;;;^cHir^ Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium Member Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/moderatingelectiOOales HB31 .M415 AO. 6-1 :V working paper department #'.?c •, of economics MODERATING ELECTIONS Alberto Alesina Howard Rosenthal No. 537 October 1989 massachusetts institute of technology 50 memorial drive Cambridge, mass. 02139 .») 91^^ MODERATING ELECTIONS Alberto Alesina Howard Rosenthal No. 537 October 1989 :-,«B,sP'' DEC 3 t law :"—,.. J ,» , MODERATING ELECTIONS* Alberto Alesina Harvard University, NBER, CEPR and Howard Rosenthal Carnegie Mellon University and MIT *This work was supported by National Science Foundation grant SES8821441 Moderating Elections Abstract This structure paper extends the in which policy legislature and of the spatial theory the executive. In institutional an model Nash has and Von several an setup stable implications which in the ("Coalition seem split-ticket voting; government with different parties majority of the legislature; and Alberto Alesina Harvard University NBER and CEPR c) b) To Proof"). consistent United States other democracies in which the executive is directly elected. split which the we apply the refinements of Neumann-Morganstern testable a) in the outcome depends upon how everybody else votes. observed patterns of voting behavior the model predicts: institutional each voter has incentives to analyze equilibrium in this game between voters, Strong to choices are a function of the composition of policy outcome depends upon relative plurality, be strategic since voting of and with The some perhaps in For instance, for some parameter values, controlling the executive the mid-term electoral cycle. Howard Rosenthal Carnegie Mellon University and a the INTRODUCTION 1. Policy outcomes typically reflect the composition of both the executive and the legislature. United the In for States, instance, the administration's influence on policy making is affected by the composition of Congress. Traditional models spatial elections of ignore this institutional complexity and assume that the winner of a two-party race has full control over policy. interaction between the These models focus on the strategic candidates and treat each voter as a passive player, voting for the candidate offering the policy closest to his ideal point. In our model the voters instead face two parties with policy-preferences [Wittman outcomes. (1977, that 1988)]; is, preferences party intermediate between policies ideal the on policy executives representing the Without "checks" by the legislature, two parties would follow distinct and polarized policies. policies defined are of 2 Voters with ideal parties two the take advantage of the institutional structure to "moderate" the executive and thus achieve a policy outcome closer to their ideal. not only depends upon the relative plurality of the identity of two parties feature of the model implies that, the in executive but the the actual policy In fact, This legislature. each voter depends upon his beliefs about other Indeed, one needs whenever policy reflects more than a coordination institutionalism' game s" between a the concern about the realistic unlike in the traditional spatial model, the decision of voters. reflects also to consider strategic single binary choice. voters the in the interaction of the voting Thus, context the legislature [Shepsle (1986), Hammond and Miller (1988)]. behavior of of behavior we consider the executive and "new the Our model of "moderating behavior" has implications which are consistent with some observed voting patterns in the United States. the executive and the legislature are elected simultaneously, voting split-ticket generally That occurs. different parties in the two elections. some is, Consequently, when For instance, we predict that voters vote for the party winning the election for the executive branch may not have a majority in the legislature. In parameter values some for fact, predicts divided government, model the with different parties controlling the executive and the legislature. Second, United model the States: is consistent phenomenon persistent a cycle". the executive the party holding elections, voting "mid-term the with mid-term In 3 the in congressional loses plurality relative to the preceding congressional elections held simultaneously with the presidential Even though other explanations of this strong regularity have been election. such as proposed, which abstracts incumbency Rosenthal as well "coattail effect", the from personal preferences, (1989)) and 4 we offer a different characteristics etc. an In of empirical presidential study, we explanation candidates, (Alesina and have shown that this "moderating", model performs at least often better than traditional empirical voting models that emphasize incumbency advantage or retrospective voting based on the state of macroeconomic policy variables. We model. ideal investigate both a In the points former, is but common full not information and in the knowledge. latter, Some an incomplete information the distribution of of the results voters' concerning split-ticket voting and moderating behavior emerge in both cases and can be more easily illustrated in the certainty model, rather general assumptions about which can be developed with utility functions, distributions of ideal and points, the impact of cycle emerges only incomplete the in legislative plurality on policy. the information model. mid-term A Explicit solutions for this case can be obtained under more restrictive functional forms, are needed for computational should assumptions result reasons. small in Small deviations quantitative from differences which these and no qualitative differences in the results. [Aumann (SN) and Peleg point of view, technical From a Whinston refinements (1987)] games. Since we consider defined only a results to for shows how Coalition Proof Nash Equilibria and (1959)] this paper continuum of a number finite of be can usefully voters, players, and we develop a directly analogous refinement for [Bernheim, (CPN) applied to voting concept CPN the use Strong Nash the Greenberg' s is (1989) continuum case. the This refinement is a Von Neuman Morgenstern (vN&M) stable set. These voters, refinements are needed for two reasons. every strategy is Nash for the individual voter, have any measurable impact on the outcome. held separately, the at "mid term" with atomistic First, since he does not When legislative elections are of a presidential the vNScM refinements lead to a unique equilibrium that term, both the SN and is directly analogous to the unique Nash equilibrium with a finite number of voters. equilibrium has the intuitive property that no voter would This SN-vN8iM like to see a decline in the plurality of the party he is voting for. Second, with either a finite or an infinite number of voters, the "all or none" feature of the majority rule used in presidential elections requires refinements beyond the simple Nash notion. the situation where no voter is pivotal In the We need refinements to address in the presidential election. specific context of our certainty model, when the president is simultaneously elected legislature, the one with party D winning equilibria: identical with to outcome SN the are two possible presidency and a legislative vote the when there party legislative elections are held separately, "D" as in holds executive the "midterm", the and and another corresponding to the outcome when party "R" holds the executive when midterm We need refinements to indicate whether one or both of the elections occur. two outcomes is "stable". We show that, president and always exists turns out that SN is too strong a refinement. It for some parameter values, there is no SN equilibrium when the legislature are elected simultaneously. when although, the parties two located with respect to the median voter, the refinements appear to match not too a vN&M asymmetrically both outcomes may be vN&M. intuition. are to the same side of the median voter, are contrast, In Again, when both parties For example, there is a unique SN-vN&M where the party closer to the median holds both the presidency and a majority in the for symmetric utility and symmetric distributions of Moreover, legislature. voter ideal points, the outcome where the party closer to the median wins the presidency is always vN&M. Fiorina has (1988) recently that model split-ticket of voting Fiorina's specification of executive-legislature interaction is such only four combinations legislature, importantly, Fiorina a There are three important differences between the which is related to ours. models. proposed of policy outcomes are holding parties possible, the executive corresponding and the while we allow for a continuum of policies. Fiorina considers does only a not one consider period strategic model, he relationship between split-tickets and the mid-term cycle. the majority Second, voting. does to in the and more Third, not four address since the IHE MODEL WITH COMPLETE INFORMATION 2. To facilitate intuition, Section 3 several restrictive assumptions are relaxed. In 2. we first present a simple version of the model. Assumptions and Institutional Setup 1 We consider two-party systems in which the parties candidates) have policy preferences. parties and the voters have In particular, unidimensional, (identified with the we assume that continuous, single strictly concave utility functions over a single policy issue. periods utility and factor (3^1. functions the utility functions are All In each period point. objectives written intertemporally are t, = t = u(x^, e^) has 9 9 and 9 objective an function distribution of voters' interval = I and There are two discount with labelled D and have R, analogous to R (1) are the two bliss points, The population of voters is infinite, . = D, j where x represents the policy issue, < peaked as: u 9 two identical except for the bliss two parties, the 1,2, additive the (1), and each voter, with bliss indexed by point 9 i, The . bliss points is uniform and normalized in the closed We also impose the unrestrictive assumption [0,1]. with < < 9 D < 9 R 1. the In voters are information model complete common control of policy, knowledge. it Thus, Alesina would be (19S8). In if preferences of both parties and the follows its ideal policy sub-game perfect equilibrium in in the fact, no a (9 in or 9 office ). has complete This is the only finitely repeated electoral game as shown other policy implemented by the elected party, its ideal policy when in office. party Thus, announced prior to elections given that the party can choose rational voters would not believe in any announcement other than the party ideal policy. Our model of institutional structure posits that policy is determined by between "compromise" a Let legislature. dropped where = V turnout, 1 - is V V be to D,R, no possibility of confusion. president, is those of the votes of subscripts Time are Since we assume full actual the and proportion the elections. When D . = J , president the legislative the in j there preferences of define us party by obtained the policy, x is , as follows: x° = 6 + kV D When R holds the presidency, x'' the policy x = e kV = e R (2) . R D is given by: , - k(l-V (3) ) R R We also impose the condition :S !k < - '@ <4) . D R which implies that the policy outcomes are in the interval [9 ,9 D R T) X < any for x V 6 legislature The is elected representation in a single national district. proportional strict by The president and that ] 'R elected by is majority rule. We consider several electoral scenarios. to mimic the United States case; the legislature elected are The most general one is meant in this scenario, contemporaneously; at at the executive and t=l, t=2, there is another legislative vote, while the president elected at t=l remains in office. is, president the serves two periods while the That serves legislature one period. Each voter moves in Randomization is ruled out. DR, or RD, where the first both periods. A voter The first period move letter represents the is can vote D or indicated as DD, presidential choice, R. RR, the second the legislative choice. single choice between D or R describes the A move in the second period, when only the legislature is chosen. period D 1, period 2 in if president, R R period in 2 if Thus, "RR in president," D illustrates an example of a voter strategy. Note strategies that do reflect not the conditional strategies in the second period. is learning no election at t=2. and shares from first the Who holds the presidency is the only information relevant for voter period. there vote on not entire the true not only because is legislature up is for Policy at t=2 depends only upon who holds the presidency size the because also but This of the legislative majority at t=l. The preceding including the assumption that the party ideal policies are fixed, discussion, implies that any finite numbers of repetitions of this game can be captured with a two period analysis. 2.2 Definitions Equilibrium: To focus on Nash equilibria that correspond to intuition, we consider the equilibria which are in the core or the Von Neumann Morgenstern abstract our game stable set (1989), which we now define. Let of an be z for the individual dominance strategy, relation be Z i's proposed (nonempty by and Greenberg compact) 1 strategy set, Z the Cartesian product of where M denotes the set of players. and S' denote subsets of the Z and z an element , Let u (z) denote i's utility under M. Consider the abstract system (W,<): W = {(S,z) For (S' ,z' ) and (S,z) in W, I S c M, S ?= } of z. Z , S (S'.z') (S,z) < oScS', u (z) > for all u (z') 1 i eS 1 i and • = z z' 8 for all J «£ S. The core of the system is the set of undominated elements B = W\A(W) . • B, where A(a)={beW|b<a) and for some subset K£W, A(K) = u{A(a)|a€K>. is, is an vN&M abstract a set K Moreover, stable set if K = W\A(K). K is internally and externally stable.) dominance This relation is (That : particularly because appealing Greenberg shows that for a game with a finite number of players there exists a (1989) correspondence between the core and the set of SN equilibria and between the vN&M stable set and the set of CPN equilibria. More specifically, Greenberg establishes the following result: For a finite set of players N, Theorem: (N,z) the elements z of the pairs (i) that are in the abstract core B represent the set of SN equilibria to defined by Z the game N (ii) ; (N,z) appears as an element of an abstract stable set if and only if z is in the set of CPN for the normal form of the game defined for Greenberg' of part s N. proof is for a finite number of players; has not been defined for a continuum of players, recursive The notion of CPN carries through to the continuum trivially. (i) argument. However the stable since it defined set however the proof is based upon a with Greenberg* dominance relation extends the basic intuition of CPN to the continuum case. That is, an equilibrium threaten to deviate from payoff. The requirement CPN is it if no coalition of players can credibly by changing their strategies and improving their of credibility, that is the requirement sub-coalition could threaten to deviate from the original deviation, that no is what distinguishes CPN from SN. apparent when we study the The importance of this distinction will simultaneous election of the become president and the legislature. It will be shown that equilibria in the stable set always yield policy outcomes equivalent to those brought about by a subset of the equilibria that can be described by cutpoint strategies, Definition element An : z of Z is a which we now define. strategy cutpoint contest if there exists 9 such that voters with 6 < an for 9 vote D and electoral voters with 1 9 [The voter type vote R in that contest. 9 > 9=9 does not influence the 1 1 analysis because of zero measure. We denote cutpoints in presidential contests by 9 and in legislative contests by We will show that legislative components of strategies always follow a 9. cutpoint rule. Instead, strategies are possible, in presidential elections, non-cutpoint equilibrium as a result of majority rule. an equilibrium (9,9) exists and there exists Sc[9 ,1], Suppose, 9<9 <1, in the presidential all members of to D for attributed vote R, given 9, u(x ,•) D > u(x ,•) for Then the non-cutpoint strategy where members of S switch S. president even election and, such that S is R '* not pivotal for example, an is also an infinitesimal equilibrium. possibility thus implying a cutpoint strategy. Note to that if these being pivotal, Consequently, a they voters would cutpoint for the presidential vote is the most natural type of equilibrium even though we do not impose this restriction. This lack of restriction in the strategy space makes the statement of propositions and proofs significantly more laborious. Consequently, in the main text we consider only cutpoint strategies. This restriction is dropped in the Appendix. With outpoint strategies, first period equilibrium. ideal points below there are only three types of voters For instance, Equilibrium : the and 9 and RR 9 9. Characterizations critical illustrate To in we have DD voters who have if 9 < RD voters who have ideal points between 8, voters who have ideal points above 2. 3 9 aspects the of consider we model, several institutional scenarios, building up from the simplest one. No Legislature 2. 3. a With no legislative inf luence, (k=0) policy for both periods. elected president the , determines a SN equilibrium exists with outpoint In this case, implicitly defined by: u(0 This the is While if 9 ,0 = u(9 ,9) ) D (5) R standard result of theory of two candidate elections. the 1/2 an infinity of other outpoints also are SN, 5^ 9 is unique a cutpoint under the assumption that no voter uses a weakly dominated strategy. When preferences are symmetric, we obtain: 9+9 ^^ 6 = As a benchmark. Figure lA indicates whether D winning or R winning is £ 9 < 1/2 ^ 9 the SN outcome for 2. 3. b Legislative Elections Let P party R 12 1 - = P u(9 u = A Condition on Dominance presidency the objective function of voter where P : be the probability, holds if 2 R < 1. R D i immediately prior to period in period Using t. t elections, (2) (1), and (3) that the at t=2 is given by: k(l-V R2 ),9 ) + 1 2D (1-P )u(9 = president R is in office or P 2 2 10 + kV R2 if D ,9 (6i) ) 1 is in office. 2 .t-i «* u Pu(e I 11 -k(l-V R 1 ),e) Rt t=l In 11 the objective function of voter At t=l the complete information model P i + can be written as: ID +kV (l-P)u(0 1 ,9 Rt can assume only three values: the equilibrium strategies imply an R victory in the presidential if imply a D victory, they or P =1/2 information model analyzed in Section From case of a in and the strict concavity of (6) In P =1 race, if P =0 incomplete the can assume any value in [0,1]. P 4, tie. (6ii: 1 the function u(*), following the result follows immediately: Lemma 1_ For fixed P voter's indirect utility function on V a , t is Rt continuous and single-peaked. Let us define V in is indirect bliss point for party R' i's s vote as the bliss point when the probability that R wins the presidency V and 1, as voter legislative election when the probability that R wins the presidency the is P, IP presidency is t=2 and as V = Hi bliss Note that V 0. that V the V H2 , when point 1 j=D,R. p is the probability that R wins the independent of the moves to be taken at we drop Thus, the time subscript. We now state our central result concerning voting in legislative elections. Proposition _1_ In period t, for any value of P , ' a necessary and sufficient condition t for (S.z) period t to be undominated by any legislative components (T,y) is: 11 where y differs from z only in the for all measurable T c S such that leT votes R in the legislative election, V (z) p \ ^ V R and R (c; for all measurable L c S such that ieL votes D in the legislative election, V (z) i v'^. R Proof : If satisfied, not is (C) votes D and V (z) V < 1 p i p or either is some LcS such that (b) some TcS such that leT ieL votes R and V (z) > R assume Without loss of generality, . there (a) R R V R (a). By continuity, there exists a R measurable subset of voters switched the period (S,z) does that T' cT whose utility would be increased legislative component of their strategy to t satisfy not condition the is dominated. So an R. The they if proof of sufficiency is immediate. Q.E.D. This proposition implies that, in a SN equilibrium, there are no voters who would like to see a reduction of the share of votes of the party they are voting for in the legislative election. 2. 3. c Legislative elections at t=2 We now establish a result . that resembles the median voter traditional two party electoral models, median voter. In our theorem. policy equals the bliss point of the we have a "pivotal voter theorem" where policy setup, equals the bliss point of the pivotal voter in the legislative election. us define as 6 elections when party Proposition 2: ideal the j In point of the outpoint voter in the Let legislative holds the presidency. Pivotal Voter Theorem e R *" The cutpoint strategy ^ 9 = R :; — ;- 1+k represents president R in office. the unique SN and vN&M for (7) 12 e +k The strategy cutpoint —— 8 = - represents ; 1+k D unique the and SN vN&M for president D in office. (8) e<e=x°<e=x"<e R (9) R D D Proof: For (0,1), g v'-" R and (3) imply (2) 9-e+k „iR _ R k R We use 9 e-e „1D _ R ~ 1 ' _1 k as a shorthand for the cutpoint strategy with 9 By the uniform distribution of voter preferences, 1-9 and 9 for V R J such that V for 9 (9 = V ) (10), 1 ^R= , I^' show that 9 satisfies involves measurable deviations from 9 then, (1,9 9 + k ^0= -W It is direct (C) for (1,9 ^''^ ) s and that any fails to satisfy (C). z * 9 , that (1,2) By Proposition does not. Hence, R ~ by Greenberg' to use single-peakedness R belongs to the core and any (I.z), ) R Substituting are given by: R 1, . J Assume president R is in office. to 9 we obtain that the unique outpoints 9 9 1) - 1 the cutpoint. J = 9 for 6 R J in = V as ! J R (Lemma ,,„, (10) D theorem, 9 represents the unique SN. The proof of (8) parallels that of (7), substitution of into (2) and and 9 9 R 12 and (9) follows immediately from (3). D Q.E.D. This result establishes that the policy outcome equals the ideal point of the voter at the legislative cutpoint. Every voter on the left of cutpoint would want a policy more on the left, 13 thus a reduction in V. K the and vice versa. This proposition also shows that voters use the legislative election to president's incumbent the pull preferred policy. legislature That from the period the For this reason, president. the away second the in is, moderate to policy incumbent's voters a most use the party receives more votes in the iegislative elections when it does not hold the presidency than when it does. and of Note that Proposition 2 holds regardless of the positions relative e median the to voter; the R D pivotal f voter is always J- even if the two parties are both located to the interior to the two parties, same side of the median. both If parties are same the to side of median, the an immediate corollary to Proposition 2 is that the more extreme of the two parties can never win control of the legislature. are on opposite sides of the median, legislature. and legislative For expositional purposes, the opposition can gain control of the elections at t=l consider the first period election in isolation. presidential vote for strategies M > 1/2, (that is, § . let us consider first the case the president and the legislature serve one period. If: if the two parties "Divided government" becomes a possibility. Presidential 2.3.d On the other hand, in which both This implies that we can Let M be the Republican z. < 1/2 with outpoint strategies) R is elected president. M Rz = 1/2, (that is, held, M < 1/2, 6 = 1/2 with outpoint strategies) a lottery is R is president with probability 1/2, (that is, 9 > 1/2 with outpoint strategies) D is elected president. 14 We first establish a useful preliminary result. Proposition 3 Any pair (I,z) is always dominated in a tied presidential election. Proof See Appendix : The basic intuition of the proof is that the voters can more effectively moderate election. which executive the Thus, imply moderation: is tied presidential a sure winner follows that a it there if with tied a no the "optimal" presidential distribution symmetric a about presidential the race is always dominated by strategies result holds even with complete symmetry; preferences, uncertainty race that is, voter of amount legislative of cannot be This SN. even with symmetric voter ideal points, party and locations symmetric around the median voter. If SN equilibria exist they imply either D legislative outpoint winning the presidency with a and/or R winning the presidency and 9 9 . Proposition 4 A necessary and sufficient condition for a pair (I,z) to be SN is either 1. and M Hz >l/2(Ris ; the legislative component of z is 6 (the following conditions + k if 9 i 9 D , R [l.Ai] e insure that 9 is l.B + k < if 9 9 D [l.Bi] [l.Bii] the following ^ condition is not satisfied: there does not exist x , R =9 D X = V 1 + R - R [l.Biii] u(x*,9' kV + 9 9' R ) = u(9 ,9' ) R 15 , 9' ~ —R -\ i "*"K not dominated by electing D -. 2 > R = R president) l.A 9 " president) which satisfy [l.Biv] e' > -. 2 . , e +k M 2. < Rz 1/2; the legislative component of z is § —-. —1+k = In addition, ; D z must satisfy conditions symmetric to those given for R president. Proof See Appendix. : Corollary There is a unique SN outcome when either 9 i 1/2. 1/2 or 9 :s D R The corollary have we that shows unique a when SN both legislative outpoints are to the same side of the median, with the cutpoint closer to the median corresponding to the stable outcome. the same side of the median whenever the Of course, both outpoints are to two party bliss points are the to same side of the median. Remarks 1. ^ (x +9 )/2 s (x +9 )/2 = d. D Analogously, r. domination for of 9 The relationships — = r + (9 +k)(l+k) = ^ ^^^^ (2-k)(l.k) 1/2, r and d= 9 < parameter regions where a SN exists. can be seen that for small far from the k 1/2, d > to the amount then define 9 the D These are shown in Figure IB for k=0. the parties and "objecting" The of 16 moderation 2. reasonably symmetric about both R winning median, winning the presidency are SN. relative ' -k)(l+k) + (9 +k)(l-k) R median, = 9' (2-k)(l+k) (9 '^ median but have I- 9 (1-k) the would we we obtain: After simple algebra, o ^ It 9' condition [l.Biii] becomes ^ * = In the case of symmetric preferences, the party is presidency too possible, far to and D from the upset the presidential victory of with k>0, parties the For other party. this situation cannot occur, 0.4), all the close larger values of as illustrated by Figure IC. around symmetry full to (such as k In fact, for median and the sufficiently close to the median, a SN does not exist. 2. Examination of the conditions in Proposition 4 thus shows that the Greenberg core to voting game this empty, can be or be characterized by two outcomes. outcome, characterized by one be that conditions however, Note, for domination of an equilibrium with an R president imply that voters [l.B] » with points ideal below the policy (x be to ) implemented if becomes D president are required to vote R for Congress as domination occurs. voters are not behaving consistently with condition (C) consistent behavior implies that they should vote DD. Such Proposition of (See Figure 2. 1: Thus, ) the absence of a core for some parameter values is not troublesome if we can show elimination that either 6 or 6 R D of this kind of inconsistency always reestablishes policy outcome in the vN&M abstract stable set. as a f J This is precisely the implication of the following proposition. Proposition 5 An abstract (I,z). The winning the stable pair(s) set (I,z) presidency always exists which are with contains and in the certainty and stable 9 set as the at least must have cutpoint one pair party R of the legislative elections and/or party D winning the presidency with certainty and 9 Proof: as the cutpoint of the legislative elections. 14 See Appendix. Corollary There is a unique vN&M outcome when either 17 9 ^ 1/2 or 9 ^ 1/2. Remarks A pair 1. implying a tie in the presidential election is not in (I,z) the stable set. The only pair(s) (I.z) included in the set election and a policy outcome of presidential ' ^ ^ symmetric preferences, In the case of 2. or 6 R imply a certain . D the analogs to (12) and (13) are: + 9 ^ , D (2+k)(l+k) +k) (9 equations + 9 (1+k) (2+k)(l+k) r'=l/2 and d'=l/2 define, winning the presidency with outcome members of abstract the (14) ° d'= The +k)(l+k) (e R _ 9 stable set. R (15) respectively, the and D winning with 9 regions where R are supported by D Figures ID least one of the two outcomes is always supported. and illustrate IE that at When the two parties are reasonably symmetric about the median, both are supported. Thus, in summary: DR2 If (i) 9 < party R wins the ^presidency with certainty, - :£ and the equilibrium outcome is unique. (ii) If > - party i 9 D wins the presidency, and the equilibrium outcome is unique. (iii) If 9 < D - < R the presidency with 9 9 is as there are two possible equilibria. 9 2 as in (ii), If the parties' but, in ( i ) In one R wins and in the other D wins the presidency and depending on parameters, only one of these may be vN&M. (iv) bliss points are symmetric about the median (9 + =1) 9 and preferences are symmetric, D R In cases tickets for 9 RD split party and (iii) of the there is always split ticket voting. (iv), ^ and DR split > tickets for 9 receives president winning are both equilibria. and 9 9 D votes fewer < That ^. the in We have is, the legislative elections than in the presidential election. In the less realistic cases legislative knife-edge case of 2. President 3e President period serves may be on either side of the 9 voting ticket Split outpoint. and (ii), (i) will occur except in the 1 the 9 = 9. and two legislature periods elected with simultaneously additional an in period legislative ; election in 2. With no uncertainty the outcome of Presidential election is known before Since no information is revealed by the first the first period elections. period elections, voters' behavior does not change in the second period. This implies that the equilibrium cutpoints in the legislative elections in the two periods are identical. More precisely, the two period case. case the strategies it can be shown that Proposition 4 and 5 generalize to Proposition 4 applies identically except that in this z of characterized by either § except that components the pairCs) characterized include (I,z) or 9 (I.z) by legislative two Proposition . in the either 9 5 stable or 9 still set . components applies have Proofs two of both identically legislative these two Propositions for the two period case are very similar to the proofs in the Appendix and are available upon request. Based upon these results the following proposition is immediate: 19 Proposition 6 With complete information, identical in both periods; 3. equilibrium in legislative the vote is there is no mid-term congressional cycle. GENERALIZATIONS OF THE COMPLETE INFORMATION MODEL This section shows that our results survive, at least qualitatively, if we relax several simplyfying assumptions adopted thus far. i) We Impact of the legislature on policy. can relax the assumption of linearity and postulate given by: that policies are ' , x" DDR = x° = e + g (V e R . - g (i-v R R (16) • ) (17) ) where g (•) and g (•) are strictly increasing in their arguments, and twice differentiable, = and g (0) g (0) = 0. o R also assume that for every value of V In keeping continuous with (4), we the following holds: R e+g(V)<e DDR R -g(l-V)R (18) '^R a) Distribution of voter ideal points. We now assume that this distribution is continuous and twice differentiable on [0,1]. Consequently, if 9 is a outpoint, V = we can write, l-H(e) (19) R where H is strictly decreasing and twice differentiable. Even Proposition under 1 these general remains unaffected: assumptions, one important feature preferences are single-peaked in V of and a necessary condition for SN equilibria in the legislative elections at t=2 is that the equilibrium policy equals the ideal point of the pivotal voter. 20 For suppose D holds the presidency. instance, x° = e = e +g D Then. (i-H(e D D D satisfies the following: 9 ^^ (20) )) An analogous result holds when R is in office: x'' = G = e -g (H(e R R R (21) )) R Since g (•) and g (•) are strictly monotone, R the implicit functions and (20) D unique imply (21) Proposition V , for x D and x R Note . that is maintained here. also is It immediate proof the relies only on the single-peakedness of voters' 1 which solutions of preferences on establish to R the following inequalities: 9 < The first and 9 < 9 third inequalities follow continuity of the distribution voters' will always exist some 9 < R D D (22) R immediately from the assumption of ideal points, voters who want which implies that there "moderate" to the president. second inequality follows from (18) and from the fact that V ^ indicates the legislative vote for party R when president D is j > V R R where V , and legislative elections are in office. possible equilibria, both with ticket splitting voters. wins the presidency and 9 is the cutpoint of the d and e when presidential As before, simultaneously, held \ R R Condition (22) also implies that the results of sections 2.3c, also apply (qualitatively) in the general case. The there are only two In one equilibrium R legislative election. In R the other D wins which, as before, the presidency and 9 is used to moderate is the cutpoint for the president. the legislature, The argument used previously to rule out tied presidential elections continues to hold. Finally the conditions under which the two possible equilibria are SN or vNScM are However in general the different from those derived in Propositions 4 and basic features of these conditions should be 21 unchanged: 5. for instance, more unbalanced the toward candidates relative to the median voter, the presidency and with particularly evident if g (O = g (•). presidents two can be degree of asymmetry in the whether affects or 9 president paribus, R it is This moderated. represent of examined is that R wins the legislative Section in * g (•) g (•) influenced by there is stable outcomes. legislature the with fact, In • the than J' • . ceteris then, D, say, if, likely that the equilibrium with R president and is most is 2 with respect to the median and 9 9 together asymmetry, D more the due to the different degree in which location of 9 R likely it instead, If, bliss points of the outpoint case the an additional asymmetry in the system, the the more equilibrium the similarity This elections. is are left the the 9 R This is because the voters could more legislative outpoint is vN&M stable. easily achieve easily or' outcomes "moderate" influenced by electing by legislature. the the president general, In mid-term cycle in congressional votes is ruled out may it impossible to derive these conditions analytically. As by who be is difficult in Section the more 2, assumption a of complete information. THE MODEL WITH UNCERTAINTY 4. This section considers an example in which the distribution of voters' preferences is perturbed by a random shock. equilibrium with a mid-term cycle. the simplest Section 2. with case, all the We To construct simplifying show the existence this example, assumptions and of an we return to notation of We also assume quadratic preferences: = u tj - )^ (l/2)(x -e t J j ^ = D,R,i (23) The extremes of the uniform distribution of voters ideal points are now given 22 by I = where a 1+a] [a, uniformly on the interval random variable with zero mean distributed a is with: w] [-w, w<e<e<i-w D both any realization of a for Thus, sides of and 9 6 R there are voters with bliss points distribution The . (24) R of a "common is on knowledge". D Independent draws of a are made at t 5 and ]_ voter types is contained in the interval = I = t_ 1+w]. [-w, equilibrium strategies are specified in terms of The set of possible 2. I section, this In Finally we assume that . w voters cannot communicate their preferences to each other. Consider first parallels Section the 2. 3. c. legislative elections at t = analysis The 2. which now The Republican vote for the legislature, depends on the realization of The expected utility of is denoted V (a). a, R voter i, with a bliss point such that B 6 1 RID 9 :£ 8 :£ when a president R is in office in period 2 is given by: IT Eu " - 41 2 1 An analogous expression for Eu - e kCl-V (a)) ^a 2w - 9 R R I 1 (25) 111 Assumption holds if president D is in office. Voters with bliss points (24) is key 1-w, by observing their own preferences and knowing that the random variable a is to (25). distributed uniformly, value of a would update, and, dominant strategies for every realization of Thus, Denote with 9 the presidency. such that 9 as a result, < w or 9 > their expected Condition (24) implies that these voters have would not be zero. respectively. 9 a: they always vote RR or DD their updating does not affect the equilibrium analysis. the legislative cutpoint in period 2 when party Also let denote EV i's indirect bliss point j holds for R' The t=2 R expected vote at t=2 when party j has won 23 the presidency at t = l. results for the second period subgame are given in the following proposition. Proposition 7 sufficient necessary and A condition for (S.z) be to undominated in the t=2 sub-game is: for all measurable TcS such that ieT votes R, EV-'(z) £ Ev'-' for all measurable LcS such that ieL votes D, EV-'(2) i Ev'"'. Moreover, ~ Q -, MM is the unique SN equilibrium when a f president R is in office r- l+k e +k ~ —D—r = R2 is the unique SN equilibrium when a president D is in office :; l+k D2 X —R = R2 R R e R — = - = —— + j- is the policy with a R president ka .-':' e +k X e* = ECx'^^) R2 is the policy with a D president ka + j- ; 9* D2 = E(x°^) See Appendix. Proof: analogy with The the complete information case policy is equal to the ideal policy of the pivotal voter Let us now turn to the first period election. that is or § (6 In order to expected the ). simplify the analysis we introduce a useful assumption: Al at t=l, the second period strategy components are restricted to the SN strategy in the t=2 subgame. In period period 2. Al 1 is voters' decisions depend upon the expected equivalent to assuming that in period 24 1 policies in voters expect the policies corresponding to the SN outcome for t=2. convenient to express is It presidential context, construct expected an where as P(e), equilibrium the probability of an R victory P, such is 9 that P e the presidential outpoint. Let (0,1). EV iP (Q) the in We will denote i's R vote bliss point for legislative the elections at t=l given 6. Proposition (7) can be directly extended to show that: Lemma 2 condition for A necessary and sufficient (S,z) to be undominated for a given and fixed 6 is for all measurable TcS such that ieT votes R in the t=l legislative (cM elections, ^^^^^ EV (z) s EV and R R for all measurable LcS such that i€L votes D in the t=l legislative elections, EV (z) i EV^^^^^ R R Using Lemma 2 and the results developed in the certainty model, the following result is immediate: Lemma 3 For (I ,z), given fixed 8, the only undominated outpoint at t=l, 8, is given by: 9 = P(9)9 + R i-po; Condition (26) and the uniform distribution of 25 9 (26) D a imply: e - :S - W 2 (2 + w - e ) K 2w e(e) = + k + e e D i-w<e<-+w D (27) + k) (1 + w £ 9 The next result follows immediately from (27). Proposition 8 Given , ! < P(6) < 1, '',.,. <. necessary condition for non-domination for 9 fixed a is that the unique legislative cutpoint 9 satisfies the following: e That is, satisfying (C ) e < 9 < D2 (28) R2 with uncertain presidential elections implies a mid-term congressional cycle: the president always has the party of lower expected plurality in mid-term legislative elections than in the legislative elections held at the same time as the presidential elections. The intuition of this result is straightforward. ^ voters with bliss points such 9 that 9 9 < i follows: in identity, these voters vote R for the first period 9 9 < 9 > the act as president's implies This ) then D 1 about legislature. the (and D2 uncertainty under 9 D2 9 < 1 say, If that they would want to "moderate" a D president despite the fact that they are taking the risk of making a R president less constrained, if R wins. D behavior for Congress, cannot be reducing thus rational, Analogous argument holds for 9 the > 9 . R2 moderation 9 < 9 D2 of cannot Finally note, 26 the president. be D an from (27), in the they switch to second period, when they know that a D president is in office, voting Then, This equilibrium. that if P(9) = 1 (or about = P(e) we have 6 = 9 0), presidential the (or outcome, = 9 R2 e cutpoints legislative the as in the complete information model, both periods; with no uncertainty^ Thus, ). D2 are the same in we do not have a midterm cycle. Let us now turn to (S,z) undominated when presidential the P(-) < < 1 vote. A necessary condition for is obviously for all measurable TcS such that ieT votes R in the presidential EU (R president legislative components of z) election, ^ EU (D | president legislative components of z) I for all measurable LcS such that i€L votes D in the presidential EU (R president legislative components of z) election, | i EU (D president legislative components of z) I Equating expected two the utilities presidential election cutpoint .k9 (C p ka - iK 9 i+k f k(l-9) + 9 + 9 < D We now 9 < /3 + R 6 we find the 6 + k + ka - d+k] (29) 9 2k(l+k)^9 9 2(l+k)(l+k+3) Note that 9 Al, is: + k 9 D 9(9; using ka - 9 1+k D The unique solution of (29) + D ka + and ). by solving the following: 9 + in < D 9 < 9 (30) R . R develop an important condition components given the legislative vote. R is president for strategies z. 27 on the presidential strategy Let P(z) denote the probability that Lemma 4 Given that the legislative components of strategies are fixed at 9, 9 D2 __» 9 necessary and a , R2 (T,y) when P(z) < < sufficient 1 and condition P(y) < < 1 for is (S,z) undominated be to by ^ that the presidential component of 2 is represented by the outpoint 9 given by (30). Proof Except : for voter the type 9=9, voters all ~* ~ 9, election have strictly dominant strategies given 9 . ~* and 9 R2 1. presidential the in D2 if < P(') < - ;. . Q.E.D. ,; . , (9,9) D R Since (30) is monotone on is immediate to show that interior solution A2. 9(9 ) > R and (27) have a solution. (30) if: - - 2 " • w and 9(9 ) D Using (27) and (30), and (9,9) D R and Q{Q) 6 < - is monotone, it There is a unique, . ,. . _ + w. 2 one can readily write the assumption explicitly in terms of the parameters of the model. In fact, by doing so it can be checked that the range of parameter values for which A2 is satisfied is quite large. We are now ready to establish the following result. Proposition 9 If A2 holds, pair of the form an abstract stable set exists. ,z). (I w outpoints 9 and 9 D2 Proof: , and 9 , This pair is denoted This set contains a unique ,z (I ) given by the unique solution of given in Proposition ^ ^ 7. See Appendix. 28 and corresponds to the u (27) and (30), and 9 R2 Remarks 1. Even when A2 is satisfied, the presence incomplete of for some parameter values, This information. can there is no SN in demonstrated be assigning fixed numerical values to the parameters of the model, "•" and (30) for the two t=l search, have increase an using computer grid outpoints and then finding, have expected in follows it outpoints that voters all utility higher Since utility. than the in at the every set of parameters satisfying A2, If and only if 9 R election. In +9 D =1 interval " spanned outpoints. quadratic have by Hence (1,2 we conjecture "'" the that, ) is for there is no SN. there is no split ticket voting in the first case this voters all On the basis of our computer analysis, dominated. period solving (27) alternative "*" outpoints such that voter types at the "'" outpoints utility, 2. by simple only, algebra on and (27) (30) establishes that: _• = e = -.» e 3. . If -•1 9 > ^. that DR, DD. is -"1 P(9 < ) -• voters: RR, If 9 ^, 1 (32) 2 the equilibrium implies In addition, -• presidential election (i.e. the RD, DD. Thus the fraction of those voting for the a presidential candidate more likely to win. the types of 1 ^ the three types are RR, < voters who split their ticket are always is three larger |6 ~ the 1 oP less uncertain the larger the fraction of split tickets. 4. <?(•)< An interior solution with uncertainty" in the sense that A2 is this occurs are shown in Figure 3A. which A2 is violated. and (30). In this 1 occurs only if there is "enough satisfied. Parameter values for which Figures 3B and 3C illustrate cases in Figure 3B shows an unstable interior solution to (27) case voters can achieve an equilibrium outcome with no 29 uncertainty the in presidential The election. heavy black lines Infinity of outpoint outcomes that correspond to the two vN&M show and 9 (9 R the game of complete information. the that sense the of ) D The interior intersection is unstable in outpoints defined by the solution to Figure Finally, dominated. "credibly" an 3C (27) illustrates and (30) absence the are an of The heavy black line now indicates a vN&M where the party interior solution. closest to the median wins the presidential election with certainty. 5. A necessary condition for A2 is given by the relative slopes of - 9 (9 This condition (30). is: w R > „ D For ?r^—2(1 + k + p) ; , (27) and k)k - 9 fixed, 9 , D R the largest ^ w needed to satisfy this inequality occurs for some value of k intermediate between and As 1. Since there predominant. k is influence executive 0, -> little scope for moderation, incentive to engage in strategic voting. As k -> - 9 9 legislative influence there becomes is little its maximum value, , 'D 'R the policy on on policy becomes predominant. The legislative vote can be used to achieve almost any desired expected policy outcome. The expected outcome will not be greatly influenced by the presidential outcome. Again there little is incentive to eliminate the uncertainty in the presidential election. 6. The case in which both the president and legislature are elected every period is obtained by setting p = case describe applies to the this electoral case as in (30). equilibrium Note well. The cutpoints every in that in this (9 Proposition period. case and 9) in this assumption Al 9 is irrelevant. 5. This paper extends the CONCLUSIONS spatial theory 30 of voting to an institutional structure in which policy choices are a function of the composition of A game between the voters legislature and of the executive. the considered; is institutional setup in which the policy outcome depends upon in fact, in an relative plurality, voter each incentives has to strategic be since the outcome depends upon how everybody else votes. with consistent States and perhaps some parameter values, patterns the model a voting of behavior predicts: United the in where the mid-term and c) the executive is and legislative the very pervasity of are elected not the mid-term cycle the United States which occurred even in those cases where there was appears who about far be to for b) split government with different parties controlling One caveat simultaneously. uncertainty be The split government prediction would also apply to nations electoral cycle. France to split-ticket voting; a) the executive and holding a majority in the legislature; like appear democracies in which the executive is directly in other instance, For elected. observed some which implications testable several has model The would richer win than the the presidency. standard Thus, this competitive party two while in little model model, future work would hopefully lead to a more complete model. In First, fact, several extensions of the basic model should be possible. abstentions should be considered as an additional moderating device, for instance if supporters of the winning presidential candidate do not vote in legislative elections. Second, rather than strategic one could consider a party's platform as a strategic variable, an exogenously variables if given parties can ideal point. make binding These platforms precommittments to become their preelectoral platform or if these precommittments can be achieved if the two 31 parties select candidates in primaries with bliss points corresponding to the desired platforms. election, party the If the two candidates choose, [See Wittman platforms. (1977, would want "moderate", platform their moderating these to as in presidential the in general, strategies. In fact, our Thus, Needless candidates would expected the the in a model with there would platforms and two model. before non fully convergent (1985).] between the in policies preferences, 1988) and Calvert always be voters with ideal points choosing choose and there is uncertainty about voters' no legislature, voters credibly can to take these say, account influence of in of the legislature may create an incentive for the two parties to diverge even more, if they know that whichever party holds the presidency must compromise with the legislature. this model may have implications for the issue of entry of third Third, parties [Palfrey (1984), Greenberg and Shepsle (1987)]. which the median. ideal The points "threat" of of the two entry of parties a are third on party Consider the case in opposite in the sides middle of the pursuing "moderate" policies may be reduced if the voters can achieve some degree of moderation of policy in a two party system. Fourth, parliamentary the basic idea of strategic moderation could also be applied to systems, where the executive Strategic voting would be even more essential is in not directly elected. 1 8 multi-party parliamentary system where the coalitions of parties which can be formed in the legislature depend upon the distribution of seats or of vote shares. 32 ENDNOTES For example, see Kramer For surveys of this literature see Enelow (1973). and Hinich (1984) and Ordeshook (1986). The existence "polarization' of American in documented by Poole and Rosenthal (1984a, 3 politics widely been has 1985). b; This phenomenon has occurred repeatedly in the United States and recently in France with the "cohabitation" of Socialist President and a conservative a legislature. 4 Erikson coattails tests (1988) alternative other and explanations of the mid-term cycle and finds that they are not supported by the data. Me show that moderating behavior is incompatible with an equilibrium result of a tied Presidential election. A more general interpretation of the parameter k would be given by writing k as a function of 9 and 9 R as follows: D k = t/((e R with <!//(•)< 1 for :£ ^ 9 .e )(9 -e R D 1 and (F.i) ) D :£ R 9 This 1. :£ clarifies the effect of the legislature on policy outcomes as the ideal policies of exogenous in this paper, the two specification '^ D parties. ^ Since and 9 a function of taken are 9 as D R the results would be unchanged if we used F. 1 for k. A much more insightful and important role would be played by the functional dependency of k on 9 and 9 endogenously chosen as in Wittman in a (1988) point in the conclusions. 33 model where and Calvert party (1985). positions were More on this 7 This institutional structure approximates not only the United States system, generally, but, systems all legislative elections; elections the Needless and abstract we say, to case the in many from in particular the district system, aspects, direct Presidential and our model can handle both the cases in which in fact, simultaneous are with France) (e.g. which are they important other staggered. institutional and the fact that Congress is not completely reelected every two years. Q We need only consider measurable subsets since no non-measurable subset can affect outcomes and thus individual utilities. 9 It should be emphasized that elimination of weakly dominated strategies is In fact even though voters with not sufficient to select cutpoint outcomes. bliss points ^ 6^9 respectively) the 1 and D 0^6 1 other have weakly dominant strategies ' ^ R voters do not weakly dominant have (DD and RR strategies in presidential elections. The proposition is not restricted to cutpoint strategies. The proposition is not restricted to cutpoint strategies. 12 ~ Since Moreover, some SN are the it (I,z) z a subset the of vN&M equilibria, (C) 5^ e . Assume (I,z), z * 13 (S,y) is also vN&M. by Proposition is undominated, € K. 9 Since (I,z) does not satisfy R 1, (I,z) satisfy internal stability therefore, 1, ) can readily be shown that there is no abstract stable set with R condition (1,6 < (S,y) where (S,y) i k. (S,y) satisfies But since, (C). To by Proposition external stability cannot be satisfied. Note that in this situation sincere voting, as in Fiorina (1988), would lead to 50-50 splits in both the presidential and legislative vote. 34 14 While we have not proved the abstract stable set is unique, Greenberg (1989) With a finite number shows that K is unique for a finite number of players. of players, we construct can also virtually K with properties a (except for integer problems) to those found for the continuum. large finite but identical properties qualitatative players, of number would there those to be a identical for a Thus, unique developed K with for the continuum. Note case, that even the actual though Proposition 5 holds stable set is not identically identical. In fact, two period the element (S,z), in the Scl of the two period stable set do not fully coincide with the (S,z), Scl elements of the one period stable set discussed in the Appendix. Consider the utility function of voter Setting the first derivative of i. his utility respect to policy equal to zero implies: Imposing the equilibrium condition IT Suppose instead, V R > R V D . This 9=9 implies 9 IDDD = e + g (1-H(e )). leads to (20). that some voters vote R for the R legislature when party R controls the presidency and D when D is president. This strategy is inconsistent with single-peaked individual preferences. 1 Austen-Smith and Banks (1988) have investigated a three party parliamentary system with a strategic voting model. The process that links voting to policy in their model follows an approach that is quite different from ours. 35 REFERENCES Alberto (1988). "Credibility and Policy Convergence in a Two-Party American Economic Review System with Rational Voters", 78, (4), Alesina, . 796-806. Alberto and Howard Rosenthal (1989). "Partisan Cycles in Congressional Elections and the Macroeconomy" American Political Science Review Vol. 83 (June) 373-98. Alesina, , . "Acceptable Points in General Cooperative n-Person Aumann, Robert (1959). Contributions to the Theory of Games in Princeton University Games" Princeton, NJ. Press: . "Elections, Coalitions, and Austen-Smith, iDavid and Jeffrey Banks (1988). Legislative Outcomes", American Political Science Review Vol. 82 (June) 407-422. , Bernheim, Douglas, Bezael Peleg and Michael Whinston (1987). "Coalition 1. Proof Nash Equilibria. Concepts", Journal of Economic Theory Vol. 2, 1-12 (June). , Randall (1985). "Robustness of the Multidimensional Voting Model, Candidate Motivations, Uncertainty and Convergence", American Journal of Politica l Science Vol. 29, 69-95, (February). Calvert, . James and Melvin Hinich (1984). New York Cambridge University Press: Spatial Enelow, Erikson, Vol. Robert 50, (1988). Analysis of Elections. . "The Puzzle of Midterm Loss", Journal of Politics . 1012-1029. Fiorina, Morris (1988). "The Reagan Years: Turning to the Right or Groping Toward the Middle", in B. Cooper et al. eds. The Resurgence of Conservatism in Anglo-American Democracies Duke University Press: Durham, NC. , , Greenberg, Joseph (1989). "Deriving Strong and Coalition Proof Nash Equilibria from an Abstract System", Journal of Economic Theory forthcoming. , Greenberg, Joseph and Kenneth Shepsle (1987). "The Rewards in Multiparty Competition with Entry". Science Review Vol. 81, 525-37 (June). Effect of American Electoral Political . Thomas and Gary Miller (19S8). "The Core of the Constitution", American Political Science Review Vol. 84, 1155-1174 (December). Hammond, . Kramer, Gerald (1973). "On a class of Equilibrium Conditions for Majority Rule". Econometrica Vol. 41, 285-97. . 36 (1986). Peter Game Theory Ordeshook, Cambridge, UK. University Press: and Pol i Equilibrium Palfrey, Thomas R. (1984). "Spatial Economic Studies Vol. 51, 139-56. tical Theory with Entry", . Cambridge Review of , Poole, Keith T. and Howard Rosenthal 1968-1980: A Spatial Analysis", Vol. 28, 283-312, (May). "U.S. Presidential Elections American Journal of Political Science (1984a). . "The Polarization of American Poole, Keith T. and Howard Rosenthal (1984b). Politics", Journal of Politics Vol. 46, 1061-1079. , (1985a). and Howard Rosenthal "A Spatial Model for Keith T. Legislative Roll Call Analysis", American Journal of Political Science Poole, . Vol. 29. 357-84. "The Positive Theory of Legislative Institutions: Shepsle, Kenneth (1986). An Enrichment of Social Choice and Spatial Models", Public Choice 50, . 135-78. Wittman, Donald (1977). "Candidates with Policy Preferences: A Dynamic Model", Journal of Economic Theory Vol. 14, 180-189, (February). . "Spatial Strategies When Candidates Have Policy Wittman, Donald (1988). Enelow, Melvin Hinich, Preferences" in James and eds. Readings in the Spatial Theory of Elections Cambridge University Press, forthcoming. , , 37 APPENDIX Proof of Proposition 3 (The proof is not restricted to outpoint strategies. lottery between two outcomes x u(x",l/2) 1. > R and x D Three cases are possible: . = 1/2 for the median voter.) {Recall that 9 u(x°,l/2). A tie generates a ) Since all voters have identical preferences except for the location of 11 bliss the R u(x ,0 under point, > ) z, must it D u(x ,0 for ) be all ^ 9 that case the Since f. exists there <l/2 ^ presidential the vote that tied is 1 some of these voters must have voted D for president under the D voters switch to R without changing their legislative vote, X such If z. they obtain with certainty. Hence (I,z) is dominated. R D 2. u(x ,1/2) 3. u(x",l/2) = u(x°,l/2); Assume A. < Proof symmetric to case u(x ,1/2). that there this implies that x" are with voters some 1. 1/2 > 9 x°. > who 1/2 > vote for D 1 R president under Since for these voters u(x ,•) z. D u(x ,•), > (I.z) can be dominated if these voters switch to R for president. Assume, B. therefore, that there are no voters with 9 1/2 who vote D > 1 for president under That z. z must is, by condition (C) of Proposition 1, have a cutpoint z must have a cutpoint 9 = 1/2. 9 = Moreover, 1/2. Then there must exist (a) a measurable interval 5 = [5,5], with 1/2 ^ 5 p < D, such that, when the RR voters in 5 switch their legislative votes to 5 < X the outcomes become x such [e,1/2] R that D max[u(x ,'),u(x ,•)]. change their r'd' x , for with x all Consequently, presidential legislative vote to , D. vote d' < x voters S (I,z) is to R d < = x r' r < x and (b) an interval [c,l/2]u[5], ulx"',-] dominated if voters while voters in 5 in switch The construction is illustrated in Figure A-1. A-1 [c, > 1/2] their To prove Proposition we need the following: 4, Lemma A-1 . . ; .. i , For (S.z) (i.e > S£[0,e ), R . ^ ]. r\ i Assume a type 9 ,^ But under e S. = S z, H 1 K 1 must be worse off and since all voters have the same utility function except for the bliss point, ^ R k -^ or X 9 Rl 9 R < e k 9 R2 > i "^ > to be better off either x But for 9 must also be worse off. 9 < all e it must be the case that But to satisfy this condition, . some R dominance is contradicted. is worse off, But since this 9 e S. k R ., Proof of Proposition 4 ,.., Q.E.D. , ,;,,,,. .... We begin by amending the statement of the proposition to permit the use of non-cutpoint strategies The measure of a set S is denoted . a-(S). Conditions [l.Ai] and [l.Biv] become [l.A.i] - 1 M + cr({i: i votes R for president under z and i 6 i votes R for president under z and i € Rz [0,9 )}) > 1/2 R [l.B.iv] -M Rz 1 +cr({i: [0,9' )}) In addition, for 9 k + D a tied 1/2. > 9 = is not [to insure that 9 , dominated by creating R R < presidential race] there does not exist 9" which solves the following maximization problem: 9" = max [l.v] x° = 9 [i.vi] + [l.vii] V [l.viii] sto 9 < x" = 9 - kd-v"^) R R R ^ =1-9 R •^ R kv'^; D T < if, + <p, s (fi s y R (1/2) u(x°,r)+u(x'^,r) = u(9 R and which, in addition, satisfies. A-2 ,Tr) [l.ix] 1 - M + cr({i: Rz i i votes R for president under and z [O.e")}) = 1/2. G Proposition establishes 3 ties that be cannot Proposition SN. 1 establishes that, when the presidential components of strategies result in an R president, domination will occur unless the legislative component obeys in the case of D president, Similarly, SN outcomes correspond to 9 possible ^ the proof being symmetric for 9 R we must have 6 and 9 Therefore, . 9 . R the only We focus on the case of 9 . D R , . First consider domination by strategies that result in a D president and a policy x By Lemma A-1, we need only consider domination via S £ [0,9 . Assume Consider a coalition S=[0,9 -?], l.A. R where members of S vote DR, elected president under resultant policy x also have x < 9 > y, 9 - ^. and > simple algebra shows that by a I-S. If implies l.A. For all members of S to prefer x about strategy y a holding z strategies constant for This can be brought . ? to 9 strategy ). that , D is the we must where some y' R members of S vote DR while others vote DD. That be empty.) is, (The subset of DD voters in S may all coalitions forming intervals can dominate [0,6 -^] R (1,9 ) Condition [l.Ai] determines whether provided D is elected president. R there exists S capable of electing D president. the case that also occurs Consequently, S. [l.Ai] is necessary and domination via shifting the presidency from R to Assume [l.Bii], Sufficiency. l.B. gives V it domination can occur via any subset of such if via Moreover, the Let legislative under obviously domination S, sufficient for D. S=[0,9') vote is and, y. for From ieS, (2), y=DR. the From resultant R policy x is given by [l.Bi], provided assumptions on the utility function and A-3 D is elected [l.Biii], president. By the all members of S strictly prefer x to 9 [l.Biv] shows that D is elected president under Finally, . Condition [l.Biv] is necessary to the election of a D president. Necessity. Conditions [l.Bi] and [l.Biii] are identities implied by the model. But V > - 1 ruled out by the necessity for members of S to be better off under if domination can be achieved with V using the previously defined, (S.y) < 1 - 9 R 6' + is R R other hand, Assume, ~ 9 * therefore that all conditions hold except [l.Bii]. occur, y. + 9' will also it , On the y. R with V R =1-9 +9'. Thus 9 R R cannot be dominated by shifting the vote to D president if and only if [l.Bi] - [l.Biv] are not satisfied.- Remark: If ^ 9 and 1/2 z is condition [l.Biv] cannot be satisfied; presidential a therefore, cutpoint strategy, cutpoints z with 9 all ^ R 1/2 cannot be dominated by shifting the presidency to can be dominated by a tie that leads to a remains to specify when 9 It D. H *.4. D lottery over outcomes x 1 4. < 3- , 9 9 < 3- This z- Moreover, . all 9. < X u(x ,y) =* R 9.< . R R Now R for the unique voter type By Lemma A-1, lottery and 9 x , :£ u(9 ,r) establishes result u(x => R that 3- who is indifferent between the y prefer the lottery to 9 ,Tf)^ we u(9 ,y) ^ u(x ,9.) R need u(9 ,9.), > R 1 consider only If S could cause subset of making all not S voting D members certainty. Hence, members S measure of <p vote of S 1 dominating coalitions where all members must vote D for president and where satisfied. . H [l.ix] is the election to end in a tie with a measurable for president, better off S since could x throw would the be election implemented to D with attention can be confined to coalitions S=[0,3') where all D for president and a (possibly empty) subset of S of votes R for the legislature. Conditions [1. v]-[l. viii] specify a well-defined maximization problem. A-4 The 6" and 9" ip which solve the problem define the dominating coalition need be considered since if smaller coalition that prefers a a Only S. tie can dominate obviously a larger coalition that prefers a tie can also dominate. D If 3u(x ,r)/9(x Remark: R D -SuCx ,9')/a(x :5 ) all symmetric utility functions, it can be R a condition which holds for ), shown that = 0. i^ In other words, the dominating coalition will vote DD. when domination must occur via a tie, Domination via a tie need only be invoked in the knife-edge case Remark: where both [l.ix] holds and there are no measurable R presidential voters in [e".e'). Q.E.D. Proof of Proposition 5 Characterization of an abstract stable set A set and K exists consists of all the pairs (S.z) SSI that satisfy either: 1. The strategy z implies R is president with vote M component of z satisfies > Kz 1/2; for members of S and implies V (C) the legislative and a policy of R X and there does not exist [l.Ai] 6' , X* = 8 kV* + [1. Alii] [l.Aiv] R V*= V + cr({i: R i€S and x' i 9 R - M = u(x, 9' ) i 9'}) ) ieS and cr({i: + Rz and < 1 u(x',9' 1 such that: V , R D [l.Aii] x [0,9' )}) € i votes R for president under z '^ 1/2. > and that there does not exist 9" and T £ S £ [0,9") such that [l.Biii] u(x,9") = u(9 + kV ,9") R D [l.Biv] 1 - M + cr({i: i e Rz z}) = 1/2. A-5 T and i votes R for president under 2. The strategy z implies D is president with vote M component of z satisfies (C) strategy The implies z the legislative 1/2; for members of S and implies a policy of x and z satisfies conditions symmetric to those of 3. < HZ legislative component of z satisfies and a lottery between policies x R with president for tie a 1. for members of Scl (C) and x vote M , = Rz the 1/2; and implies V • D and there does not exist G", , x V , such that either: 3. A [3.Av] = e X kv + R D [3.Avi] = V + cr(U: V R ieS and x ^ B 6"}) < R 1 u(x*,G") = (1/2) u(x^, e")+u(x°, 6") [3.Avii] [3.Aviii] (r({i: and ieS [0,6")}) > votes i R president for under z and e i 0. or 3.B [3.Bv] = e X - k(i-v R ) R V^ = V - cr({i: [3.Bvi] R ieS and x* i 0"}) > 1 [3.Bvii] identical to [3.Avii] [3.Bviii] cr({i: > 6 R ieS and i votes D for president under z and i€(6",l])}) 0. Existence If u(e ,1/2) u(e ,1/2), 2: R cutpoints e it is direct to show that < 1/2, e , satisfies (1). (Note that, since x R u(x ,1/2).) Likewise, 1/2, e , < 9 , D if u(e ,1/2) uO D ,1/2), ^ R e > where (I,z), z has D satisfies (2). Hence K * 0. D A-6 (I,z), u(e ,1/2) > R where z has cutpoints External Stabil ity (C) 1. By not satisfied. Proposition legislative components for ^ is It 1/2. exists there 1 such that € T. i where y differs (T,y), (S.z) possible to find a dominating (T,y) K because cr(T) 6 in Now consider M (T,y). < only from z can be sufficiently small that T is not pivotal in the presidential election. M = either (T,y) satisfies (3) or, 1/2, it does not, if there exists If T' c Rz T, presidential where well as shifted for all icT' and (S,2) (T',y') satisfies as < legislative components of (T'.y'). It follows that (T',y') e K since members of and by construction, (C) strategies are T' prefer the outcome with a certain presidential winner to the outcome with a tie where satisfied and, moreover, unable are to shift the outcome to the is (C) certain election of the other presidential candidate. satisfied 2. (C) A. Conditions [l.Ai] T = {i€S and i€[0,9')}. - [l.Aiv] satisfied and therefore (S,z) K. Let members of T in [0,x In the dominating strategy y, use DD and members of T in (x ,9') use DR. «£ By the construction, ] D is elected president under y and members of T receive higher utility under y than under z. Hence, (S,z) < Moreover, (T.y). (T,y) trivially satisfies (2). Hence - [l.Biv] (T,y)6K. B. Conditions satisfied. [l.Ai] - [l.Aiv] satisfied, not [l.Biii] For T in the construction, members of T continue to vote D in the legislative election and thus satisfy elect a D president. It (C). is also direct to worse off by switching back to R president. belongs to but K. [Note that the By construction, A-7 c T can show that members of T would be Hence, lottery between •^ no T' (T,y) +kV 9 D satisfies (3) and represents the and 9 R R outcome that generates the largest "defection" from S that satisfies (C).] A similar argument applies when D is elected president and (2) is not satisfied. Finally, either S, 3. it is consider the case of a tie for president and (C) satisfied but A or 3.B satisfied. using an appropriate subset of voters in Again, possible to construct a dominating (T,y) that belongs to K. Internal Stability Given that members other of construction used K result that in members of K are obviously stable against satisfied, is (C) (3) the in guarantees that upset by shifting to a certain winner. same presidential presidential Similary, outcome. ties where the other party wins the construction of (1) and presidency. the remains to demonstrate, It without loss of generality, that a member of K satisfying (1) cannot be dominated by a tie that satisfies ties that satisfy [l.Biii] - [l.Biv]. tie that satisfies (C). (C) Then a voter 6" is indifferent between a lottery and in the lottery must be to satisfy Consequently, . vote D in the (C) Moreover, ( I , z) all 6 in the tie, legislative election. dominated by a tie that satisfies (C), Consequently, 4, the policy less than x and the coalition that creates the tie can include only voters in [0,6"). to X other than Let (S,z) satisfying (1) be upset by a By arguments parallel to those used in proving Proposition X. to be guarantee that certain winners in K cannot be dominated by members of K (2) X cannot in K The But < 6" strictly prefer x all defectors must continue then x = x. So if (S,z) is [l.Biii] - [l.Biv] must be satisfied. K is internally stable. in the Stable Set Finally, if S = I and given a sure victory in the presidential election. A-8 the outpoints for the legislative election are either the proof by condition or 6 9 (C). complete We presidential outcome, (I,z) by showing must generality, ^ 9 D T = ^ 9 conditions The 1/2. I, the legislative vote without Assuming, . [3.Av] [3.Avii] - satisfied because there is always some subset of voters in X D (1/2) u(x have Now lottery. the to , )+u(x 9 shown thus , 9 9" that A 3. > 1/2 3.B) (or V>V R [3.Aviii] => [x R is where z leads to a tied presidential race is in of trivially who prefer ] * u(x ,9 T > ) satisfied for S=I. satisfied for S=I. is ,9 D • loss are =»x>x=> T implies [3.Avi] ) tied a + e R cutpoint the represents (I,z) if To satisfy (C) for « K. e satisfy that Hence, no We (I,z) K. Q.E.D. Proof of Proposition The key 7. proof the to is that the realization of only a affects the relative proportions of voters with dominant strategies of voting R and D as a result of (24). It 1. immediate is show to that necessary a condition non-domination of (S,z) is that all measurable subsets of S in [0,9 ] for vote D D and all in [9,1] vote R. R If 2. <?:.(V ) of V R (1. holds, ) (25) can be written in terms of the derived density as R ^V t2 Eu = l+w-9 R RR-R +cr and V = ) l-w-9 RR +cr 0(V )dV - 9 R R V —R where V k(l-V - 9 1 and R =cr{i: cr R R 9 RID >9 >9 and i votes R under z}. 3. Since Eu R is 1 quadratic in V , Eu R A-9 R 1 can be expressed as a function of the mean and variance of V invariant in depend only on EV shown be that is readily shown that the variance of V preferences between alternative strategies By an argument analogous to the proof of Lemma . preferences single-peaked are in EV Proposition . can it 1, follows by arguments directly parallel to the proofs of Proposition Proof of Proposition is R voter Thus, z. It . R then 7 and 1 2. 9. We develop the proof using a restrictive assumption in addition to Al. A3. Strategies z are restricted to be cutpoint strategies. Without this restriction, that used for Proposition the proof requires a construction similar to ^ 5. , , Characterization of an abstract stable set. The abstract stable set K consists of all pairs given either, or, C z, 1 and C p are satisfied for all i (S,z), € any of these conditions are not satisfied for if SSI such that S in the first z, S does not period contain the cutpoints in z that correspond to the conditions that are violated. addition, . It * (I w has z = ,z) 9,9. the second period cutpoints are Remark is direct to show that In D2 R2 the unique member of K of the form ~* _* _* zs(9,9,e,e). D2 R2 /^* External Stability. Assume that (S,z) i K and that there exists a cutpoint ^ contained in S for which the appropriate C condition is not satisfied for one or more two or more contests share an identical exists a Coalition T either of the form all i € Moreover T violate cr(T) cutpoint) [C~c,C] or Then contests. [C.C + c] (c>0) there such that the C condition for one or more contests referenced by can always be made sufficiently small of T reverse their z votes for these contests, A-10 such that, leading to some y, (if <^. when members T satisfies appropriate the Hence, conditions C given T contains < § and y other no cutpoint. e K. (T, y) Internal Stability Without loss assume generality, of 9 opposite the , being case symmetric. is (S.z) (S.z) If 1. K and no cutpoint in z internally stable by A3. (Note: boundary, some T cutpoint the e on is the on a boundary of in S or is if one boundary of S S can in open but is defect still S, another to cutpoint strategy y with A3 satisfied. 2. A3, Lemma 2 and Lemma 4 imply that (S,z) e K is internally stable if (S,z) or its boundaries does not contain both 9 and 9. 3. A3 and Lemma 2 and Lemma 4 further imply that if (S,z)€K and (S,z) where (T,y) -' z = (9 .6 ,9 9' condition is that * 9 D2 ,9 9' , and ) R2 * 9 = y (9' . 9' , 9' D2 . 9' ) R2 necessary ^ a , < This means that y must differ from z in . both t=l components. 4. Assume, therefore, first show that all (S,z ) that the necessary condition internally stable. are must include the half-open intervals defined by 9 the stability property of A2 can be used 9(9') (or Hence, both) is in the direction of 5. " the C conditions are not satisfied on dominated by a member of domination occurs cutpoints with 9' z * z K, that both t=l cutpoints cannot both and 9' We any dominating T and 9 9' and But . cutpoint from the T, implying that or cutpoint. ' (S,z is ) not K. Next consider (S,z) e Assume By A3, satisfied. establish that either 9(9') to the is > 9^. If strictly be are . on a But A-11 (S,z) interior boundary then 9' it e K, to of S. <9^ or is direct to show S. Case members Assume a. of S in a neighborhood of Since T c £ (e'.e'^) 7. * 2. will not be strictly better off with (T.y). 9 Moreover, S. at , one least C is satisfied not on S => the of eie"^) parallel Case to strictly interior to for Hence, (T,y). Therefore, a. (S,z) S, and e"" inequalities therefore that domination is achieved with is s C^ must on S be if (T,y) 6' < 6 ^ . =* b. it thus must be (S,z) e assumption that z * case z . Assume Proof of non-domination K and no t=l outpoint is is internally stable. assume the interior outpoint is 9 the is It z Finally assume one outpoint is interior and the other is not. loss of generality, g"". i eCe"") u that either C Case K. (6^,9') strict. using the stability property of A2, therefore direct to show, or C*" So that This 0^ = 6(9^). fact . Therefore, permits proof of Without For S to satisfy C 9 5* 9(9) from non-domination the in manner parallel to the preceeding paragraph. Thus, all (S,z) 6 K are internally stable. Q.E.D. A-12 , a Strong Nash Equilibna for k = D Strong Nash a: Strong Nash Equilibria for k = 0.4 Strong Nash Equilibria for k = 0.2 1.0 2 5(Jong 0.9- 0.9 ^^ D Strong D Strong Nash/^ Naih 0.8- \ No R Strong Nash Strong Nash 0.8 a; o 0.7- \ R No \ Strong Nash V Strong 0.6 o 0.7 / 0.6- ^ /^Infeasible fork=0.2 X 05- 1 0.0 f- 1 0.2 0.1 Infeasible for k=0.4 0.3 1 0.5 1 0.4 0.0 0.5 Figure 1-B vN&M 1.0" 0.9- Equilibria for vN&M k = 0.2 1.0 N. 0.8- \\ D&R 0.8- \\ o 0.7- R vN&M / ^y^ 0.0 0.7- 0.2 Figure 1-D RvN&M 0.6- = 0.2 050.4 0.5 / ^^y 0.0 / y^ y^ ^ Infeasible for k DvN&M x\ o ^r / \ a: \\ 0.6- 05- \D&R D vN&M \. \ EquiUbria for k = ,04 \ 0.9- \ 0.5 Figure 1-C \ ^\v 1 0.3 0.2 0.1 Infeasible y^ fork = 0.4 0.2 Figure 1-E 0.4 0.5 Figure 2 The Strong Nash Dominating Coalition P This coalition dominates 6p by voting DR <= <^ These voters do not satisfy (C) they vote These voters not in S vote These voters not in S vote D R for the for the legislature legislature =^ when R for the legislature X' The <= % vote e R vN&M Dominating Coalition :This coalition dominates: <= These :p voters must e' DR ^ These voters not in S vote These voters not in S vote D for the R legislature legislature Voters DD to satisfy (C) x= R for the Figure 3 Equilibrium with Incomplete Information k=0.70 k=0.34 e(e) \ .5 -P^ .45 ^9(9) V-^ V' ° e e„ 3-B 3-A m k=0.05 .45 ft(0) — ' 1 6d=-^ L_ «R= ^D ._, ' ^R 3-C Notes: w= 0.05 in Heavy all ^R panels. lines denote equilibria with Presidential winner cenain. e 'r' e Figure A-1 Domination of a Tie When Median Voter is Indifferent at Tie DD switch to RD RR RR voters under switch z to RD + + ^ i/2 = e 1 x°' x° / x^' x^ Defecting CoaHtion LI ^385 UIO Date Due MAY 05 c^'a--?^ 1991 Lib-26-67 MIT LIBRARIES DIJPl 3 I TOAD D057aT7T ^