MIT LIBRARIES 3 9080 02618 2151 LIBRARIES Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium Member Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/liquidityinsuranOOshim ^E'^EY HB31 .M415 ^3 Massachusetts Institute of Technology Department ot Econonnics Working Paper Series LIQUIDITY AND INSURANCE FOR THE UNEMPLOYED Robert Shimer Ivan Werning Working Paper 05-23 September 22, 2005 Room E52-251 50 Memorial Drive Cambridge, MA 02] 42 This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Network Paper Collection http://ssrn.com/abstract=^^HH^ r^ Social Science Research at A (^'\'L^ MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGV i I NOV 1 h 2005 LIBRARIES Liquidity and Insurance for the Unemployed* Ivan Werning MIT, NBER and UTDT Robert Shimer University of Chicago and NBER iwerning@mit.edu shimerOuchi cago.edu First Draft: July 15, 2003 This Version: September 22, 2005 Abstract We study the optimal design of unemployment insurance opportunities over time. absolute risk aversion preferences unemployment, on the duration of the from of this benchmark, more elaborate roles for policy to smooth spell, it is and the desirability workers have constant optimal to use a very simple policy: a constant a constant tax during and When employment that does not depend free access to savings using a riskless asset. Away for constant relative risk aversion preferences, the welfare gains policies are minuscule. toward the unemployed: their consumption; and (b) (a) Our results highlight two largely distinct ensuring workers have sufficient liquidity providing unemployment benefits that serve as insurance against the uncertain duration of unemployment 1 workers sampling job We focus on the optimal timing of benefits of allowing workers to freel}' access a riskless asset. benefit during for spells. Introduction There wide variation is (Figure 1). in the duration of unemployment benefits across In Italy, the United Kingdom, and the United OECD countries States, benefits last for six months. comments from Daron Acemoglu, George-Marios Angeletos, Hugo Hopenlrayn, Narayana Kocherlakota, Samuel Kortum, and Ellen McGrattan, and numerous seminar participants on this paper and an earlier version entitled "Optimal Unemployment Insurance with Sequential Search." Shimer's research is supported by grants from the National Science Foundation and the Sloan Foundation. Werning is grateful for the hospitality from the Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis during which this paper was *We are grateful for completed. . . CO O ^^gc&-SS^& CD Pi *^ :3 forever. b C o — S N <U benefits lapse after one year Which country has standard argument G <U oj ^ '3 — CI. . C — ' S OT f^ Kh "3 'i C Cj C3 rd 2; n° Ph M CO Duration of unemployment benefits and Wages 2002, Table 2.2. *Duration Germany A *^ 1: Benefits In ^^ Qj ii CJ Q Figure d a a 3 •"= ^ S , in select is OECD countries. Source: OECD unlimited in Belgium. and France after five years. In Belgium they last the right policy? for terminating benefits after a few quarters that extending is the duration of benefits lengthens the duration of jobless spells (Katz and Meyer, 1990). But benefits also proAdde insurance unemployed (Gruber, 1997). of optimal Determining which policy Many British, is best requires a dynamic model unemployment insurance. Shavell and Weiss (1979) and Hopenhayn and (1997) develop such models and spell. and help workers maintain smooth consumption while show that Nicolini benefits should optimally decline during a jobless economists have interpreted these results as broadly supportive of the Italian, and American version of unemployment insurance. But they hinge on some subtle assumptions, notably a restriction that the unemployed can neither borrow nor save and so consume dual role: their benefits in each period. This means that unemployment benefits play a they insure workers against uncertainty in the prospect of finding a job and they provide workers with the ability to smooth consumption while unemployed. In this paper, we reexamine the optimal timing by allowing the worker to borrow and save. have of benefits, distinguishing the Our main conclusion sufficient liquidity, in either assets or capacity to is that two roles when workers borrow, a constant benefit schedule of unlimited duration against unemployment temporary drops Our in optimal or nearly optimal.^ The constant benefit schedule insures is risk, while workers' ability to dissave or borrow allows them to avoid consumption. two conceptually distinct results suggest roles for policy toward the unemployed. ensuring workers have sufficient liquidity to smooth their consumption; and sec- First, ond, providing constant unemployment benefits that serve as insurance against the uncertain duration of unemployment This dichotomy spells. Feldstein and Altman's (1998) recent policy proposal for is consistent with the spirit of unemployment insurance savings accounts (see also Feldstein, 2005). We represent the unemployed worker's situation using McCall's (1970) model of sequential job search. Each period, a risk-averse, infinitely-lived unemployed worker gets a wage offer from a known distribution. forever. If she rejects it, Our main purpose is If she accepts the offer, she keeps the job at a constant wage she searches again the following period. to compare two unemployment insurance policies. We begin by considering a simple insurance policy, constant benefits, where the worker receives a constant benefit while she is unemployed and pays a constant tax once she can borrow and lend using a riskless bond. reservation wage although her reservation wage is assets An show that the worker adopts a constant unemployment benefit and the employment duration-dependent consumption level for the that depends on the length of the jobless spell. An tax, a insurance agency dictates a unemployed, funded by an employment tax The worker has no access to capital markets and so must consume her after-tax income in wage the best insurance system possible. of The utility. then consider optimal unemployment insurance. off'ers spell. insurance agency sets the level of benefits and taxes to minimize the cost of providing the worker with a given level of We employed. The worker and consumption decline during a jobless increasing in both the form of moral hazard. We is or randomization schemes, this is each period. Absent direct monitoring of The path unemployment consumption and employment taxes determines the worker's reservation wage, which the insurance agency cannot directly control. It sets this path to minimize the cost of providing the worker with a given level of utility. Our main result is that with Constant Absolute Risk Aversion (CARA) preferences and no lower bound on consumption, constant benefits and optimal unemployment insurance are ^This does not necessarily imply that the Belgian policy notably in the maximum yearly benefit; see on the optimal duration of the optimal level. benefits. In OECD is optimal. Policies differ along other dimensions, Benefits and ongoing work for Wages 2002, Table 2.2. This paper focuses a separate paper we examine the determinants of That equivalent. the cost of providing the worker with a given level of utility is, her reservation wage the same, and the path of her consumption is insurance systems. In both cases consumption the worker unemployed, both during and is can borrow and save, this Our is constraints in the same, the same under both by a constant amount each period that after the unemployment consistent with a constant benefit result that the optimal benefits with borrowing falls is is and spell. When the worker tax. unemployment insurance can do no better than constant and savings contrasts with a large literature on the need for savings dynamic moral hazard models.^ Rogerson (1985) considers an environment which a risk-averse worker must make a hidden employer's profits. He in effort decision that affects her risk-neutral proves that optimal insurance is characterized by an "inverse Euler equation," '\P{l+r)u'{ct+i), u'{ct) where E^ the expectation operator conditional on information available at date is particular, since the function "1/x" is t. In convex, u'{ct)<EtPil+r)u'{c+,). An individual facing this path of consumption would and hence consume less today and more tomorrow "savings-constrained" by optimal insurance. In contrast, in our model a worker is confronted with the optimal unemployment insurance policy satisfies this Euler condition with equality. We also explore optimal insurance We ences. do than CARA tion. And this for two reasons. preferences. We want with Constant Relative Risk Aversion First, CRRA preferences are theoretically (CRRA) prefer- more appealing to explore the robustness of our findings to this assump- second, this introduces a nonnegativity constraint on consumption that limits a worker's debt to the amount that she can repay even in the worst possible state of the world, Aiyagari's (1994) natural borrowing limit. We highlight an interesting interaction between a worker's ability to borrow and optimal insurance. The breaks "A perfect equivalence between optimal down with recent example CRRA is preferences, but unemployment insurance and constant we find that our results with Golosov, Kocherlakota and Tsyvinski (2003), who emphasize CARA benefits provide an that capital taxation may discourage saving. Allen (1985) and Cole and Kocherlakota (2001) provide a particularh' striking example of the cost of unobserved savings in a dynamic economy with asymmetric information. They prove that if a worker privately observes her income and has access to a hidden saving technology, then no insurance possible. is important benchmark. As CARA in tlie case, optimal unemployment insurance dictates a declining path of consumption for unemployed workers and an increasing tax upon reemploy- ment. However, the implicit subsidy to unemployment, the amount that a worker's expected from the insurance agency lifetime transfer rises if she stays unemployed for an additional period, increases very slowly during a jobless spell. By But if its very definition, constant benefits are always at least as costly as optimal insurance. the worker has enough liquidity so as to have a minimal chance of approaching any lower bound on assets, the additional cost of constant benefits weeks (or about 0.01 seconds) of income in our leading example. optimal time-varying and time-invariant subsidy If the worker is is minuscule, The less difference than 10~^ between the also very small. near her debt limit, the difference between constant benefits and optimal is unemployment insurance is larger. This is because benefits are forced to play the dual role of providing insurance and smoothing consumption. However, using benefits to create liquidity in this indirect problem The way is likely to be less efficient than measures designed to address the liquidity directly. general message that emerges from our model should be simple — a constant benefit and tax, is the following. CARA With that unemployment insurance policy combined with measures to ensure that workers have the liquidity to maintain their consumption for these results is level during a jobless the optimal more time. unemployment subsidy risk averse as consumption However, this wealth unemployment spell constant. falls; this effect is explains is able to we note that our use Nicolini (1997) CRRA With why risk; as utility, a consequence, the worker becomes the optimal subsidy increases over small during a typical, or even relatively prolonged, provided the worker Before proceeding, Hopenhayn and is intuition and consumption that utility the fall in assets occurs during an unemployment spell does not affect attitudes toward Our spell. and many smooth her consumption. of a sequential search others, model departs from which assumes that there is only a job search effort decision.'^ There are three reasons for this modeling choice. First, our model produces stark results on optimal policy trinsically useful. On results. Indeed, the in a straightforward way, the other hand, the sequential search model paper most closely related to ours is Werning which we believe is in- not critical for these (2002), which introduces hidden borrowing and savings into the Hopenhayn and Nicolini (1997) search 'Shavell and Weiss (1979) allow for both hidden search effort and hidden is effort wage draws. See model. also exer- Ljungqvist and Sargent (2004). However, both of these models assume that employed workers cannot be taxed and neither examines optimal benefits when workers have access to liquidity. cise 21.3 in and some of his results are analogous to ones we constant benefits and taxes are optimal under monetary. Despite this, and in contrast to benefits are not equivalent to optimal since preferences if the cost of search is our results here, in Werning (2002) constant CARA utility, always desirable to exclude the worker from the asset market. it is Feldstein and Poterba (1984), a unemployment is number empirically relevant. of authors have jobs. The sequential search model Third, the sequential search model is Starting with the work of documented that an increase wage and consequently reduces the benefits raises workers' reservation which they find fact. CARA unemployment insurance, even with Second, the sequential search model at report here. For example, he proves that in rate a natural one for thinking about this is the backbone of most research on equilibrium unemployment. At the heart of the Lucas and Prescott (1974) equilibrium search model and of versions of the Pissarides (1985) sequential search problems. economy More matching model with heterogeneous firms are individual recently, Ljungqvist which each individual engages in and Sargent (1998) examine a large in sequential job search from an exogenous wage distribution. This paper proceeds as follows. Section 2 describes the model's environment and the two we policies der CARA consider. Section 3 then establishes the equivalence between the preferences. Section 4 quantitatively evaluates optimal and optimal constant benefits with unemployment insurance and Two 2 begin describing the two policies There we unemployment insurance highlighting the relationship between hquidity. Section 5 concludes. Policies for the We 2.1 CRRA preferences, two systems un- common Unemployed physical environment of the model. consider, constant benefits We then discuss the and optimal unemployment insurance. The Unemployed Worker is a single risk averse worker who maximizes the expected present value of utility from consumption, CO E_i5;]/3yQ), t=0 where /3 function. < 1 represents the discount factor and u{c) is the increasing, concave period utiUty At the A start of each period, a worker can worker employed at w produces w the cumulative distribution function distribution. The worker observes she accepts w, she and is of the next period. If F.'^ w > Let w units of the consumption In either case, the worker decides The worker cannot The it (3-^ The in the current unemployed consume to recall past If it. at the start at the wage end of offers. is employed does not observe the worker's wage, even after she decides objective of the unemployment insurance agency of providing the worker with a given level of utility. We assume is to minimize the cost costs are discounted at rate -1. Policy 2.2 how much is good assume that an unemployment agency only observes whether the worker to take a job.'' = each period; she in denote the lower bound of the wage she rejects w, she produces nothing and or unemployed. In particular, r or unemployed. the wage and decides whether to accept or reject the period, after observing the wage draw. We good w worker receives a single independent wage draw from employed and produces future periods. all units of the consumption An unemployed never leaves her job. be employed at a wage policy we I: call Constant Benefits constant benefits constant employment tax f, is defined by a constant and perfect access unemployment benefit to a riskless asset with net return r = j3~^ 6, a — 1, subject to a no-Ponzi-game condition.^ Since the worker's problem is stationary we present it recursively. Start by considering a who is employed at wage w and has assets a with budget constraint a' = (1 + r)a + w — f ~ c. Since /3(1 + r) = 1, she consumes her after tax-income plus the interest on her worker assets Ce{a,w) = lifetime utility is ra +w— f, so that assets are Ve{a,w;T) F = kept constant, ^— . a' = a. This means that her (1) finite expectation and that there is some chance of drawing a some w > 0. ^If the wage were observable, an unemployment insurance agency could tax employed workers 100 percent and redistribute the proceeds as a lump-sum transfer. Workers would be indifferent about taking a job and hence would follow any instructions on which wages to accept or reject. This makes it feasible to obtain the first best, complete insurance with the maximum possible income. Private information is a simple way to prevent the first best, but other modeling assumptions could also make the first best unattainable, e.g. ''We assume that positive wage, so is F{w) < continuous and has 1 for moral hazard among employed workers. ^That is, debt must grow slower than the interest rate, linit-^ao{i + T)~^at > 0, with probability one, where at denote asset holdings. Together with the sequence of intertemporal budget constraints this is equivalent to imposing a present-value lifetime budget constraint, with probability one. Next consider an unemployed worker with assets a and and lifetime utility, given policy parameters b I4(a; where If a' = (1 6, = y°° max jmax f) + r)a + h — c. unemployment benefits is 6, r) denote her expected "(^" , ^) +_^^- | dF{w)., c and saves a' in (1). solution to the Bellman equation defines the worker's Cu{a), reservation wage u)(a), and next period's assets Otherwise, she the current period, and remains unemployed into the next period, obtaining expected continuation utihty The \4(a';6, f). unemployment consumption conditional on this period's a' {a), Given these objects, the cost of the unemployment insurance system assets. (2) worker chooses whether to accept a job or not. given by Ve{a,'w:f) in equation consumes 6, 14 (a; This must satisfy the Bellman equation + /?\4(a^ 6, f )) An unemployed she does take the job, her utihty collects {u{c) f. let is defined recursively by S{a] b,T) A = lb+ worker with assets a of the fails is F{iu{a)) is the unemployment benefit b plus the discounted S{a'). If she finds a job, the present value of her tax An unemployment (3) . to find a job with probability F{w{a)). In this event, the cost unemployment insurance system continuation cost 1 ^-^^ payments "^'" is insurance agency chooses 5 and f to maximize the worker's utility given some available resources and an initial asset level. Equivalently, we consider the dual of minimizing the total resource cost of delivering a certain utility for the worker. optimal constant benefit policy solves ^{vo.a) Vu{a]b,f) = . = minj .^ 5(a; 6, f) + (1 + The subject to 7-)a vo. Since there are no ad hoc constraints on borrowing, a standard Ricardian equivalence argument implies cost, so 2.3 it that: follows that Policy II: V{a; C"^(t;o, b, a) f) is = V{a -\- x]b — rx,f independent of a. while a worker rx). The same is true with total Abusing notation we write C'^{vq). Optimal Unemployment Insurance Under optimal unemployment insurance, a worker who 6t, -\- who finds a job in period job, for the remainder of her life. One can t is pays a tax unemployed Tj, in period t consumes depending on when she finds a conceive of more complicated insurance policies where the agency asks the worker to report her wage draws, advises her on whether to take the job, and makes payments conditional on the worker's entire history of reports. is, one can model unemployment insurance as a revelation mechanism We problem. deterministic Given {bt} Her hfetime prove in Appendix mechanism and A that the policy {rj}, consider a who worker in a principal-agent we consider here does as long as absolute risk aversion is That as well as any non-increasing. chooses a sequence of reservation wages {u't}- utility is 'f-i The worker is unemployed at the start of period a wage below Wt, she rejects it and her period she takes the job and gets utility u{w — Now consider an unemployment with probability Hslo F{ws). utility is u{bt). If she she draws draws a wage above iDj, each period, forever. {bt, Tt} to minimize the cost of providing the worker with Vq-. C*{vo)= mm f]{l + r)-{]lF{iLi,)](btF{wt)-^-^Tt{l-F{wt))), subject to two constraints. ommended reservation least as well using the U[{wt,bt,Tt}) > First, the worker's utility wage sequence, recommended U(^{iUt,bt,Tt}) t'o = U[{wt,bt,Tt}). reservation That is, must equal And wage sequence as vq if second, she must do at any other sequence {wt}, the agency recognizes that the worker will choose problem describes optimal unemployment It is useful to express this solve the - problem (5) she uses the rec- her reservation wage sequence {wt} to maximize her utihty given {bt^Tf}. this If insurance agency that sets the sequence of unemployment consumption and employment taxes utility Tt) t The solution to benefits. recursively. The cost function defined above must Bellman equation C*{v)= mm ((b + ^f^)F{w)-^-^T{l~F{w))) (6) subject to V = {u{b) + Pv')F{w) u(w - f°° + / \ Jw «W+'^"' = Moreover, the optimal sequence _ t) ' dF{w) (7) P -' 1^^ {t(;t,6t,Tt} (8) must be generated by the BeUman equation's pohcy functions. An unemployed worker starts the period with some promised chooses consumption for the unemployed employed v' , in the 6, the tax r it will collect current period, the worker's continuation utility and the reservation wage w in order to the reservation wage then the cost is minimize its cost. If if utility v. The agency on workers who become she remains unemployed the worker gets an offer below the unemployment consumption h plus the discounted cost of delivering continuation utility v' in the next period. If instead the worker finds a job above the reservation wage then the agency's costs are reduced by the present value of Equation taxes. equation (8) is reservation (7) imposes that the policy must deliver wage at the point of indifference ance. First, there and tion r^ is CARA relative to optimal utility unemployment is insur- a restriction on the time path of unemployment benefits and taxes, so are constant. Second, the planner does not directly control the worker's and so Finally, between accepting and rejecting the wage. There are two disadvantages to constant benefits bt v to the worker. the incentive constraint, which incorporates the fact that the worker sets her Equivalence for a Benchmark: 3 utility consump- constrained by her savings choices. This can be thought of as an additional dimension of moral hazard. In general, constant benefits are more costly than optimal un- employment insurance: C^{v) > C''{v); however, in this section we prove analytically that constant benefits achieve the same outcome as optimal unemployment insurance for the case with CARA limit on the amount of debt that workers can accrue and towards preferences, u{c) lotteries over future show that these = -exp(— pc) with c 6 K. A all key feature is that there good benchmark 10 no workers have the same attitude wages, which makes the model particularly tractable. results provide a is We for other preference specifications. later For the results in this section it is convenient to define = u-M CE(t7)) u{msix{i-u,w})dF{u>) / the certainty equivalent for a worker of a lottery offering the CARA u{ci maximum of w and w~ F. The —u{ci)u{c2) for any Ci and Co. Constant Benefits 3.1 We (9) . has a convenient properties that we exploit throughout this section, utility fiuiction + C2) = ) characterize constant benefits in two steps. given unemployment benefits b, employment taxes choose these parameters optimally. subsidy hj The It is we First, f, and characterize individual behavior assets a. Then we discuss how to convenient to define the net benefit or unemployment B = b + f. first step follows from solving the Bellman equation (2). Proposition 1 Assume CARA preferences. The reservation wage, consumption and utility of the unemployed satisfy {l + r}w = CE{w) + rB. w—f Cu{a) = ra ujra - f + CE(tD)) j— K{a) = (10) (11) -{- Proof. In Appendix B. Equation (10) generalizes a standard eciuation wage, e.g. (12) for a risk-neutral worker's reservation equation (6.3.3) in Ljungqvist and Sargent (2004), to an environment with risk aversion and savings. It can be reexpressed as the condition that a worker between accepting her net wage benefit today, w — f today and rejecting and then earning the certainty equivalent id — f - ^ CEfti;) Equation (10) indicates that the reservation wage subsidy B. This is it, CE(tt;) getting her — unemployment by 11 unemployment — r iD is raising indifferent f thereafter: increasing in the net the essence of the moral hazard problem in our model to protect the worker against is unemployment unemployment — the more one benefits tries and funding the benefits by an employment tax, the more selective she becomes. that a worker's assets a do not affect her reservation wage, so it is The equation also shows constant during a spell of unemployment. Consumption in equation (11) has a ary savings component. Assets wage in excess of the permanent income form with a constant precaution- by w;— fall unemployment > J5 subsidy, as long as there F{B) < 1.' is some chance of getting a Consumption CE{w) — w by falls each period that the worker remains unemployed. Unemployed workers face uncertainty: a wage draw above CE(u)) draw below CE(w) The next step is is good news leading to an increase is bad news leading Sia; 6, wage consumption. independent of -— 1 + = r \ r — —— 13 . r [w) J Optimal constant benefit policy minimizes S{a;b,f) a. Using the constant, equation (3) becomes is r is consumption while a wage to minimize the cost of providing the worker with utility vq. result that the reservation which to a decline in in -I- (1 + r)a subject to (10) and (12). Proposition 2 AssiLme CARA independent ojvq. The reservation wage ^ , , CE(iD) b and f + r - wFCw) — F{w) are then determined by equation (10) C'ivo) independent of = ^ the optimal constant benefits policy is w* G argmax^j, $(u;) where satisfies 1 and Then preferences. and {u-\{l - p)vo) - , (12). (1 The minimum + r)$(ir)) ^ cost is (15) , a. = Vu{a; b, f). result characterizes the worker's allocation given optimal policy. We take Proof. Use equations (10) and (12) to solve for b and f as functions of w and v Substituting into the cost (13) delivers the desired result. Our next current unemployment utility and describe the evolution v as a state variable, express the allocation as a function of v, of v. ^Substitute equation (11) into the unemployed worker's budget constraint to get a' w < B, condition (10) implies w > CE(7l;). But the definition of the certainty cciuivalent possible only if F{ui) = 1, a contradiction. 12 — (9) a +B — w. implies this If is . Proposition 3 Assume CARA ployed at the beginning of a period. Then c^{v) and her unem- preferences. Let v denote the utility promised to the = agent remains unemployed, she consumes if the w* - CE{w*) + u-^ {{1 - P)v) (16) utility evolves to = -u{w* - v'{v) wage w, she forever // she accepts a job at after CE{in*))v. (17) consumes cAv,w = w - CE[w*) ^ u-\{l Proof. I3)v) (18) = This follows directly by changing variables from a to f tions (11)-(12), Ce{a,w) = ra w — -\- This proposition will be useful f, and the budget constraint when comparing constant y„(a;6, f) using equaa' = + (1 r)a + benefits with optimal b — c. unem- ployment insurance, which we turn to now. Optimal Unemployment Insurance 3.2 We characterize optimal unemployment so, it is convenient to first insurance using the Bellman equation (G)-(8). To do deduce the shape of the cost function directly from the sequence problem. Lemma Assume 1 CARA {?!}(*, 6f* let {zDj*, + X, Tj* — Proof. Let bf = 6^*. t^} denote the x} with X bt + x and = cost function satisfies = -^u-\{l-P)vo) + C*{vo) Moreover, The preferences. ^"'((1 it = Tt optimum for — P)vo) —x IS for all t. initial C*(^^y promised utility optimal for any other Use equation show that adding a constant x to unemployment consumption (4) in (19) and u(0)/(l initial — /3). Then promise CARA vq. preferences to each period and subtracting the same constant x from the employment tax simply multiplies lifetime utility by the positive constant —u{x), that is U[{wt, bt, tj}) = —u{x)U[{ijj, 13 6, f }) . The result follows immediately. The optimal path for wage for the reservation since promised utility reservation wealth effects with To is CARA lemma two while the path features. Indeed, implies that the optimal results are implications of the absence of preferences. to eliminate the (8) p) then employment tax r. The Bellman r 1 + \l-f3)) r ' ^ -^-±L(^^^u-\{l-P){u{b)+(3v'))){\-F{w))\ subject to The the cost -^^ = -{u{h) + [5v')u{CE{w) - solution to this cost minimization problem 6 + ti~-'((l — p)v')/r unemployed. The first + eciuivalent to b = w — eliminate b and v', and = P'v' u{b)/{l C'E(tu). — subproblem solve the + = +Pv' of minimizing to those remaining u{b) (22) The promise keeping /3). constraint (21) is then Substitute these conditions into the Bellman equation to — solve for C*(u(0)/(1 (l is (21) order condition for this problem yields ^Ju{0)\ Cl-^]=where $(tD) must (20) w). of providing a given level of utility u{b) {l-p)v' or equivalently u{b) (6) becomes wAv'W \1-P) reflects these utility, problem further, we substitute the cost fimction from (19) into — u(0)/(l These be constant. and use the incentive constraint = with promised unchanged. The cost function will solve the agency's equation at v shifts in parallel a state variable for the problem, the is wage path consumption p)) to obtain F{iu)w-CE{w) ^mm^— ^/, r)2 . ^ = (1 + r)^ ^^ ^max$u)), ^ (23) defined in by equation (14). The optimal reservation wage w* is independent of promised utility and hence constant over time. Substituting equation (23) into equation (19) proves that the cost to the agency of providing a worker with utility v is identical to the cost with constant benefits C'^(u) in equation (15). Once we have found the optimal reservation wage consumption, employment tax and continuation and (22) along with Lemma 1. The next u;*, the associated unemployment utility fall out using equations (7), (8), proposition summarizes the main result of this 14 section. CARA Proposition 4 Assume reservation wage is Under optimal unemployment insurance, preferences. constant over time and maximizes <&(w), given by (14)- U the agent o-'n and remains unemployed, she consumes Cu{v) (equation 16) and has has expected utility v continuation utility v'{v) (equation 17). If she accepts a job at wage w, she consumes Ce{v,w) (equation 18) forever. This is the the cost is the same, C^(fo) = same allocation as under an optimal constant and benefit C*{vq). Thus, when the worker can borrow and lend at the same rate as the agency, a very simple policy attains the same allocation as optimal unemployment insurance. Of equivalence implies that the timing of transfers unemployment. If bt not pinned down, only the net subsidy to is a worker takes a job in period present value terms. course, Ricardian she must pay taxes equal to i, "'"'"''^' in ^ she remains unemployed for one more period, she receives a benefit If ^^ and then pays taxes in present value terms. The sum of these is the unemployment subsidy, a measure of insurance: B, , (,, + (1±I)!£ _ !i±l r Using + ((1 bt = r)w* c^{vt) — and Tf CE(u}))/r. problem with constant At the other end = w — c'^{vt,u') of the extreme (1979) and it calls for case, benefits Hopenhayn and by equation is constant and the same as B = in the (10). spectrum from Ricardian equivalence, imagine a worker who can neither borrow nor save and so this with eciuations (1G)-(18), we find that Bt The unemployment subsidy benefits, given (24) r and taxes lives hand-to-mouth consuming current income. are uniquely pinned Nicolini (1997). One down, as in Sliavcll and Weiss interpretation of this extreme case decreasing benefits and increasing taxes. However, it is In is that equivalent to think of the insurance agency simultaneously lending to the worker and providing her with a constant unemployment subsidy. Conceptually, even in this case, between these two components of 4 remains useful to distinguish policy. Liquidity and Wealth Effects: The sharp it CRRA utility closed form results obtained so far were derived under an assumption of preferences and in particular allowed consumption to be negative. 15 We now CARA turn to workers with constant relative consumption. Let a risk aversion > (CRRA) preferences with nonnegative constraint on denote the coefficient of relative risk aversion. Then the period = log(c) corresponding to risk aversion of again consider our two alternative policies: optimal unemployment insurance and utility function is = j^^ u{c) for cr with n(c) 7^ 1, one. We constant benefits. The erences. Nevertheless, equivalence between these two policies breaks we find little welfare gain in unemployment insurance. Moreover, we analytically with CARA down with moving from constant find that the optimal policy CARA case is pref- benefits to optimal and allocations obtained provide an excellent approximation for our For both reasons, we conclude that the CRRA CRRA specifications. indeed a very useful benchmark. Optimal Unemployment Insurance 4.1 Optimal unemployment insurance solves the Bellman equation utility function is different with CRRA preferences than with (6)-(8). CARA The form of the preferences and so the We analytical expression for the cost function in equation (19) no longer holds. therefore use numerical simulations to examine the economy. To proceed we need to of relative risk aversion a, (1997), we view make choices for the discount factor and the wage distribution a period as representing a week discount factor of 0.949. We fix and F{iu). set /3 so Q."^ we normalize by Euler's constant, With CRRA setting z = in + r)"\ \. = the coefficient Hopenhayn and 0.999, ecjuivalent to cr = Nicolini an annual 1.5 but later 6.^ = exp{—zw~^) adopt a Frechet wage distribution, F{w) parameters z,6 > As {1 the coefficient of relative risk aversion at consider the robustness of our results to a higher value, a We = p — with support (0, 00), and the parameter z acts as an uninteresting scaling factor, The mean and the standard deviation log wage draw of log wages is is then ^, where 7 ~ 0.577 is -^ ~ ^^. ^Hopenhaj'ii and Nicolini (1997) use the much lower value of ct = 1/2 in their baseline calibration. They argue that over short horizons a high intertemporal elasticity of substitution may be appropriate. In our view, this remark resonates introspectively, but is regarding consumption and net income paths. In their lent; at the same time misleading since it confounds attitudes model consumption and net income were equiva- but our model allows saving and borrowing, and as a result a worker displays an infinite elasticity of substitution with respect to the timing of transfers. ^A Frechet distribution has some desirable properties in this environment. First, it displays positive n wage draws within a period from a Frechet distribution with parameters (2, 9), and must decide whether to accept the maximum of these draws. The distribution of the maximum wage draw is also Frechet with the same d and z = nz. Thus there is no loss of generality in our assumption that the worker gets one wage draw per period. skewness. Second, suppose a worker receives 16 40 30-- ^ 20 'Ed a CD Q 10-- 1.00 0.95 1.05 1.10 Wage w Figure 2: Wage = density: F'{w) ew-^-^e-"'~\ = 103.56 Following Hopenhayn and Nicolini (1997), we set 9 so that the unemployment spell is about ten weeks, consistent with evidence weekly job finding probability of ten percent 6 = the density function F'{'w). wage We 1.2 percent. ^"^ and the expected duration of unemployment. specification with those obtained from the coefficient of absolute risk aversion equal to a/c. functions obtained for a CARA case. CARA CRRA worker with coefficient of absolute risk aversion p we chose minimum 6 so that a risk-neutral worker without making use of equation c note that has local worker with the approximation provided by those of a begin by discussing our results for the 0.90, this end, who consumes = a/u~^{{l the consumption equivalent utility as a proxy for consumption. •'^Specifically, F{w) = To This suggests comparing the cost or pohcy can be computed analytically using our results from Section We Figure 2 plots which increases the dispersion a worker with a constant coefficient of relative risk aversion a we take Meyer (1990) on a be useful to have a way of comparing the cost or policy functions obtained from CRRA titious an also consider the robustness of our results to changes in the in wages, raising the option value of job search our wages of about distribution, in particular to a substantial decrease in 6, It will in of United States. This requires setting for the 103.56, giving a standard deviation of log mean duration (10). 17 — f3)v), fic- where The approximations 3. cost of providuig a worker with unemployment insurance would have exactly 0.015 0.010 0.005 CD O a V Sh 0-^ CD an Q -0.005 -- -0.010 -0.015 0.4 0.2 Utility Figure a given level of measured CRRA utility. we 1.0 (consumption equivalent) u^^{{l Difference between actual values and specification, CRRA 0.8 CARA Recall that with find that the cost we do not graph the is utility, this function of the worker's promised shows how Uo = is we compare the utility, when utility same utility is For our slope. For cost obtained from CARA exercise. The solid and this CARA approximation exceeds a certainty equivalent of policy, the left panel in Figure 4 unemployment consumption and r evolve over an unemployment b — /?). Although initially spell starting slightly negative, after a sufficiently long together, a worker's expected utility Vt with unemployment consumption falls 0.3. shows that, as a b is increasing (solid line). initial The right panel promised value high and the employ- is unemployment tax rises to a high level and unemployment consumption it is when see equation (19). while employment taxes r are decreasing (dashed orange ^i(l.l)/(l ment tax linear is specification with an approximation provided by the Turning to the optimal allocation and line) approximations. nearly hnear with almost the cost function. Instead, small, less than 0.0001 in absolute value brown P)v) cost ^, black line in Figure 3 shows that the difference between C*{v) is — CARA consumption equivalent units with a slope of in this reason, the 3: 0.6 spell the employment to nearly zero. Putting these declines over time. This line is not graphed because only slightly higher than, and would be scarcely distinguishable from, unemployment consumption We also bt- look at the subsidy to unemployment, the additional resources that a worker gets 18 1.25 0.2 0.6 0.4 0.8 200 1.0 u-\{l - p)v) Figure 4: Optimal unemployment consumption subsidy Bt = bt + ^^^^ - ^^. by remaining unemployed for 400 800 600 1000 Time (weeks) Utility employment taxes r^, and unemployment one more period, as previously defined in equation (24). bt, dash-dot blue line in Figure 4 shows that this unemployment subsidy is small when The utility is high at the start of an unemployment spell and then increases gradually as promised utility falls for and the Bt of the spell continues. CARA The dash-dot approximation with p The unemployment subsidy Bt blue line in Figure 3 illustrates the high accuracy = a/ir^{{l lar. The picture for Werning finds that it (2(J02) is bt and r^ (5)v). paints a very different picture of optimal unemploy- ment insurance than do unemployment consumption tion. — in Hopenhayn and bt or employment taxes Nicolini (1997) in isola- qualitatively simi- is computes the net subsidy to unemployment from r^ their allocation and nearly constant, starting quite low and rising very slowly. This distinction between unemployment consumption and subsidies is crucial in understanding the differ- ence between the results of this paper on the one hand, and Shavell and Weiss (1979) and Hopenhayn and Nicohni Finally, Figure 5 (1997) on the other. shows the probability that an unemployed worker accepts a job, 1 — F{wt), under optimal unemployment insurance. This starts just above ten percent per week when promised utility is high, then initially rises before falling low. This non-monotonicity illustrates two opposing 19 when promised utility is very forces at play as the worker gets poorer: 0.1005- ^ I tT 0.1000 0.0995 ;S <^ O "^ 0.0990 bC ^ 0.0985 r 0.0980 1 1 0.6 0.4 0.2 Utility Figure 5: 0.8 u~\{l - 400 200 1.0 \ 1 600 800 Time f3)v) Optimal Job Finding Probability 1 — 1000 (weeks) F{wt). the increase in absolute risk aversion and the increase in unemployment subsidies. effect encourages the worker to accept more jobs, while the second an endogenous response to the first, effect, which encourages her to become more selective. red line in Figure 3 shows the high accuracy of the CARA approximation. It The is first partly The dashed follows that the non-monotonicity of the job finding rate with respect to promised utihty v found in our CRRA case. specification reflects a non-monotonicity with respect to risk aversion p in the The next subsection policy with CRRA Before closing, ability that a 10"^. explores this notion further by studying the constant benefits utility. it is important to emphasize that in this worker remains unemployed for 100 CRRA weeks or more is specification, the prob- remote, on the order of Over the relevant time period, the unemployment subsidy and the job finding prob- ability are virtually constant. benchmark 4.2 CARA for the CRRA In this sense, our results with CARA provide an excellent specification. Constant Benefits The Bellman equation a constant benefit b (2) describes the problem of an unemploj-ed worker with assets a facing and a constant employment tax 20 f. In addition, since consumption is nonnegative assets cannot a! A natural borrowing limit. below some, possibly negative, fall level a, Aiyagari's (1994) worker can borrow as long as she can pay the interest on her debt following any sequence of wage draws. The natural borrowing limit w— max{6, ~ is max{5, w} — f f] r r Thus, the details of the natural borrowing limit depend on whether the smallest possible wage, w, is In the bigger or smaller than the net first case, w>B, unemployment and the natural borrowing limit is This implies that a change offer. B = b + f. —2^^^, since a worker with consumption and pay the assets above this level could always have positive debt by taking the next job benefit, interest on her wage in the left tail of the distribution can substantially affect a worker's debt limit, and potentially her behavior, even if she is extremely unlikely ever to accept a wage from this part of the distribution,^^ w < li B, the natural borrowing limit unemployment income unemployment effects. job (insurance) and (liquidity). there is The it for Vu{a;b-,f) by an increase is increase in the net and a budget balance change in in f, which the worker does not absent from the model with CARA is then find a unemployed preferences because limit. method (3) + /)a (1 S{a]b,f). + S{a; 6, we begin with a affect the Bellman equation of solving the worker's It is then simple to choose b /3 = specification 0.999, where (2) and f to minimize f) of providing a worker with utility v parameterize the economy as before; where benefits = — -. An ability to use her allows the worker to go further into debt while she and equation 103.56. Thus, in b income to states transfers discusses an efficient the total resource cost We = It liquidity effect no borrowing Appendix C . to pay the interest on her debt, so a benefit, obtained has two distinct determined by a worker's is = Vu(a; = 1.5, F{iu) = exp(— to^"), w = < B so that we are in the a b, f). and case borrowing constraint. In the next subsection we turn to the other case. To start, we examine the oretically this is showing the cost cost of providing the worker with a given level of utility. The- higher than the cost under optimal unemployment insurance. Rather than directly, the solid purple hne in Figure 6 plots the additional cost of con- stant benefits on a logarithmic scale. At small values of utihty, the cost of constant benefits is reasonably large, equal to a few weeks consumption. ^^With is CARA preferences, Proposition 1 irrelevant for equiUbrium behavior. This show that the is at high levels of utility, near distribution of wages below the reservation because there 21 But is no borrowing limit with CARA wage preferences. I 10^ m 10-2 tuO O X O \ 10- w= «- = S' O 0.95 Ad Hoc 10 6 __ .1— Q 10- + + 0.2 0.4 + 0.6 0.8 1.0 Utility (consumption equivalent) ^"^((1 Figure 6: — Additional cost of constant benefits. those corresponding to a net resource cost of zero, around v using a constant benefits system On for is is 1-/3 very small, about 0.01 weeks of consumption. who typically starts much an unemployment spell demand higher than the optimal time-varying unemployment subsidy Bt line). Workers with lower because they are closer to utility is more important them to it. Liquidity goal of this section this, first is to isolate the insurance role of unemployment observe that under the Prechet wage distribution F{w) probability that a single wage draw is less than 0.95 is = > w = 0.95 and F(ti;) = otherwise, i.e. To do benefits. exp{—w~^°^'^^) , the minuscule, approximately 10"^^. Consider an economy very similar to this one but with the wage distribution F{io) if lu for higher benefits for two reasons. First, they have higher absolute risk aversion, and value insurance more. Second, relaxing the borrowing constraint The B with a given level of utility (solid purple a worker with the same level of utility (dash-dot blue 4.3 the additional cost of ^ the other hand, Figure 7 shows that the optimal constant unemployment subsidy a worker line) P)v) with a (small) mass point at 0.95. = F{w) It turns out that the optimal reservation wage always exceeds 0.95 and this change has no effect on 22 icq a CO CD 0.4 0.2 Figure 0.6 = Net Unemployment Subsidy B^ 7: optimal unemployment insurance policy. But this slight borrowing The limit, change i.e. 1.0 in the wage b^ + {l — + r)Tt r in the original if then the natural borrowing limit was —b/r while Thus, 0.8 (consumption equivalent) u~^{{l Utility in the may distribution p)v) ^^ r and B b + economy we had modified economy T. B < —{w — it is in the availability of liquidity. green dashed lines in Figure 6 and Figure 7 show unemployment subsidy turns = 0. high. into a pure insurance In fact, the optimal subsidy unemployment subsidy is at the For example, at v same — is how When w > this matters. level of utility i^J > 0.95 but 0.540 when w is high, subsidy (Figure A w = 0. and hence There little collecting is much lower than with (dash-dot blue line) , the optimal time- varying subsidy spell. is little when at least is 0.0278, rising to The optimal constant subsidy need for time- varying utility is 0.0288 if unemployment subsidies additional cost of providing utility through a constant 6). slight modification in policy Suppose that and ii mechanism and The only slightly higher than the optimal time- varying 0.0283 during a ten week unemployment w= f)/r. lead to a significant increase in the B, unemployment subsidies no longer play a role in increasing a worker's liquidity. u) .95, after the w—f has an effect that is similar to this change in technology. worker draws a wage, she has the option of exiting the labor market thereafter. She accepts this option 23 if her reservation wage w falls below ^ ui}'-^ When this (^+'')("'~'^) happens, the cost Like the lower since ^ bound on the wage must be paid it; in all future periods. distribution, this option can substantially affect a worker's debt limit and her behavior even The only (^) is if she is extremely unlikely ever to exercise it. is that the policy involves a cost to the planner, while the alternative distribution does not. However, since the odds of getting a single wage draw below 0.95 difference are negligible, the odds of the worker ever accepting w= benefits are indistinguishable with summary, when the distribution lems, optimal unemployment insurance 0.95 or with of is wages is cost of the policy are to ensure that workers are able to smooth w= 0.95. such that workers have liquidity prob- well-mimicked by a two part policy: a subsidy to unemployment, which insures workers against the of and hence the This means that the cost and optimal unemployment subsidy under constant infinitesimal. In w their failure to find a good job; and measures consumption over unusually long sequences bad wage draws. Insuring workers against the small probability of a very bad shock pro- vides liquidity. Together the two policies mimic optimal unemployment insurance, which unemployment subsidy involves a nearly constant for a long period of time, followed by a sharp increase in the subsidy when workers are sufficiently poor (Figure An open question is how wage distribution from even if F(0.95) ~ to interpret the finding that raising the lower 10~^^. In our view, model as a 4.4 we view the it is a shortcoming of exogenous incomplete markets simplicity and transparency can easily circumvent the market Constraints anj^ tighter ad hoc limit. prohibited but that the the natural borrowing limit worker a lump-sum transfer unemployment benefit to b — (1 + -l- limit, To be is it is useful to note that pol- concrete, suppose borrowing negative, a r)a at the start of the < an ideal instrument for is is Consider giving the 0. initial period, ra and raising her employment tax to f changes the timing of payments, and is On virtue. Ad Hoc Borrowing loan, but borrowing. affect of the exogenous incomplete Although our analysis focuses on the natural borrowing icy bound on the to 0.95 can have a significant effect on the constant benefit policy models that vanishingly small probability events can significantly other hand, 4). while lowering her — ra. This simply equivalent to providing the worker with a risk- free circumventing any ad hoc borrowing constraint. ^"In our numerical examples, a worker only accepts w on her debt. 24 if doing so is the only way she can pay tiie interest Optimal unemployment insurance, taken mouth consumer, taxes much (as in Tj is literally as a policy geared towards a hand-to- also a loan. It pays out the duration-dependent sequence Hopeuhayn and Nicolini, 1997). Figure 4 and collects shows that the net subsidy Bt may be lower than consumption while unemployed, reflecting the accumulating employment tax liability over the jobless spell. Thus, an important component of the agency's gross transfers are not net present value transfers; the agency pays out early much b^ on and collects later, as a loan. For completeness, we also consider briefly the case where, for some unspecified and ar- bitrary reason, the insurance agency does not circumvent the ad hoc borrowing constraint. This may significantly affect both the cost and level of an extreme case, suppose a worker has no assets and no sume her benefit each period she and taxes for this case. is unemployed. The black dotted line in We optimal constant benefits. To take ability to borrow, so she must con- compute the optimal constant benefit Figure 6 shows that this raises the cost of providing the worker with a particular level of utility by about three to six weeks income, a substantial amount given that unemployment spells to provide both insurance much subsidy 4.5 last for The need only ten weeks. and consumption smoothing makes the optimal unemployment higher, in excess of 0.5 over the usual range of utility (Figure 7). Robustness This section asks the extent to which our results depend on the wage distribution, in partic- ular on the assumption that a worker finds a job in ten weeks on average. There are a few reasons to explore this assumption. Fust, our results indicate that constant unemployment benefits and constant employment taxes do almost insurance policy. last longer notably It could be that this result would go away and therefore presented a bigger much as well as a fully optimal of Europe, unemployment risk to individuals. unemployment duration at least in part a response to if unemployment is Second, in unemployment spells tended to many countries, substantially longer, although this benefits that are high is compared to workers' income prospects (Ljungqvist and Sargent, 1998; Blanchard and Wblfers, 2000). And third, workers typically experience multiple spells of unemployment before locating a long-term job (Hall, 1995). raising Although modehng this explicitly would go beyond the scope of unemployment duration may capture some aspect To explore this possibility, we choose 9 = this paper, of this longer job search process. 21.084 so that the weekly job finding probability 25 is about 1 — F{w) = 0.020, one-fifth of the earUer level. standard deviation of wages, by a factor of We of job search. revisit five, to 0.027, which increases the option value our main conclusions under this alternative parameterization: Under optimal unemployment insurance, • This raises the unconditional ''^ a worker with utility equal to a constant consumption of 0.080 and rises to 0.145 during the time her first 10.75 years of 1.2. The optimal job finding rate changes slowly. The optimal subsidy 0.6. same experiment, In the is unemployment, during which a consumption equivalent of utility falls in half, to Suppose we start the subsidy Bt rises slowly. 2.005 percent per week to 2.010 percent per week during the first it rises 10.75 years of from unem- ployment. The • CARA CARA case provide a good approximation. ployment subsidy of 0.084, rising to 0.156 would suggest an when absolute initial unem- risk aversion doubles. The approximate and exact job finding probabilities are indistinguishable. • If the lowest wage is high, here w= 1.03, the optimal constant subsidy similar to the is optimal time-varying unemployment subsidy, 0.087 at the start of the unemployment spell and 0.175 once the worker's benefits is utility has fallen to small, approximately 0.0004 at the start 0.6. Moreover, the cost of constant and 0.017 for a worker with utihty 0.6. • If lowest wage zero, the is at the start of the The This optimal constant unemployment subsidy unemployment cost of constant benefits last number still is spell and 0.698 also higher, 0.745 for a worker with and 5.56 at these higher, 0.240 is utility of 0.6. two utility levels. only represents about a one percent increase in the cost of the unemployment insurance system. We cr = 6. have also examined the robustness of our results to higher Optimal unemployment benefits are higher than the benchmark with a CARA approximations would also suggest. For example, u(l)/(l — /?), the optimal Otherwise this change ^^Specifically, 1 risk aversion - F{w) = we unemployment subsidy in preferences set 6 to has rises little effect for = by setting 1.5, as the a worker with utility equal to by a factor of four from 1.4% to 5.5%. on our results. ensure that a risk-neutral worker without unemployment insurance would have 0.020. 26 Conclusion 5 This paper characterizes optimal unemployment insurance search model. with Our main result is borrowing and lending of a free access to preferences, constant benefits coupled riskless asset optimality of constant benefits breaks down. rises very slowly over time. is optimal. CRRA With inefficient to distort the worker's savings behavior. is if CARA that with McCall (1970) sequential in the In particular, it preferences, the exact We find that the optimal unemployment subsidy However, we find to a constant little loss unemployment subsidy workers are given free access to enough liquidity. This quantitative result is robust to the key parameters of the model. There are important advantages to simple with free access to markets that our policies model does not capture. Free choice of savings decisions may be intrinsically valuable for philosophical reasons (Friedman, 1962; Feldstein, 2005). Such policies on practical grounds because they are likely to may also be valuable be more robust to the numerous real-world considerations that are not included in our model. This paper has not focused on the optimal on their optimal timing market. and on the who computed to be optimal for the United States. optimal unemployment subsidy determinants of the is They Still, much benefits is it to are not, however, out of line somewhere between 0-10% of wages possible to construct examples where the higher.^' In ongoing separate work, we focus on the level of benefits. have deliberately written a stark model of job search relatively simple and focus on the the model lends itself to forces that we believe are in order to keep the analysis most important. Nevertheless, a number of extensions, some of which we mention here. to keep our analysis comparable to Shavell (1997), subsides, but rather unemployment subsidy turns out utility is also quite low. with results in Grubor (1997), unemployment desirability of allowing workers free access to the asset In the examples in this paper, the optimal be low unless the worker's We level of we have assumed that all and Weiss (1979) and Hopenhayn and jobs last forever. First, Nicolini Relaxing this assumption permits an examination of how optimal unemployment subsidies depend on a worker's entire labor market experience.^-' ^''Suppose the wage Second, we have focused on deterministic unemployment insurance draw can take on two values, Then Wi < u'2. Moreover, suppose the first-best features the unemployment subsidy to W2 has the desired effect and moreover fully insures the unemployed; it attains the first-best and is thus optimal. '^Wang and Williamson (1996) and Zhao (2000) have explored optimal unemployment insurance, without borrowing and saving, in an economy with repeated spells of unemployment. worker onlj' accepting the high wage offer. setting the 27 — There are situations mechanisms. of optimal in which an employment lottery can reduce the cost unemployment insurance even if workers have CARA or CRRA preferences.-^'' Future research should explore the potential gains from using employment lotteries and their interpretation. By Third, we have assumed that wage draws are independent over time. introducing some serial correlation, this model could potentially capture the idea that some people are much more early on that a high extensions, it will wage is likely to obtain a high wage job quickly while others learn an unlikely event. Our results suggest that for these and other be important to evaluate the relative efficiency of simple benefit policies coupled with free access to the asset market and to distinguish between insuring workers against uncertainty in the duration of a jobless spell and ensuring their ability to smooth consumption while unemployed. Appendix A General Mechanisms This section uses the revelation principle to set up the most general deterministic mechanism that an unemployment insurance agency might contemplate given the assumed of information. We allow the worker to make reports on the privately observed allow taxes to vary during an employment spell. is useful: We show that neither asymmetry wage and we of these capabilities the planner does just as well by offering unemployment benefits that depends on the duration of unemployment, and setting employment taxes that depend on the duration of the previous unemployment spell, not on employment tenure. The Recursive Mechanism A.l For notational convenience, we present the general mechanism directly in this can be justified along the lines of its recursive form Spear and Srivastava (1987). Our general mechanism involves the following steps: 1. The unemployed worker starts the period with some promise utility V. 16 We are grateful to Daron Acemoglu for pointing out this possibility. 28 for expected Ufetime The worker then 2. id to 3. If receives a offer w from the distribution F{vj) and makes a report the planner. w < the worker report and wage is w, she rejects the job, receives unemployment benefit b{w), promised continuation utility v'{w), starting the next period in step 1, described above, with this value. 4. If subsequent period n = w, she accepts the job and pays a tax T[vj,n) in each 1,2,.... The Planner's Problem A. 2 The w > the worker reports full planner's problem may be expressed recursively as follows: subject to the promise keeping constraint v= {u{h[w)) + l3v'{w))dF{iu) + ^^ and a ^/?"ii(iy Vn=0 / -^"^ - dF{w) t{w, n)) / set of truth teUing constraints for all w, w: oo oo y^ /?"u(t(; - r(ty, n)) > ^ /3"n(w - r('«:', W^W n)) >w (25) n=0 71=0 oo ^ /3"^i(ii; - t{w, n)) > u (6 (w)) + pv' (w) w> w>w (26) w >w>w (27) w > w,w (28) n=0 oo (6 (tu)) + pv' (w) > ^ /3"u(w - t{iu, n)) n=0 u We {b {w)) + pv' {w) >u{b{w))+ pv' (w) proceed to simphfy the planner's problem. Lemma 2 (a) Suppose an optimum has the schedules that replaces these with a constant schedule b abuse of notation), is also optimal, (b) — b{iu) b{w) and v' and v'{w), then the mechanism = v'{w) for any w (with a slight The incentive constraints (25)-(28) can 29 be replaced with the single equality condition oo i{b)+pv' = ^P''u{iu-T{iv,n)), (29) n=0 and constraint Proof, X, (25). Condition (28) implies that u{h(w)) (a) From the independent of w. {b{w) , v' (w)) + G argmaxb,t,'{6 one can select a solution that (b) For constant b and side of constraint (27) is v' pv'{w) — majCw<u,{u{b{w)) planner's objective function C{v')} subject to u{b) is + Pv' = x we is + pv'{w)) see that given optimal. = x any Consequently, independent of w. the constraint (28) , + increasing in w, it is is trivially satisfied. Since the right hand equivalent to oo u{b) for all so it w> + Pv' > w. Constraint (25) implies J^/?"u(t(} n=0 - t{w, n)) w = w maximizes the right hand side of this inequahty, reduces to CX5 L{b) + yY^P^'uiw-T^w^n)). pv' (30) n=0 Next note that inequality (26) is now equivalent for all w>w oo ^/?"ti(w - T{w,n)) > u{b)+pv'. n=0 li w> w, then oo where the oo oo y^ P'^u{w - t{w, ?^)) > ^ n=0 n=0 first inequality uses (25) Therefore the preceding inequality - P'^u{w t{w, n)) > Y^ p'^u['w - t{w, n)), n=0 and the second uses monotonicity of the is tightest when w = w, utility function. so inequality (26) is equivalent to oo Y^ P^'uiiu - r(u), n)) > u{b) + pv'. n= Inequalities (30) and (31) hold if and only if equation (29) holds, completing the proof. 30 (31) Constant Absolute Risk Aversion A. 3 So we have not made any assumptions about the period far utility function u except that it is increasing. This section examines the imphcations of having constant absolute risk aversion preferences. Lemma being CARA utility, independent of w and n. 3 With exponential Proof. an optimum must feature the tax on the employed T{w,n) With the utility lo on both sides of (25) cancels, implying that the remaining term X^^0'^"^(~'''(^' ^)) i^^st be some value independent of w. Let x denote this value. It follows that an optimum must solve the subproblem HP'-n=0 oo subject to X = 2^/3"^( ~ 'Ti:w,n)'). n=0 The first (w, n). order condition for this problem reveals that an t{w, n) must be independent of B Lemmas 2 tion prevents CARA and 3 allow us to rewrite the Planning "employment insurance," so the tax rate r preferences and jobs that last forever, the plicative taste shock. This ensures that all transfer schemes, which makes it With non-CARA cases, it utility, may be wage is in (6)-(8). Private informa- independent of the wage. With effectively acts as a permanent multi- employed workers have the same preferences over impossible to separate workers according to their actual wages. Since workers have concave some problem as utility, introducing variability in taxes is not efficient. workers with different wages rank tax schedules differently. In possible to exploit these differences in rankings to separate workers according to their wage; see Prcscott and Townscnd (1984) for an example. decreasing absolute risk aversion (DARA), including wages are more reluctant to accept intertemporal CRRA If workers have preferences, those earning lower variability in taxes. One can therefore induce these workers to reveal their wage by giving them a choice between a time-varying employment tax with a low discounted wage workers would opt for the cost and a constant tax with a high time-varying schedule. income from low wage to high wage workers. 31 It is High This does not, however, reduce the planner's cost of providing an unemployed worker with a given level of transfers cost. utility, therefore not optimal. since it B Proof of Proposition The u{ra 1 worker's sequence problem implies that the value function must have the form Vu{a) — f + — ki)/{l some constant P), for the solution along with We ki. = determine this constant, and the rest of it. The maximization with respect to consumption in equation (2) delivers = Cu{a) + ra + r)-\rb + {1 - ki f) (32) Substituting this back into the value fimction (2) gives T / 1 = ^ Ktlfi) / This implies that the worker accepts hy w= {rB + ki)/{\ + r), —u{ci)u{c2) to write (33) . 7 ^ K(a;6,f) = - j wages all B = where again + ki-f\ rb \ ( ™3^ <u\ra-\ f°° n b lu + , , u[ra +w— -xl t) > ,^. exceeding a reservation wage f. Use and the identity this u(ra-f) f^ \_^ ,, _, u{ma.x{w,w})dF{w) = , , , w u{ci defined + C2) J Substituting A;i = u(ra - f + CE{w)) ^ ^_^ ^ CE(u;) into equation (32), and ^"i)/(l + C Computing the Worker's Value Function We are interested in solving equation (2). Ricardian equivalence implies that delivers equations (10) employment tax f (33) = as: establishing equation (12). ?') V dF[w). and impossible to work with the natural borrowing limit a —— . ^ (34) w = {rB + (11). to zero without loss in generality. First ad hoc borrowing constraint, a > , ^^ We assume = —— , B> w. we can It is numerical^ and so instead we impose an consider values of a arbitrarily close to test the sensitivity of the results to the exact borrowing limit. set the The results we report —— to in the paper are not sensitive to this choice. Take a worker with consume enough assets a very slightly greater than ag = a. A worker at this point to reach the borrowing limit. This implies K(a) = max ( (u((l + r)a + B~ ao) + f3K,{ao)) F {w) + /" !^ir^^dF(u: 32 will We can evaluate this directly at a u{rao K (ao In addition, we can = = max ao: + B)F{wo) + jhg JZ ""(^^o + w)dF{ . I tuo — fit [wo) differentiate with respect to a using the envelope condition and evaluate at a to get = Vl{ao) where we use 1 — Next, for any level of a Equation /J (1 = r^ n > + U'(rao + 5)F(u;o) + / + w'(rao «Orf^(ti')] , to simplify the expression. we 1, r) define recursively a„, Ki(an), and V„'(a„). Let a„ be the highest such that a worker with assets a this period wants to have assets a„_i next period. (2) implies u'((l+r)a„ which uniquely defines a„ since reservation wage + 5-a„_i) =/?yj(a„_i), decreasing and \4'(a„„i) u' is is known. It follows that the solves w((l + r)a„ +5 -a„_i) +/?K(an-i) = u{;ran + Wn) ^Z n the value function solves 14(a„)= (u((l + r)a„ + 5-a„_i)+/?K(a„_i))F(a)„)+ and, using the envelope theorem again, K(aj = (1 + r) U'((l + r)an its H ''^''^^^''^ dF{w), derivative solves + B- a„_i)F(tD.„) + / u'{ran + aOrfF(t^)J . For each level of assets a„, we can also compute the expected discounted cost of the unemployment insurance system. At So Oq, So \ = f= S + -—— l + rj F{wo) 33 - {l + r)BF{wo) l+r-F{vj) - while thereafter Sn= [B + -~The ] F{Wn-l). cost of providing the worker with utihty Kt(a„) compute the cost at arbitrary utility levels is (1 + r)an + 5„. We and choose unemployment interpolate this to benefits B to minimize cost. Next consider cannot fall w>B,so below — = r . accepting any job In fact, ' if a worker is the worker's best option. who ends one do = a slightly , a violation of the borrowing constraint. = — ^ilf) Below changed by this constraint: this point a ,,, , K(ao) worker's assets period with assets a ^ remains unemployed, her assets the following period are no higher than 5 < —= A a' = < — 4tt-t r(H-r) (1 Thus the natural borrowing + r)a + limit is worker must accept any job. K,(ao) and VJ(ao) are /^ u(rao + u;)fl!F(ii;) = -= ^—^ , and V^iao) = (1 + r) u'irao / + w)dF{w). J w_ The cost of a worker at the borrowing limit initial conditions, a„, Ki(a„), V^(a.n)) is zero, since she accepts any job. Given these and 5„ are defined using the same inductive formulae as before. References Aiyagari, S. Rao, "Uninsured Idiosyncratic Risk and Aggregate Saving," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1994, 109 (3), 659-684. 4, 21 Allen, Franklin, "Repeated Principal-Agent Relationships with Lending and Borrowing," Economic Letters, 1985, 17, 23-31. 4 Blanchard, Olivier and Justin Wolfers, "The Role of Shocks and Institutions in the Rise of European Unemployment: the Aggregate Evidence," Economic Jownal, March 2000, 110 (462), C1-C33. 25 Cole, Harold and Ncirayana Kocherlakota, "Efficient Allocations with Hidden Income and Hidden Storage," Review of Economic Studies, 2001, 68, 523-542. 4 34 Feldstein, Martin, "Rethinking Social Insurance," American Economic Review, March 2005, 95 (1), 1-24. 3, 27 _ and Daniel Altman, "Unemployment Insurance Savings Accounts," 1998. NBER Work- ing Paper 6860. 3 _ and James Poterba, "Unemployment Insurance and Reservation Wages," Journal of Public Economics, February- March 1984, 23 (1-2), 141-167. 6 Friedman, Milton, Capitalism and Freedom, University of Chicago Press, 1962. 27 Golosov, Mikhail, Narayana Kocherlakota, and Aleh Tsyvinski, "Optimal and Capital Taxation," Review of Economic Studies, 2003, 70 (3), 569-587. 4 Gruber, Jonathan, "The Consumption Smoothing Benefits American Economic Review, March 1997, 57(1), 192-205. Hall, Robert E., "Lost Jobs," Brookings Papers on of Unemployment 2, 27 Economic Indirect Insurance," Activity, 1995, 1 (1), 221- 273. 25 Hopenhayn, Hugo and Juan Pablo Nicolini, "Optimal Journal of Political Economy, 1997, 105 (2), 412-438. Unemployment Insurance," 2, 5, 15, 16, 17, 19, 25, 27 Katz, Lawrence and Bruce Meyer, "The Impact of the Potential Duration of Unemployment Benefits on the Duration of Unemployment," Journal of Public Economics, February 1990, 41 (1), 45-72. 2 ^- ^ . Ljungqvist, Lars and Thomas Sargent, "The European Unemployment Dilemma," Journal of Political Economy, June 1998, 106 (3), 514-550. 6, 25 _ and _ , Recursive Macroeconomic Theory, second ed., MIT Press, 2004. 5, 11 Lucas, Robert E. Jr. and Edward C. Prescott, "Eciuilibrium Search and Unemployment," Journal of Economic Theory, February 1974, 7(2), 188-209. 6 McCall, John, "Economics nomics, 1970, 5^ (1), of Information 113-126. 3, and Job Search," Quarterly Journal of Eco- 27 Meyer, Bruce, "Unemployment Insurance and Unemployment Spells," Econometrica, July 1990, 58 (4), 757-782. 17 Pissarides, Christopher A., "Short-Run Ecjuilibrium Dynamics of Unemployment, Vacancies, and Real Wages," The American Economic Review, September 1985, 75 (4), 676-690. 6 . Prescott, Edward C. and Robert Townsend, "Pareto Optima and Competitive Equi- libria with Adverse Selection and Moral Hazard," Econometrica, 1984, 52 35 (1), 21-45. 31 Rogerson, William, "Repeated Moral Hazard," Econometrica, Shavell, Steven and Laurence Weiss, "Optimal Payment of 1985, 53 (1), 69-76. 4 Unemployment-Insurance Benefits over Time," Journal of Political Economy, 1979, 57(6), 1347-1362. 2, 5, 15, 19, 27 Spear, Stephen and Sanjay Srivastava, "On Repeated Moral Hazard with Discounting," Review of Economic Studies, 1987, 54 (4), 599-617. 28 Wang, Cheng and Stephen Williamson, "Unemployment in a U, Dynamic Economy," Carnegie- Rochester Conference Insurance with Moral Hazard Series on Public Policy, 1996, 1-41. 27 Warning, Ivan, "Optimal Unemployment Insurance with Unobservable Mimeo. 5, 6, Savings," 2002. 19 Zhao, Rui, "The Optimal Unemployment Insurance Contract: 2000. Manuscript, University of Chicago, July ''284 ^1. O 36 8. 27 Why a Replacement Ratio?," MIT LIBRARIES •- "•m|l(|llMr- 3 9080 02618 2V5I