is some reason to think that the core is a meaningful political concept. If a group of people find themselves able, using only their own resources, to achieve a better life, it is not unreasonable to suppose that they will try to enforce this threat against the rest of the community. They may find themselves frustrated if the rest of the community resorts to violence or force to prevent them from withdrawing. In the absence of some assumption about the reaction of the part of the society not in the coalition to the coalition threat, detailed predictions of the equilibrium situation are not possible. But if a society stays inside the core as it is defined here, there is a minimal rationale for everyone to continue to participate. The conflicts that will naturally arise over the redistribution of initial endow- ments will still be there. But no group will have the power to alter the situation in its own favor unilaterally. This is a very crude and intuitive argument for the relevance of the core to political reality, but the whole theory of political equilibrium is in its infancy. Duncan K. Foley Massachusetts Institute of Technology Bibliography [1] [2] Theory of Value Debreu, Gerard. Sons, 1959. . New York: John Wiley & "New Concepts and Techniques for Equilibrium Analysis," International Economic Review 3 (September, 1962), pp. 257-273. . , [3] "Resource Allocation and the Public Sector," Yale Economic Essays 7 (Spring, 1967), pp. 43-98. Foley, D. , [4] Johansen, Leif. "Some Notes on the Lindahl Theory of Determination of Public Expenditures," International Economic Review 4 (September, 1963), pp. 346-358. , [5] Karlin, S. Mathematical Methods and Theory in Games, Programming and Economics Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley 1959. [6] , , . Lindahl, Erik. "Just Taxation - A Positive Solution," reprinted in part in Richard A. Musgrave and Alan T. Peacock (eds.) Classics in the Theory of Public Finance London: Macmillan, 1958. . [7] Samuelson, P. A. "The Pure Theory of Public Expenditures," Review of Economics and Statistics 36 (1954), pp. 387-389. , [8] [9] "Pure Theory of Public Expenditure and Taxation," unpublished manuscript. . "A Limit Theorem on the Core of an Economy," International Economic Review 4 (September, 1963), pp. 235-246. Scarf, H. and Debreu, G. , Date Due IBL 20 "If Sep g AU6 87* 4 'r% -«. AUG 2 3 198! i Lib -2 6 -6 7 MIT LIBRARIES 15A 771 TOflO D03 3 MIT LIBRARIES 3 "nQfiD DD3 T27 L51 3 TDflO DD3 T5S bbM MIT LIBRARIES 3 TDfiD DD3 T5fi 714 MIT LIBRARIES P!l 3 TDflD DD3 TSfl bE3 MIT LIBRARIES 3 TDflD DD3 =156 7fc,3 MIT LIBRARIES 3 TDflD DD3 TE? hT3 MIT LIBRARIES 3 TDflO DD3 TSfl 3 TDflD A3T DUPL MIT LIBRARIES DD3 TE7 bbT MIT LIBRARIES 3 TDflO DD3 =127 b77 M G" i.G *fSH