Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium Member Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/dissolvingpartneOOcram working paper department of economics DISSOLVING A PARTNERSHIP EFFICIENTLY Peter Cramton, Robert Gibbons, and Paul Klemperer* November 1985 406 Number massachusetts institute of technology 50 memorial drive Cambridge, mass. 02139 DISSOLVING A PARTNERSHIP EFFICIENTLY By Peter Cramton, Robert Gibbons, and Paul Klemperer* November 1985 Number ^06 . *Yale University, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, and St. Catherine's College, Oxford, respectively. This project was begun at Stanford University and financially supported by the Sloan Foundation, the National Science Foundation, and the Center for Economic Policy Research. We are grateful to David Gold for posing the problem and encouraging its .analysis and to Roger Guesnerie, Christopher Harris, David Kreps, Robert Wilson, and two referees for helpful suggestions. , DEG3 1988 Dissolving a Partnership Efficiently By Peter Cramton, Robert Gibbons, and Paul Klemperer* November 1985 Abstract Several partners jointly a valuation for the own an asset that asset; the valuations arc a common probability distribution. We may known be traded among them. Each partner has privately and characterize the set of drawn independently from all incentive-compatible and interim-individually-rational trading mechanisms, and give a simple necessary and sufficient condition for such mechanisms to dissolve the partnership ex post efficiently. is constructed that achieves such dissolution whenever it is A bidding game possible. Despite incomplete in- formation about the valuation of the asset, a partnership can be dissolved ex post efficiently provided no single partner owns too large a share; this contrasts with Myerson and Satterthwaite's result that ex post efficiency cannot be achieved when the asset is owned by a singlf party. "Yale University, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, and St. Catherine's College, Oxford, respectively. This project was begun at Stanford University and financially supported by the Sloan Foundation, the National Science Foundation, and the Center for Economic Policy Research. analysis, We are grateful to David Gold for posing the problem and encouraging its and to Roger Guesnerie, Christopher Harris, David Kreps, Robert Wilson, and two referees for helpful suggestions. Introduction 1. When a partnership When municipalities jointly need a hazardous-waste site is to be dissolved, and how much should it or children divide an estate, who should buy out his associates and at what price? dump, which town should provide the be compensated by the others? who should keep When husband and wife divorce, how much should the family house or farm, and the others be paid? We consider partnerships in which each player is i endowed with a share be traded, and specific capital or other transaction costs on the market and efficiently [3] We split the proceeds. make it inefficient of r,- a good to to sell the good look for procedures that allocate the good ex post while satisfying interim individual rationality. Unlike Myerson and Satterthwaite —who show that no procedure can with uncertainty (r\ = 1 and r? = yield both properties in two-player bargaining 0) — we show games that the distributed ownership found in a partnership often makes the two compatible. For the case of n players whose valuations are independently drawn from an arbitrary distribution, is we derive a simple condition that necessary and sufficient for efficient, individually-rational dissolution, and simple bidding game that will accomplish such dissolution whenever Bayesian Nash equilibrium The it application that inspired our analysis was the Federal proposed to make the can be achieved as a some extensive-form game. in Communication Commissions allocation of licenses for cellular-telephone franchises. After closing the FCC we introduce a final allocation list of applicants, the using a simple lottery. Prior to the lottery each applicant has an equal chance of winning, and so can be thought of as owning a l/n share in the license. Our analysis suggests that the applicants would do better to form a cartel (that would win the lottery with certainty) and then allocate the franchise to one via our bidding game; this to resell. A is more similar example is efficient than the lottery, even if the winner airlines shares in the slot equal to their weights in the two-member permitted proposed lottery, is and to assign the let them play - game we propose. As another is number the Federal Aviation Administration's proposal to allocate landing slots at busy airports by lottery. Again, a more efficient approach the "bidding of their application of the theory, consider the following buy-out provision of many partnerships: one side submits a "bu3 -out" offer, and the other side then has : 1 the choice of either buying or selling at these terms. Since this scheme does not guarantee ex-post efficiency (the will player will not, first be inefficiently allocated valuation), it general, submit his valuation, so the object in the other's valuation if is between the first player's bid and too can be improved upon by our bidding game. The bidding game that achieves efficient, individually-rational dissolution differs typical auction in that every player pays or receives a players' bids. Moreover, the set of bidders who pay sum of money that a positive amount is a function of typically is to the winning bidder, but includes the second and other high bidders as well. —such as first- and second-price rational dissolution. This part of our analysis He in the Since such which in efficient, individually- was inspired by Samuelson a similar problem and solves a two-player example distribution on [0,1]. — can achieve all not limited bidding arrangements are not frequently observed, we determine the circumstances more common auctions from a [4], who describes which types are drawn from a uniform finds that split-the-difference bidding (the average of first- and second-price) yields an efficient allocation, but he ignores the individual rationality constraint that players should prefer participation in the game to retaining their current share. (He imposes instead the weaker constraint that players prefer participation to being dispossessed of their current share.) We consider n players and arbitrary distributions and and other similar auctions ma}' accomplish only when efficient, partners' shares are very close to equal. Coase Theorem under incomplete information: instead sion that efficiency exactly this individually-rational dissolution, but Samuelson also provides an interesting interpretation efficiency show that may be when is of his work as an exploration of the of the complete-information conclu- always achieved and that property rights are immaterial, he shows that lost and property efficiency can rights may matter. In these terms, our analysis shows be achieved and how property rights matter. » The tion rest of the game paper is organized as follows. In Sections 2 and 3, we analyze a to determine the set of partnerships that can be dissolved efficiently. introduces a bidding game that accomplishes and Section 5 characterizes the Section 6 shows that efficient dissolution set of partnerships for commonly observed auctions which whenever it revela- Section 4 is possible, efficient dissolution is possible. are efficient in some circumstances. } The Revelation Game 2. n players indexed by Our model has good to be traded Each are € (r, player's valuation € N= r< = and X3"=i [0, 1] is « known 1) { 1, . . n , }. Player owns a share i an(^ ^ias a valuation for the entire privately, but drawn independently from a distribution . it is F common knowledge with support r, of the good of t/,-. that the valuations and positive continuous [r, v] density /. We valuations v t(v) = game consider the direct revelation = {i\(v), to player t. . {v\,. . . tn ,v n (v) }, = r = where {n,. for all v = and then receive an allocation s(v) } s; is (Since this allocation ownership rights, and ^ii(v) , .. which players simultaneously report their in .. € trader-specific, is We ,r n }.) [v,v] the ownership share and n The . may depend on it money the net is f, («),..., s n (t')} { «i outcome functions transfer the vector of initial require that these allocations balance: pair of and {s,t) is Cs i'( v) = 1 referred to as a trading mechanism. A in player with valuation money and u,-, the asset. Also, share to be v,r;, while afterwards player i it is t>_,-.. when he announces S,(tv) is player + is £,'. Let -i = K\i v;r; + m,, which is linear endo%ved with enough money, is utility, mechanism and let only net transfers (s.t) can be taken £_,{•} be the expectation and money transfer define the expected share for by v, = t?;s,- £-i{si{v) } and = Ti (17) £_, { U(v) , is Ui{vi) (s.t) has utility Because of the linear feasible. Then we can so the player's expected payoff The mechanism m,- before participating in the trading i's utility operator with respect to and money we assume that each say v, that any required transfer matter, so player r,-, = VjSj[vi) + Ti[vi). incentive compatible if all types of players all want to report their private information truthfully: tf.-fc) >"t-vS,(u) By the Revelation Principle (Myerson + Ti{u) [2], Vi among attention to incentive-compatible mechanisms. 3 € TV, tv, others), we « - € [r, lose The mechanism t>]. no generality by restricting (s,t) is interim individually rational if all types of all players are better off participating in the their expected payoff) than holding their initial > Ui(vi) The following Vi r,f,- £ lemmas develop a necessary and incentive compatible and individually mechanism (in terms of endowments: A' and v,- E [r, v]. sufficient condition for a mechanism to be rational. Since the proofs are either simple or standard, they are relegated to the Appendix. Lemma i £ N, The trading mechanism 1. Si is increasing {s,t} is incentive compatible if and only if for every and V T (v;)-T (v )= [ i i 'udSi(u) i (IC) i € for all Vi,v* Lemma \v,v). 1 follows implies that U,- from the fact that convex and increasing is in v;, continuity of V, implies that the net utility Lemma at v- = with derivative — C/,(t',) S,- has a r,t>,- Linearity asset. almost everywhere. The minimum over v,- € \v,v\. 2 identifies this worst-off type, and this allows us to restate individual rationality as a single condition Lemma money and the utility is linear in 2. in Lemma 3. Given an incentive-compatible mechanism (s.l), traderi's net i[inf (V.*) + sup(V*)] € = V* In the simplest case, {Vi £,• \ is worst-off type satisfies Si(v*) r,-; equal to his initial ownership right be neither a buyer nor a < T{ Vw < Vi\ S;(w) continuous and has = seller of minimized where [v, v], Si(ll) utility: is that r,-. is. r; > Ti Ww> Vi}. range, so the valuation of the in its the worst-off type expects to receive a share Intuitively, the worst-off type expects on average to the asset, and therefore he has no incentive to overstate or understate his valuation. Hence, he does not need to be compensated in order to induce him to report his valuation truthfully, which This is why he is the worst- off type of trader. an interesting generalization of a similar result exchange for bilateral seller (v) are longer clear is worst who is (r off; = In {0,1}). [3] and who is Myerson and Satterthwaite [3] the lowest-type buyer (v) and the highest-type here the worst-off type typically selling in buying. -1 is between v and v, since it is no ( Lemma 3. for all E i An incentive-compatible mechanism (s,t) individually rational is if and only N r.(O>0, where is defined in v* i Lemmas 4. 2. and individually rational, stated in For any share function s such that transfer function only Lemma (ir) 1-3 lead to a necessary and sufficient condition for a trading mechanism to be incentive compatible LEMMA t such that (s,t) is Lemma 4 below. S, is increasing for all E N, i there exists a and individually rational incentive compatible if and if n m rv V [ i>v Vi J2 [ \l-F{u))udSi(v)- f where v.* I is defined in The "only if" Lemma > "if" part of the — lemma * is F(u)udSi(u) >0, (/) 2 lemma follows part of the balance conditions J2 s ( v ) The if anc^ T2 f «" v) directly = from the previous lemmas and the budget which even feasible mechanism must - 0, proven by constructing a transfer function compatible and individually rational provided the inequality following intuition precise: there exists a transfer rule t (7) holds. t that is satisfy. incentive The proof makes the that entices the worst-off type of each trader to participate in the mechanism, because (J) guarantees that the expected gains from trade are sufficient to bribe every trader to 3. Ex The trading mechanism of the tell the truth. Post Efficiency (s, t ) is mechanism {s(v),f(v)} is ex post efficient if for each vector of valuations v the outcome Pareto-undominated by any alternative allocation (ignoring incentive constraints). Thus, ex post efficiency requires that the asset go to the trader with the highest valuation. post efficient partnership (r,F) can be dissolved efficiently trading mechanism (s,t) that Such a mechanism we A will is For economy of expression,, mechanisms that are incentive compatible and individually rational as efficient trading mechanisms. efficiently will there exists an ex incentive compatible and individually rational. be said to dissolve .the partnership. will henceforth refer to ex post-efficient if A be referred to as a dissolvable partnership. 5 partnership that can be dissolved We now prepared are to answer the central question of this paper: At can be dissolved efficiently? partnerships to some and is empty; that first glance, one might think that the set of dissolvable This F from A 1. can be dissolved efficiently v* = -P an efficient partnership with ownership rights -1 ^,"" 1 Proof: Ex post and G{v t ) ) if and only efficiency requires that the 1 among them. F{u)udG{u) Si{vi) v' satisfies (D). I 4.. An , J Efficient In this section, (t;*) n~ 1 = Bidding we trading mechanism. to dissolve because it (D) 0, good go to the trader who values it the most: < max r,- i.',- = if Vj maxT'y. = the expected share function S, Pr{tV > max t;,,-} r,-, so v' = = F -1 (r " -1 i Fit;)"- ). it. 1 = is given G(v,). game that serves the same purpose Using terminology analogous to that introduced is Lemma 4 yields Game introduce a bidding This in bj' Substituting into (J) of dissolvable partnership, one could use an efficient trading game > Since ties occur with zero probability, they will be ignored By independence, Thus, and valuations independently drawn two or more traders have the highest valuation, then the shares can be (In the event that follows.) trading mechanism. = Ffa) n-\ if what following theorem gives a necessary if !0 split arbitrarily r \l- F{u))udG{v)- / where The not the case. is sufficient condition for the existence of THEOREM partnerships the incomplete information about valuations necessarily leads is, inefficiency in trade. What a useful mechanism as an efficient in Section 3, given a or an efficient bidding complement to the revelation-game analysis of Section 2, uses strategy spaces familiar in practice, namely bids rather than valuations. In a general bidding game, the n players submit sealed 6 bids, the good is transferred to the highest bidder, and each bidder pays a total price Pi{b\ In the efficient bidding game that can precede the bidding. Note that in the efficient bidding game t analyzed below, the total price P, p, (b 1 and a side-payment c, . , sum the is . . , the winning bidder pays a positive price bidders. As bj n p,-, — ) '*—* 1 bj may as usual, but so the second and other high a standard auction, a higher bid buys the player a larger probability of winning. in Here, however, making a higher bid price of losing tickets THEOREM of a price = 6„) b„). A 2. is bidding buying more lottery tickets is like in that the purchase not refunded. game with prices p,(6i,...,fc n ) = 6,- -— J^6y, (P) preceded by side-payments rv' c,-(r 1 is ,...,r„)= an e&cient bidding game: PROOF: We solve for a strictly use the strategy fc(-), then t's UfaA) = all = J" b(vj) but the highest of the 71 | — [ti - + b; and "(ry u) 1 condition is is is b(u).) positive (negative) for satisfied. We | -b(u) n - u) = 1 The 6,- fc,- (C) -6(t/)] - the v,- 77 ["' 1 others is dG(u) F(vj)/F(u). (Since types are independent, same expected i value, conditional on therefore solves than (greater than) 6(u,-), the second-order are interested in the symmetric solution, which satisfies 6(v,-)= — 1 best response for less If with valuation + J! other bids generate the the value of the highest bid: this Since dUi/dbi udG(u), ' expected utility from bidding / dF(vj rv' increasing symmetric Bayesian equilibrium. Jfc-i(6,) where 5(u) " any dissolvable partnership. dissolves it j 'udG[v)--J2 / vdG{v) + b{v). Since 6' > the good. 0, this equilibrium The constant game the rules of the 6(r) is ex post is arbitrary, efficient: the trader with the highest valuation receives equals the lowest amount, presumably zero, that (it when allow a player with valuation v to bid), and disappears p, and b are composed: Pi [b( Vl ),...,b(v n )] Some simple = - f' udG(u)+ -L-J2 ( u )- algebra verifies that (T) and (C) define the transfer rule used Lemma of the proof of 4, so individual rationality Since the side-payments depend on F, but not on v is udG I"' = r = is guaranteed. {n,...,r n } that follows, since the prices p,- who in the "If" part | (through t>* = {v\, {vi,...,u„}, they can precede the bidding procedure. to compensate large shareholders, P) . . ., t* }) Their purpose are effectively dispossessed in the bidding are independent of r and so treat all and game shareholders alike. Accordingly, the side-payments are zero for the equal-shares partnership (jf,...,^). 5. Characterization Results We now offer four propositions that characterize the set of partnerships which efficiently. First, The proofs can be dissolved are not of interest in themselves, and so are given in the Appendix. we formalize the idea that it is large shareholders that make interim individual ratio- nality difficult to achieve: for any distribution F, the equal-shares partnership but the partnership PROPOSITION in The 1. is dissolvable set of partnerships that can be dissolved efficiently is a nonempty, which one player owns the entire asset convex, symmetric subset of the n shares partnership (£, PROPOSITION 2. A . . . , is not. — 1-dimensional simplex and is = ,r„ centered around the equal- ±). one-owner partnership {rj l,r2 = = 0} cannot be dissolved i efficiently. Proposition 2 generalizes to seller relationship rationality. many .buyers Myerson and Satterthwaite's [3] result that, a buyer- cannot simultaneously satisfy ex post efficiency and interim individual This speaks to the time-honored tradition of solving complex allocation problems by resorting to lotteries: even if the winner is 8 allowed to resell the object, such a scheme is . inefficient because the one-owner partnership that results from the lottery cannot be dissolved efficiently. These propositions are derived by making the appropriate substitutions orem 1. Note that each partner's ownership share As an example, if into (D) of The- enters the inequality through v' r, the traders' valuations are drawn from a uniform distribution on [0, 1], then (D) simplifies to z_ Thus, if for a (D') is uniform distribution, n + 1, (D 1 ) 1 the extremities of the simplex cannot be dissolved from be dissolved efficiently if i and only determines a convex, symmetric subset of the simplex, shown as the unshaded region in Figure number y 1 a partnership r can By Proposition satisfied. - ' for the case efficiently. n = 3. Only partnerships in For the uniform case, as the of partners (n) grows, the percentage of partnerships that are dissolvable increases 58% to 93% largest possible to 99% owner in as n increases from 2 to 4 to 6. Also, the percentage share of the a dissolvable partnership increases from 79% to 82% increases from 2 to 20 to 200. FIGURE 1. Dissolvable partnerships with ?! = 3 and F(v) = (0.1.0) (.3.. 7.0) (.7. .3.0) (1,0,0) .7.0..3) .3.0. .7) u. to 88% as n By amount contrast with Proposition 2, however, partnerships with an arbitrarily small may of distributed ownership (Note that the proof employs a very special be dissolvable. distribution.) Proposition some for 3. Any partnership not owned by a single player can be dissolved efficiently distributions F. Finally, if any partnership number replicated a sufficient is of times then can be it dis- solved efficiently. Consider the partnership R(n = 777) | {r,- = l/m, i = 1, . ., . m; r - ; = 0, j = m+ 1, . . .,nm}. m times — the of m goods, so This partnership results from replicating the n-player, one-owner partnership m partners who own own positive shares each 1/771 of endowment the total partnerships continue to be represented by points in a simplex. any other n-player partnership can be represented Proposition 4. such that for all Given m > F in replication of a similar way. and an n-player partnership {n M the m-fold The m-fold , r„}, there exists a finite M replication of the n-player partnership can be dissolved efficiently. We think of this result as complementing the core-convergence theorems for exchange econ- omies: replicating the economy sufficiently often reduces the effect of the incomplete infor- mation to An zero. interesting special case is R{2 | For 771). 777 = 1, Myerson and Satterthwaite (and our Proposition 2 above) proves that the partnership cannot be dissolved For larger values of and Satterthwaite here each bidder 771, [l], R is much like the double auction studied by Wilson may demand up to m units of the good. Satterthwaite show that ex post efficiency on each side of the market. is efficiently. and Gresik [5] When is (Think of each l/m achieved for the When approached in the limit; each bidder wants same example when there m more specifically, for if there are units, on the other hand, are as few as each side of the market. (To see this, check that [D') holds for R{2 10 share of each bidder wants one unit, Gresik and the uniform case, they find that 99.31 percent of the gains from trade are realized ex post efficiency s result although there each bidder wants only one unit of the good, whereas the partnership as one unit of the good.) six traders : | two traders on 2) for this example.) . Simple Trading Rules 6. The efficient Although the same bidding game proposed efficient trading mechanism implicit we effect, prefer the bidding mentioned above, more important, shifted from the of it in Theorem in game for 2 dissolves in Lemma any dissolvable partnership. 4 and game mechanism designer 1 achieves the two (somewhat imprecise) reasons. And uses strategy spaces familiar in practice. the bidding Theorem First, as second, and probably a great deal of the computational burden has been to the players: the designer makes a simple calculation side-payments and prices, using (C) and (P), while the players do most of the work their calculation of the optimal bidding strategy b(v,). In the trading in mechanism, on the other hand, the players simply report their valuations while the designer shoulders all of the computational burden. In this spirit, we find it disappointing that the side-payments given by (C) in depend on the distribution F, for it than do the players. Ideally we would seems plausible that the designer like a of J", so that the designer could always will recommend it may depend on F and game We less well vithout assessing the distribution of analyzes the composition of the players' strategies and the designer's players that know F 2 bidding game that can be described independently the partners' private valuations. Unfortunately, the Revelation Principle no guidance as to how to decompose this Theorem map from is game no help here: rules, it but gives types to outcomes into strategies for the rules for the designer that are independent of F have not addressed the issue of finding the optimal bidding game or trading mech- anism that is independent of F, in part because of the difficulty (Asking only for independence of F, for instance, is in formalizing this notion. not enough, because the designer can ask the players to report F, and then implement the side-payments given by (C) ports agree, and forbid trade if the reports do not agree.) Instead, approaches to bidding games that are independent of F. in the we offer if the re- two speculative hope that these ideas will be expanded upon. First, it may be possible for the designer to use the players 1 bids to estimate F, and then to use this estimate to construct side-payments that relax the individual rationality 1 constraints, like those in (C). This process seems both complex and delicate. 11 Second, some bidding games that are independent of In particular, the the set of dissolvable partnerships. equal-shares partnership for any distribution F. when compared other virtues and familiar. Second, saves the cost of all it is can dissolve a limited subset of game we discuss below dissolves the game in Theorem and the good is a u k + 1-price auction" in For k k = = 1/2 this it is the b t are is like first- all = l[kb e simple = + (l-k)b f important. When it relies less ), 1 it is like ... ,b„}, and k E a second-price auction, the split-the-difference scheme described by Samuelson is third, each of the others and second-highest bids from {61,62, a first-price auction, for k the bidders. This it is required to pay. is [0,1]. and for [4]. Mote that the revenue from bidding (namely, the highest bidder's bid) among First, three which the players submit sealed bids who pays transferred to the highest bidder, p{b l ,b 2 ,...,b u ) where bj and And losing bids by submitting only one nonzero bid.) we consider 2. game has vulnerable to collusion. (In the efficient bidding game, a cartel heavily on the risk neutrality of the bidders, since only the winner Specifically, bidding In addition, this to the efficient bidding less F is divided equally the original ownership shares are unequal, the individual rationality constraints could be more easily met by paying losing bidders in proportion to their shares, but then partners owning different shares would have different equilibrium bidding strategies so the partner with the highest valuation might not win, violating ex post efficiency. 2 We begin by calculating an equilibrium bidding strategy for this auction. Calculating the interim expected utility associated with this equilibrium then determines the set of partnerships that can be dissolved efficiently using the k is analogous to that introduced PROPOSITION 5. A k + in Section 1-price auction -f- 1-price auction. (Again, the terminology 3.) has a symmetric equilibrium bidding strategy given by b Proposition auction is 6. The ^= V ' \F(r,) - • A-]" set of partnerships that can be dissolved efficiently using a k a nonempty, convex, symmetric subset of the simplex and equal-shares partnership (^ , i). 12 is + 1-price centered around the Thus, an equal-shares partnership can always be dissolved auction. Such a simple auction only works, however, when equal, since the auction ignores the ownership rights efficiently by any k + 1-price 1 partners' shares are approximately and this makes large shareholders r unwilling to participate. For the uniform case, the A-f 1-price auction dissolves a partnership < (maxr,)--' which for n = = n and n if and only if no partner's share exceeds 57.7%, 5.5%, and 0.5%, respectively. if the uniform distribution is jj^y, The 2.) intuition is efficient = 200 satisfied is (A special property of bidding game, which are given after that, because the auction treats all players as share l/n, large shareholders will participate only the cost of being, in 20, that these results are independent of k. Contrast these results, however, with the corresponding results for the Proposition 2, effect, dispossessed. As n if if they owned the expected gain from trade exceeds increases, the expected gain from trade of the worst-off type decreases: a player with high share and high valuation becomes almost certain to be just outbid by players with slightly- higher valuations. if n<Kp . and PROPOSITION N some there will exist in a € [0, 1] the limit, only shareholders with p<l/n are willing to participate. in 7. As — n oc, the only partnership that can be dissolved efncientiy That is. by a t + 1- letting p n be the largest n-player partnership thai any partner can have such that the partnership can be — dissolved efncientiy. jj^ 7. given a share p such that a partner with share p will be willing to participate only p price auction is the equal-shares partnership (£,...,£). share Thus 1 as n — oc. Conclusion A simple extension of Myerson and Satterthwaite [3] shows that with incomplete information no mechanism can guarantee that an object to be traded who values that if it most, if the ownership possible. Further, is it is initially among a possible, it owned by in is be allocated to the person a single party. In contrast, we show partnership, ex-post efficient allocation is often can be achieved by a simple bidding game. In a of partnerships, our observation that the be dissolved efncientiy way is distributed when more general model influencing the the object will range of partnerships that can centered around equal shares suggests that this might be a factor which partnerships are formed. 13 Footnotes 1. More precisely, estimating an example, suppose that F F seems complex and using the estimate seems known is to be approximately uniform on delicate. with v € [0,T>] [11, As V]. Consider playing the bidding game of Theorem 2 without the side-payments. Then for every pair of players {i,j}, use the remaining ?i — F, as follows. 2 players' bids to estimate use the symmetric equilibrium bidding strategy identified in the text to distribution of valuations F into a distribution of bids. distributions described above in order to And second, vary maximize some goodness-of-fit the two distributions of bids, one observed and the other calculated. calculate the side-payment cy(ri, ... r„) given in (C) and let , this construction, the i map F an arbitrary over the set of imposed on criterion Now First, use this estimate to pay j the amount cy/(n— payments received by any one player depend only on the other 1). In players' bids, so the equilibrium strategies are unaffected. Therefore, the size of the subset of the set of dissolvable partnerships that can be dissolved in this way depends only on how elaborately constructed side-payments mimic those defined by (C) 2. We could for even- partner j divide j's bid among the when F known. is other (n well these — 1) players in proportion to the other's relative shares, since then incentives for the bidders are unaffected by their relative shares. This is an example of the type of auction discussed in the previous footnote and would typically perform better than the auction considered here, at some cost in terms of greater complexity. 14 . Appendix This Appendix supplies the proofs of Lemmas LEMMA (s,t) is incentive compatible if T i €A , 1. The trading mechanism S{ is increasing and Propositions 1-4 1-7. and only if for every and Titf) - r = Ti{vi) u dSi(u) (IC) i for all Vi v* , €E PROOF: Only T,-(u), or [v, v] If (s,t) is If. = incentive compatible, then Ui(v,) + T (vi) > { r,S,(u) + equivalently > Ui[vi) Ui(u) + ( Vi - u)Si{u), implying that U; has a supporting hyperplane at v with slope and has derivative ^Ef = S, almost everywhere. Also, U i (We use the = (v i )-U,(v:) S, £,-(«) > 0. Thus, U,- is convex must be increasing, and 1^' S,iv)du. Stiekjes integral throughout this paper, so that any discontinuities in the ex- By pected share function are accounted for in the integral.) P = Si(v) dv ViSiivi) - i.;S,-(t.;j - 1 which together with the definition Adding the integration by parts, jT' udS,(u). 1 If. ViSj(v;) of 17, yields [IC). identity Vi\Si{vi) - Si[v*)] = dSi{u) / vi to [IC) results in Vi[Si{vi) - 5,-(t>?)] + r.lv.) - Ti{vfi P = * where the inequality follows because the integrand Si is increasing. is (tV - «) dS,-(u) nounegative for Rearranging the terms on the lefthand side yields v,s,{vi) which is '» incentive compatibility. + Ti{vj) > | 15 v,Si{v*) + r,(i.;), > 0, all 7,7,11 € [v,w], since LEMMA at v* = Given an incentive-compatible mechanism (s,t), trader 2. i[inf(V;*) + sup(r')] V = * {v, | t PROOF: The net by Lemma 1. Therefore, trader S;(u) > or v' = r,- and or S,(u) decreasing < r, v, respectively. > such that 5,(u) r,- 3. for all € i An € [ t'* = r,- V r, v < net utility bound w,- V is E/,-(t',-) w > — v,}. r U] , , is convex But r,. -^ = 5, minimum then the in f, and left almost everywhere, First, S,- suppose that occurs at the boundaries = i'* (1) suppose jumps past r,-, = 5,- r,-, is continuous and strictly increasing, which minimizes trader then the v,- at which S,- i's net utility; jumps minimizes net over an interval, then each type in the interval incentive-compatible mechanism {s.t) is v w three cases deal with the case where there exists u and r,-: is is equally worse B individually rational if and only if N We Lemma > (in) o. 2. need only check individual rationality at the valuation v' Lemma 2. or Tjv'-rTj(v') > denned r,-v' . in I Lemma 4. For any share function transfer function only which r,-v,, Thus, the individual-rationality constraint becomes v' Si(v*)-rT,-(v*) > r,-v*. minimized arbitrarily select any valuation in the interval to be the worst-off type. v" is defined in PROOF: r, r, Four cases need to be considered. r,(v,') where is minimized at the point where the is such that S,(v*) S,- S,(w) > v,; with valuation u,-. and S;(w) < utility; (3) finally, if S,(u) Lemma in The next not continuous and o5 and we can i's for all u then there exists a unique (2) if Si is i with respect to {/,- T, is < Sj(u) net utility where [r.r], utility to trader right derivatives of increasing, e i 's t such that (s,t) s is such that S,- is increasing for all i € N, there exists a incentive compatible and individually rational if and if V y2\[ where v' is defined in [l-F{u)}udSi{u)- r* F{v)udS;{u)]>0, Lemma 2. 16 (I) PROOF: Only Lemma Suppose if. (s,i) incentive compatible and individually rational. is Then from 1, = Tifa) Titf) - J\dSi(u). t Integrating over all types in \v,v] yields V £i {Ti (v )} t = T,(v:)- [ = Ti(v-)- udSi(u)dF( Vi f' — * ) 1 V r I dF{vi)udSi(u)+ J u=v' J t,=u = - J\l - Tiiv-) F(v)} v dS,(v) + 12?=i t>i v ) = line follows v, F(u)u dSi{u), J"' — I where the second fu= v JI"=r dF(vi)udS,(u) •' from changing the order of integration. Budget balance requires we have for all v, so £>{r,te)ww {I>(»)}=.o. 1=1 Therefore, summing over all L r'( r r = . From Lemma if. is traders yields V S [ \l-F{u))«dS,iu)- f' must be nonnegative 3. T,-(v*) The proof ) t=i for all TV,- t>( v ) = = Lemma c,- - = c; - individual rationality if and only = -X>,(tv)+ " ,=1 which results in 2V(t£) = >' = 0- is Then, — 0- J S. ± E"=i u dSJ (")i after changing the order of integration. incentive compatible. F(u)]udS,-(tt), Finally, by Lemma so we can choose l udSiiu)-——J2 r[l-F(u)]udSj(u), r,-(t';)>0. 3, we have A little algebra shows the hypothesis of Lemma 4 ^"_i T,(r*)>0. ['' / + -i- ?['[!- if T,-(t:*)>0. to be equivalent to the condition c, c 5_ dS,- («) -r udSi(v) f" guarantees that (s,f) 1 ^>'( t; *) rvj i u / Q implies J2?=i Ti{vi) so which implies ^"=1 by construction. Let U (v) where 32?= i i, F(u)udSitv)}. " | 17 j*i J s. ' PROPOSITION 1. Tie be dissolved efficiently set of partnerships that can convex, symmetric subset of the n - l-dimensional simplex and shares partnership (^ Proof: Use (D) to is is a nonempty, centered around the equal- £). , define <j> — £" : > Z by V = 21 ^(r) f Convexity follows from concavity of dd -t.--dF(r-)"- __ d 2 d> (£ n_1 drf — TT where the equality l dvt . — 1 —r < 1 r, 0. dr,- > because at v'(±) = we have f tv/(r,)F(tv) n - nF"~ — t? — dt, 1 and 0, n dr; d-d> = 1 -v; dvj_ _ follows from relabeling the partners. Finally, </>(£,...,£) ) = 1 72—1 dTidrj F [ vJiv^Fivi)"- which we have because 4>, dri Symmetry - 2 A' r./(v.)F(t:,)"- dr, (n +" 2. n dv, dtV - A for all t;,- £ B" 1 f - dvi «.-/(«,-)^(tv) dv, : : / arises after integrating each — l)F r'<l PROPOSITION F(vi) / 2 = {rj 0, term by parts, and the inequality holds since \v',v}. so the first one-owner partnership > term dominates the third. I.t? = rn = I 0} cannot be dissolved efficiently. PROOF: For the n-player partnership {rj = l.r 2 = r„ = 0}. integrating by parts in (D) yields F"~ 1 dv+ which fails for all finite n. Proposition for some 3. Any / F"dv > 0, ! partnership not owned by a single player can be dissolved efficiently distributions F. PROOF: The proof where a E (0. i) is by construction, using the distribution F(u) and u(v) = 1+ {[T - l){v - v)/{v 18 - = v)} (so u{v) {1 = — \u{v)]~°}/{l — T~°} 1 and u{v) = T). Take an arbitrary partnership {r -2 for .p" Fn~ and l < r,| n u *w-E=i nOf" in T = cf — T 1 ° 1 Using a binomial expansion . in (D) yields l-2o i/ -(n-2) 1 2q 1-2q v 1-cr a — terms let l-o - Q 1 i=i t, -(n-1) - Q T in +• - 2q 1 show that the above terms to and and performing the integration indicated ( It suffices V:} 1 r- 11=1 ignored are of lower order, and so are insignificant, and all < 1. limits are finite because u(v*(r,-)) approaches a finite limit, Vr; have r,- terms < in T = since u(v'{\)) 1, T, which does not stay approach oo, replace T by — (1 1 a) -1 / and T— factor of oo, d (1 — — d). ! 1 - 2a d(l-a)J Since q • € (0, i), 2 1 for d Proposition 4. such that for all £ vt3§--. 1)- Given m — — < ^ (It is crucial that > F 1 - 2d d(l-a) This yields collect terms. (n-l)(l-dy-i + rf(l-2a) ' So 6{r) > > it has an extra — 1 provided 0, for sufficiently large T. and an n-player partnership M the m-fold we To show that the oo.) the hrst term goes to oo as d 0. so the the terms in the lower Therefore, the second term above can be ignored, since 1. 1 which holds T finite as 1 =r((i-flAs +oo with 7\ because the braces tend to in i {rj,. ..,r„ E tiere exists a finite }, M replication of the n-player partnership can be dissolved efficiently. PROOF: By the concavity of established in Proposition <j> holds for the n-player partnership {n = = l/m = = j which is {r,- : and the partnership 1, , m; of interest tj is {r, = = l.rj r„ = m + 1, 71/.V = j . . . 1 r." nl , = rj A (A'- r' 1 —l j = . Then {N/n) we have d?/ T ,/ v - f*'- show that the mn = N = ! 1 to J dV -L, 19 f ( 1) NFN - i result 0}. the 772-fold replication of mji}. Let N/n: 1 After integrating by parts in (D) and collecting terms, **(*)- V(JV-1) 1. it suffices - {n - A'(.V-l) df n ) du + m= N/n 1,..., TV}. = where t>* = v'{n/N) pair of terms = ^{(n/N) (k - : Consider two arbitrary values k\ < N— J = oo, v* Jll — F N du. Then /£ tfr K du (v' - (fci - v)A^ + . and 7 A we have 7 let < ki /£ F*" < A- 2 r / -r „ >Ai J (A-j (tv-^lAT + (* - r-Sr - n)At t>* =A] — e > 0. and let A'i = 1 — ie, and so the last ratio above approaches fixed ti, as required. Proposition 5. Let / . for = t = Jk F 2 1,2. As du and J[K\. So f^ du A*o 1 = 1— i£. — ic and Then rj A- 2 ) A'f k2 (A-l-l)(AV^2) Fix v* (/:,-) J/K2 < du < 1 = F A", A^A"^', we have I+J Ji: if n (li,* ), J/A'j and first : 1 1 (*, >K +J> J> du du 1 over [r*,U], the positive for sufficiently large A' > F*- - 1)F A'<1 (A' J^F K du + J^F K du _ ^Af- + /;= f»-i du + ;;• I+J ^ /; f^-i du Since I < 1 F*'" du is f» from A- 2 so for sufficiently large v, pair — ['• jv 1 1) j;;: lim A-oo A'F^" - Since ]. The second strictly positive. is — A + K-*2)" ' (A~i/A* 2 ) — A • made can therefore be while v' to exceed — 1 A2 — — v — A2 , (l/n) for I AH l-price auction has a symmetric equilibrium bidding strategy given by v f b{Vi) = \F(~] ~ V; \F{vi) PROOF: Let G(x) = F(x) n ~1 b(vj), then r*s expected utility Uifabi) = [ + '' f If . i — - ' f T [*6(:r) 7! — with valuation + (1 - fc)6,-]) 1 r,- others will use the strategy is dG'(x) -[kbi +(l-k)b(x))dE(y\x)dG(x) r -[*%) + » " y=<>- l (b.) Jx=b-Ub.) r=t->(i.)-Jv=b(''.) / d- " Jx=b-l{bi)Jv=v + b, /-i" A-]" conjectures that the from bidding (v, - - 1 20 (1 -*)&(*)] dfi"(y | x)dG{x), — where H(y n — 1 = x) | [F(y)/F(x)] n 2 (for other bids given that the largest ^L = („ - 6,)p[6- 1 (6 1 do, The symmetric is x. The is the distribution of the second-largest of the best response for ^lir[6- )]^ do, 1 (6 1 therefore solves ; )]- 2 (r[6- I (6 1 n )] - k) = 0. - b{vi) = n b{vi) —f(^r- differential equation can be solved using the integrating factor \F(vj) This linear is y<x) equilibrium 6(17) satisfies vi solution . — k] n \ the a one-parameter family satisfying [v, - b(v,)} \F{vi) - k)" = \F(v) - k] n du. J"' We to choose c to make the righthand side equal to zero at ±00 F~ as Vi approaches 1 (k) from above or below. This choice *(*)-*- efficient: It = F~ u,- 1 [F(vi) - (k); otherwise, bids of c yields the tend symmetric k]n V > Finally, since (k). 1 — equilibrium and truth-telling occurs at = F~ v,- 0, this equilibrium is ex-post the partner with the highest valuation receives the good with probability one. That remains, then, to verify interim individual rationality. U'[Vj.b(vi)) — t;v, >0 for all v; r ( Vi € \v. vj. — - where [fc&(x) C7"[f,-, fc(t-*;)] - (1 - is, we want u>(r,-, r,) = is k)b{vi)]) dG(x) n Jv l + [ f" -[kb(vi) -f I' ±[kb{y) Partially differentiating with respect to for fixed 77, w is minimized at ~~w{ri) =(l f"(r,-) + (1 + r, k)b{x)} dH(y \ x) dG(x) (l-k)b(x)}dH(y\x)dG(x). and applying the = G -1 (r,). Let w(rj) - k){-±- fb[x) dG(x) first-order condition = - w\vj (r,),r,]; then ri b{v7)} + a-{j>*)"- 2 [i - rK)]6(»D - /'' + -^r f 21 fc (*) dGr (*) b(y)dS(y\x)dG(x)}. shows that, — PROPOSITION auction is The 6. set of partnerships that can be dissolved efficiently using a k a nonempty, convex, symmetric subset of the simplex and is -f- 1-price centered around the equal-shares partnership (£,.-.,£)• PROOF: Convexity follows from the concavity of u;(r,), which holds because tc'(r,-) = — v*(r,-) i and = — jf-v*(r,) < u/'(r,) since terms involving — 1 k. We n = G~ l F(vl) n-2 — x b(x)dG(x)>T j[ v- We [1-F(v*)}b(v:)> fc(x) in l i b(v:) the integral and simplifying. I 11 ./ Z V P b{x)dG{x)-— [ - [ b(y)dH(y\x)dG(x) x= „- J v =v- E 7. As n — do, tie only partnership that can be dissolved efficiently That price auction is-ihe equal-shares partnership (1,. ..,£). PROOF: It suffices is. ~- to — 1 as j; — oc. show that given 6 > 0. N there exists individual rationality fails for a player with share (1 -f such that for ,1- 16. ==-) r, i |( — 6^ < all + (d»-*)(v). Thus, is necessarily false for and valuation of winning) (value of winning) <(!)(!) (1 Let d(8) n > = F \v{ T>( / (probability of losing) (value of losing) ) + (probability S)/n. ^— Interim individual rationality for a player with share iv( 1- letting p n be the largest r r by a k-~ partnership that any partner can have such that the partnership can be in a n-player dissolved efficiently, which second, (l/n), again by substituting b(v') for b{x) and b{y) in the integrals and simpli- PROPOSITION share And have Jv = G~ First, consider the V {\/n) by substituting b[v*) for consider the terms involving k. fying. follows from relabeling the have -L_ at v' Symmetry ). Finally consider the equal-shares partnership in two steps. partners. at v' = F _1 (r^ -1 t'* + ±6) all sufficiently < I + tuT -1 large n. 19 I , : c ) N . i •*- ripg interim s i ) < implies 1. References [l] Gresik, Thomas market becomes A. and Mark efficient as the A. Satterthwaite: number "The rate of traders increases: at which a simple an asymptotic result for optimal trading mechanisms," Research Paper No. 641. Graduate School of Manage- ment, Northwestern University, 1985. [2] Myerson, Roger B.: "Incentive compatibility and the bargaining problem," Econometrica Vol. 47, (January 1979), 61-73. [3] Myerson, Roger B. and Mark A. Satterthwaite: bilateral trading," Journal of [4] Samuelson, William: Economic Theory "A comment on "Efficient Wilson, ROBERT: for Vol. 28, (April 1983), 265-281. the Coase theorem," in Models of Bargaining, edited by Alvin Roth, Cambridge University [5] mechanisms Game Theoretic Press, 1985. "Incentive efficiency of double auctions," Econometrica Vol. 53, (September 1985), 1101-1116. 23 Figure 1. Dissolvable partnerships with n = 3 and F(u) (0.1,0) (.7, .3,0) (1,0.0) 7,0, •3,0,.7) [Mrl) 24 .3) - u. I k J J Date Due 91991 JUL 1*199! Lib-26-67 c^ N