Document 11141618

advertisement
p
nenverr
eve g u
ive p n ever
ver
r
nev
r
er
up nev
never e
e
nneveer
ev r
vr
never nee
give
ne
never
nver
nev
e
n ev r
never
r
v
up
give
up
givenever
n ev er
e u
never
e up
gvie up
er
never
n evenr
ever
nneevver never
gi veup never
ne v e r
n ev e r
n ev e r p
up p
up
nev er
e
r
r
r
e ve
never
u
e v er
u
gi ve
v
never
r
n eve
e
nnever
n everv
eer
nenver gi
never ver
ne
ve
give u p
n ever
e
r
never
e
r
nev
ver gi neve
e up
up
give
neve
nv e
r
never
n ever
n ever
r
er iv
r gi ve
neve giupve up nev ngver
r never nerev
nev n n ever
ne
er
e
ne v e
nenveveerr er ever
nev
gi e
never
gi
neve
vr
r ne
never
n ver
r er n veer
n ve neve n ev
nev er
r
nv
never n
e ver er
nevenrever never
never
ne v er
never
e
never
e
nev
neve
r
n ever n ever
never gvie up
give
neve
gi
ve
n ever r
gve up
never n ever neiver
never nev
neve
er
r ne r
ve
er
never
nev u
g up up r n give e u pnev ernever never never
evveerup givnever
giveup give up iv e gi ve
v up
r
never
e
nre v er
give up
ne ve
e
r
u
e
never
r
ve ne
ne ver
ve up
never neve
p
gvie
er
nev
never
never
never
up gi veup never
er
nev r ne
nvverer
ne
n ev e r
er
neve
nev
give up
never
never
e
e
nev
nev
er
never
n
gi ve up v r nev
ee
nev
never
e
nev
up er nev er
give nev
nev e
r
n eve
er
nee
vr
e er
never
never
neve
r
neve
never
neve
never
nv
never
neve r
neve r
er
nrevnever
never
up
never
give
neve
r
ne ver
r
r nneevv eer n eve
p
giveu
gvie up
never
er
nev
ne ve
r ive u
g
er
n nev r
nuepv
er pn er
ev
ve nev r
n giever e neverr n ver
n ever
e
nnever nenv egivve upiveup
er g
p
i ve
neger
v
nev e
r
ev
nneveerer
nv
r ne er
neve v
never
r
nevneerve
p
never
nev
ne ver
never
neve
e
p
u
er
ver
nevenrev nee
u
gi ve r
r n r ne never
r
e nevenrever
r never eve n e v er u
er v
giv
never
er e neve r
never
nev
r
ve
nev nev
er
v
r
nev
gi egive
ne
n eve ne er
n ever
never
never
r
gi v
v
never never
r
r never
eve
ver
neuvper n never ne
gi ve up
n ever
er
r
give v er
nev
neve
er
nneever
nev r
p
DI A N OI A
DIANOIA
up
gi
r
ne
nev er
ve
e
nevnever
r
give up
never
r
r
v
g i ve up
r
up
i v e up
v r
v r
v er
r
g i ve u p
up
g iv e
i
up
n eve r
up
g i ve up
gi v e
e
up
up
p
e up
g
n e v ievre
up
g i ve
er
u
g i ve u p
up
n e v er
g i ve u p
v r
up
g ve up
e
n ever
e
n ev e
r
up
e
er
er
ne v
e
ne v
er
ne v er
r
er
ne v e r
r
ne v e r
e v er
v er
r
ne v e
up
iv e
p
up
g iv e
up
p
e
g i v e up
g ve u
p
e r i g i ve u
u
e v er
gi ve up
p
e up
ne v e r
i ve u p
r
n ev e
e
up
g i ve
up
i v e up
u
r
up
n eve r
neve
giv e up
gv
e
u
e up
p
n eve
ie
e
e
ne v er
ne v er
gi v e up
ne v e r
i v e up
ne v e
r
up
v
v
i
ne
up
v
e
e
nevr
r
gi
r
ne ve
g ie u
giv e
ne
r
give
ne ve r
up
eve r
v
neve
e up
giv
ne
ne ve r
never
ne
i ve u p
ve
gi
e
ne v e r
u
u
e
nev
gvie
never
never
u
give
r
neve
give u
never
ne ve r
giv
p
neve
up
r
ne
ne ve r
u
give
give
u
up
up
g iv e
nev
r
rne
ne
er
ne
neve
never
r
r
n eve
never
never
ve
r
ne
never
ne
up
never
never
never
e e
never
gvieup
never
ver
ne
n ever never
n ever
gi
g i ve u p
v
r
up
ver
r
ne
p
gi ve u
neve
never
n eve r
v
ne ve r
never
e
eve
p
ve up
eve r gi
v
e
never n ev rne
ne
ne ver
giv e
er
gi
ne
nev e
ne
never
give up
e er
ne ve r
ee
ne
p
nev enr everne ve
never
ne
gi ve
e e ver
neve
never
giv e
g i eurp
e ver
er
ne
ne
never
never
gi
Featur ng an nterv ew w th R chard Kearney
Char es See g Professor n Ph osophy
g i ve up
ne
r
gi
neve
ne
nev e
n eve r
ne
n ev
e
nev
e
nev
ne ve
eve r
ev
n ever
give e
never
r
p
neve
e
ne
n ev r
ne ve
e ne ver
n ev
e ne
n ev
r
n ev
r
e
gi veu
er
e er
nev
never
gi
ne ve r
e
ne v r
n eve r
er n
e
n ev er
v
r
ev
e
n evernever
rv
gi
giveup
g i v e up
gi
n eve r
e
ve u
r
r
e
n ev er
g ie u
p
eu
e
ne ve
ne
n eve
r
n ever
ne
neve
nevner e
ev
p
e er
give
gi
gi ve up
r
r
r
u
neve r
never e e
n e n ver
r
e
p
ne e
ev n
nev e
ne ver
v
neve
ne
n eve r
give
e
g iv
never
n ever
e
ne v r
never
never
ever
nevee u
n ever
ne ve
r
r
r
neve
r
ne ve r
er
n ev
nev
gi
e up
never
r
neve
r
never never
e
neve r
ne
n eve
g i ve
neve
p
give
never
neve
r e
ne n
r
nneevveer
neve
e er
never
nev
n ev
nev
neve
e
r
ve
ne
ver
e
ne
nev
u
gi e
r
ne
never
give up
eve
never
neve
r nev e
ne
n
ne v
nevereve never
ne v
n ever
gi
ev
g i veup
ne ver
never
never
p
never
never
giv e
r
n eve r
up
e
ne v
v
ne ve
ne v e
never
ne
r
e
n eve r
ee
eve
en
ne ve
p
never
ne v
ne ve
nev er
eve r
er
ne v
p
r
ne ve r
ne ve r
v
gi
p
i e u pr
n ev e
p
n e ve r
giv e up
g i ve up
ve r
gi v e u p
g i ve up
e
e
up
n eve r g i v e
p
up
gi
p
r
e
ne
up
g i ve
p
g ive u p
up
g i v e up
n ever
up
r
ne v e r
n e v er
up
ve r
g i v e up
n eve r
gi v
n e u
n ever
ne v e
r
ne v e r
gi v e
up
e up
giv e u p
ne v e
v egr
p
p
p
i
up
up
ve
p
e
giv e
u ep
up
g iv e
e up
e ve r
up
p
uu
v e rn e v er
ne
n e v er
u
v er
ne
gi v
e
v er
ne
v r
e
g iv
g iv e up
ne v er
giv e
ne v e r
ne v e r
n ev er
r
ev e
n eve r
giv e
ne
gi v e u p
gi ve
p
p
i v e up
v er
n ever
n ever
n eve r
ne v e r
n eve
ne v e r
er
n e v er
p
r
giv e u p
v e up
gi ve up
r
n ev e
r
iv e
ne v
n eve r
e
ve
n ev er
v u
g
g i v e up
p
g i ve u
u
ve
gi v e u p
er
gi v e up
v er
ne
up
gi v e
e
r
ne v e
e v er
e e
r
ne v e r
p
g i ve up
n e v er
n eve
p
up
r
ve
ev r
n
nee vv ee
e n
u
r
gi v
e
n
n e ve
g ve ev e
n ev er
n ever
p
n eve r
n eve r
r
up
gi v e
p
giv e
n ev e
g i v e up
g iv e u p
p
g i ve u
up
r
i v e up
ne
r
v
ne v e
n e
r
er
ne
up
ne e e
ve
p
ne ve r
ne v e
g i ve u p
e
iv e
p
v
up
n ever
p
e
r
ne
v
e
p
gi v e u
gi v
e
n e v er
v
giv e u p
e
n e v er
ne
ne v e r
r
neve
e
up
e e
r
up
up
i n ev eu rp
g i ve
iv e up
g i v e up
g i v e up
r
r
ne v e
g iv e up
e
g ve up
r
n ever
ne ve r
ve
ne
ver
e
nev
ne
ne ver n eve r
neve r
ne
up
never
gi
never
ne ver
never
ne
neve r
up
ne
ve
gi
nev
up
r
up
p
give u
ne
gi
neve
give
give up
never
e
ne ve
give
ne ve r
never
gi
gi v u
ne
g ie u
g i v e up
g ie
never
gi v
never
ne ve r
u
r
r
up u
r
r
r
p
up
neve r
eve r
p
r
ne ve r
r
neve r
r
never
e
ee
ne
ne ve
e
give u p
nev
vr
nneveere
g iv e
r
ne
neve r
neve r
gi
n ever
g ie up
ne ve
neve r
gi
never
n ever
ne
ever
ve
neve r
nev r
v
ne
ne ve
never
ne ver
neve
ve
ne
e
ne v
ne
give up
ne ve r
ne v r
never
eve
give
giveunpr
up
p
e
neve r neve r
g e
r
r
r
r
ne ver
ne ver
ev
ne ver
vu
ne ver
n ev
ne
p
ve u
ne ve r
ne ve r
ve
ve
n ever
never
ne
gi ve
neve
nev er
ve
nevup
e er
e u
i v e u pp
give
neve r
neve r
ever
ever
ne ve r
e
er
ne v
ev er
ne ver
neve
never
neve
nev
nev
e ver gi
n ever
n ev
ne ver
ne ver
ne ver
ne
never
ever
give up
n ev er
p
ee
neve r
r
r
neve r ne ve r
e er
never
gi
neve r
gi veup
ne
never
p
never
r
g iv e up
e
gi v
ne
ever
nev
e
ne ver
neve r
r
ne ver n ever
er
ne ve r
nev
ve
neve r
er
nev
neve
gi
gi
never neve
gi v e u p
up
r
ne
giv
u
e
neve
neve
never
ne ver
g i ve up
ve
r
up
ne
r
u
er
ne v
e
ne v
ve
e giv
ne
up
up
nev e
vu
ne ve r
never
p
ne
er
ne v
give
p
gi
ne ve
give
nev e
n ev e r
e
e
n ev
p
r
ne
never
ne ve
ne ve r
gi
gi
ve
ne
never
g i eu
n ever
ne ve r
e
e
e
e
nev
neve
e er
nevgievre up
never
up
gi
n e v er
p
nev
g ie u
never
gi
gi
ne ver
never ne ver
never
ne ve r
r
gi ve u
ne
nev er
n ev r
r
neve
ever
e
p
ne v e
never
r
er
neve
ne
gi
gi
give
up
up
n ev
give
ne vergiv
never
r
r
ne
eve r
u p nev e
p
r
p
ne ver
er
ne v
e
r
nev
e
gi v
r
neve
e
give
ne ve
neve
give up
r
never
gi
r
r
g
n ev e
give u
er
ne v
gi
e
ne v r
gi
neve r
gi
ne ve r
v
nev
ne
r
e
e
g
r
neve r
er
ne v
up
give
eve
ne ve r
ne ver
ne ve r
ne ver
e
ne
give
never
give
n eer
er
ver
r ne
gi
never
r
neve
never
ne ve r
r
ne
r
nev e
gi
neve r
nev er
ne ver
ne ve r
r
nev
ne ver
give
e
e
n ev n
ne ver
ne
nev e
n ev e
e
give u
give
ne
never
never
never
never
up
nev r
ee
nev e
neve
nev
giv e
ve u
eve
never n
never
i v e up
nev
give
u
give
giveu
r
never
up
ve
gi
e ve
ne v
ne
nev
never
u
er
g i v e up
v
n enveev u veernev e
r p
g
v
r
n ev e
gi v e u p
ne ve r
g i v e up
up
e
n e v er
g v e up
g iv e up
v e up
g i ve up
n eve r
n
ne
g
e
v e r n e v e r e uepv ne
n e ve v
n
e
r
v
e
e r n n e ver
e r e v e eve g p
ne e u
n r
nee ver ne
n eve r
ne v e
r
p
r
ev
p
n e ve
g i ve up
e up
p p
u
gi v e
g i ve u p
r
u
v
v e nev e r
e er
gi
ne e
n e veevnee ve
n ev
n e vernv e
r
n ever
never
n ev er
er
ne ver never gi
u
give
e
r
up
ne
r
ne
n e er
n ever
ee
v
ne
n eve
neve
give
nevene ve r
give
ne ve
up
never
giv e
nev er
up
g iv
r
never
p
ee
u
gvie
ne e r
ever
r
p
r
gi
er up
v
give
e
gi
gi
ne ve r
p
ee
e ver
r
nev
n ev r
neve
neve
p
ne ve
ee
r
up
giveup
ne ve r
ne ver
g
gi e
p
r
r
er ne ve r
ne
e
give u p
r
e
neve r
give
ne ver
giv
up
ev r
e
n ever
nev r
e p
giv
ne ver
never
never
ne v r
neve r
give never
p
ee
nev
nev
ne
ee
n ever
p
r
giv e
neve r
ne ver
e
ne ver
u
up
up
u
r
ne
e
nev
never
p
up
p
up
r
r
r
up
r
gi
ne
ne ver
neverne ver
e
ne v
p
e
ne er
never
nev
e
ne
nev
gi
never
n ev
ve
ever
g ie p
never
up
never
give
u
e
ne ve r ne ve r
n eve
up
p
up
give
give
ever
ne
ne ve r
gi
r
r
r
never
gi
giv u
ee
gvie u
neve r
gi
v
give
nev e
give
r
r
u
up
up
r
r
r
e er
ve
gi
er
nev
giv
p
neve
r
never n e
er
p
n eve r
eu
g i v gvi
give
never never
ne ve r
never
n e er
ne ve
up
r
n ev
n ever
e
n eve
ne ver
r
neve
up
up
r
r
neve
p
ne ve r
give
neve r
p
p
up
up
give
n
e
gi e u
eve r
gi
r
p
r
up
nev ereve
ev r
gi
nev e
neve r
v er
ne
gi
e
e
e er
ne ve r
u
give
never
e
ne
ne venr
r u
nneevveer gi ve
never
never
e ve
u
p
never
ev e
n ever
nev e
nev r
e
up
up
u
r
up
r
ne
e
gi
ne
never
nev er
never
neve r
never
never
neve r
e
ne neve
gi ve
u
g e
e
nev r
ne
ne e
p
p
give
e
n eve r
nev er
giv e
neve
ne ve r
p
r
up
r
ne ve r
gievu
u
give
give
n ever
e ver
nne ver
p
up
r
r
r
ee
n ever
e
ne v
ne ve r
e up
e
ne
gi
ever
e
giv
ne ve r
neve r
never
p
ne ve r
r
r
r
r
p
r
u
give
e
ne v
never
up
give
gi
neve r
e
nev
gi e
never
ne ver
ne ver
never
nev er
e
ne ve rn eve
ne ver ne ver
n ev r
ne ve r ne
ver
ever
eer
p
gi ve u
ne ve
ne ve r ne ver
nevenre ve
never
g i v e up
p
gi
nneevveer
neve
ne ve r
ne ver
never
up
gi
gi
neve r
p
give u
r
e
ev
g igi ve
i
gi ve
give
n eve r
eve r
r
r
r
p
veu
ne
never
give u
ve
ne
g
up
gi e
neve r
never
n ever
neve
e
never
never
ne
gi
ve
ne
gi
ne ve r
ne ver
e
giveup
ne
ne
gi v e
never
neve r
ne
ne ve r
ne ve r
give
ne ver
ne ve r
ve
ever
gi
ne ve r
n ever
ne ver
gi
e
e er
e
ne ve r
gvie up
v
ne
e
neve
up
up
v
give r
ne
ne
g i ve
never
e
never
ne ver
ne ve r
ne ve
e up
e
ne
v
nev r
neve r
e
never
ne
gi
never
u p never
neve r
ne
never
e
ne
ee
e
g ve up
gi e
never
nev er
gi e
r n ever
nev
e ev e r
r
ne
ne ver
gi v
ne ve r
n ever
neve r ne ve r
ne vernever ever
n ever
ne ver ne ve
nev er
ne
ev e r
up
ve
ne
up
p
ne
gi
r
r
give
ve
give
g ie p
v
gi
ne
i v e up
give
ve
ne
gi
ne ver
er
ne
ne ver
ne ver
ve
ne
ne ve r
neve r
ne ve r
n ev
e
ne
ne
ever
gi
gi v
neve r
ne ve
ne never
ne ve
giv u
ever
n ever
never
never neve
gi
gi
ev
never
ne v
n ever never
up
never
e
ne ver
ne ver
never
ne ve r
never
neve r
ve
neve r never never
n ev er
ne ve r
ne ve r
ne ver
n e er
n ever ne ve
give
ev
r
e
v
p g ve up
e
e u eve p
g ve
v
n
ngeve up
e
neevve g ve u
n e
verne p
nee
er r ev g ve
neve eup r nneevvee
eve e eveeve
e
n
n
neve
n ever
n ev
never
ne
give up
e
ne ve
e er
never
er
n ev
never
ne ver
neve r
p
give
neve r
n
never
ne e
gi
ne e r
never
never give
ne ver
er
ne ver
neve r
ve
ne
n ev
g iv e
e
ne
never
n eve r
p
give u
er
ne ve r
n ev
neven e
ne ver
neve r
e up
g ig i e up
e
ne ver never
r
nev
ne ve
ne ve
gi e u p
er
nev
never
p
r
up
p
r
r
gi
up
give
v er
ne ve r
n eve r
ev
ne ve
ne ver
neve r
ne ver
n e er
never
give
v up
neve
never
ne ver
give
n ev er
gi v u
ne
ne
n eve r
ne ve r gi
e eup
giv
e
ne
gvi eu
p
give
never
ne
p
giv e u
ne ve
nev
give
never
neve r
never
r
gi v u
er
n ev ne ve
n ever
ne ve
never
ne
ne ver
p
ne ver
ne ver
n eer
never
ne ver n ever
ever e
ne v r
n ever
neve
gi
up
p
ne
eve
n ve
give up ever
neve
gi ve
ne
ne ver
u
gniveeve
neve
g i ve up
ne v er
e
nev r
r
never
e
ne
ne ver
ne ver
ne ve r
r
ne ver
ne ve
ne ver
never
giv e
e r
nv
ne
never
eer
gi e
gi
up
giv
nev
giveu
gi v
giv e
ne
e
ne
never
n ev e
n
ne
ne
n e v e re
er
gi v e u p
n e ver
g iv e
r
up
up
up
giv e
g iv e
r
r
ne v e
er
up
ve r
v e up
i v e up
ve
r
n ev e r
up
ver
ver
up
n ever
e rn e
e up
e
giv e
p
i ve up
gi v e u
g i v e upp u
g i ve u
up
g
v i ve up
rg i v e uupp
ve r
n e v er
g i v e up
e up
p
u
g iv e
r
e v er
ve r
up
gi e
e v e rn e v e r up
g iv e
v
er
v
n ev er
er
nev er
ev e
er
ne ve
er
nev
ev
p
n eer
r
give
gi
ne ve r
ne ve r
neve r never
nev
gi
never
ne ve r
ne ver
up
p
gi
gi
e
ne v
nev e
ne ver
ne ver
ne
giveup
e
ne ve
ne
e
n ev
n e v er
gi e
gi
gi v e u p
ever
never
gi ve
nev e
r
nev er
never
n ever
never
e
give
ne
neve r
n ev e r
e
gi
never e
ne ver
r
ne v
r
neve
giv e
never
give
never
ne v e
r
ne e
nevve
neve
ee
e
n e v er
e
ne ve r
give
er
gi
g i ve up
ne
n ever
give u
ne ver
neve
gi
ne ve
ever
up
gi ve
ne v r
ne ver
ne ve r
neve r
ne ver
ne verne e
v
e
e er
give
e
gi v
neve
e er
vne
e er
p
e er
ve
eer
ISSUE III
Spring 2014 Issue III
e
ne ver
ve u
ne ve r
never
ne ve r
n ever
r
r ee
nev n
r
ne
v
ne
neve r
ne ver
ve
ne
e enre ve r
r
up
r
up
r
r
r
neve
neve
ne ve
never
never
neve r
ne
r
nev
p
giv u
giv
n eve r
e
up
gi
ever
neve r
never
e
nev
ev er
neve r
never
er
ne
n ev r
g i ve u p
neve
gi
never
ne ver
ne ver
nev e
p
ne ve
neve r
ve
nev er
giv e
e
nev e
neve r
neve r
neve r
neve r
p
er
gi u
ne
never
g ie u
e
gi
nev
ne ver
e
gi
ne ve
ne ve r
never
ne ve r
ne
u
ne ve r
never
ne ve r
e
ne ver
never
ne ve r
ne
gi
ne ve
e
give
never
n ever
up
neve
gi
ne ve r
ever
ne ve
never
never
ne
n ev er
n ever
ne ver
e
ne ve neve r
ne ve r
gi
ne
r
ever
ne ve
e
e
gi
gi
ne v r
n ev r
nev
give
gi
up
r
p
r
r
up
up
r
r
ne ve
gi
neve r
gi
never
ne ve r ne ver
ve
er
ne v
giv u p
p
give
neverne ver
p
give u
e er
give
ne v r
r
r
p
p
up
r
p
r
r
up
r
up
r
r
up
up
r
r
nev
never
ne
never
ne ver
give
n ev er
ne e r
gi
r
ne ve
never
never n ev r
neve r
ne ver
r
up
up
r
n
gi
ve
v
ne
up
ne
n ever
gi
give
er
ne
gi
neve r
neve r ne ver
u
u
up
up
ne ve r
neve
nev
never
ne ve r ne ve
never
e
give
up
give
ne ve r
r
u
ne ver
e
ne ve r
never
neve r ne r
ve
ne ver
never
ve
ne
ne
ne ver
ne ver
neve r
ne ver
nev r
ne v
giveup
up
r
r
r
r
p
r
r
ne ver
n eve r
gi
n eve r
e
ne erne ve r
ne ve r
never
v
e
p
g i v e u pgi ve e u
neve
neve r
nev
never
e nev
nev
nev
ne ver
ne
ne
gi e
give
n ever
gi
ee
ne ve r
up
give
nev
neve r
ev r
evne v r
e
ne
gi
n ever
neve
r
p
e vr
neve r
ne ve rnever
ne ve
e e er
n e er
give
giv up
p
eu
gv
ne ver i
ne
ne er
ne
gi
nev
g i v e iu pe u p
v
gi
er
eve
e
ne ver
ne ve r
e
ne ver
ver
ve
give
er
ne
never
u
r
r
r
r
neve
nev
ne
ne
up
give
give up
never
never
nev
e up
nev er
never ne ve r
r
up
r
p
r
r
p
r
r
r
neve r
ne ver
eve r
ve
ne
nev
v
e
gi
n eve
r
nneeve
ne
r
r
r
r
e
ne
nev
e g ve
ne v i
ne ver
r
ne ver
never
never
neve
e
n
ne
neve r
neve r
never
never give u p
eevr
e er
nev
ne
nev er
up
ve
u
g vene u
e
e
e
r
r
ne ve r
neverne ve
ne ve r
v
ne
ne
e
ne v r
nev
never
give
egi
ne
n ever
never
g vnev ever up
g
ver
ne
e
ne
ne
never
never
S P RI N G 20 1 4
r
ne ver
neve r
ne ver
ne ver
nev
e er
ne
e
giv
r
ne ve r
p
give u
never
neve
p
p
give
gi
nev
ne
up
neve
neve r
r
r
r r
r
e
ne v
gi
e
ne
never
n e erne vene ve
never
r
r
neve r
ne ver
ne
ne
ne
ne ve r
ne ve r
neve r
give p
neve
ne ver
gi u
ne
ne
ne ve r
r
ee
ne ve
neve
ne ve
g
p
ne ver
gi
ne ver
v
g v erner e
nevneve
nev er never
ever
giv e up ne nnever
ee
give
ne ve
ne ver
never
ve
give
up
nev
ne
p
eup
ne
ve
ne
ee
v
neve r neve r
n ev r
r
ne
ne ve r ne ver
give u p
gi
g ve nev e
ver
e
r
up
never
neve r
never
er
n geive up
give
ne
e
e giv
ne ver
ev r
ne ve
ne ver
nev
give
never
ne
nev
ver
ne ve r
u
give
e ne
r
r
r
gi
e
give
ne ve r
r
neve
ne ver
ver
r
r
p
giv
e
ev
n ev r
u pnev r
give
ne ve r
never
r
r
r
r
ne ver
neve
er
ne ve r
ne
n ev
e
v
ne
u
neve
give u
give
ne
n ev er
ne ve r
e ver give
give u n
e
ne v r
ne ver
gi
ver
ne
ev u
ne ve r
up
gi
nev
ggi i ve
n ever
er
ne e r n e never
givev u
e
n evneve
ne ve r
e
r nev
never
r
ne ve r n ever
ne ve r
eevr
e ver
up
neve r
ne v r
neve r
give
gi
e
ne
n ev
u
ne
er
ne v
ne v
ne
ne ver
ne ver
er
gi veu
neve
p
r
r
ne ve
ne ve r
ne ve r
nev r
p
gi u
er
ne
ev
ne ve r
ne ver
ve
e er
r
p
giv
n ev er
ne ver
nev er
n ever
ne
neve neve
ne
ne ve
neve
r
ne ver
give
neve
ne
never
ve
give
ne
ne
r
gi
neve
ever
ne ver
ne ve
give u
never never
up
e
e
e
iv
eg
nev
eegi
ne
e er
neve r
ne ve
v
e
e e
n evne v
ev er
pn
ne ve r
p
r
e
ne ver
ve
ne
ne ve r
r
gi
ne
ne er
e
e
ne
n ev
gi
r
gi
ne v
gi
nev r
ever
e
er
ne ne
ne ve
ne ve
r
gi
give
e
gi
gi
nev
e ver
ne ver
ne ve r
ne ve r
e
ne
e
ne ver
never n e r never
r
p
never
eve
nev
ne ve
give
ne ver
r
give
gi
never
gi veu
up
r
gi
ne ver
e
r
ne ver
nev r
eve
ne ver
ne ver
ne ver
ne ver
gi
ne ver
e
e e
ne
n ever ne ver
p
r
r
ne
ne ver
e
ve
ne
never
neve
neve
enev
ne
n ev e
r
n ev
neve r
up
gi
ve
ne
neve r never
p
r
r
up
r
r
nev e
give
p
up
ne ve
ne ve r
give
vr
ve
p
neve r
n ever
e r neve
nev
neve
neve r
gi
e
ne
r
u
ne
ne
e
nev
ver
ne
e
ne n never
up
ne
give
neve
nev
r
neve
neve r
ne ve r ne ve r ne r
ne ve r
v
ne
r
e
nevve
up erne ve
ne ve rnev
nev r
e
p
e
ne
ne ver
gi
ne
r
neve
ne ver
ne ve r
never
gi
v
nev e
ne ver
ne
r
never
ne
e
ne v
never
p
r
r
e
ve
ne
gi
gi
e
ne
ne
e
gi
gi
never
ne
ve
p
never
ne ver
gi ve
r
ne
up
gi
v
never
ve
u
gi
ne ve
ne
e
ne ver
n ever
e
ne
up
ne ve r
ee
n ever
neve r
ne
p
e
ve
e
ne
ge
ne
ne
n ev
e
ne
neve
gvie up
ne
g iv e u p
r
ever
eve
e
ne
ne
n eve
e
ne v
n ee
u
p
up
nev
n ev r ne
r
ne
v
p
ne ve r
ve
ne
r
e
neve r
ne
give
ne ver
n ev
up
u
give u
ve
ne
e
ne
neve
ne e
r
e
ne
ne ver
never
r
ne
ne
ne
gi
p
neve r
e
ne ve
ne
ne
never
neve
ve
neve
ne v
er
ne
e
e
ne
neve
neve r
e
ne
p
e
up e
nev
nev
p
e
ne
ne ver
gi
nev e
never
i v e up
gi
give
neve
ne ve r
ne ve
n ever
er
ne
ever
ne
gi e
giv e
nev e
e
ne v
gi
e
never n
neve r
ne ver
never
never
ver
ve up
gi
n ever
ne ver
ne ve r
never
ne v r
up
gi
e er
ne
n
ne
giv
give
ne ve
ne ve r
ne ve r
er
ne
ne ver ne
ver
ne
er
n
ne e
neve r
ne ve
give up
er
ne
ne ver
ev r
n eve r n
neve r
up
neve
never
er
never
ne v
neve
r
neve
r
nev
e
neve
give u
n ver
neve e
r
ne ve r
er
neve
ne
neve
ne ve
ne ver
neve
ne ve r
r
n ever
ever
en
r
ne
ne e
e
ne ve r ne ve r
never
ne
ne ve
never
nev e
never
r
r
e
r
e
ne
neve
e
ne vnever
neve
neve r
neve n everv
ne ver ne er
e n ev r
n ev
gi
p
never
never
r
r
r
r
r
never
ne ver
nev
ne ver
ne
gi e
ne ve
er
r
r
r
r
r
neve
neve
ev
never
never
up
ne
u
gi e
never
never
n eve
r
r
r
p neve neve neve
ve eve nevenevenevenenvee nev
ve g e
n ver
nev
n
up nre nev e nevee nevene e
e
v
e
g
nev
ne e
n enenev e neve
er vr neve r nev nev er
ve nveeve n eve ne
e
n
ve
e
n
never
nenevveerrnrevevenuepvnee ngevveenguevvee up
e
neve r
g
n
n
n
e
ne ver
evge vgeguve up
n
e
n
e
r
r
veeve
v
v
e
r
p
e
n
n
v
e
r
e
nev
e
e
e
e
n
v
en n eve ne n n eve giv nevv e rnevern g n neve
n
g
n e er
e
e rn e nev er n g v e upneveg
upnev enreve er
e
n
e
v
e
g
n
i
v
e u pg ve up neveneve
nev er g v e neve
r
v
i
e
g
r
e
u never uepggvveeuupp
v
e
n
never p nev e
n e
g
i
e
v
u
p
p
r e
p
u
g ve
g veenue ver nev e neve rg ve ugp v nevuernneevve
never
v
g vvee up ne v n e
e r ne
e upneevveer g vgeveee pg nvegupene
ne neve ne neve
ne e
nev neever up
ne
never
g ve up
n
g venueve ne
eve n n e
ne ver n
n
e
p
n ev e
ne ve ern
n g ne
ne epg u
e e
e uve
ne
g ee
n
v
e
n
n
e
v
g
u
e
p
ve neve p g
ne ve g e
neve
g
nev erngevveeup
r e
e
n
n
nenveer neve ne e u pe e venevevene
eve
r
n gv
neve
nenv e ve ee u
g ivnen v neve
g
e
ne
n
u g ve urp gnvee u
n
ne g
g
v
e
up g e neve g e up
n
ne v e
e
e g
v
neve
e e
e
v
e
e
n
neve
neve
n
v
e
e
p
e
n
g
e
e
v
u
n
r
e
v
e
r
r
e
v
ene
e nev e up
n
gg g v e r neve
e
n
g eve
e
n
v
e
n
ne nev e ene e g g
n
n
g
e
gv
ev e ne e
ne ve
gv
neve
n
u
e
v
e
e
ver ene eg
g
g v e up up
p g v e nuepve g e
r
r
e
n ev ve e r g
nevenr eve ne
g
e nevenneev enenve e
n
r
e
e
r e v neve ve g ve u
nev er r
never ne e
ne
e
nev n ever
ne ne
e
neveve
n
r n
n
e
v
e
n nev er
nevneegvreneveu
nevern
ve
n
n
gever ne e
r
r
r
r
r
neve
neve
nev e
ne
never n
neve
p
gi veu
neve
never
gi
never
ne ver
never
gi ve up
r
neve
r
r
r
never
ne er
ne ver
never
never
er
never
never
n ever never
e
r
never
r
never never n env ve
ginveu p
never
nev
never
never
n eve
ne
v
er
never
never give
never
never
e
r
n
p e
n
n er
nev never
ne
n
n r never
nev never
never neverver
nnevevrer g v u
never
ve up neve
never
n ever ver
never never
give up never nev ergiveup
r
never ev
giv enuever ngievveup ver
v
r
er
er e ve
r
vr
ve up
iep
gvie u pever
never
give
never
never
never ne ever
r up
neve
never
nev n ever
never
never
never never
n
r r
r r
nv
never
never
n ever n ver
r neve
never never
never give up
e
er
never
e
vr
er nee
never never er
never
e up
er
never n ever
nenveerver n
never give up
nev
ne
er
nev
er
neve
nev er
never
neverr
e ver negivve u p er
nev enr ver
nev
er e upver gri v
e
neveer
ver never
n ever
nenv ever
r
v
giv up v
give up
n vneerver er never gi ve uep
nev gi neveneve
never
n ever
never v
ne
e
gni ve up neve
never
gi
p
nevenrever neeverrne er er
r
nev
never
give up
never
n
ver
v
u
give up
u
gi veup
never
up n ever neve
never never
v
r
p
never neve nev
p
never
e r
r
eevr neverever
gi ve u pnever neerver never
u
e
g up
e
r
e
v
n
g
e
v
i
v
u
p
v
e
n
v
er
v
i
e
v
e
e
v
e
n
v
e
r
r
n
e
r
g
n
e
e
e
r
n ever n
r
r
r
u never p i ve
gin ev
r never
nev never
r gi
n ever
er
er
never
er evnee r n e ve
vergive p nev
er
er
r
nv
ne
neve n e v er
neve nev er
neerv
never
never
never
ve up
nev n ve
nev
neerver
n ever
vr
er
nev
giveu p nneeve
e r
ver
ne ver rve u
er ver
vr
r
nev
er
never
neverv
r
n r
n n
r eve n p
v
e
v
never
nev
nneevveer
nev er
never
nev
n
e
nev
r
n
p
e
n
e
e
v
r
n
i
n
r
v
u
n
er
ever
ever
never g e p
e e ev
giveeve
r
up
nev
give up
never
n v giveu p
never
ver
n
r
nev
give up
n
ne
give never
r
er
up
never
r never
nerev
nevenr ee
never
never
e
e
e n eve er
r
up
ver ver
never
vr ne
never n ever
give
nevneer
never nevveer
n
nev
neverer never
never nev
n e ver
never
gi n
veeuvper
g
nev er
never give ve up
nnee
neve r
ver
n evegriv
nev
ver give up
ver ever
never
er
give up
never
never vie up
v
v
n ever n
n er g
ne
e up never
up
r
r
nneevver
never
never gi ve u p
r
ne r
upn e er
give u
gvieup nenveevr eer
never e v r
n enveeve
ever
e never
n
ver
ev r never
nevrer r vveup
never
never
never
never
nv
v giveup up
iveup ever
never
gi v
give v
never ever
p
e e p p
g up n e
never
vr
never
never
never
n
n
r
er
neverg
never n
ve e
er vie
nev negvi vvee uupe u
e
n
e v
nevenreve
r
e
e never
neever
n ever
never
nev n r nenveergvier nneevverr
er
ngeivevenev
nev
never g p
gi v
never
up
n ever ever ive up
nev
never
never
r
never
giv
never ne
n ev
gi
r
nev never
never
er eve
er
nve r
never
give v give up r
g
never
iveu e
gi ve
ver
never
never
n ever
giveup
neve
ie
never u pr
up
never
er
er gv up
nev er
never
giv eupnr ver never never never
never
e
er
never
n ever
n
n eve
ve
never
never
up
gi ve
e
giveup never give u p nev
g
i
r
nev never
never e up
n
n
r
r
v
n
r
e
r
n
e
e
v
e
r
e
e
e
v
p
e
ve
ever g unv
nev
r give up
u r
never
r
er
r
give up
never rgevi n
nevere er
never nev
never n ever
ve never
r n ve
vie
never g
n ver
never
eer
n
nevenrev e
never
neve never
nev
nev er
n ever n eve
ever neve never
er nev never
never v
never
v nv
nv e
er
r
ve
p up
rnv
neve ever
never n
er
never
never
er
never
nev
never ever eup
r r
neve
ever
giveu ever never ne
never
r
ver
never
nev
u nnever
e
give up
never
gi ve up
n
giv
r
n
v
e
r
r
r
r
g
n
v
u
p
v
r ngei ve up
e
e
never
never
ie
neve r
r
nv
er p
nenveerr
vr
r
r
neve
never
v
er
r
nevernever never n ev
never nev
never
neve
n ever
e
n ver
nevgiveu
r
ev
neve
er
ne
eve
nev
n
never
e ne
v er
nev
neevr
never
nev r
r
neve
nen never
never
n ever
n ver
giveu p giv e u p
n ever
er
nev
never
neevr
never
e gi veup
ver
neve
give up
never
ne ver
r ever
e never p nev ener ve n er never
giveupe er ver
nev g e up
er
r
r
never
n
up
erveeupr n veri v
ev
never r
never never
ne ver
ve
gvie up
up
neever
er
never
n
r
er
never
never gi
give
nev n ve
ve r
nevneve
er r
r
nevenreve
nev
er
ver
r
ve up
nev
r
nevenre
n ever
r g ve up p r ver
p
never
er
r
eve
never
up
r
giveup
nev neve n
n
n ver
never
neve
nevevrer n
never
r
neve
neve
i eu r
gi ve u p
neve
never
neevr
never neve nev giveugipveu r never
ver n
gi veup ve up
r
ever r
r
never
r
n eve
n evn
ereve
gi v ev
giv neve
n ever
r
r
ver
verer
give unep ever
e
up
never
neverg
neve
r
never er
n eve
never r
giveup
never
up
neve
nver
up
n er
never
nev
ive up
never
neve
v
n ever
never
ve
never
never
never
r
ev
e
never
ever
ne give
gvie up n
ene
ve r
g
v
r
n
n
e
e
n
v
r
v
e
e
v
e
r
e
v
e
r
give up
giive up
e
e
e
r
u
r
n
r
e
r
ve
up
neve
nee
v
r
ne
er
neverever
nev
n eve
ne
g ne v er
neve ne
nev er er
never
never e r never
nev
r n p
r
e nevernever
n
nev ver
vr
v
ver
n ve
nev
r
nv
neve
ver
n ever
p
ever
never geivev rup
gi
never never
up
eve
evr
e
nv
neve
never
ne
n everg up
r give u
never
r
ver
gi n
ve up
nevernev er
n
ee er
e
r
g
r
e
e
n
e
v
e
n
n
p
never
n
e
e
e
n
r
n
i
v
e
i
u
v
n
v
n
e
e
e
v
e
r
e
v
e
r
v
e
e
r
n
r
never
ver
ver
give
ne er
verr
er
never
giv
n v never
p n ever never v r g eup
r
er r
nev
neve
ve
never
e
never
never give
never
give up
nev n eve
r
neve
never
never
neve n
never
never neivver
r
never
never
nevegri ve u p n
e
never ver
never never
never
never
never
rr never v ne never
nevern ever
n eve
n egvier up
never
never
ever give up
ve
ver n ver
up
ne er
never
nneever
ve
ve up
ve up
never
er ver neve
never
ne
giv ev nevern evpe
nevernever
u n ever
nev ne
up
never
ver
never
give up
gi eup
e
er
n
never never r
never never never r
never ve ueverver
ve up
ne
n er
never
er
er
never never
give up
nee
vr
never
gvie u p
never
never
never er
v
never er
n ever
n ever erev
n ever
nee
vr
er
ve
gi venuep
gi nevner ne
giv eup gi ve upnever up
gi
up
ngevver
nev
never
nev
never
never never
n ever ngeveer up
neeevv
u
er
ver
nev
vr
r
er
give
i e upneve
i vnever give up er
ve u p r
nev
never n ever
never
never
e
give u
n eve
nrenevverer v
neevr
r
gi veup r giveup never e
r
er
ver never never
v r gi ve up
e
e
give u
p nee
givenuepve
er
neve v
giveup
give u p
neve n ever
neve
nev
never
r
nev neevr
ne
nev
veup
nev
neve
never never n ver
e never
never
nee
vr
never
never
never n never
er
never
never
r
ver
never
n ever
ever
nev
given vuerp n
never
n ver
n ever
er
never
never
nevern ever
neve
n everne
ver
never
e
never
ver give
n
give up
g eupe
gi ve up
ern
never
r
r
give u p
v nev
r nev
up
never
never
nev evernev er
never
n r
e er iv
e
ver
givenuee
never
pv
ve up
e
gi er
never
neveerve
nev ne v
r
r
r
neve
r
r never
gvieeup
ever
e
r
e
e
e
e
v
n
v
e
n
n
v
e
r
v
n
v
v
v
never
e
e
v
v
e
r
e
e
e
g
i
v
e
u
p
v
e
r
v
r
e
e
n
e
e
n
n
r
ne
vr
er
ne
v
never r
nen
n
vr
ne
v
n ever
r
r
n ver
eve
never neve
n ever
never
give u p
ne
never
never
r
gi veup
ev
never n
gi ve up
neverr er
r
ver
never
n
never
never
never
never
ne ver
never
n
never
ve
never
give up
never n neve nev
n ever
vr
v g u en
ve r
r
er
r
give
never nee
never
gi ve up
never
nuep ver
never
r
ver
ne
e
ver
n
e
neverne er ive p giv
e
r
r
u
p
er r
e
r
v
n
e
n
r
e
e
r
n
e
v
n
v
n
n
v
e
e
ever
n e never
never
ever
er
give p
giv
never ever
never ne v er
up
never nev
r
never n e
never
nev
n ever
v er
er
n
never e
ve up
e
p
r
nev
never
ev r
up never
never
vr
er
er
n ver
never
ev
n eve
n ever
nee
vr
neve
er
u
give
nver
n ever
p
r
er
e er
never ne er
nev
never
nen
r
ev r ve up up never never nev
nev er
n evergiveup nenveerver gi ve p
n
neevr
n ever give uper never
nev
v
p neve
eu
r r
u
never n e
gi
never
gi ve u p
e
gvie up never
never giveup never never
giv
nenveveerr n ver
r
r
ve
up
nev
gi ve
never
nevern ever
neve
giv
eve
up
ver give
never
neve
never
ver
gvie up
ne ver n r
r
never
neevr er never
er
never
ne
r
never
give
never
ne
givevuepr i up giveuepver
ev
nevnever
vr
r
nv
n
neve
up
nver e never gi ve up
r never give u p never
nevenr
never n e ver ver
never
n ever
never
n n ever
er
n ever
giveup nneever gve
v
ver
never n
ne e neve never
n v ne r ver
n
never
neve
n ever give up
gvie u p iv p
never
r
never er
up
give upnever
ver
never
neve r e
n ever
r
r
er ve
never
never give up never gvieup
gi ve u p
ever evr v r
r
r
geu
never
neve
ver
never
giveup
nev
never
evr
ve
v up
r
e
neve never
ever never
never gvie gup up
ever
ne
eev
n
r
r
e
n
e
n
r
e
e
e
e
r
e
n
g
e
v
e
r
r
u
p
v
v
r
r
r
ive
never
n
ver
n
giv eup
vie
n
n
ver
never
never
never
ne
nev
nveev
n evneever ne ver
n eveneve
up
never
never
gvie u p ne
r
ve up
e
nev
up nevneer
never
never ne never
never neve
never
u
ve up ne
ver
givneeveur
never r
er
never
giv er
r
nev
r ne r
n
ver
nee
vr
giveup
ver
er
r
ve upve p
n ever
ev
v
r
r
gvie up
er
ever ve
p
gvie up
give u p
n
e
v
u
n
e
u
e
e
n
v
r
u
n
r
e
r
p
e
r
r
u
r
ve
ver ne
ve
nve
n
gi
n eve
n
never
never
ver
g e p
never
gi v e upnever
never give p ver
e
n
r
ver er
nevernever
never
v
er
ve vuep
gi ve uerp
r
u ne i v u
never ever
never never
n eveer
never
er r
nee
vr
er gvieupgiveup
never
up
nev
n ever
n ver
r
up r
never
nev
nev eev
n ever never
neve
never up
n
r
nevevrer
nev
neve
never
gvie up nver
n
gi v e up n ve
gi ve up
n eve
never
giveer gnievvee u
r
r neverneve
never
never
e
never
r n ve
r
r
p
never never
ve
never giveup
never
never
nev
r r never
vern
e r iveu
never
never
neevr
e
nv e
never
nevenrever
giveup
nevenrev er never
never
er
vgiere up er
gi
g p
ve r
give up
iv u
r
ve up
neve
nev
nee
v n ever
never
p
up
v nev r nev
never
give uperne
er
never
ne
ngevere
rr
ve up
r
never v
never
ie
r
r p
p
er never
er v
e
r
eu
u
e
r
g
n
g
e
v
u
e
v
n
e
n
r
g
i
v
e
e
v
i
p
e
n
v
p
e
v
v
e
e
e
n
g
e
e
i
p
n
r
e
v
r
n
e
v
e
v
r
v
e
u
p
u
v
e
v
n
e
e
e
u
p
v
v
n
n
n
v
ever
eve never
nenev
n
never
neer e
n ev
gi ve up n ever
never
ever
r
v
e
ge
up
up
ever
evr n ev
never
ne
ver
gi ve u
n ever
gvie up ne
n
never
giveup
gvie up ne
gvie up
gi ve
n ve r
er
e up
r never
gi ve u p n
r n v er
er
r
give up
r
r
evernev
never
never
never
er
never
neve
nerv
n
ne v er
neve
up
v
er
nne
evver
e
er r
r
e
r
give
give up
n ever ever
e
r
n
never
give gvie u pgive
neve
neevr never
ver
up
er
n eve
n ever
neevver
never
r
n
iv u
ne ver
v
u
never n
r never n ever never
up nev
never
neve
e
ve
neve
never
n
never never
never
never n ever never
n evenervneevrer n ever
never
never negver ug e p
nneveveer r n eve never never
ver n v r
ve give
gi
gi veup ve up
gi ve up
never
nev
r
give up
v
er
ivvee upp
never
e
ve up
give up r
never
r
nev
ve
never
give up
up
never
ver r
nee
v never
e
never
never
never
ee
e
gi veupever
gnivee up
never
never nevenrever
ve up
nenvver
giveup neve neevr er
neve
ver
n
never
er
nee
vnever n ne
r
r
n eve
n ever never
givenuepver
r
neve
never ev r never
never
neevr
giveu
v
gi
u
g u
ever ver e r
nev
nev give
give u p
er
er
ver
r n
never
e
n e
never
gvieup v up
r
never up
nevevre p
nve
never
nev
never ive p
never
n ever ve r
never
never e
gneive
ve
nevveer
never
gvie up
ever never
n
n
vere
never
er up n
n r
n ever r
never give up
up
er
up n
neve
never
never ne
n ever
v
ngiveeve rveguivpeneuvper
never
ve up
never
nenev never
never
up u
never
r
gniveever
nevernever
nev
never uppgi
give
ever
never
giev p
never
v
never ne ve
n
never
never
ne
give up
gvie u p g up
gi veup e
up
ver
ver never ver
veerr ever
never
giveu
give up
give ve up
ver
never n
never
ver
ive
r
nevernever
nne veerr ev rpgnivee up nneeverver
ne
n
never
ne
ever
nen ver never
neverr
ne nee
vr never r
never
neve
v
e
r
er n venr eve
er
ever
neverever
e
r
ev giv u
n
n
r
n
r
n
v
v
v
e
e
n
n
e
e
n
e
e
r
e
v
v
e
r
e
e
e
e
n
e
e
v v
never
r
v r giv
p r neve
v
n
ever er never
gvie up
never n ever
nevr n e ver p p givepu
ve
e never
up
er
neve
r
give u p er
n ever
u
nev
r
er
e u neve
up
n
never gvie up
nev
r
neve
n
give u p
neve
nev
never ep
giv eu
never never
never
nev er
giv
never
n ver
up
r
gvie u p
vr
er
nev ne giveup
never
er
neve
ve up
never
neevver
never
give up
ve
give
n
ver
ve
r
r
nev
vr
r
n
neve
gi veup
n ever
up
ve n ever
never vve up
p
ver
gvie up ever
nenveer r
e e never
p
nev
r
neve
never
neve
ne
vr neve
neve
ve
nevepr give up ve unev r
giveup
never
ne ver
negevivr
never
nevernee
ne
nev nev
er v er never
er
ne
giveup
r
nenveever never
er
er
p
e up
v
r
ver
nee
vr
up
r
up
gi e
nev
never
never
give u p
r
up
ver
never give u
er
er
eu
never never ne
r
never
nevergiveup p
give up
p
up
nev
ne never
nev
n ever
nv
ve
giv
give up e
never
giv
neve
give u p
ver
gi ve u
give up
up
nv
ve u
up
never
never
give upne
r
er never
up
neve
giv
p
n ever
e n
er
u
never
p
un
er v e
nevgere up
eevr
nev
i ve r gi ve u p
give up
er
r
nev
never griveu
eve
p give p ever
never
gi e
n r
nver
never never
nevner never
iv gi v euper
neevver
nevgereve
never gi veuepver
v
er
ne
vr
v
er
vr
er
er
never giveu p
ve
n
never
give up
iveup never
never
nev
never
neve
n ver
n
v
up
ve up
never
ngevier
nev
giveu p
r
e
p
r
e
e
n
p
e
r
g
i
e
u
e
u
r
vr
v
n
n
e
p
e
e
n
e
v
v
g
v
e
u
u
u
ever
never
n
er
nevr never
never e
never
e
neve r
n e ver
evre
e
er
giveunp
give u e r
ve
n ev
up
giv
never
neve
er
never nevergivgiv
nev
never
r
n
never
giveup
ever
gi
p
ne n ver
er
er
n
neve never
e
never
g veup
nev
vr
nev
give up
nenveer
never
giv e
e u nev er
r
up
r never
nrever ever e
nev
ever
n ever
nev
neve i
p
r
v
v
n
e
e
r
n
e
r
n
n
p
e
v
e
i
e
v
n
g
e
v
v
e
r
e
v
n
v
r
n
e
ev
ver
u
never
r
nv
ne
e
give up
nre
e
gi u give
ne
giveu ver
never never
never
never
r
er
er
give
neevr
never never n ver
never
n ever
niever
verver
never
nev
nnever
p
r
r
nevern veer
never
er
ve unpe
up
u
r give u
ever
never
r never
er e
nev ever
n ever
n er
neve
nee
v r gi ve up gve up n er
r
ver
give
never
never
n
nev
never neve
ver n
egvive upp
r ev r
nveevrer
n ever give up
giveup
never
ne
never
n
neve
gi
give up
never
neevr
n ever
giveu
ver
v e up
e
never
r
r
giveup
giveup never
give up
never ever er
n er n eveerunpever
never
never
nneevr
up
never
neevr v r never never
neve
neve
er ev
never
r
ver
nev
giveup
never never
n ever
up
r
give up
neve
ever e
u
nev
neevr
iveu ve
never
ne
r
n ver
er
neve neve
give u p
n ever neve
give
r never
r
e g
e
give u p
gi ve up n
never
vr
r
nev
neveevrer
giveup
er
giveup
nevernee
never ve
giv
nev
r
nver
n
er
never
never never
never
e
v
nvveerr
nneever
never
never
n ever er
never
ve
nev
never
n
give up
never
r nev er
r
n
gi veupgiveu p p
never
neve
nev
never
ver
r
r ever
give up
never
nevenr ever
e
r
never
e
r
u
e
r
v
givenup
e
r
v
g
u
n
e
v
r
r
e
v
n
e
v
e
e
r
v
v
n
e
e
e
r
e
p
i
v
neve
v
never
ne
n
er
ne
n
neve
e
e
ever nevere
up
n ever
ve up
nevernevnereve nev
n ever
er never never give up
never never
nev
ver
neve
never
r
ne
vn
nev
never
giveup
e u
n
give up
r
e
nver
ever
never
never
p
gi ve upp ve
never
n
never
ne
ev gvie up
never
never
nev er n ever
never
eve
up ve
u
v
n
v
i
n
g
e
v
e
n
g
e
r
i
e
g
er
rv
r
ive u
e
ver r
n gvi e
p
never
gvie up n ver
ve u p
p
gi ve up
gvieup
giv
neve ne er
neve
p
eu
up
r
e
give
ver
give up gvie up
gi ve u p
giv
n ever
ver
ne r v e
never never
never ver never
neev neve
never
v
e
r ever nver nenever
ne ver
give up givepu
ver nevr
giv
n ever
up
up rnever
ne
nevern eve
eer
neve n
neverr
r
ver
never
never
never v rve u
p
giveup
gv u
giveup up
e
e
never
never never
give neve
never
n evergi ve u p
neevr n vn ever never
er
r r
gi ve up n ever neve
p
r
eu
gvie up
neve i e p
give
giv
v
er
n ver never neve
gi v
give up
r
never
nev
ne ver
neevr vup
up
r
nev
neevr
giv
up
neve never never
r
v
p
neevr
never neve
nv
ever
n eve
never
e
rne
er
never gvieup
r never
gvie up give up
v er
neve r
never ve
giveup never
nenveeve
n ever
giveup
er never never n ever gvie up
u gi veup
never
neve r n
giv
r
ve n nevernever er
er
never
nev
ne r
neever r
ve
up
never
nev neve never
gie
v up
give up n neve
e
nev
n er
never
never
e
never never
never
n
e er
never
never ver
never
never
nevergi ve up veevu
nev
v
n
p gi ve u p gvie u p gi ve up
never
i up
p
n ever
er
r
never
never give up
never
negiver p
give up
never np v
nev r give up
never v e
give u p
nev r never
ve p
gi ve up gi
negvveer
give
r ver
r
never
give u u
e
ve up
ve u
er
r
r
never
e
r
give u
gi ve up
ne
n eve
give up u
v never
never
p
giveup
neve
n ever
nev
rr
gi ve up nee
never
v
gi ve u p
gi ve u p
gvie u
er n
neve ne r r up veu
never
never
er
never
ne ver
nneevevr never
never
v
r
n
never
n ever
neverr ver
ever r
vneeve e
r ne
up
er
v
r ne r never
never r
never
er
r never nneevveerr never
g r
never
giveup give up
never
nev er
never
never
n eve ne
neve
give
neve nneevevrer ver
never
nevgievu p
r
ve
give up
er
give up nneevveerr
ever
e
up
gvi
e
v
v
p
v
r
u
n
n
g
i
v
e
n
e
vn r
eu
ever
never
r
never
give u p
never v
p
gv
r
er
neve
nev
never
gvie u p
npever
p giveu givegive up gii veeupup
n
ne e
nev
er
neverr er r never never give up
gi ve u p
n evernever
er
give up
never up
giveu
never e
pe
v
neve v
never
nev up
e
er
r vr
u
n
r
e
e
e
never
g
i
v
e
u
p
n
r
p
e
p
p
r
i
e
e
up
e
e
v
v
n
r
g
nv
n nev
ge
neve giv up
never
nev r never
u
nv
n e ve v
never give up g i
never
iv
never never
ev n ever
ev
e up ver
n
give
give u
n ever
giveup
v
nneveeverr
give g givpe never
ver
never
givngevier
e
never
give e u n ever
r
ne
re
up
never
neve
vie u
giveup
never
iv
never
never
never
r
never
nev er
never
r
pg
neveerver
never
ever
giveu p
neve
ve
nev
er never p
r
ive up
i
never
er
up
e
g
nneev veup
giv
v
v
n
e
i
r
r
e
v
e
u
p
n
n
e
g
v
v
g
e
e
v
e
e
r
g
i
v
e
v
e
e
p
r
e
ne r
n
never
n
n
ne
never
nv
r
nev
ver
er
p
ne
neverer
er
r
neev
never
gi
v
neve evnervenr ever
n ever
er
er
ver ever
n ver
n ver
nev
nneevveerr
never
nev
n ever
never
nev
giveu
never
never
neve
u n nev giv
p gvie u p
n
r never
nev
gvie up never
g up
n e
er
r
give up
give up
n
gi veup giveup gi ve u p
r v
r e
never
gvie u
gvie up
neve
nev
neverver
r
u
up never
r ive
r
n ever
n eve giv give up everver
ve up
never
n ever
up
nee
v
n
e
v
e
never
r
e
r
never
i
v
e
r
v
n
e
p
u
r
g
n
v
e
g
i
e
u
n
e
e
up
n
nev
gi veup
neve
neve
giv
e
neve
givenuep
up
never
gi
i
up
e
up
never
eer
er
ver neve
n
giveu p
v
r
er
never
er g ve up
e
nenveverer
er n ver
give
nev
nenvevr
never
r never ever
r
e
never
never
r
never
never neve
never
nev neve
nee
v r nenverve v
neevveerr
n ever never
nev
nev
r
v
up
ver
never
p
e g e up
giv
never
give
er ve
r n
r
nevneerver
never never
n ever
neve eup
never
never
giveu
neveevrer n ever
gvie up never
never
vi
never
er
never
n
vr
ever
r
give up
er
never
n r
gi v
er
n ever
n eevverer v e upne e
p
neve r
ver
r
give up
ne
nee
v
nev
never
rneve
ve
never
r
giveup
ne
neve
ve
ne r
ge u
neve
giveup
never
up
r n ver
gi
er
never
ver
er
er iv
er
eve
r
ve urp
r
v
n
n
r
e
v
v
e
v
n
r
n
e
rev
r
e
e
n
n
e
p
p
r
e
e
e
e
e
v
e
e
v
n
e
n
e
n
e
r
n
e
e
e
v
r
n
n
v
e
n
e
v
p
v
er
vr
n ve
e
v
n
e
nevernever
give u
give u ev gi veupnev
up
e
er
give up gi ve upver
never
give up
up never
never
giveu
er
er
never
giev give up
n er
ne
er
r ve
rr
neevr eve
nenevver
up v give e r
never
never
never
ne v er
nev
give
r
nev
n eve
neevr evnever
g up
neve
never
r
never gi ve up
er
n
er
n ever
gi veup
giveup
gi ve up
gi ve
up
er never
never vie
r
n ever
neve
never
up
ever
v
never ne er
never e
giveup
nev
nev
r
n
g
g
u
e
r
r
g
e
v
e
e
n
u
p
i
p
n
v
v
e
e
e
i
e
e
r
e
r
e
v
r
n
u
p
r
n
e
e
v
e
n
v
e
r
e
v
p
v
eu
never
n
vr
r
v
n ve
giv
ever
gvie
upne e veup
n
ne
v
e
never
g
gi
never
never n ever
gvie up
giv
never n
n
never
never ne
never
nevergi ve v gi
never
neve
never i ve u p
v
gi v
never
give up
giveup v
nv
r gvieu p
ve
g
upnever
gvie up
r
ve
ve up neve
nv
up ne
neve n ev er
never
gi ve u p ggiivvee uupp
e
never
never
never give
neve
neve
neve
neve
never
er
up give up
e up
n ever
ver e
er
u
r
p
v
never
up
p
e
v
v
e
i
g
i
v
e
e
e
n
v
n
v
e
u
e
r
u
n
n
e
r
n
v
g
p
u
n ver
ne
gi
vr
e
give
gvie u p ver
never
never
never
up
r
never
u
ver
er
nev er
never
er
give up
p
never
ve
er
er
er
never
never
nev
never
e ev
r
ver
vr
never
p
p
n nee
never
nev
n
never
never
nev
gvie up
nev give u
nev
never
never
neveverr
r neverup
nneevveerr
gi v ne
ne
neve nev
v r ve up
g
never
gi ve up up
give up
eve
r
never
n
r
givveer
e
er v r gvie u p
p
n
e
r
g
u
n
r
n
e
p
r
e
p
e
e
v
v
e
v
i
e
u
n
g
e
e
r
e
e
e
n
v
e
e
n
v
r
u
v
e
r
e
e
i
v
e
u
p
r
v
r
n
v
g
i
v
e
u
n
v
r
e
e
v
e
e
ever nevenreve
er
never
gi v
n
n
n
gi ve up
ve
r
nev
give
gi
neve never
give up
never give
r never
giveup n e v
n eve
never
ne
r
gvi
giveu
never
never ever
er
r
ve
up
er
n ever
r
give up er
r r
never
e
give up
neve
n e v er
neve
gvieup
n
ve
e
vr v eu
never
nevr
nneveerv er
nev
up
give up er
ne up
never
ve
nevneere
n ever never give upeve
give up
never gve up
r
give
er
r
ver
n ev
nenvveererer
never
neve
gi veup negiveu
eup
er
never
never nev r
e never
never
never
never
gi
never
nneevve
n
i
up
nev
nv
nev never
never
neve
never
gvie up
neve
nee
v
neer
give up
u
ve up
giv r
nevever
nev
r
gvie u p
gi ve up
give up gvie u p
e
never n ever ver
give
er
never never
give up
n
never nev
neve
rn
e
gvie u p
neevr
never giviv
nev never
ne v er never
neve
up
nver
neve
neev
ginvee urp
e never
never
up
up
never
never
giv
v
r
n ever never
g eu
ve
e
give
r
never
nevergivn ever
give
r
nev
i ve
never
gvie up
gvie up
u p ne
nev
never
gvieup
r
ver
never
neve
gvieeurp
giveup
n
give up
er er
never
ve up v ver
neevveer nevger e
er
never
r
r
ne ver
ne
up
give up
u r
ver
r up
ive
n ever
gvie up
nev nev
ve up
n r
n evenrev
nev
n ev r
neve
never
er
nneveveer
neve
nenever
never
neevr
nepve
neve
nevernver n
u
r
give up
never
up eve n e gvie up
neevr
nevegr
n everer
n ev
nneever
giv
r
neverr
gvie up
nev
never never n ever
r er
e
r er
ver
e
n ev er ever
up
up
er
give
er r
up
up e p
ver
n eve
ve
nev
eup
gi
er
nve
gi ve up
giveup
give
nev
give
never n eve
nev give up
gvie up
nev r e u
ne
gi ve uepve nneevveerr
gvieup
e
neverver
n er
nev
nev r
r neev
er
upever
ve r n
giveup ngievveeruupp n er giveu giev up never
gvieupg eup
n r
never up
never
never never er
never
veu
never ev
never
never
n ever
never neever
e
ever
give up
never
ne
n
gi v
gi ve up
iv
gvieup ne
up gvie up
gi ve up
nev r
never
give up
give e v
gvieup
gvie
ve upgi
ve up never
gi v
giveu p
giveup giveup never
up
never
nrev
e up
e
never
give
ive
e
e
n
g
v
v
ig
e
e
n
r
g
u
p
v
e
r
r
r
neve v
eve
gvie up iv never gvie up
p ne
never
never
never
ve
never
gi ve ug p
n ever
n eve
ne
ver
ve up
u
neve n everve
neve
r r
never n ever
never never
u
r nevergvie up p
e
give uerp
never
vie up
er
ne
r
v e u p giv up
up
gi ve up n
er
never
n ev
ve u
er
ver give
en v
nv
r
enever
give up
never
up give u
never
never
never
never
nevernev
n ever
n e ver
never p
er
giveup never give up
n ever up nee
vr
nev
r
r
e
p n ever n
p
gi ve u p
neve
giv e up
er
gi
e
gi ve up
gi ve up p
r
e
never
give
n
never
neve r never r
nev
ver
up
up
never
never gi ve u
n ever nev
give ve
u gi v eup
never gnivveerup
enveerv er
ne r
v
give up ve neve
v
never
give
er
give up ne
r e up
neve er
gi veup
n eve
never
gi giveup ve never
never
giv eurp p
p
n
never never
r
n ever
n ever
givne u
never
gvie uepve ver nev
never
ver u p
never
never
neve
v
nev
r
vr
r
p
giveu
never n e er
giveup
neve
neve
nn eevvee
n r
er
ever
never up
never r n ver
n eve
r
r nneveer
never
n vn ever
give n e v er
never
v
r
n
up
e e
e
ve
gvieup
never
nenver
n ever
never nenveever
ver
n
ev r
n er
give up
ve r gvie
vr
r
er
eup never giveu
giv
never
give up gvie upgiveup give up e er give up
neevr
gi
p giiveup
gi veup n ver g up
neve never never
never u
give up ne v er
give up
er
u
give upp ev
nv
neverp
giv
ne v er gi ve up
er
neve n
p
nnever
give up
giveup
er
r
gvie up give u
giveup
give p
gvivieeu p
give u g
e
up
gvieu
n er
ever
up
nev
neevr nneve up give ugpiveup
e
give p n ever
egri
nen veer
neve p e vnever
up
er
nev
n ever never
v i ve
give up
giveneupver
never n
give
nev ve up
r
ve
ev
never
nev
giveu
up
nver gvie up
er
giveu p
n ever
ng
never
eve never
give up
gi
gi veup
gvie up
never
give up
never
never
r
up
never
p
nev
neve
give p
giev
p
never ever give up
give
never
never
gvie up
ne ver
r
give up ngievve
p
gviieu p
never
r give up up
e
er
never
giveu
give up n er
n ev er
never
never e giveup
r
g ve up e up
giveu
v er
giveup
nev
never
er
ev
g
nv
never
er
p
p
u
e
e
up
v
e
v
p
n
e
v
i
e
p
e
e
n
u
g
i
e
u
v
n
u
e
e
g
v
i
r
v
never r
n
g
i
v
e
n
e
v
n
n
e
g
g
v
e
r
eve
v up
r
ve up
iv
neve up
e
n ever
p p
n ever
give up
p
r gi ve
er
nv
never
never
r
r
er
n eve
nevernever
p
p
r
r
nev
gi ve up
n ever
never
p up
er
never
nee
v nevernever egive up
give u
never
give u u
r
r
neve
u
ve
give u
nevnever neve
give
ve
never
neve ne r ne
p ve
e
r
nevevre up
ver give up nev enever
gvie up
e e er never
n ve
eu e
er
never
never gi
never
never never
never
n evergi ve
ve
ve give up
never
giveup
never
never
e u upve up
give up
giv
giv giv nevernever ne
nev ever
nneeevver
v u
giveup
give upgive up p
iveup
n v never
n ever
never r
give
up
never
giveup
giv
e
never ngeivveeru p n e verup
n
ve r g
r
er
u
give up
p
neve r g up
gvie up
up
n
n eve
neve
negv up
giveup
giv eu p
never
e
er
vie
e
never
give
v
ive
neve
gi v
neve
giv
nev
v eup
er
e never
nne
give p
ve uper
r
r
e up
er never n
give up
nev er
neve r
never
ver never nneevveerr never
er
er
nev
nev
never
nnever
e
ever
giv
never gi ve unpe r
n
n
never
n ever
nev nev
nev
never
r
r
giveup ever
egverup
neev
nev
never
never
ve
ver
give upn
never
n
ve up
give u p
gi v eup
ne v er
never
ve r
ve up
eu
er
ve
n
ive never
never never
never ve
n ever
e giveup
v
up
gi ve
neve r
nev er
ever
never
ever n
gi
never
p ive up u
n
up
pnever
giveup
nevevrer
gvie up
nev
nev
gi
nevegrvie
giveupnever v
give up
give u p g
nev
n ever never
up
nenver nevveerr
giveu
nneever
never
er ever
give up
up
gvie up
nee
v
give up
neverve
ne er
r
gi ve up
give up g
giveup
e
give up
never
gi ve up
nevrer
u
n
neevr
v
never
ver
never
gi
n ve
giv
er
never
neve
give up
n ever
give u p
never
er
give up
never
nv
eu
give up
never
ne
never
n ever
n e venrever e
give
v er
gi ve up
never
never
neve
ne ver
never
nneevver
giveup
er
er
n
giveup
giveup
gi up
g
n
gvie up
r
nev
never
v
v
ev
giveup
n ever
never
p
never ever
r
never
never
nneevveerr
r
p
e
giveup
n
v
e
n
u
e
e
e
e
p
e
r
u
gi
gi v
never never
gvie up
n ver
nev
ver
p
n e
r
never
neve
r
never p
give up gi veup
gvie up v r
neviveu p
v up
er
r
n ever
never
giev
never gve u p
never
up r
er
r
g
gi ve u
p
n eve
give u
giveup never
ne v er
er
never
up
nee
v
n ever
never
nev never
pn
r neve
up
e
gigvie u
nev
give p gvieup
neeverr
r gvieeer
r gvieup neverg
gi n
up gvie up gi vieeupr p
give up
give u p
up n ever up ne
eup
iveup ugpiveup
ever
ver p ive u evegr
ive up er never
n ever
neve never nevenerver
nev
e
g
n
g
i
e
v
e
p
n
v
v
e
p
n
u
e
g
v
e
u
e
r
r
e
e
i
v
n
e
v
e
i
i
p
e
e
e
n
e
r
v
u
i
r
n
v
e
g
n
v
r
v
v
r
n
e
g
e
e
v
v
g
v
n
p
u giveu g ievveup give u
ep
iv e u
iv
n ev
give r
v p
giveu egup
never
give up
never
gi
never
ne ver eu
gi
n evperp
givegiveupergiveu
giveup
never
nev
er
give
never
er e
v r n ever
vr
up
giveup
g never i
neve giveup n ev er gie u
n ever
never
er
ver
nev
neve
never
er
p
gnieev giveup
gi v
never n
never
gi venup
give up
never
never
r
ngevi veup
gve up
never
nee
v
ne n ever v er
nev
e
er
vr
give up
never
give n ever
giv
give upn ever
ver never ne ver
up
vr
n
never
p
up
neve
giveup
e never
n ver up
nev
up griveup
gvienu p
gi ve up
nev r
v
ver nnevevrer
r
r
e
r
n
e
n
v
e
n
e
e
never ver giveu
r
n
e
v
e
e
v
r
n
r
g
n
r
e
r
give up
ve
nev
ever
iv neve
eve
eve
e
give up give
gi veup
never
n ever
never
gi ve gup up
never
n eve
ve vup
give up
giveup
nevgeirve up
e ne
ve up
v
nenveve
iv e
n ever
r
r p
r
give up
e
never
n evnerver ver
never
r
n ever
r
never
nee
v
gie
v p giv
n ever
ve ver
never
ve
never
gnieveveup
neve giveup
never never never
nen e
give up
er
v
ve up
er
never
never
e up
gi up
gi ve
gvie up
up ever
give
givpe u p
r
n ever er never
never
nev
ve
never
nev
never p
n
give up
r giveup
r
neve
gi ve up
n e v er e
ve up
up
never
er
ver gi
gi veu p
give u p neve
ve up
giveu
give u
n ver
ne
gi nv eeveurp
gi ve give up
give up up up
never
give up
give up
p
up
g eune
nev
giveu p
iv
never ver
er
never
gvie up
r
never
er
giveiuvp p
r
er
ngerev r
ev r
give
n ever
v e up gvie ever up nev
ve u p
never
never
give up giv e
never
giveup
nev v r
n e ver
r
up
never
nev
n ever never
gvieup i ve p n e
n eve
er
er
n ever n e ver
gi ve u p giveup
nv n
ne ereup up nev e
r n never
e
r
never
nev
nnever
r
er
nn r
never
never ne
up e
gi v r giveu p
never nevernever
n eve
giveeurp gi ve
never
ever
neve
n
never
never
e g
never
ev r
giv ne
nev
n everrevereve
v
e
ver
er
g
r
ve
give n v er never
n eve
nev
e
ver
gi veup
neve
give up
nev
giveu
give
never
never gvie up
nee
vr
n ever
neevr
give up
er
never
give up
up
n er
never
n ever
er
gi ve up
nee
v
give
u
never never
nev
r
never ev
never
never
never
giveu
never
ve
nenvever
never
never
never
ive
n r
never
up
r
r
ie
r
rg
up
ve uevpe g up
never
gi veup
giveup
p
n r
ve
n evernever
nevn
ereve
neverg v
i ve
n eve
v
v
g
e
e
n
v
e
r
n
n
e
u
i
e
v
r
r
n
e
v
e
r
n
v
e
v
e
e
never
never
e er
eve
never
r
gvieupgi ve u p eu
gvie up
u
e
give up
nevnerv
n ever
up giveu p
giv
never u g up neve never
never
give up
never
n e v er ever
ver
neve never
p
never
negvverup
giv
ve
v er
never
n ver
ive
r
n
pgive
r
ver
er p
never
ie
gvie u
ne v er gvie
gi
nevergive up
v ne
never e
neevr
neve
uvie up
er
n ever
r gi e up
up
u
r
never
r
ve
eve
g
e
nev
v
i
u
r
e
r
u
e
e
p
e
v
i
n
e
n
e
g
v
p
e
r
v
r
v
v
r
n
g
n
e
n
v
e
e
g
v
e
v
g
ve up
give u
v e
n ever eve
ne
n ver
neve
n ve
nneever
gi
gi v
never gvieup
gi ve up n e v er
never
gi veup
giveup giv
give u
r
gi eup
p
ve up ne
never ne n ever
never r
ne n ev
p
give
never
never
gvie up
nnevee
ve u p
ever
n ever
gvie u p
nev r
never
never
ver
e
p
er
neve
give u
giv
ev r
er
n e
r
ne ver
never
nee
v
gi ve
e
e
upn ve
p
give u
give up
never
n eve
neve never ev r
giv
n ever
ngeviveu p
never
never give up
never
n ever
gvie up
give up
never
er
ne
up
never r
nee
v
p
p
ve up
never
give g up
p
er
neve
ver
e
never
never
give
g unevn er
n er
eu
neve
neve
gvieup
nev
giveup
n e ver
ive
give up
eu
eu
ver
r
e
giv
giveiveup p ever
give
giv
giv
gi veup
up
gi v v u
gi v
ne g p
pev
gi ve up
up eve
never r
giv
gv u
ve up
er
v up
upv give
never
give up gvie up
er
up
give up
give up r
r
ne e
ni e p neve
gi ve n
nev veu ver vie nuevere never
gvieeur
ne v er
give
gievue p
up e
er eer
give u
nev
giveu p
ve up
never
giveup giveup
n ever
r
p
vr
r er v up
give up
n ve
gi ve up r n ever
give
nev n v
n ve
er
r
er
up
never
n ever
never
er
give up
never
never
never
neve
nev
r
never
ggiveiveup
nev
never neve
nev
neve
e
giv
ver
n
ne er
never
e
nerver never
never n ver
gvie up
nev
gvie up
up
ve up v
e
u pn ever
gi v
up
e
er
never
r
r
give up
give
never
giveup
give
e
never
give
never giv
give give up
giveup
giveu never
r
nevnerever
gvie up
gvieup neve
gi ve up
nneveveer
n eve
er
never
never
gvi never
gvie u p
neneveverr
n
ve up
never
nev
r
never neve
n ever
nev
never
r
vr
g never
ne v er
never
give up
n er
never
never
v
never
neve
r
enere
give upnev
never ev
neve
giveu p
r
ever nevneerver
n e v er n ever
r
ver
n
e
n
r
e
e
e
v
v
e
n
n
e
r
r
v
r
n
e
r
n
g
i
v
e
u
p
v
ev
nev er
nee
r
ever
neveve
p
r
er
eve r
ver
never
er
e
er
er
gvie u
neve nevneever
nr
r erneve r
never
gi ve up
nev
gvie up
neve
never
givneup
never give upgvie up
nev
nev
never
give
nev
e
ver
neve
nevenrever
give up
v
never
never
n ever
never nevegi give
nevern ever
n
gi veup
ver gi v
p
never ne
give up
give up
never
er
never
gi ve u p
er
up
rn
give
never v nuever gvie u p nenveerver
gi veup
giveu
never
give u
nev
r never evenevevrer
e upnever never
negvevieup never
never
n
n
gvie u p
giveup
n
er
never
r
n
give unpever
gi v eu p
never
nevneevrerp
neveervenrev
n ever gi veup
never n
never
nevneerver ever
nev
n ever
ne vner er
e
er
give up never
neveerver
eveg
n ever
er
er
neve n e r
n ever
vr
r
giv
nev
never
never
v
give
nev
gvie upn ive up
v r never
p
er
never
nev r
ve
given uvper never e v
never
neve never
giveu
r
nevrer n ever
e r
u
r
r
give upeer
nev
e
p
v up
nevneerer
never
n eve
never
er
e
ne ne v er
never
neve
n eve
give uer p eu p never
up
e
up
pne
never
g up never
r
never
v
never never n v
nev
giveup
eu
vnere er never
p
n
never never
nev
never
n e v gi v
up
p
e
gi ve up give u ver
never give
gvieup
give
n ever ive
gi
give up
n ver
v
up
neve
giveu
n ever
u
giv
r
nerev
never
never
n nee
never
giveu ne
v
p
ve
er
never
never
n ever
never ve up
up
e
ne v ergi ve
ge u
never
ver
g up
give up
e ur p
nev r
neve er
n eveevrer
give up
nev
e
never
n ever
give up
evr
eu
never vi
never
never
giv gi ve u p i ve
give up never n ever
e
e
nev
gi vneve
ve
p
gi
giv
never
n ever
er never
ne
p
ne
n
er
e
n e
nev
r
giveup
never
nev
never
never
er
never never
nev
up
n neever
neve
p never never
er ver ev r er vn r
e rg e up
nev
nevper
p
never
up
gvie up never
u
v rp r
e
n
neve
v
u
e
i
e
nnevever eup
v
e
r
u
u
v
e
e
e
e
p
r
p
r
v
n
n
e
n
n
i
v
v
ver giveup
e
up
r
ev
r
ev r
g
u p ve up
r
give
u
give u
neveer
giv give
neve give up
never giv
giveupp
ne
nev r n r er give
gi
never neve
gi veu p v
r
giv
gvie up
negvievenevveer
n r
p
never
neve
v r ver ne ve
ve
nevrer ver
vr
r
e evneev
up
r ne
neve never
neve giveeveup
giveu nevere ever never up
neerve
e
ne
e
never
never
never
giveu
er
p
give gvie up
give n ever
never
g
never
giv never
gvie
giveup giveup
nev
never
nev
nev nnever
er
u
never
n ever
p
er
ever evr n ever
u n ever
never
giveu
never
give
n
nev
never
up
er p
up
never
gvie u
never
gi veu p
nnv n e
nevver give p
neve
e
nev er r
nev
never
neevr r
give
r
er
gni veeeupr
giv
giv
never
up
ne
never
nev
n ever
neev
never
v
er
ev er ee
n ever
r
gi veu p
r
e up
up
giveu
never
r
never
giveup
give
nv
never
nev
giv give
v up
p
neve never
n ver
never
ve
r
n ever
e
er
never
r
ver ne er
nenever e
never
never
never up
n ever r
never r
nev
nev
up
n r
up
neve
verne r
n
nneever ve up v
nee
vr
give
e
p
r
e
neve
never
never
never
give up
never
neve
never
e
ve
never
gi ve
gi v
give up
up
n r
giveunpver
n ve
neve
give u
e up
nerver
neve
giveu
u
never
giveup
up evneever
ne r
give
gvieup
gvie up
never e
give r
v
r
never
n ever
e
er
n ver
r
n e v er
ve
e
n gv i
ve
give gvie neve r
n
never
never
giv
neve
nev
give up
r
g ve up
never
neve
nev
up
up
up never
r
giv e up
up
ve
p
eve
er i
give
neve
up g up
r r
neve
never
e
rn
r
gvie u
never
e
n
up
neerv
i
r
n
e
v
give ni evveegri ve upver neve neve
r
v
e
i
g
i
e
v
g
p
g
v
e
u
v
r
e
e
r
n
vie u
gi ve up
n
ge
n
never
n e neve
gvieu p
nev
neevvrer
e
ne
up
ginever
v
never
never nevenrever
never
r
p
never
giveu never
r
n ever
never
vr
ne ver nevenreve
n enveerve
never
giveup
giveup
n ever
ne v er
v e up
u
ve u p
give up
er
never nee
never
never never
giveup
v
never
gi ve
e
r
r
eu
nevnever
neverr gvieup
ve
v neve
ve
never
never
g
never gvie up
never
never
neve never
r
nnever
gvie u p
never
ver
n rn
give up
gvie up
neve never
ne
n ever
never
v eve r ever
er
er never
r
never giveu neve r giveupp
nev
n ver
n neve
n ever
nev
neevr
never
give up
give up
r e
ve
never
u
never
n ever
er
ne
give up
never
never
give
never
never
n
nev
ve
r
nev
er
up
p
never
v
never
e
er
n eve
nev
never
never
n ever
e
er
r
e
gi ve u
r g up
up
never
v up
pr
e up gie
up
nev
ver nev
giv
never neve vie gi ve u p
never
give
r evr
gi v e up
give
give up
u
up
n
p never
never
never
give
never
give up
g
ve
nev
give up never
nevenreveerver
ne ver p
vr
er
e
n ver ver n v r neve n e
gvie u
n
never nev er
vr
g
ne
give u
nev
never
gvie up
giv
r
er
n
ne
n e ver
n ever per
n ever ever
p
never
nev
v er
r
p
g
u
i
u
e
r
n
r
e
n
r
u
e
u
p
i
v
e
n
e
v
e
g
v
e
i
ever
ver eve
never
gvi
v
er
gi ve
giveup never
n e ve
nev
n e
never
never never
never
nenverr
never
give up
never gve give e
ve
up
up r
ne v erp
never
gvie up
nev
never
n
u
never
er
neevverr never
g
eve
never
n evr
give neve
nevrer
gvieu
never
never
e
never r
never
nev
give up
r
nev r
never
never
giveup
gi v
gvieup
r
ve
r
n eve
n eve
up r ver never n r
e
er
up
neve
neve
neevr never giveu p
n vegrive up
never
never
neve
never
nev
never
ve
never
r ve
giveup
never gi e
n
er
up
neve r n ever
gi veup
ve
v up
ngeivve e
never
p
n
never
never never
g veup
never e
never
nev
n ever
give p
gi ve
r n ever
er
e n
never
u
r r
up
nevegripuev
neiver
never
r
never
never
r
gvie u
n e ver
p nr
r
er neve
e
never
e
n
r
e
er
v
v
r
e
never
n
n
e
v
e
u
v
re
n
e
v
e
r
v
p
e
er
give up
er
er
n ver
n
ne
gi
e
vr
v n er
neve never nev
never ever
never vernever
neverr
neever
r
never
nev
nev
e
er
up
never
neverive e
ve
e
ev
n evenre
n
ne
never
n eve
nev
er gi ve
giveup
g n evr
er
ne
never
up
nev
p
n
er
er
ver
g
i
v
e
nev
v
i
give u p
r
g
p
e
e
u
p
v
v
g
e
e
v
r
r
v
v
e
i
r
u
e
n
v
e
gi ve
ne
v
eu
giev u p nenveer
nev
give ne r
ne
u g up
u
enr r
neve
ver
n
p
ve
r
give up
nev eve
never
vie
er
er
r
never
give up
never
never
giveup
nev
nev
never
n ever never
p never
e
er
up
r
never
gvie up
never
neve
giveup
er
gvie up
never
e
never
nev
never v er ive u
never
gi ve up
never
eve
never
never
give up
never
e up ever
ive never
nev
never ne ver
v
r
r
n evveerr
g
i
e
g
e
n
n
e
e
g
n
v
v
v
n ne er
ne
never
ne
er
nevenrever
give up
never
give up
p
v
never neer never
never
never
giev
r
er
nv
er
nev
never
neve
er
r
nev er
nev er
e
eu
p
n eve
nev
vr
r
nev
nevegrvie u p
e
er
giv
ever
neve
nev
up
r
giveup
give u
neve
nev
nnever
gvie up
never
never
r
neve
never
ve
gvie up
never
gi veu
r
v
gvie up
never nee
never
never p
never
nv
up e
r
e
never
p
r
neve
never
giv u
r never
e up
gi ve u
r
never
never
u
r
er
nerve
up
n r
giv
never
neve
p
up
never
giveup
giv
never
e
never
never
nev
up
neever
gvie u
er
give
nevergiveup
nrever
never
giv
never gi v eup
r
r
nee
v
never
give up
r
ve
e n er
r
e
never
nev
never
never
up
ev e p
never
give up
neve nee
giv n eveerv
ern ever
v eriveup
p
nv
er
gievpu r
giv
r
p
never
never
neve
v
ne giveup
neve
gnive u
e
r
g
nev
never give up
e r
nev
er
er
eu
er
nevernever
never
gi
ver
n vep
n eve
n
give up
g e up enrgve
nev v er
nev eer
er r never
r
never never
nev
gi v
p
n ever
giveeu
never
gi veup giveup
r
neevr
n v never
giveup i v nev ive up
ne
giv eup
p e
r
eu
never
n eve
n
p
er
er
er neve
never
never
gvi
g e up
r neve
r never up never n ve
er
r
u
never
never
nev give u
er vi
nev
er
give up
up
up
never
n erev
never
n ever
neverr
r
give p
nevnever
nev
neve
n ever
give up
nev
give up
ve
ve up
gi ve
give
up gi ve up
nev
never
never
gvie u p
n eve
ve
up
n ve
never
ern er r
ver
er
up
r
g
i
v
e
u
p
n
n
n
e
e
e
v
v
r
g
e
v
v
r
e
v
v
e
r
e
v
r
e
e
e
e
e
i
i
v
e
n
v
e
r
n
v
e
r
n
e
v
u
p
r
e
p
v
n
ne
n
n
giveu ve n
ge
ve
v
ve
r
giveu ver
never
n ever
up
er
r
neve
never
gi
never
up nneever
er
up
up
neve
ev
never er
er
ne
n eve
ep
never
ev
e
up
giveup
never
gi v e upver
givgeiveup
give
gvieeup give up ever
gnevievup
nee
ve
er
ne
p
rnever
nev
gvie up nenveveerr n e
p
nenevveer
e
never
n
gvie up
never
nev v
r
v e neve
nev
never
gvireu
n ve
n
n
e
n
e
v
v
r
n
u
i
e
g
e
u
p
v
e
r
e
r
e
v
r
e
e
give up
ve up
ne
e
er v r
nv r
u
ne ve
g never never
e
gvieup never
give ever
giveup
ver
er
n
ve up
er
nev nev
v
gi veup
er
nev
give
neve never
veerver
n
nev
r
r
r
give up
give u p
p
ne
never
r
nev
never
never r
n ever
r
eu
gvie u p
neveer never never
neve
e
never
ve up
never
give up
gi v
never
never
never
er
r never
nnneevevrer neverver g
nne vveer
r
never
nev
never
nev
ever ne
never
ive u p
never
neve
give up
eiveup
never
p
never giveup
never n ever
never
never v
never
never
nnevgever
er
neve
r
ne
er
gi veu
nev er
n ever
nee
vr
er
never
r
gigvi eveuupp
nev
n eve
never r
never
nev ver
giveup nev n evevrer
never
p r u
u
never ever
up
never neve
ever
neverr
never
never
never ve r neve r
n ever n
ne
n
n
en
e u evegivenever give
ne
ver
never
er
never
n eve
ver
nev
never
neve
gi v n
n
er
nev
neve
r
give u
never
never
neevr
p
everiveup
nev
neev ever
er
er
r
r
never
never
p
never
n
n everer
r
u
e
n
p
v
r
e
i
u
r
u
r
e
n
e
e
e
e
e
e
p
v
v
n
v
e
r
v
e
n
e
r
n
r
n
v
e
n
g
v
e
p e
gi ve u
ever
r
n ver g
r nev
v
eve
e
neveeve
gvie up nver nerver up ne p
n eve
nver ver
never
ne
never r
n e v er
giv
r
r
r
ne
e u n ve r
never
never
n eve
never
never e give e
neev
gi v
r
never
never
neve
er
ne
giv
n
v ve up
never
gi ve up
giveu
never
gvie up
r
p
enrev
gi iv u p ver
neve r never
give u p
n ever
never
neve r
r e
never
n ever
r
nev
neverg e vneu
never
veup g e u
i p
nv
eu p ne
n ev
n ever
n ever
eve
never
ve up
r gi neve i v gi ve gve
gi e vp
e
veu
p
r
never
giveu never neuvepr
ver
nev
gnvie up
never
ver
rnevernever n e ver
ve
gi ve u p
nev never
eu
ne er
v
never
n ever
never
never
giv
never never nevergive up er ve up
giveup ne
ngvi
e
e
n ver
never
p
er
n
er
r
er
nev
r
never
r
nev up
nev
nev
er
neve veer never
never
nev
never
gi v e
never ver
neve r
never never never
neve
ve
never never
nevneerve
never
n ve
n ever
nev n
n ever
ne
never
gvie up
r
ever giveup
neevr never
e
n
r
never
never
giveu p
gi ve up
nev
never
neve
er
gi veup gi ve up
neevr
nevernever
ver
never
never
giveup
gvie up
e
never
never
g
n ever
ve up
n
neve
p
nev n
ev
up
gvie up
giveup
neveevre nvie up
r never never up
ver
never e r never
ve u
give up
neve r
ever
n
r give
er
never
give
ver up
n
neve neve nee
give u pnever
n
e
never
nev
gi
v
g
g
e
r
n
r
p
e
e
r
r
n
i
v
e
p
n
v
e
r
e
i
v
u
u
ev r
ever give
nve
ver
give u p
neve
never
nev
er
e
ve up
never
give up er
ne never
never
give p
never
never
gi
r
r
ne ver e up
er nevere up
r vr
give u
never
n ever
n ever ev
n ever
ne
never
giv ever
n er
up up n
p
n ever nev giv
ne e
giveup
r p
er
r
r nv
never
never
giveup
never
ver
neve give upg eup
never
pe
up
ever gi
er
gi ve upn ever ver gi ve u
never never
giveup
n ever n
er gi egriveup
er neve
nev neve never
never
never
i v er
gi e
nnevver
er
r
e uvi
ne ver
ngeivveup
nneeveverr
g i ve
nev
n ever
g
ver
n ever nev gi ve up
nev
neve
never never
giveup giveup
giv g
v r nevegrive
e
never
nveevepr nee
u p neve
up
n
ne r
n evnereverngvievr eu p p
ne
give
v er
r
never
nev
u
nv r
give up n r
u
e gievpu ver gri ve up
gi ve u p
gi v e eupver never
e give u p r give up
p vever gi ve up
e
er
never
nver
never n ver
r
never
e iv
ver
give up
e
never
n ever
never
never
never
gi ve up
neve
n
gnivee up eve iveup ne
rneve
nv
give u
never
gi v r ggi
never
never
nev never
gi ve u pnever
v n everneve
never give up
giveup
never ernneverg
r
up
never g eup
n
ve
up
ver
neve
giveup
ne v er
nev up r n eveerr
iv
give u
n ever
never
ne
r
r
r
never
r
p
r
give pn ve
never
er
giveup
gvie up
neuvper
given urp nev er neve ve u p
er
e
never
never
eve
give up
n ever
giverup
neverveu e
nev
eve give u p n ever gi
give u
gnivever g p
r
never
e
er
p
ver
gigivveeup
never
give u p
never
e
ne er
r i
up ive u
n eve
n ever n
p
g up
neve rp
nneevveer
never g eu
never
nev
give u
n ever
ne
r
giveup
v
r
n eve g
n ever n enveerver
er n
nver vie
r
never give up
n ever negve
up
u
r
giveup giveup
ver
eve
iv p
r
veu p
r
e
e
i
e
v
n
n
e
e
n
n
e
e
v
e
r
r
e
v
r
neve
nver
er
gi ve up
nev
never
never n r
gi veup up
r
n everneve
v
gi v p
p
er
nev
neve
never
n
never
nev
n ever
u
up
g
er
nevereve
never
r
r
eu
e
never never
gi ve up ever
never er
er
gi ve up ver
nev
giveup
give
e
neveer
giv
ngevvee up
r
never
eev
gi ve
ver n ev p giv
nenver
n ver
e never
giv
u
ne
v
gi veeupr
i
never never
u
ever
never
ne never neve
give up n
nneevverr
nevernever
e
er
n ve
never n ever
give up
neve
ne veri gviupe ver ver
give up
nev
give u
er
never
r nevergvie up
r
never g i
neev
never
never
never
give u p
neevr
gve n e ne
never never
nev
r
gi ve up
never r
ever ne ver
e
giveup
never
er
r
p
p
g ve n
e
nverni upnev e ne v er
give nevern ve r
up
up r ngeivveer up neveerver never n ev
give upi e upevegrvie u p
nev n er
give u
n ever gvie up never nevnerevenrevegirve neveri gievup u neve
r
never
gve
n ve up
n ever
r
ve u p
ev
never
gv e
n
n e v er
gvie up
e
g u
er
neve
never
never
never evenrever never iv u r g up
u ever
p
v
neevver
r
giv
never ive p v
r
g e pn ve ive
never
n
nev r
r
up
er
nee
give up never
n
ever
v give u p never g never never
never
never
r
eu
ne ver
neveveu p
e
never
never
n eve
p
neev n
r
nev n ever
never
giv
er
up
r
gi
never ever never
never gi ve up
never
neve
gi
e
nev
vr
up
never
ever neve
neve
never
n n never
gvieup give
e up
er gv
neve
never
n ever
e
r
r
n ever
never
never
nev i up n
r
er n ever
ver r
neve
never
gi ve up
never
give up never
neve ve up
neve
never giv
e
r
e
e
e
never
e
g
v
i
v
n
v
r
n nev
r
never
n
never
nee
n ever
giveup er
neevr
nenveever
ve
r
never
never
er
er give up
n er
never
up
p
n ever
r
nev
neve
give
nee
v r nev
ne v er
r give up er g u p
e
never
never
never
neve g e u g eup
give u p
never
never r nev er
er
giv
ever eevveerr gvieup r ne giveup er
ive
i v iv
never never
up
ne ver never
er
give uper
ver
e
give up
gvie up
n never ver ver
r
e pnev
n e ver
n ev
nev
nee
vr
er
never
nev
nev
up
er
r
ne
n ever giv u
er
gi ve up
nneevver
n ver nev
up
v
givneever
ne
never nee
nev r
v
never
er
n
give
n ever
never
p
n
n ever
ver never
n er
nevenerver
n e v erneve
giveup
never
ver v up
nev
r
never ever
never
r ever
never
neve e v
e
rve negveir
r
n eve
ver
vr
gi veup e up
ever
eve
ve up
p v u
er
ne e r neve
gi v eup
never
neve n
n ever
n ever
never
never nnevveerr
nevgi veup
nevenr r
neve
ne
v
gi v n e ver
p ne
r
giv e ugi p
ne
ver
never
never r
gi ve up
never
ver
ngevneereup
er
ne never
nee
v n ever
never neve ver neve
e
up
r
ve n er
never
giveup
ivn ver
nev er
never give up
neve r
p
er
er r
er
up
give up nev
giveup
pg
r
er
give up
n eve ne e v
gvie up
never
never g i e
give up
give up
nev never never
giveup
never
give up
pnever
gnievve up
n er
never never nev er
give uneve
r
never
never
never
ve
e
r
gi ve up
r give uvper r
giv ep never r ev
vrer
veune ver
u
e
v
never
n
e
r
v
e
e
n
v
p
n
v
v
i
e
nev eerr
u
v
e
r
g
e
v
g
never
ve neer
ive u
vr r
up ver
never
never
nevveer
ne
nevner
ne neve
give up
v
r
never gi ve up
n
neveeup
giveup
neve never
neve
never
up
neve r
ne
n eve
r
gi veurp
neve
r
r
neve never ne e
r
n never
p
never
r n ever p
r never nevenreev r
never
e never p
gi v
givenepver
vr
gvie up
r
r
er g
give u
r
never
n enevveer
nev
u
u
gvie u neve
gi veup
neve
ie
n
n ever n ever
never
e
never
neve
never
never
er
er
never
giv
p
nev
nee
v
neve
never
never
nev
never
er
never
p i eup
r
never
never
never never
never
nev
never never
never n ever
r
p
neveer uper
never
r
r
ver
neve never g up
n ver
never
e gv
giv nev
n
ver
ne
never e
gi veu pgiv e up
r nevernevneever ive
r
gi v
er n erev
er
give up
ne up
er
gi ve up never never
n ever
nev
neve
er
never
nev
er ve n
nee
never
v
n ever
nev
ne v err g
er r
never
never
neve
nev
gie
v p
gi ve up
n
never
gi ve up givuep
ever never give uvpr
gvie upr
never
never
nevneve
nevernever ve
neve iveu
n ever
p
never
never
neveveerr
up
r
nevneeevveer
never
give up
n r
ne
never
er
eve never
ve
er
up
never
r
r
e
gi ve u p give up
nev
never giveup
n ever
n ever gvie unp
nenver
vr
iv
eve
nenveerver nee
giveup never never
r
p
r
v
e
g
n
g
i
v
e
u
e
n
e
e
e
r
v
e
nev
n ever
never never
n
u
n ever
er
nv
never
never
ve
never
never
nev
never
er
nv
neevr
n ever ver
r
n v never up r
u
give up never
gvie up
n eveeve
ne
gi veup
ver
never
r
never
ve
er
never
giveupn er
er
never
nnever er giveup
er neve
n
ne
gi ve u p never
n ever
g
never nev
ev
neevve
v gi n ev ernever
r gi ve u p
nev
ever nev
e
never
p
r ver n
ne
er vie up
r
er
never
n ever
nev
e
ever n evevre u never n ev
never
never
give up
nev
pg e up n
never never
nev
giveup
never
never
never
p gi ve u p
iv ever
r
never
never
never
never
never
n ever n ever
v er
rver never
up
u
never ver
neve
never
gi vne u p
give
r
up
never ne
ne
r n ever
never
enver up
never
e
er e
n
u
v r evr never n r
nee
v
r
never
gvie up er
nee
v
nev giv
neve give upp
ne
givepu r neve
n ever
ver
r give
er
never
n ever
ev er never
nev
e er ver never
n ever never
ne r
nev
n ever eup
negviveer up iv nev
never
n ever ver
giveup
never
er
p
r
n nev er
n ever give up ngever
never r gi v give up rever
p
v
r
pu
never
e
ver
vuep
e
never
e eve r
neve r
never
r
geue
nev
never v
never giveup
giv
n
er
er
enr ever never
giv i v
v
nev
er
r
never
nev
er
nev
nevergi ve up
never ve u
neve
nev
never
p
p
never
give up
eu
ve
gi ve up
never
er
er
never
gi
nnevee
r
ver
nev n
nev
v
r
p ve
er
ne
give up
never
u ne
nev
never never
never
neve
neve
giveup
nenveevrer r
r
ive
never nver r ver
r er
g p
n
never
ngever never
up er i ve u
eve
up ver
neverve
never
er v
gi ve
nevernev
never
never vie n ev
r nev er ne
nev r
never
ver
never vr
never
nevenre er
r
gi u
er ve ve
r
never
nevernever never givepu ngver
er
n ver er never
n eve nevneerver neve
v
e pe
nenev nenveer neveurp
v
e
upnv e nev v
neve
neeverer
nev
never gnevgeir n ever never r never neernever up
r
er
never
never
iv e n veerr n e er never
give nneerver v r
nevner v nneevveerr n evenr i e u veupnnever
ev
egviever up
never
n
up e u ggvie up nnevver
n
v
e
r
e
v
e
r
n
v
e
ev
ne
ever
r r
neve
n ver
n ever
nevveer
gi ve up
r
neve
r
never er
r
never
r
nev
never neve
n
never
never
ver
r
never
nneevveerr
n evneever
never
ve
r
ve neve
r ev
n
neve
r
T H E UN D ERGRA D UAT E P H I LOS OP H Y J O U RNA L OF B OS TON COLLE G E
g e
u e
n e ver
e e ve r
r
never up
give
e
never n
nenvevrer
ever
gi
e
never never
p e up never
e gi ve u v n ever gi v eup
never
gi veup
er
nev
e
r
gi ve up
er
nev
nev
never
n e ver
never
r
nev
r
neve
gvie up
n ever
neve
r
never
ve
n ver
n e ver
ne ver ever
n
never
e
never
ne
never ne e ver never
vr
n ever
n ever
never
never
ee
ne
n v rn ever
never
never
gi ve up
never
never
never
e
never
never never
e
e
never
e ver
e
ne
ver
ne
n ve
never
e
ne
neverne er
v
never
v
never
ve up
gi
giveu p
v
never never erer
nev
ve up
gi
ne
n ver
nveerv
n er
never
r
never
n ever
neve
neve
r
never
never
ver
never
up
v
neve
ne
never
never
never
never
never
never
ver
er
n ver n ever
never ev
n er
er
give
er
nev
er
er
nev
ne
e
n ever
ver
never
er
neeev r
ve up n v
gi
neve r ne e
ne
vr nenver r n ve
ever
ve r n
n neve nevere
n r neevr
r eve n v
gv u p
nevieer
never
nenveerver
ne ver
er
e
r
e
nev n v
nev
nevneer
verver
neve r
The Undergraduate Ph osophy
Journa of Boston Co ege
n
n ever
ne
ver
ne
n
never
ver
never
ve r
er n
ve
never
ne
never
nev
r
e
902980_Cv ndd 1
er
nev
4 18 14 2 45 PM
DIANOIA
The Undergraduate Philosophy Journal of Boston College
Spring 2014
Issue III
902980_Text.indd 1
4/18/14 2:17 PM
902980_Text.indd 2
4/18/14 2:17 PM
DIANOIA
The Undergraduate Philosophy Journal of Boston College
Dianoia fosters open philosophical discussion and writing among undergraduate
students at Boston College. The journal provides a necessary venue for sharing
creative, philosophy-based papers that bridge academic disciplines.
The ancient Greek word ˗Ԇඥဎ‫ڗ‬ԆǓ translates as “thought” but connotes a
discursive direction or search for a higher form of knowledge.
Dianoia is sponsored by The Institute for the Liberal Arts
and The Philosophy Department of Boston College
902980_Text.indd 3
4/18/14 2:17 PM
Dianoia Staff 2014
Editor-in-Chief
Karel-Bart Celie
Managing Editors
Lucilla Pan, Andrew Skaras
Editors
Nicholas Anderson, Eleni Callas, Daniel Cattolica,
Gunnar Lund, Ben Markely, Ben Miyamoto,
Peter Sheridan, Alec Walker
Copy Editor
Timothy Bak
Designers
Nicholas Cokonis, Jasmine Rebadavia
Faculty Advisor
Rev. Ronald Tacelli, S.J.
The editors of Dianoia would like to express their gratitude to the following
individuals for their generous support:
Mary Crane, Department of English and The Institute for the Liberal Arts
Susan Dunn, Center for Centers
Rev. Arthur Madigan, S.J., Department of Philosophy
Yasmin Nunez, The Institute for the Liberal Arts
Cover illustration courtesy of Juan Osborne: Never, Never, Never Give Up, 2011,
Digital, 3161 x 2001 pxl. All rights reserved. Readers are encouraged to visit
www.juanosborne.com for information and illustrations.
The materials herein represent the personal opinions of the individual authors and
do not necessarily represent the views of Dianoia or Boston College.
If you have questions regarding the Journal or would like to submit your work
for review, or if you’d be interested in joining next year’s staff, please contact the
Journal at bcdianoia@gmail.com
Dianoia
The Undergraduate Philosophy Journal of Boston College
Spring 2014 Issue III
Boston College
140 Commonwealth Avenue
Chestnut Hill, MA 02467
Printed by Progressive Print Solutions
© 2014 The Trustees of Boston College
902980_Text.indd 4
4/18/14 2:17 PM
Letter from the Editors
v
W
inston Churchill was as much an intellectual as he was a political figure.
His leadership of Britain during the Second World War helped the Allies
defeat Nazi Germany and re-establish peace in Europe. However, Churchill was
more than just a British prime minister. He was a prolific author who penned numerous, comprehensive, and well-written publications, for which he won a Nobel
Prize in Literature in 1953. It might be said, then, that Churchill’s strength as a
public figure had its source in the strength of his intellectual life. By all accounts,
Winston Churchill was more than just a statesman—he was a public intellectual.
The theme of this third incarnation of the undergraduate philosophy journal
of Boston College is the role of the public intellectual in contemporary society. In
light of this theme, Dianoia is pleased to publish the highlights of an interview
with philosopher, Richard Kearney. Kearney—a highly regarded public intellectual
who played an influential role in the peace talks between northern and southern
Ireland—serves as the Charles Seelig Professor in Philosophy at Boston College,
where he continues to author books and teach students. We would like to thank
him especially for contributing to this year’s issue.
From a number of high-quality submissions, Dianoia is also pleased to present
a selection of five essays that we hope will contribute to the intellectual dialogue
on campus. “Banksy: Dissident Artist” examines the role of street art in critiquing
consumer culture. A thoughtful analysis on the dialectical interplay between Kierkegaard and Hegel is presented in the essay “Encountering Paradox: Movements
of Faith and Reason in the Dialectics of Kierkegaard and Hegel.” Plato’s famous
Third Man Argument is examined in the most analytic essay of this year’s issue, “A
Critical Examination of the Third Man Argument.” Though more literary in style,
the Journal has also included “Nietzsche the Autobiographer” for its pedagogical
value in understanding Nietzsche’s own assessment of his life and works. Finally,
“Divine Simplicity: The Centerpiece of Aquinas’ Doctrine on God” provides
philosophical and theological insight into the thought of Aquinas.
This year, Dianoia has opted to publish fewer essays that are, in turn, lengthier
on average than a standard paper. Our hope in doing so is that anyone who does
not know much about a given topic—say, Nietzsche’s life—can pick up this Journal and learn from the content. Dianoia seeks to be a forum for intellectual debate
and dialogue in the Boston College community, and we believe that this year’s
issue reflects that goal. Please enjoy the third edition of Dianoia, and we look forward to your continued support.
Sincerely,
Karel-Bart Celie, Editor-in-Chief
Lucilla Pan, Managing Editor
Andrew Skaras, Managing Editor
902980_Text.indd 5
4/18/14 2:17 PM
902980_Text.indd 6
4/18/14 2:17 PM
Contents
vii
Interview with Richard Kearney, Charles Seelig Professor in
Philosophy
1
Banksy: Dissident Artist
13
Alexander Trimes
Encountering Paradox: Movements of Faith and Reason in
the Dialectics of Kierkegaard and Hegel
21
Francis Adams
A Critical Examination of the Third Man Argument
35
Gjergji Evangjeli
Nietzsche the Autobiographer
45
Anthony Cossette
Divine Simplicity: The Centerpiece of Aquinas’ Doctrine
on God
61
Jonathan Phillips
Author Biographies
902980_Text.indd 7
68
4/18/14 2:17 PM
...being involved with the public means trying
to be answerable to, and attentive to, suffering
and pain. As well as then imagining, through
hope and utopia, alternatives of that.
902980_Text.indd 8
4/18/14 2:17 PM
Interview with Richard
Kearney, Charles Seelig
Professor in Philosophy
Richard Kearney, Ph.D.
1
902980_Text.indd 9
4/18/14 2:17 PM
2
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
As a part of this issue’s theme of the public intellectual, Dianoia conducted an interview
with Richard Kearney, the Charles Seelig Professor in Philosophy at Boston College.
Hailing from Ireland, Kearney has been extremely influential both philosophically and
politically in the public talks surrounding the Troubles of Northern Ireland and the
Peace Talks that occurred between the Irish Republican Army (IRA) and the government of the Ireland. Since then, he has appeared publicly in numerous forums to discuss
issues of terrorism, politics, and philosophy.
Dianoia: Could you describe your role in the Northern Ireland Peace Talks?
Kearney: In 1977, I cofounded a journal called the Crane Bag, which was an
interdisciplinary intellectual review founded by the Arts Counsels of northern and
southern Ireland. It was a way of bringing together politicians, philosophers, writers, teachers, and professional people to develop a dialogue on the future of northern and southern Ireland. It was open to all points of view. So we did an interview
with the head of the IRA and with the Minister of Communications of Ireland at
the time (you couldn’t find two people more opposed). It led to a controversy with
Margaret Thatcher and Ian Paisley, who openly denounced it in Westminster Parliament saying, “Here’s British public funding going to a journal that shook hands
with the IRA.” While our point of view was: “You’ve got to shake hands with the
devil.”
So it was the idea that philosophy—or a philosophy journal—should be something that develops public debate. And also that all are admitted, because philosophy is a discipline which, as Husserl said, is really the “science of sciences.” It is a
foundational investigation for all disciplines. So it’s a forum—an agora, as Socrates
put it—where people can come together and share opinions. That was kind of the
beginning.
Then, in 1984, we did a special issue of the journal—called “The Forum Issue”—and this was an issue that published the proceedings of the forum for a new
Ireland that was set up by all the political parties in Ireland to imagine new solutions for the future. One of the solutions that I, as a representative of the south of
Ireland—with a Catholic, Nationalist, Republican background—proposed (and
I co-presented with another philosopher from the north) was a model of joint
sovereignty for Northern Ireland. Now sovereignty per se has always been defined
as “one and indivisible,” going back to Rousseau and Bodin. So, if that’s the case
and you’ve got a claim for a united Ireland, as was the case with the Republican
Nationalist cause, which a majority in southern Ireland and a minority in northern
Ireland supported, and then you’ve got a contrary claim for a United Kingdom,
supported by the Unionists who are the majority in northern Ireland, then you’ve
902980_Text.indd 10
4/18/14 2:17 PM
INTERVIEW WITH RICHARD KEARNEY
3
got a conflict of sovereignty claims that is absolutely incompatible and irresolvable.
If sovereignty is going to be indivisible you can be British or Irish, but you can’t
be both. So we proposed that you should be able to be both; and even though joint
sovereignty is legally and constitutionally a contradiction in terms—that was the
only solution for a contrary society like Northern Ireland! Which in a sense is an
oxymoron, strictly speaking, because you can’t share sovereignty. But, by putting it
in terms of a contradiction you can lead to new thinking. Constitutional impossibility calls for imaginative possibility! And poetry works like that—Yeats talks
about “beautiful despair.” You grow up between opposites and contradictions, and
when you put the two together, you get poetic imagination. Or as Seamus Heaney
put it, “Two buckets are easier carried than one, I grew up in between.” And our
big wager was, “If you put two contradictory positions together, you get political invention.” So we proposed joint sovereignty. And that was eventually one of
the three proposals that were brought by the government of Ireland to Margaret
Thatcher: joint sovereignty, federal Ireland, and a united Ireland. And she famously responded, “Out, out, out!” to my proposal and to the two others.
So that was my first exposure to tough political debate as a public intellectual.
My first foray into politics—British-Irish mainly. Although in my book Postnationalist Ireland I also explored pan-European-federal solutions, seeing Ireland as a
region within Europe.
Then I did a number of television programs and public broadcasting. I used
to have a weekly program on Irish national television on politics, philosophy, and
literature. We interviewed the likes of Vaclav Havel, Noam Chomsky, Umberto
Ecco, Paul Ricoeur, Jacques Derrida … they were all the published in a book called
Debates in Contemporary Philosophy. And that was kind of a weekly attempt on
British and Irish television to create debates between intellectuals—philosophers
from Europe and North America.
There was in Ireland and Europe at the time the idea that philosophers—or
academics generally—could be public intellectuals. It is less so here [in the U.S.].
For the most part, philosophy remains much more of a … specialized professional
activity I find. Regrettably so.
Dianoia: You mentioned the different roles that philosophers play in the U.S. versus in Europe. Did this shape your role in creating a public forum? What brought
you to the place where you decided to start your journal and have those public
conversations?
Kearney: Growing up, doing European philosophy—here sometimes called
Continental Philosophy, although often more Continental American philosophy—
902980_Text.indd 11
4/18/14 2:17 PM
4
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
some of the main people I was studying were Camus, Sartre, De Beauvoir, Merleau-Ponty, Paul Ricoeur. They all edited and wrote for journals. These different
intellectuals were all involved in public broadcasting and public intellectual debates. Some of them taught at universities but the rest of the time they were out,
engaged with the public. The first president of Czechoslovakia, Masaryk, was a
Ph.D. in philosophy, a philosophy professor, who studied with Husserl and Freud.
And his follower, Jan Patochka, a great philosopher in Prague, went on to found
the famous peace rights movement, Charta 77, and was imprisoned and tortured
for his trouble. But he left a huge legacy on Vaclav Havel and a whole generation
of intellectual dissidents who brought about the Velvet Revolution in 1989.
In other words, the people I was studying were people who were involved
with the public. The split between a professional academic specialization—called
philosophy—and applied philosophy, practical philosophy, engaged philosophy,
simply did not exist in that way. And this also appealed to me because I was doing
philosophy and literature. Most of these publically committed philosophers were
themselves writers—some of them, like Camus and Sartre, even being awarded
the Nobel Prize for literature. When teaching existentialism, I always start with
Nietzsche, Kierkegaard, and Dostoevsky—who are as much literary writers as
they are philosophers. I actually found it quite strange to come to North America,
where philosophy departments were often cordoned off.
In 2008 I set up a Guestbook seminar here at BC [Boston College] with fourteen different departments involved, faculty and students. The idea was to develop
philosophy in dialogue with literature, art, physics, psychology, political science,
romance languages, and so on. And it was great fun. I still very much believe in
interdisciplinary teaching and publishing.
The third point I would make, which is relevant to all of you as undergraduate
and graduate students, is that I resent the fact that everything revolves around the
question: “Where are your philosophy students placed?” And if they are not placed
in an academic institution—and usually a tenure track—it doesn’t count. You
won’t get points for the ranking. Whereas, I would say that a good portion of my
grad students since I came to BC ended up in public positions, not in academic institutions. One is running an NGO in Jerusalem, as co-director for the free movement of Palestinians. She wouldn’t have gotten that position without a philosophy
degree. She’s also writing philosophy—she does both. But that doesn’t count as a
placement. The last two presidents of Ireland had Ph.D.’s in philosophy—neither
would be counted as placements here. If Obama had a Ph.D. from Boston College
or any American university—his being president in the White House would not
count as a placement. So it’s considered an academic “failure” to put someone in
charge of an NGO or a government. Tell that to half the ministers in the French
government—all Ph.D.’s. Doesn’t count. Havel—doesn’t count. Masaryk—doesn’t
902980_Text.indd 12
4/18/14 2:17 PM
INTERVIEW WITH RICHARD KEARNEY
5
count. So it’s kind of absurd, expressed in the narrow view that if you do philosophy at a graduate level, it has got to be to teach at a tenure-track university job.
Whereas a lot of European and Continental philosophy, in any case, teaches in a
very broad and interdisciplinary way. So it’s a huge plus to go into an interview
and have a graduate degree in philosophy. It’s very sought-after. And not just in
Europe—where it certainly is—but also, I believe, increasingly here in America.
Or at least that is what some of my grad students out there in the market tell
me. It’s kind of a prestigious thing to have—undergraduate or graduate, M.A. or
Ph.D.—going into non-philosophical jobs.
Dianoia: Would you say that the philosophical environment in the United States
precludes philosophy students from functioning as public intellectuals?
Kearney: It is hard to speak in general terms. With a graduate degree, you have
the choice—1) to become a professional academic philosopher, teaching in a university or 2) do that and have a public role, or 3) just have a public role. But either
way philosophy will form you—it’s a foundational humanistic formation. And this
should be touted and promoted as a plus. I taught in Dublin for 21 years in our
Ph.D. program, and I would say maybe 50% went on to teach in philosophy programs. Most of the rest went into public functions. That was always my interest—
philosophy and something else—not just specialized logic-chopping. But that
doesn’t mean one shouldn’t have a really rigorous academic training. Of course one
should. But it should always be in dialogue with other disciplines. Or at least have
the option of doing that. These should be equi-primordial options—to stay in academic philosophy or to apply your talents to public discourse and debate. Or both.
Dianoia: Do you think that is changing at all? Do you think people are becoming
aware that the inter-disciplinarity is important?
Kearney: I think it’s growing. And for two reasons. First of all, people are opening their minds. They are realizing that specialization is going to disappear into a
hole. And second, the Ignatian humanistic spirit of BC and other Catholic universities—and I talk about that in a broad sense—caused them to always have this
broad education in the humanities. So BC is ripe for that. But I think there was
a tendency for a while to ape the Ivy Leagues and say, “We should be doing what
Harvard and Yale are doing.” When what the Jesuit intellectual tradition is doing is far more interesting and profound and life-changing than the kind analytic
knit-picking and conceptual navel-gazing that passes for philosophy in certain
esteemed quarters. It’s an intellectual inferiority complex which infuriates me.
902980_Text.indd 13
4/18/14 2:18 PM
6
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
“We’ll drop in the rankings if we don’t become like Harvard.” Well, who makes
the rankings?
So I think that is turning around, and BC, in its intellectual and spiritual culture, is very open to interdisciplinary, humanistic education. There’s different ways
of doing philosophy—as technical rationality or as humanistic reason. Analytic
philosophy, which has predominated in so called “Anglo-Saxon” thinking, privileges the former; so called “continental” philosophy the latter. Every student should
be trained in both, but I know where my preference lies.
Another factor, of course, is that there just aren’t enough academic jobs today
for Ph.D.’s. There are not enough university posts for Ph.D.’s, so people have to
think out of the box. But that is not a reason not to study philosophy. We have all
these unemployed Ph.D.’s in philosophy so what can they do? How about running
the country? Running NPR? Running the diplomatic corps? Running a publishing company, setting up journals, running theatres, running NGO’s?
Dianoia: Do you think there is a cultural reason for this? Something in American
culture that is the reason why the role of philosophy is perceived so differently
here as compared to Europe?
Kearney: I think exactly the same reason that the government took away public
funding from NPR. Same thing. Thinking is dangerous. Keep it cloistered. Of
course, that’s putting it too bluntly. But when I pay taxes I want some of those
taxes to go for public education, public broadcasting, and public debate. Yet there
seems to be a prejudice in certain quarters that if funding for public broadcasting
comes from taxpayers instead of from private individuals, it is somehow suspect.
It’s an extraordinary indictment of what one means by “public.” And that division
between public and private is, in my view, ruinous.
Some people would say: well what about Greece? And I would say well that
went to the other extreme, where you had 80% of the people working in public
or state positions, and that has got to be countered. But America has gone to
the other. I throw up my arms in despair at the way certain people use the term
Obamacare as a slur. Rick Santorum, for example, described it as “apartheid.”
Saying, “How can Obama be celebrating Nelson Mandela’s memory when he is
introducing apartheid here?” So what can you do? There can’t be a sense of ownership of the public domain, either of health, education, or broadcasting, when the
term ‘care’ is treated as a term of insult.
Also, there tends to be a sense that the disciplines should be quantifiable.
It’s very hard to quantify theology or philosophy. If you want to do so you need
to adopt a quasi-scientific form of reasoning that can get grants and work with
902980_Text.indd 14
4/18/14 2:18 PM
INTERVIEW WITH RICHARD KEARNEY
7
strict criteria of verification and falsification. Now that is a certain side of philosophy—Aristotle wrote the Physics, as well as the Metaphysics. He did both. So
I’m not saying that there shouldn’t be a scientific philosophy or a philosophy of
science—there are wonderful people here at BC who teach that. I’m all for it. But
the tendency since the 50’s and 60’s has been to focus on a certain brand of philosophy that is “measurable” in terms of proofs. And then certain philosophy departments (Princeton, Yale, Harvard, and so on) tried to ape the sciences in narrow
ways—though things are beginning to open up again now and the whole analyticversus-continental divide is happily beginning to erode. Some scientists replied:
don’t try to do our job, do your job, and then we will talk to you … because you can
teach us things about foundational human questions that we’re not doing here in
our laboratory. But don’t try and compete with the rats in our laboratory—we’re
doing very well, thank you very much. And of course that gave pseudo-scientific
philosophy an inferiority complex. They couldn’t measure up to the sciences! But
as I say things are beginning to open up again. I’m delighted, for instance, that
Shawn Kelly is the chair at Harvard—he comes from Merleau-Ponty and he can
do cognitive sciences and phenomenology of perception. The important thing is to
get the two traditions to talk to each other.
Dianoia: You’ve alluded to the fact that, in Europe, there has been a more active
role played by public intellectuals than in the United States. Do you think that
the media also plays a role? Should public intellectuals function to filter what is
presented to the public? The media is there to correct factual errors, but there is no
discussion about ideological errors.
Kearney: That’s a very good point. And it’s a lack of a middle ground—a mediating ground. You’ve got the ideologies of government, as it were, and the statements
and proposals come out, and then you’ve got the big public. But no one is really
mediating. So more and more the media has taken up the role of mediation—as
they should. But they should be a forum for public intellectuals and commentators also. And there still are some out there, but increasingly it’s becoming pundits
in an entertainment game. It’s like sports commentary except it’s political commentary. Tick-tack, tick-tack, but it’s not a deep, informed, philosophical debate.
It’s all sound bites. (I’m talking mainly about Fox News and even CNN, more
than NPR which has some excellent cultural programming of course—but they
are always under such huge financial pressure.) It has become increasingly about
entertainment rather than education. BBC, when it was set up, was founded with
a few principles, one of which was definitely education. In the media, it’s important
that you get the fact-checkers—that’s essential, the media should be there to invigilate the facts. But the second role is commentary and interpretation, and that’s
902980_Text.indd 15
4/18/14 2:18 PM
8
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
become incredibly impoverished. You go into an airport or a hotel, and you’ve got
split screens and it’s just to-and-fro news clips and “opiniators.” It’s a spectator’s
sport—gladiatorial, adversarial chit-chat—but rarely real in-depth interviews apart
from NPR/PBS, which has a minority audience. Now, I repeat, the latter is often
excellent but it absolutely reduces me to tears to hear them have to beg five days in
a row during fundraisers. In the meantime, they can’t have a debate because they
have to get the money to support it. And to me that is just not a democracy—
when people have to scrape, borrow, and beg to get enough to talk intelligently
about things! I mean on one level it goes back to the American spirit and that’s
fine—we all pay for what we get. I’m all for things from the ground up rather than
the top down. That can be extremely important. People get together, and there’s a
groundswell of opinion from beneath. Yes. But NPR has to appeal for money to
individuals in their cars, in their homes, on their way to work. It’s almost always
an appeal to private individuals. Not a community or province or state thing. And
public radio is communal. So it should be paid for communally.
Dianoia: Do you find the literature in Europe—in philosophy, for example—more
accessible to a general reading audience than it is here? Conversely, is the general
reading audience more informed, so that a higher-level journal is more accessible
to them?
Kearney: I think it works both ways. Remember, in France, Germany, Italy, and
several other European countries, philosophy is part of the high school education—it’s taught to all students prior to graduation. You don’t have to wait till you
go to university to study philosophy—you are already formed and informed by it.
And that makes a big difference.
But I don’t wish to be too down about American education. I came here for a
reason. I came here to work, so it’s not like I don’t see the wonderful opportunities
and advantages of the great universities, libraries, research institutes. They are really wonderful, among the best in the world. My argument is not about resources.
It is elsewhere.
Let me put it in the form of a question: “What happened between the intellectual heyday of Jefferson and Franklin, for example, and our own day to explain
how, for some reason, the intellectual-philosophical work isn’t as central to the
culture?” Why did it get cloistered and confined to academic campuses (often in
remote settings like Dartmouth, Wellesley, Princeton, even Boston College) in a
kind of cultural apartheid? Why this quarantine of philosophy? One learns great
things, but far from the madding crowd. One thinks great thoughts but apart from
the world.
902980_Text.indd 16
4/18/14 2:18 PM
INTERVIEW WITH RICHARD KEARNEY
9
Dianoia: You teach philosophy of imagination, and you’ve written several books
on imagination. Could you flesh out what you see the role of imagination is for
the public intellectual?
Kearney: Well, it enables one to enter the kingdom of “as if.” And that opens up
the space of possibility, a laboratory of possibilities, so that you can think otherwise. And if you can think otherwise, things can be otherwise. It reminds me
of Bertolt Brecht, a German playwright and poet, who said, “The most radical
poem I ever wrote was of an apple growing silently in a Berlin orchard during the
height of Hitler’s power.” This was radical because to imagine something beautiful growing in the middle of evil was a categorical imperative that things can be
otherwise, that things must change. So imagination opens up the future, it opens
up the realm of possibility. And I think that’s why, say in Northern Ireland, the
road to the peace process was paved not just by politicians and jurists but by poets
and writers, able to imagine what it was like to be the enemy, to empathy with the
adversary, to image the possibility of the impossible. To imagine what came about
with the Good Friday Agreement in 1998.
I’m currently directing an international project called “Guestbook,” which
started here at BC, where we bring together young people, students, from different divided communities—Northern Ireland, Kosovo, Jerusalem, Dokto—and we
get them to exchange narratives. First of all, we get them to share their own story.
And then, in the second part, they imagine a new story. They create something
together from the components of their respective histories. The wager is that if
they can come up with an aesthetic solution in images—it can be poetry, video,
drama, graffiti, comic-strip animation—something new may be created in reality
afterward. There’s a prize at the end of each year. A prestigious committee decides
on the winners and they come to Boston College to screen their work and receive
their prize.
That’s all based on the idea of narrative imagination. You tell your own story,
and then you listen empathically through your imagination to the story of your
enemy. And then you co-create a third story. So that’s the philosophy of imagination applied to the public pedagogical domain. I’m working with young people
because, in these split countries/cities, the thing is so trans-generational. The hope
is in the young people making new images and stories with their iPhones, computers, and flip-cameras. That technology has changed the world. They are coming up with some remarkable work which they post on our website—guestbookproject.com—and then engage in exchanges with other international students on
our interactive website and blogs.
902980_Text.indd 17
4/18/14 2:18 PM
10
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
Dianoia: Do you think that your designation as a public intellectual has shaped
how you view yourself and your work? How do you see that designation shape you
as you continue?
Kearney: Well, it means that I’m always wondering, “How does this relate to
what’s happening in the world now?” So you could say that that is Socratic existentialism. Of course, I’m not comparing myself to Socrates—I’m talking about
the method. You go into an agora, and you see what the debates are. What is justice? What is war? Let us not forget that Greek philosophy and drama first arose
in response to war—the Peloponnesian War, the Trojan War, the Persian War, and
so on.
So being involved with the public means trying to be answerable to, and attentive to, suffering and pain. As well as then imagining, through hope and utopia,
alternatives of that. Now, I’m not saying all philosophy needs to do that. There is
always that moment, absolutely indispensible, when one needs to take a step back
and retreat, and contemplate, before going out into the world again. Philosophy
has two lives— the vita contemplativa and the vita activa. You need both.
There are so many distractions, so many things to plug into, and so on. My
own personal retreat is the south of Ireland—we still have a little house there. I
go there every summer for three months, and that’s where I get all of my writing
done. If I didn’t have that, I couldn’t do the more public stuff. One needs to step
back to step forward.
This interview was conducted by Karel-Bart Celie, Editor-in-Chief, and Andrew
Skaras, Managing Editor, with Richard Kearney in December of 2013.
902980_Text.indd 18
4/18/14 2:18 PM
INTERVIEW WITH RICHARD KEARNEY
902980_Text.indd 19
11
4/18/14 2:18 PM
It is through Banksy’s dissidence, his dedication
to graffiti, and his determination to reveal
what he perceives as consumerism’s threat to
humanity, that he attempts to resurrect and
propagate a culture in which social relations
are not mediated by financial interactions.
902980_Text.indd 20
4/18/14 2:18 PM
Banksy: Dissident Artist
Alexander Trimes
I
n a conversation with author Tristan Manco, Banksy, the anonymous graffiti
artist from Bristol, England, states, “All graffiti is low-level dissent, but stencils have extra history. They’ve been used to start revolutions and to stop wars.”1
Banksy’s own use of stencil graffiti has earned him an international reputation as
a political artist whose pieces challenge the status quo and undermine authority
around the world.2 Perhaps most prominently, Banksy’s art functions as a critique
of consumer culture and the heavy influence that advertising holds in contemporary society. An analysis of his pieces through the lenses of Herbert Marcuse’s and
Erich Fromm’s Frankfurt School philosophies provides a greater understanding of
Banksy’s status as a dissident artist.
Banksy adopted and developed the use of stencils in the early 1990s, a technique that enables him to produce pieces more quickly and thus reduces the
“danger of detection that is the risk of a slower freehand piece.”3 The illegal status
of graffiti is significant as it endows Banksy’s art with a dissentient quality it
might not otherwise possess. As Herbert Marcuse claims, society has invalidated
the “subversive force,” that is, the “truth” of art that would ordinarily be considered
political by “assimilating its antagonistic contents.”4 By operating outside of the
mediums condoned by the “new totalitarianism,” which relegates political works of
art to objects of leisurely contemplation accessible only in museums, Banksy’s art
makes it impossible for society to absorb the “destructive content” of his art, as its
very presence disobeys the law and transgresses the norm—it cannot be ignored.
In this sense, Banksy’s art “saves its substance by denying its traditional form and
thereby denying reconciliation.”5 It is perceived by the legal system not as art, but
as crime.6
Much of Banksy’s art critiques the oppressive influence of advertising agencies
and corporations over society and the subsequent rise of consumerism. According
to Banksy:
The people who truly deface our neighborhoods are the companies that
scrawl their giant slogans across buildings and buses trying to make us feel
13
902980_Text.indd 21
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
14
inadequate unless we buy their stuff. They expect to be able to shout their
message in your face from every available surface but you’re never allowed
to answer back. Well, they started this fight and the wall is the weapon of
choice to hit them back.7
As the quotation suggests, Banksy interprets consumerism as the pursuit of a
specific brand of adequacy, one that is constructed by the companies that manufacture the advertised products. Such a conception of consumer culture resembles
Erich Fromm’s sentiment that, “the individual, primarily alone and self-sufficient,
enters into economic relations with others as means to one end: to sell and to
buy.”8 In Banksy and Fromm’s understandings of consumerism, objects function
as mediators for social interaction, the dynamics of which is dictated by the producers—in order to adhere to the established norm, in order to avoid “feel[ing] inadequate,” that “we buy their stuff.”9 Banksy, however, chooses not to adhere, but
rather to engage in the “fight” and raise issue with the contemporary paradigm.
In his effort to retaliate, Banksy employs “the wall,” the same public medium
used by advertisers, to undermine consumer culture.10 His 2011 piece Sorry! The
lifestyle you ordered is currently out of stock is a prime example of this technique. The
piece, which is simply the title spelled out in large font, is painted over a space
regularly reserved for advertisements. It expresses Banksy’s notion that companies,
when advertising, are not advertising their product so much as the lifestyle they
want consumers to associate with their brand; the product is a means of achieving a certain “adequate” lifestyle. The fact that the lifestyle is “out of stock” suggests that the lifestyles that companies advertise, and lifestyles in general, cannot
be bought. A way of life is not contingent upon a single purchase. By depicting a
deficiency of consumer culture, that no product provides the lifestyles companies
construct and advertise, Banksy exemplifies Fromm’s definition of “disobedience”
as an “affirmation of reason and will.”11 Through his attempt to disillusion consumer society by promulgating what he identifies as the truth, Banksy realizes
“man’s capacity to see, to say what he sees, and to refuse to say what he does not
see.”12 He is, essentially, prompting the viewer to think critically so that he or she
may discern the disjunction between what is advertised and what can actually be
bought.
Banksy encourages his audience members again to consider their purchasing
habits and the way they perceive the stores where they shop in I Pledge Allegiance
to the Bag. As Eva Branscome describes the painting, it depicts “three sweet little
patriotic children [who] are taking part in a flag-raising ceremony.”13 In a twist on
the term brand loyalty, it is not a flag that has been raised at the top of the flagpole
but a Tesco bag. The Tesco logo remains intact; Banksy does nothing to deface it,
but he does alter the context in which it is displayed. The work suggests that consumers live according to the dictates of brands, as they are conveyed in advertise-
902980_Text.indd 22
4/18/14 2:18 PM
BANKSY: DISSIDENT ARTIST
15
ments. The viewer is encouraged to consider how he or she perceives companies
and how his or her purchasing decisions are influenced by advertisements.
I Pledge Allegiance to the Bag is not the only work where Banksy portrays a
relationship between children and consumer culture. His 2007 piece ATM Girl
exemplifies a separate instance in which the artist comments on consumerism’s
effect on children. The work displays a robotic arm that, having emerged from an
ATM, is grasping a young girl by the waist. When considered alongside I Pledge
Allegiance to the Bag, this piece clearly shows that Banksy takes issue with the way
materialism influences children. The pieces, like Marcuse, both suggest that “products indoctrinate and manipulate” individuals.14 Banksy proposes that children,
who enter this indoctrination process at birth, who spend their entire lives and
mature in consumer society, will know no alternatives and will remain obedient to
the brands that they see advertised—they will pledge their allegiance to brands.
In such a society of material consumption, the children are, as Banksy implies,
controlled by and are at the whim of the ATM, that is, money, which will enable
them to participate in society through the medium of products produced by those
brands they are raised to obey.
Banksy’s critique of consumer culture gains a more serious, morbid dimension
in the piece Shop ‘Till You Drop. The work, which he painted during the 2011 holiday shopping season, is located about halfway down the length of a tall building
in London and portrays a woman grasping onto a shopping cart as she plunges to
her death. Distinct from the previous two paintings, Shop ‘Till You Drop does not
overtly elicit critical thinking regarding the viewer’s relationship to companies or
brands and does not initially call into question what exactly brands are attempting to sell the consumer and how the consumer is influenced by advertising, but
instead posits that materialism and consumer culture are harmful, even deadly,
to the individuals so thoroughly immersed in it. The work induces the viewer to
consider how consumer culture affects him or her negatively; it conveys Marcuse’s
notion that, through indoctrination, consumerism “promote[s] a false consciousness which is immune against its falsehood” by illustrating how products destroy
humanity and human relations.15 As materialism becomes a “way of life” that
consumers can perceive as nothing other than “a good way of life,” it displaces the
previous ways of existence in which products did not facilitate all social interaction.16
Banksy adopted an alternative method of criticism of conveying his criticism
when, in October 2013, he set up a stall in Central Park to sell “100% authentic
original signed Banksy canvases.”17 The stall, which sold the paintings for $60
each, performs two functions. First, it undermines the commodification of art, as
a BBC article reports that “many of the pieces [are] estimated to be worth up to
£20,000 [$32,000] each.”18 By selling the works for so much less than the market
902980_Text.indd 23
4/18/14 2:18 PM
16
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
says they are worth, Banksy makes the monetary values assigned to works of art
appear arbitrary.19 Second, as Forbes writer Kathryn Tully explains, “the Central
Park sale ably proves the artist’s point. Without the context or hype, New Yorkers
can’t spot a signed Banksy original when it is literally right under their noses.”20
The stall’s lack of success illustrates the influence of advertising in sales; despite
the value of the pieces, the stall only sold eight canvases and generated a mere
$420 in revenue after customers negotiated for lower prices.
The manner in which Banksy conducts himself, both with regard to the “huge
prices” that his “anti-establishment art commands” and his decision to remain
anonymous, embodies the ideals Plato establishes in the Apology.21 Though
Banksy’s own financial status is unclear, his art, as graffiti, is inherently free to view
and consider.22 In a 2007 interview with the New Yorker he acknowledges, like
Plato’s Socrates who has never “exacted or sought pay of anyone,” that he “give[s]
away thousands of paintings for free.”23 In the article, he proceeds to admit, “The
money that my work fetches these days makes me a bit uncomfortable, but that’s
an easy problem to solve—you just stop whingeing and give it all away. I don’t
think it’s possible to make art about world poverty and then trouser all the cash”
[sic].24 Similar to Socrates, Banksy does not seek monetary compensation, but
uses his art as a means of “examining” the status of society and prompting others
to think critically about the consumerist culture in which they live.25
Additionally, Banksy, like Socrates, is unable to lead “a public life” free of
persecution, due to the nature of his work.26 As previously mentioned, it is the
illegality of graffiti that enables his art to be truly subversive. Aware that he “has
issues with the cops,” Banksy is unable to reveal his identity without encountering
legal consequences.27 Were he to pursue a public existence under his real identity,
he would be unable to continue his art, his dissent, the very things he “dedicate[s]
[his] entire life to.”28 It is for these reasons that only his work can remain public,
that it must remain public, while Banksy lives anonymously. In order for Banksy’s
message to be interpreted politically, it is necessary for his art to explicitly undermine the culture it opposes; to critique consumer culture as a spectacle with an
exhibit inside a museum that charges an admission fee would damage the work’s
integrity as well as the artist’s credibility. Under such circumstances, Banksy’s options are limited to outlaw or apolitical artist.
In Wall and Piece, Banksy writes, “The greatest crimes in the world are not
committed by people breaking the rules but by people following the rules. […] As
a precaution to ever committing major acts of evil it is our solemn duty never to
do what we’re told, this is the only way we can be sure.”29 The statement embodies, though perhaps hyperbolically, Fromm’s notion that disobedience, with which
“human history began,” can function virtuously to perpetuate existence, while “it
is not unlikely that [humanity] will be terminated by an act of obedience.”30 It is
902980_Text.indd 24
4/18/14 2:18 PM
BANKSY: DISSIDENT ARTIST
17
through Banksy’s dissidence, his dedication to graffiti, and his determination to
reveal what he perceives as consumerism’s threat to humanity, that he attempts
to resurrect and propagate a culture in which social relations are not mediated by
financial interactions.
1 Tristan Manco, Stencil Graffiti (New York: Thames & Hudson, 2002), 76.
2 Provocative pieces such as those depicting children escaping over, or peering through the
shattered remains of the West Bank Barrier in Israel earned Banksy a spot on Time Magazine’s list of the 100 most influential people of 2010.
3 Eva Branscome, “The True Counterfeits of Banksy: Radical Walls of Complicity and Subversion,” Architectural Design 81.5 (2011): 116. In this article, Branscome summarizes the evolution of Banksy’s method.
4 Herbert Marcuse, One-dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1991), 61.
5 Herbert Marcuse, Eros and Civilization: A Philosophical Inquiry into Freud (London: Routledge, 1998), 145.
6 Ibid.
7 Banksy, Wall and Piece (London: Century, 2005), 8.
8 Erich Fromm, Escape from Freedom (New York: H. Holt, 1994), 9.
9 Banksy, Wall and Piece, 8.
10 Ibid.
11 Erich Fromm, On Disobedience: Why Freedom Means Saying “no” to Power (New York: Harper,
2010), 24.
12 Fromm, On Disobedience, 24.
13 Branscome, “True Counterfeits of Banksy,” 116.
14 Marcuse, One-dimensional Man, 12.
15 Ibid.
16 Ibid. Emphasis Added.
17 Banksy, “Central Park,” Banksy NY, October 13, 2013.
18 “Banksy Stall Sells Art Works for $60 in New York,” BBC, October 14, 2013.
19 Banksy has previously undermined what he identifies as the “small group” that “create[s],
promote[s], purchase[s], exhibit[s] and decide[s] the success of Art” by hanging his own
pieces in major museums including Tate Britain, the Louvre, and MOMA. Banksy, Wall and
Piece, 144.
20 Kathryn Tully, “Would You Buy A Banksy From A New York Stall For $60? Not Many
Did,” Forbes, October 14, 2013.
21 Will Ellsworth-Jones, “The Story Behind Banksy,” Smithsonian, February, 2013, 2.
22 According to Branscome, “Banksy has made money through the sale of his book Wall and
Piece,” which was a bestseller when it was released in 2005, “selling 90,000 copies and taking
£1 million.” Branscome, “True Counterfeits of Banksy,” 116.
23 Plato, “Apology,” The Internet Classics Archive, Trans. Benjamin Jowett (MIT, 1994-2009), 11.
Lauren Collins, “Banksy Was Here,” The New Yorker, May 14, 2007, 6.
902980_Text.indd 25
4/18/14 2:18 PM
18
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
24 Collins, “Bansky Was Here,” 6.
25 Plato, Apology, 14.
26 Ibid., 12.
27 Ellsworth-Jones, “Story Behind Bansky,” 1.
28 Keegan Hamilton, “Village Voice Exclusive: An Interview With Banksy, Street Art Cult
Hero, International Man of Mystery,” The Village Voice, October 9, 2013, 3.
29 Banksy, Wall and Piece, 51.
30 Fromm, On Disobedience, 1.
902980_Text.indd 26
4/18/14 2:18 PM
BANKSY: DISSIDENT ARTIST
902980_Text.indd 27
19
4/18/14 2:18 PM
Kierkegaard’s hostility towards Hegel was
like that of an angry sibling: however much
he rejected and ridiculed Hegelian dialectic,
nonetheless antithesis and its explication was
for him, too, the key. His notion of dialectic is
similar to Hegel’s in the sense that it involves a
“becoming,” but unlike Hegel, it is a subjective
becoming not an objective becoming.
902980_Text.indd 28
4/18/14 2:18 PM
Encountering Paradox:
Movements of Faith and Reason
in the Dialectics of Kierkegaard
and Hegel
Francis Adams
T
he disquieting feeling that usually accompanies reading the works of Søren
Kierkegaard arises from the daunting realization that he is challenging us to
critically evaluate our existence; to consider the possibility that we are not living
in the most authentic way of which we are capable. He does not say this explicitly,
but it is implicit in his unusual method of communication—what he calls “indirect
communication.” The challenge in reading Kierkegaard is in unraveling what he
means by indirect communication. We can get at in the following way: as a whole,
his literary production shows great thematic breadth, ranging from the poetic to
the philosophical and into the religious. His chameleon-like versatility is further
shown by the fact that he unfolded his production through a series of pseudonyms. They appear in many of his works, either by themselves or in tandems, and
each speaks his own mind. It becomes clear, then, that he is not concerned with
merely espousing his theories and leaving it up to his readers to decide whether
or not they agree with him. He is challenging the reader to enter deeply into the
existential questions he engages, to restore what he thought was the essential
element in the human search for meaning: passion. It is for this reason that he is
often referred to as the “father of existentialism,” (although he would probably not
enjoy being associated with an “ism,” for reasons I hope will be clear by the end of
this analysis). At the same time (and this is the crucial point), there is a definite
order with which Kierkegaard, as the manager of these various characters, holds
their views over and against each other. The whole of his production is meant to
be a theory of existence, an expression of the journey of the individual through
various stages, which he sees as culminating in the religious stage with the character who poses the ultimate challenge to our existence: Jesus Christ.
Much of Kierkegaard’s thinking was in reaction to what he considered to be
the highly speculative nature of philosophy down through the ancient, medieval
and modern periods. It is unfortunate then, (for the German philosopher, Hegel)
that he was the man that received the butt of the criticism, for Kierkegaard’s
criticism really applies to all the great metaphysicians in the history of Western
philosophy. Nevertheless, we will examine Kierkegaard’s specific problems with
21
902980_Text.indd 29
4/18/14 2:18 PM
22
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
Hegel and all the thinkers who were so greatly influenced by him (many of whom
were Kierkegaard’s peers at the University of Copenhagen in Denmark, where he
lived). His primary grievance with this brand of philosophy was that it reduced
the real to the rational; that is, it asserted that all truth could be expressed in rational categories. Kierkegaard strongly disagreed with this view and held that there
are other truths, truths more relevant to the human condition, which could not be
explained rationally. In Concluding Unscientific Postscript, he undergoes his most
comprehensive critique of Hegel and asserts that truth is subjective as opposed to
objective; that is, truth is grounded in the individual and not in a larger system of
knowledge, as Hegel asserted. Although Kierkegaard is critical of Hegel in this
sense, there is an important thread that unites these two thinkers that will serve as
a useful tool for illuminating their philosophies: their use of dialectical reasoning.
Hegel’s dialectic does away with the distinction between subject and object and
therefore determines truth to be an objective, assimilated whole, whereas Kierkegaard’s dialectic is entirely subjective, as it traces the movement of the individual
through what he determined to be the three stages of existence: the aesthetic, the
ethical and the religious stage. These differences in dialectical style point to distinctive epistemologies and worldviews. It is only after our comparison of Hegel
and Kierkegaard that we will be able to understand that authenticity for Kierkegaard can only be fully realized subjectively as one navigates through the various
paradoxes of existence.
Hegel’s self-proclaimed project as a philosopher was to advance the field of
philosophy away from being merely a love of knowledge and into an actual attainment of knowledge.i He believed that metaphysical truth could only exist in a scientific system, that is, objectively, for otherwise it would be tainted by the various
prejudices of subjectivity. He claims, therefore, to have apprehended the realm of
truth, “as it is, stripped of all integument, in and for itself, implicit and explicit.”1
He claims to have grasped the Darstellung Gottes, that is, God’s presence, as he was
in his eternal essence before the creation of nature and finite spirit.2ii Kierkegaard
reviled this tendency of systematizing knowledge (again, present in ancient, medieval, as well as modern thought), for its abstract, speculative quality. Hegel, on the
other hand, was deeply animated by the belief that he could grasp the universal
order of things. One of Hegel’s pupils, Hotho, described his mentor’s ambition
as follows: “It was precisely in the depths of the seemingly undecipherable where
this powerful mind pried and poked about with splendidly self-confident ease and
i. It is telling that Hegel misrepresents the meaning of the word “philosophy” by substituting the
word “knowledge” for “wisdom,” thereby extracting the distinctly human quality from the word.
ii. It should be noted that Hegel’s use of “God” is ambiguous and should not be understood in the
theistic sense. Scholars seem to think Hegel merely used the word “God” to save his chances of
gaining a position as a professor. Hegel is considered a pantheist. The words, “God,” “Spirit,” and
“Absolute” will be used synonymously throughout this analysis.
902980_Text.indd 30
4/18/14 2:18 PM
ENCOUNTERING PARADOX: MOVEMENTS OF FAITH AND REASON
IN THE DIALECTICS OF KIERKEGAARD AND HEGEL
23
calm.”3 Merold Westphal, in his essay, Kierkegaard and Hegel, captures the essence
of Hegel’s ambition as a metaphysician, while helpfully contextualizing him in the
history of Western thought:
Hegel’s insistence that philosophy must be scientific answers Kant’s question whether metaphysics can be objective knowledge, free from perspectival subjectivities of sense, opinion, tradition, authority, interest, and so
forth. It is easy to recognize in this aspiration to objectivity not merely a
modern awe of physical science but an ancient awe of mathematics that
goes back to Pythagoras and Plato. When this awe gives place to envy and
this envy gives rise to the quest for metaphysical comfort that comes from
metaphysical certainty, we have a dominant tendency in Western philosophy.4
In Hegel’s thinking, the only true method was the one that included all regions of thought. He strove towards a unity of cognitive thinking that encompassed contradiction, that is, he apprehended actuality as structured in opposites. “Yes” and “No,” “A” and “non-A” are thought to both be expressions of pure
thought as such, so through a triadic movement of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis,
the two opposites are apprehended into the Whole, the Absolute.iii This means
that oppositions like true and false are merely different ways in which the substance of the Absolute expresses itself; a contradiction, therefore, represents an
advance, and each negation is a positive act of cognition leading to a higher and
broader level of truth. Through this dialectic movement, the Absolute is thought
of as in a continual process of becoming. Hegel’s dialectic is interrelated with
history, as history comes to be seen as a series of stages in which the Absolute is
actualized:
All historical events admit of being regarded from a viewpoint according to which they represent opposed opinions, contradictory attitudes and
contrasting elements. It is a truism that history proceeds in movement
and countermovement. It likewise seems to be unequivocally clear that the
movement of history repeatedly leads to a kind of equalization in which
antimonies are sublimated.5
To get a clearer picture of Hegel’s view of history, it will be useful to highlight
some of the significant periods of history in which the supposed development
of Spirit can be seen. He regarded Spirit as being asleep in nature before human
beings came to be on earth. With the rise of human beings, Spirit “woke up” in
the self-consciousness of the human. Further down the road, Christianity came to
represent one of the higher stages of Spirit’s self-consciousness. This was the stage
iii. The unique German word for this triadic movement is Aufhebung, which combines the senses
of “cancelling out,” “nullification,” and “sublimation,” and therefore connotes a development, together with a dissolution, of what came before.
902980_Text.indd 31
4/18/14 2:18 PM
24
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
in which Spirit came to understand itself by way of representation. The metaphor
of God becoming man in Jesus represents Spirit becoming conscious of itself. In
this sense, he regarded Christianity as true in content, but not in form; a merely
representational form of truth is ultimately inadequate for Hegel because, in his
view, a historical point of departure (God existing in time through Christ) is
incapable of being given for an eternal consciousness. Hegel’s rather arrogant view,
therefore, is that religion is “defendable” in the sense that we cannot all be philosophers, but “pure” philosophy is the proper form in which truth exists. It follows
from Hegel’s dialectic that the distinction between subject and object is lost as the
two are sublimated into the Absolute. Kierkegaard, as we will see, took subjectivity
very seriously and used this distinction as a point of departure for creating his own
dialectic grounded in the individual existing person.
Kierkegaard’s existential dialectic is unique in the sense that its stages are
presented as a hierarchy of three stages of existence: the aesthetic, the ethical,
and the religious. Kierkegaard’s hostility towards Hegel was like that of an angry
sibling: however much he rejected and ridiculed Hegelian dialectic, nonetheless
antithesis and its explication was for him, too, the key. His notion of dialectic is
similar to Hegel’s in the sense that it involves a “becoming,” but unlike Hegel, it is
a subjective becoming not an objective becoming. For Kierkegaard the dialectic is
a lived process by which the individual moves towards fulfillment. As the German
philosopher and psychologist, Robert Heiss, notes, “it has similarities to experiments in depth psychology where the subject is made to talk, to present himself in
the flux of his different life situations, of his ideas and his objective and subjective
relations.”6 This analysis helps illuminate what Kierkegaard is trying to accomplish through the work of his various pseudonyms; their navigation through the
stages of existence (which we are about to explore), can be regarded as a sort of
self-analysis of the existing person. From stage to stage there is (as with Hegel)
an Aufhebung, and each step of this dialectic process grows in scope and intensity,
as the individual himself grows in passion and inwardness.
In Volume I of the first pseudonymous work, Either/Or, Kierkegaard first
demonstrates a unity, that is, the aesthete. The aesthete’s writing is romantic literature in the highest sense; it is written in a whimsical, undecided spirit, in which
the negativity, and the ultimate lack of viewpoint of the author shine through. The
irony with which this part is written is clear and perhaps exaggerated at times:
“To be a perfect man is after all the highest human ideal. Now I have got corns,
which ought to help some.”7 Nevertheless, his criticism retains a caustic humor as
well: “It happened that a fire broke out in a theater. The clown came out to inform
the public. They thought it was a joke and applauded. He repeated the warnings,
they shouted him down. So I think the world will come to an end amid general
applause from all the writs, who believe that it is a joke.”8 Everything he touches
902980_Text.indd 32
4/18/14 2:18 PM
ENCOUNTERING PARADOX: MOVEMENTS OF FAITH AND REASON
IN THE DIALECTICS OF KIERKEGAARD AND HEGEL
25
upon in this volume seems to be dealt with in a half-serious, half-mocking tone.
It is meant to express a peculiar state of indecision, a wayward shifting from irony
to seriousness with no particular goal in sight. In Volume II of Either/Or, there is
a dramatic shift in tone, style, form and character. This author is a married man
whose purpose is to defend marriage to the author of Volume I. In his defense of
marriage, he also attacks his friend’s whimsical attitude towards life and his existential position. The high aesthetic quality of writing of the first volume is replaced
by a didactic tone in the second:
…You take great delight in “comforting” people when they have recourse
to you in critical situations. You listen to their exposition of the case and
then say, “Yes, I perceive perfectly that there are two possibilities, one can
do either this or that. My sincere opinion and my friendly counsel is as follows: Do it or don’t do it—you will regret both.” But he who mocks others,
mocks himself, and your rejoinder is not a mere nothing, but a profound
mockery of yourself, a sorry proof of how limp your soul is, that your
whole philosophy of life is concentrated in one single proposition: “I say
merely either/or…life is a masquerade…”9
The essence of Kierkegaard’s dialectic in this case is in unmasking what he has
shown to be a unity (the aesthete) so as to reveal him to be, in fact, a disunity, a
man in despair. The married man’s concern quoted above is to elevate the aesthete
into the ethical stage of existence. Thus we see part of Kierkegaard’s dialectical
purpose at work: to bring about a confrontation between the aesthetic and ethical
stages of existence. When one finds himself in the midst of the despair of the aesthetic stage, one inevitably makes a choice: to either remain an aesthete or to enter
the ethical. This decision, as Kierkegaard sees it, can only be formulated dialectically: “choose or do not choose, in either case you have chosen.”10 Quite clearly,
the ethical man is the higher type for Kierkegaard; he lives more passionately, with
more intensity, and is therefore closer to authenticity.
In this progression from the aesthetic to the ethical stage of existence we can
see similarities to Hegel’s dialectic: one stage is left for another in a forward movement characterized by contrast; whatever the new level may be, it is not reached by
any sort of direct development, but by way of contradiction. In both cases there is
progression that results from these contradictions. Despite Kierkegaard’s contempt
for Hegel, the fundamental nature of his own brand of dialectical thought is quite
dependent on him.
In Kierkegaard’s well-known work, Fear and Trembling, we see the formulation
of the religious stage of the dialectic. The radical change in seriousness in terms of
tone and subject matter that takes place in the transition from Either/Or to Fear
and Trembling was shocking to his contemporaries, who had considered him a
mere poet and man of letters. In Fear and Trembling we see him abandon irony al-
902980_Text.indd 33
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
26
together and enter into the religious pathos of dread. Instead of dealing with what
previously seemed like light-hearted themes, he turns his attention to the great religious figure, Abraham, and the story of the binding of Isaac, in which Abraham
is commanded by God to sacrifice Isaac, his first-born son. It is clear from the
outset that Johannes de Silentio, the pseudonym in this work, reveres Abraham:
“No one is as great as Abraham! Who is capable of understanding him!”11 He is
referred to as the “Knight of Faith,” the paradigm of the faithful man precisely because nobody can understand him. Abraham’s willingness to sacrifice Isaac, whose
birth was a miracle of God, simply cannot be understood from an ethical point of
view; if anything, we might understand it ethically as intent to murder. Kierkegaard tells us, however, that Abraham’s action involves what he calls a teleological
suspension of the ethical, in which the duty to the society (i.e. the universal) is given
up in favor of duty to God. Kierkegaard is very careful to make this point; for this
is the point at which he breaks decisively from Hegel. In the Hegelian system, the
laws and customs of society represent the highest moral duty. In other words, for
Hegel, Kierkegaard’s ethical stage of the dialectic is the highest. But it is precisely
this movement beyond the ethical, which Abraham makes, that comprises the last
stage in Kierkegaard’s dialectic; namely, the movement of faith. In this movement,
Kierkegaard reveals the paradox that is faith:
Faith is precisely the paradox that the single individual as the single individual is higher than the universal, is justified before it, not as inferior to it
but as superior…[for] the single individual as the single individual stands
in an absolute relation to the absolute …the paradox of faith, then, is
this…that the single individual determines his relation to the universal by
his relation to the absolute, not his relation to the absolute by this relation
to the universal.12
The movement of the single individual through faith is a paradox that goes beyond
human understanding and communication, precisely because it does not reference
the objective world of the ethical, but rather the subject-based relationship with
the absolute. Indeed, only faith is “capable of transforming a murder into a holy
act most please to God, a paradox which gives Isaac back to Abraham, which no
thought can master, because faith begins precisely where thinking leaves off.”13
We see, then, that the individual’s ultimate duty is to God—that this represents
the fullness of truth, and that therefore the state cannot be the embodiment of the
teleological fulfillment of the Divine Reason, as Hegel claims.
Now that we have the three distinct stages of Kierkegaard’s dialectic in place,
we can begin to examine the qualitative shifts that take place in the movement
from one stage to the next. With this in mind, it will be important to take note of
the subtitle of Fear and Trembling: “A Dialectical Lyric.” The lyrical component
of his dialectic helps distinguish it from Hegel’s dialectic because the implication
902980_Text.indd 34
4/18/14 2:18 PM
ENCOUNTERING PARADOX: MOVEMENTS OF FAITH AND REASON
IN THE DIALECTICS OF KIERKEGAARD AND HEGEL
27
is that it does not take place in the dimension of rational thinking, but in another
“lyrical” dimension. The dialectical movement for Kierkegaard is defined by the
movement of the individual through the stages of existence; therefore truth is
subjective, (grounded in the individual), and not objective (grounded in the realm
of rationality). We saw how in Either/Or the aesthete lived in a state of whimsical,
ironic paradox; he lived his life indecisively and without passion. The introduction
of the Husband, that is, the ethical man, presents a schism; whereas the aesthete
treats paradox as an existential game and makes the most of life in the midst of
this paradox, the ethical man compels a decision: to continue living in despair or
to grow in passion, to rise to the ethical stage or to remain in the aesthetic. The
ethical man’s didactic tone, (as opposed to the aesthete’s ironical tone) is more
serious, a quality that Kierkegaard calls, an “inward deepening,” an intensification of passion, and a move towards authenticity. In Fear and Trembling the tone
of the dialectic movement darkens even more; it changes from a didactic tone to
a dreadful tone, as the horror of Abraham’s predicament becomes manifest. Thus
the passion it takes to get from the ethical to the religious stage is far greater than
the passion needed to get from the aesthetic to the ethical stage. This intensification of passion is what Kierkegaard sees as the highest form of authenticity and is
described as “making room so that God can come.”14
The Kierkegaardian dialectic differs in another important respect from Hegel’s.
Rather than proceed by way of a synthesis between opposites halves of a paradox,
the Kierkegaardian dialectic proceeds by a deepening of paradox without clear
resolution of its terms. The qualitative shifts in tone that we have just witnessed
reflect not only an intensification of passion, but an expansion of paradox that occurs as one moves through the stages of existence. The “either/or” that the aesthete
confronts in his whimsy, always shifting between decisions and unsure why it even
matters that a decision be made at all, turns into a dreadful “either/or” for Abraham in which the consequences of the decision have suddenly become ominously
fateful. Philosopher Walter Kaufmann said of this characteristic Kierkegaardian
quality:
Nobody before Kierkegaard had seen so clearly that the freedom to make a
fateful decision that may change our character and future, breeds anxiety…
I know of no other great writer in the whole nineteenth century, perhaps
even in the whole of world literature, to whom I respond with less happiness and with a more profound sense that I am on trial and found wanting,
unless it were Søren Kierkegaard.15
One of Kierkegaard’s primary goals in Fear and Trembling is to challenge those
who read the Genesis story from what he would likely call an “aesthetic” point of
view, that is, those who admire Abraham for his faith, yet do not hesitate to abhor
any religious fanatic who resolves to act like Abraham. In his analysis of this hor-
902980_Text.indd 35
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
28
rible story, he asserts that an authentic faith requires that one obey God even if it
is required that one disobeys his conscience.
As a Christian, much of Kierkegaard’s animosity towards Hegel was in reaction to his claim that his system “completed” Christianity by restoring it to its
proper conceptual (i.e. philosophical) form. In Hegel’s view this was the only sense
in which Christianity could be true, for a historical point of departure could not
be given for an eternal consciousness. Thus, in Concluding Unscientific Postscript,
Kierkegaard undergoes his most thorough philosophical critique of Hegel’s system, through the mouthpiece of a new pseudonym, Johannes Climacus. Although
it is clear that Kierkegaard admires Hegel in the sense of making use of the dialectic and praising the rigor with which he constructed his system, he is nonetheless
ardently opposed to this type of speculative philosophy because it relegates the individual to the level of a “fantastical abstraction,” a non-person with no orientation
in life. The essence of his critique is that Hegel trespasses over what he considers
to be an insurmountable gap between the human and Divine understanding; he
erroneously tries to explain the nature of reality sub specie aeterni (in the aspect of
eternity). This is not to say that Kierkegaard disbelieved in systematic knowledge
as such. It is merely to say that if a system of existence did exist, it could only be
known by God. In other words, only God could be a Hegelian.
Furthermore, Kierkegaard considered Hegel to be overly troubled with history. He preferred not to live thinking about the past, for it extracted from his
self-awareness as one living in the present. He termed this preoccupation with
history as a form of “absentmindedness,” a psychological trick the individual plays
on himself in order to divert from his awareness as an existing person. He sees this
decision to speculate about the past as a form of inauthenticity, for it estranges
the individual from truth, which is grounded in his subjectivity. He diagnoses this
absentmindedness and reluctance to live in the present as a spiritual disease of the
age:
Perhaps the reason our age is dissatisfied when it is going to act is that
it has been coddled by observing. That is perhaps why there are so many
fruitless attempts to become something more than one is by lumping together socially in the hope of impressing the spirit of history.16
He recognizes that complacency readily gives way to speculative thought because
it is only through speculation that one is able to extract oneself from lived life. In
perhaps his most debilitating criticism of Hegel, however, Kierkeegard exposes
Hegel’s dubious presuppositions by pointing out that the system requires a human being to create it, which raises the vexed question of how it could ever be
completely objective. He poses a few questions rhetorically: if the Spirit’s only
objective is to manifest itself dialectically over the course of history, how does one
explain the fact that it wastes so many generations of people and so much time to
902980_Text.indd 36
4/18/14 2:18 PM
ENCOUNTERING PARADOX: MOVEMENTS OF FAITH AND REASON
IN THE DIALECTICS OF KIERKEGAARD AND HEGEL
29
set the dialectic in motion? Why is the process so slow if this is all God wants?17
Furthermore, Kierkegaard (and indeed many other philosophers) thought it
arbitrary to import movement into logic: “It is indeed curious to make movement
the basis in a sphere in which movement is inconceivable or to have movement
explain logic.”18 This point is made clearer as Kierkegaard analyzes the way in
which Hegel tries to get his system off the ground. The opening chapter of Hegel’s
Science of Logic, deals with this very problem and argues as follows:
Thus the beginning must be an absolute, or what is synonymous here, an
abstract being; and so it may not presuppose anything, must not be mediated
by anything nor have a ground; rather it is to be itself the ground of the
entire science. Consequently, it must be purely and simply an immediacy,
or rather merely immediacy itself…the beginning therefore is pure being.19
Climacus sees the problem with this line of reasoning: “How does the system
begin with the immediate, that is, does it begin with it immediately?”20 His
objection shows how the lack of regard for the individual thinker is the death of
the system before it even gets started, for it requires a human reflection to decide
to begin with immediacy and not some other beginning point. Ironically, this is a
point that Hegel seems to concede. He writes, “All that is needed (at the beginning of the system) is simply the resolve, which can also be regarded as arbitrary,
that we propose to consider thought as such.”21 But Climacus sees this starting
point as anything but the harmless starting point that Hegel considers it to be,
for two reasons: firstly, the resolve to consider thought as such assumes that it is
possible to conceive of thought without a thinker; secondly, that it is appropriate
to do so. Climacus seems to think that is not appropriate to do so, for it would
once again be elevating the individual to the level of God. In the end, regardless
of whether or not these contentions hold water, Hegel’s decision to embark upon
the system assumes that Kierkegaard is wrong, and therefore breaches the system’s
own requirement of a presuppositionless point of departure.
As we can see, the highest task in life for Kierkegaard cannot be to think objectively, that is, to risk falling into the trap of speculative thinking, but to become
subjective, to find “inwardness.” Chapter II of the Postscript commences by setting
out to identify what it is to be subjective, to begin to exist inwardly. He starts by
commenting on the nature of objective reflection versus subjective reflection:
Whereas objective thinking is indifferent to the thinking subject and his
existence, the subjective thinker as existing is essentially interested in his
own thinking, is existing in it. Therefore, his thinking has another kind of
reflection, specifically, that of inwardness, of possession, whereby it belongs
to the subject and no one else. Whereas objective thinking invests everything in the result and assists all mankind to cheat by copying and reeling
off the results and answers, subjective thinking invests everything in the
902980_Text.indd 37
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
30
process of becoming and omits the result, partly because this belongs to
him, since he possesses the way, partly because he as existing is continually
in the process of becoming, as is every human being who has not permitted himself to be tricked into becoming objective, into inhumanly becoming speculative thought.22
Here we again see the emphasis placed on process, the individual’s movement
through life; objectivity seems to be represented as a kind of stasis. Truth is to be
found in subjectivity, for it is only subjectively that we are aware of ourselves as
existing persons. Truth is to be discovered inwardly through what he calls “inward
deepening,” and any retreat from this is seen as gratuitous speculation: “Essentially
viewed, the knowing that does not inwardly in the reflection of inwardness pertain
to existence is accidental knowing, and its degree and scope, essentially viewed are
a matter of indifference.”23 This is to say that all knowledge is essential only in
as much as it relates to the knower. Only momentarily, in subjective inwardness,
can one be in a unity of the infinite and the finite that transcends existing. He
calls this “the moment of passion.” Hegel believed that we can transcend existence
objectively, but this is not the case according to Climacus. This can only be done
subjectively, in the moment of passion. The moment of passion is essential because
it is the way in which we move through the stages of existence; it is what stands in
the face of paradox and asserts the individual’s will to truth. He also sees passion
as essential because it is the way in which we relate in truth to the eternal, revealed
truth—Jesus Christ.iv It is how we are lifted out of the finiteness of our existence
through faith. He holds that Christ is a paradox, fully God, fully man, and that
any hope of relating to Him must be purely subjective, for, “[the fact that] truth
becomes a paradox is grounded precisely in its relation to an existing subject.”24
Christ, for Kierkegaard, cannot be understood objectively by reason. The person
who chooses the objective way is doomed to fail because God himself, as figured
in Christ, is a person, a subject, and must therefore be related to as such. Climacus’ passion begins to shine through as he discusses “the wise person” who, in his
inwardness, does not waste his time trying to apprehend God objectively, for he
knows that every moment in which he does not have God is a moment wasted.
Indeed, “God is something one takes along a tout prix [at any price], which in passion’s understanding, is the true relationship of inwardness with God.”25
This is a re-articulation of the description of authentic faith displayed by
Abraham in Fear and Trembling—the willingness to not demand objective certainty, but to trust in God. Kierkegaard speaks of this moment of passion as a decision
iv. It would be interesting to consider how Kierkegaard reconciles his view that truth is grounded
in the subject with the notion of revealed truth, which is of course essential to holding a Christian
worldview. This is a question he takes up in his work, Philosophical Fragments, which we unfortunately can’t delve into here.
902980_Text.indd 38
4/18/14 2:18 PM
ENCOUNTERING PARADOX: MOVEMENTS OF FAITH AND REASON
IN THE DIALECTICS OF KIERKEGAARD AND HEGEL
31
a man must make when he comes to a fork in the road where he has to decide
whether to risk objective uncertainty and have faith, or keep objective certainty
and lose faith. On the one hand, he observes nature and does indeed see omnipotence and wisdom, but on the other hand, he sees immense suffering. Yet for him,
faith must triumph in this situation, for:
At the point where the road swings off, objective knowledge is suspended… (but) the inwardness is so very great, precisely because it grasps this
objective uncertainty with all the passion of the infinite…Without risk, no
faith. Faith is the contradiction between the infinite passion of inwardness
and the objective uncertainty. If I am able to apprehend God objectively, I
do not have faith; but because I cannot do this, I must have faith.26
The claim that Christ is a paradox is essential for Kierkegaard, as it forms the
foundation for his explication of “indirect communication,” the way by which we
relate to Christ, in his work, Practice in Christianity. Now under the pseudonym,
Anti-Climacus, he argues that without acknowledging the fact that Christ is a
paradox, (the eternal essential truth come into existence in time), it is impossible
to be an authentic Christian. To objectify Christ, as he claims so many speculative
theologians do, is to misunderstand Him, to idolize his teaching, to reduce Him
to the level of a moral teacher. Moreover, to deny the paradox is to do the same as
Hegel, that is, to suppose that we can see from God’s point of view. Kierkegaard
reminds us that we are no position to do so: “I am only a poor existing human
being who neither eternally nor divinely nor theocentrically is able to observe the
eternal but must be content with existing.”27
Anti-Climacus so despises speculative theology that he thinks it worse, and
more dangerous, than the modern trend to demythologize Christianity, pointing
out that it “accepts the paradox [of Christ], but does not stop with it.”28 The reason he is so hostile to this is because he thinks there is no need to go further than
the paradox, for when a person in faith continues to adhere firmly to it, he deepens himself in the inwardness of faith and “does not stop either.”29 In fact, that
is the reason Christ chose to reveal Himself as such, with the summons that the
existing individual go further and further in the inwardness of faith. By trying to
go beyond the paradox, the speculative thinkers are not, in fact, explaining it, but
correcting it. In doing this, they not only extract the existing person, that is, Jesus of
Nazareth, out of the paradox, but they extract the existing quality from the person
who encounters the paradox as well.
Christ’s decision to abase himself, that is, to become fully human, is the heart
of Christianity because it is what makes any communication between us and God
possible. Christ is the sign of contradiction, however, so direct communication is
impossible. This is where the notion of indirect communication comes into the fore;
the idea that Christ communicates with us not directly, but rather indirectly by
902980_Text.indd 39
4/18/14 2:18 PM
32
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
being the embodiment of the paradox, fully human and fully divine. This mysteriousness makes Christ’s communication with us on earth anything but a straightforward teaching on morality of the kind that a speculative theology would like
to provide; it requires a deeper, more intimate part of our humanity: the heart.
Kierkegaard realizes that Christ, fully perfect yet fully abased, can only appeal to
this part of our psyches. We cannot imitate Christ before we are drawn by and
begin to love Him; this is what Kierkegaard meant by indirect communication.
In other words: “[Christ] exercises power over (man), the power of love, which is
indeed capable of everything, above all of making alike; (man’s) whole deepest inner being is transformed little by little, and he seems to be beginning to resemble,
however imperfectly, this image that has made him forget everything—also the
world in which he is, which now regards him with astonishment and alienation.”30
The essence of the Christian faith is in accepting God’s love and being drawn to
Him through Christ. This is what Christendom has lost in objectifying Christ by
turning Him into a moral teacher; it has lost that very mysterious, yet very real,
intimate form of indirect communication that far surpasses rationality and penetrates the depths of the soul in appealing to the heart. Thus any objective moral
system derived from Christianity without first going through faith subjectively is
essentially lifeless.
In the end, it is clear why Kierkegaard has been such an influential thinker in
our time. By insisting that truth is subjective, he sought to restore the essential
element of passion to life. The only thing that mattered to him was how we live;
what we know is meaningless, it is vanity in the face of death. This is why he is
often called the father of existentialism. Nonetheless, he does not merely forget his
favorite speculative thinker (to criticize, that is), Hegel, but appropriates his notion
of dialectical movement into his body of work. The dialectic he espouses is very
different from that of Hegel, as we have seen, but it is effective because it works
by the same Hegelian principle of Aufhebung, in which contradiction, or opposition, is acknowledged, but the movement continues regardless. Unlike Hegel, who,
when confronted with paradox of Christ, rises above it and attempts to explain it
objectively, Kierkegaard sees the appropriate response as a sort of yielding to and
communication with it. This principle of embracing paradox and advancing onwards in inwardness is the heart of authenticity for Kierkegaard, for it is also the
essence of moving through the three stages of existence. Once we arrive at Jesus
Christ in the religious stage, the essence of faith will become the paradox itself.
We are confronted by contradiction in life’s journey at each stage: the movement
through the stages requires “a moment of passion” in which we push forward
and grow in inwardness despite paradox. We see this growth in each individual
moment of decision: at first the aesthete is complacent and whimsical, then the
ethical man enters the picture and demands decision, and finally in Abraham we
see the supremely inward decision of placing his trust in God. Similarly, in our
902980_Text.indd 40
4/18/14 2:18 PM
ENCOUNTERING PARADOX: MOVEMENTS OF FAITH AND REASON
IN THE DIALECTICS OF KIERKEGAARD AND HEGEL
33
relationship with Christ, rational considerations must be left behind, and we must
compel ourselves in inwardness to relate to him in truth, that is, as the abased human person.
1 Heiss, Robert. Hegel, Kierkegaard, Marx: Three Philosophers Whose Ideas Changed the Course of
Civilization. Trans. E.B. Garside. New York: Delta Books, 1975, 9.
2 Ibid.
3 Ibid., 10.
4 Westphal, Merold. “Kierkegaard and Hegel,” The Cambridge Companion to Kierkegaard. Ed.
Alastair Hannay and Gordon D. Marino. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998,
112.
5 Heiss, Hegel, Kierkegaard, Marx, 99.
6 Ibid.
7 Kierkegaard, Søren. Either/Or. Trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong. Princeton University Press, 1987. 42.
8 Ibid., 45.
9 Ibid., 48.
10 Ibid., 50.
11 Kierkegaard, Søren. The Essential Kierkegaard. Trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong.
New York: Princeton University Press, 1991. Kindle Edition. 49.
12 Ibid., 56.
13 Ibid., 58.
14 Heiss, Hegel, Kierkegaard, Marx, 291.
15 Kaufmann, Walter. “Kierkegaard and the Crisis in Religion”. Princeton University. 1960.
Lecture. YouTube.
16 Kierkegaard, Søren. Concluding Unscientific Postscript. Trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H.
Hong. New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1992, 138.
17 Ibid., 159.
18 Kierkegaard, The Essential Kierkegaard, 196.
19 Westphal, Kierkegaard and Hegel, 114.
20 Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, 111.
21 Westphal, Kierkegaard and Hegel, 114.
22 Kierkegaard, The Essential Kierkegaard, 191.
23 Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, 197.
24 Ibid., 199.
25 Ibid., 193.
26 Ibid., 195.
27 Ibid.
28 Ibid., 197.
29 Ibid.
30 Kierkegaard, Søren. Practice in Christianity. Trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong.
New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1991, 224.
902980_Text.indd 41
4/18/14 2:18 PM
One can see throughout the Parmenides
that one of the basic dissimilarities between
Socrates and Parmenides is that the latter is a
committed materialist, whereas Socrates is not.
902980_Text.indd 42
4/18/14 2:18 PM
A Critical Examination of
the Third Man Argument
Gjergji Evangjeli
W
hat has come to be known as the Third Man Argument has brought
scholars of Plato and philosophers at large many headaches, due to the
seeming end that it brings to the Platonic theory of the Forms. Most puzzlingly,
it is included in the Platonic corpus itself. One could assume from this that this
could either be a window into Plato’s own doubts about the Forms, or an exercise that Plato meant for his students to undertake a solution that has been lost
through the ages. This paper will show that the Third Man Argument and the
infinite regression resulting from it can conclusively be proven to be unsound and
the regression dissolved. To achieve this goal, a three-step process is appropriate. First, recent scholarship will be analysed along with two arguments, one from
differences in predication and one that seeks to show that there is an inherent
inconsistency in the argument will be examined. This analysis will show that the
first argument is successful but leads to a further problem that in turn needs to
be solved and that the second misunderstands the nature of the Forms. Second,
an original argument solving the Third Man will be offered, supported by recent
developments in formal logic. Lastly, an attempt will be made to conclusively solve
the predication problem in the first part through appealing to the original argument offered in the second section.
I. Analysis of Recent Scholarship on the Third Man Argument
The argument in Parmenides 132a1-b2 comes as a series of attacks by Parmenides on the Theory of the Forms, which include questioning whether any
particular participates in only part of a Form or in it fully. Having been unable
to argue against the Forms in that way, Parmenides proceeds by saying that there
must be an infinite regression of Forms, since every time a Form is considered
to be the principle behind a set of objects that share a certain property, a new set
arises which includes the first set and the Form, which itself necessitates a new
Form. Unlike most of the other arguments, however, the young Socrates does not
give a response to this argument, and it is ultimately swept under the rug for the
purpose of advancing the dialogue. Though this is not the only time Plato does
35
902980_Text.indd 43
4/18/14 2:18 PM
36
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
not choose to follow a particular argument to the end, this particular instance
seems rather problematic, in that solving the regress which Parmenides argues to
be inherent in the Theory of the Forms is both central to Platonic philosophy and
does not seem obvious.
The name ‘Third Man Argument’ comes from Aristotle,1 who made the argument famous, but in Aristotle’s account there are added complications. First, there
is the issue of trying to put Platonic Forms into Aristotle’s categories. Since the
Forms cannot be fully put either in the category of ‘substance’ or ‘form/essence,’
Aristotle’s version would necessitate a prolonged discussion of whether the Forms
can be put appropriately into one of these categories. Before treating the argument proper, Aristotle reminds the reader that substance is made up of essence
and matter, which means that the Forms cannot be accurately described as substances. If this were true, Aristotle would be correct in saying that to believe the
Forms exist would lead to an absurdity, since it would necessitate that all things
simply are replications of the same thing. As Plato does not argue that the Forms
are material, however, this view is patently false. The Forms being essences is not
a path which Aristotle takes and one is left to wonder why this is the case. The
fact that humans are used as the illustrating example is a further difficulty, since
neither Plato nor Aristotle has a very clear account of how Form or essence fully
relates to humans, and the debate still rages concerning a correct understanding of
both philosophers’ views regarding this issue. Therefore, since the logical structure
of the argument does not change much between the version in Parmenides and the
Aristotelian version, it would be more prudent to treat the argument as it appears
in Parmenides and avoid the additional metaphysical hurdles in the Aristotelian
version that do not directly relate to the Third Man Argument as such.
In terms of logical structure, the argument relies on three basic principles. The
first principle is the Principle of Abstraction, which says that for every property f
there must be a Form, F-ness, through which all objects with f get that property.2
There are multiple places in the Platonic corpus where this is affirmed. The second principle, known as Uniqueness, states that for each set of objects that share
the property F there must be one and only one Form F-ness through which F is
instantiated. The third principle, here referred to as the Feedback Principle, asserts that the Form F-ness and all the objects that it substantiates form a new class
of things with the property f from which a new Form F1 must be posited.3 The
Feedback Principle is drawn out of two enthymemes, namely Non-Identity, which
follows directly from Separation, and Self-Predication. Non-Identity means that a
Form is not identical to any of its instantiations. This is a logical necessity and well
supported within the Platonic corpus as being directly deductible from Separation, which is to say that a Form is by itself or “one over many.”4 The Principle of
Self-Predication is also well supported within the Platonic corpus and gets to the
902980_Text.indd 44
4/18/14 2:18 PM
A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF THE THIRD MAN ARGUMENT
37
idea that a Form F-ness is (a) f 5, where ‘f’ is the quality for which it stands. Since
the Feedback Principle contradicts the Principle of Uniqueness, the latter is false.
From this can be concluded that the Theory of the Forms leads to an infinite regression and, as a result of this, is absurd. Mapped out, this argument states:
(i) (Abstraction) For every F there is a Form F-ness, through which all
objects with F get that property.
(ii) (Uniqueness) For each F there is at most one F-ness.
(iii) (Separation) Each F-ness is one over many and itself by itself.
(iv) (Non-Identity, from iii) F-ness is not identical to any particular pf.
(v) (Self-Predication) F-ness is (a) f, where f is the quality for which it
stands.
(vi) (Feedback Principle, from iv and v) For every set (F) = {any f}, there is
a second set, (F1) = {F + F-ness}.
(vii) C1 (from i and vi) Therefore, there must be an infinity of Forms, Fness, F-ness1, F-ness2, …. F-nessn.
(viii) C2 (from C1) Therefore, ii must be false.
There has been some discussion among academics concerning whether the
Principle of Self-Predication and the Principle of Separation are mutually exclusive and that, therefore, the argument is invalid and the Principle of Separation
has to be excised from Plato’s Theory of the Forms in order to make it coherent.6
This position, however, seems to misunderstand Plato in what he means concerning Separation. Both Separation and Self-Predication (though there could be
a better name for it) can be held in common if one properly understands that a
Form is different from the objects it instantiates since the instantiated objects
contain the property in question imperfectly, whereas the Form holds it perfectly
and is the ultimate source for instantiations. Others have considered the Principle
of Self-Participation as precisely trying to bridge this gap. However, careful text
analysis of Parmenides and other Platonic dialogues shows that the instantiated
objects are always taken as participating in the Form, which implies that the Form
not only has the property which it instantiates, but is the ultimate possessor of it,
from which other objects ‘borrow’ that property.
Constance Meinwald7 notes that there are simply two different modes of
predication within Plato’s Theory of the Forms, namely predication pros ta alla, by
which particular objects are instantiated, and predication pros heauto, by which the
Form itself acquires the quality it represents. Whereas objects that do not possess
a certain property f as being in their nature are predicated through participation
in F, F receives its property f by its very nature. Meinwald failed to recognize that
a difference in predication leads to an understanding of a distinction in participation, which Francis Pelletier and Edward Zalta point out.8 The Form F, then, is
both predicated by and participates in itself (though this phrasing seems redun-
902980_Text.indd 45
4/18/14 2:18 PM
38
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
dant, everything fully participates in itself ) by virtue of its very nature. By offering
this argument, then, the Third Man is resolved since there is a qualitative difference between F and all objects that exemplify f.
Bryan Frances, however, challenges this view due to certain details in Meinwald’s analysis. Though the first ‘part’ of the Third Man seems to be sufficiently
answered by the pros ta alla and pros heauton distinction, there is a second Third
Man that arises from it, or at least so Frances argues.9 Specifically, he argues that if
all the Forms receive the property of being eternal pros ta alla, as Meinwald argues,
then there is an infinite regress formed there. The simple solution to that problem,
however, is that not all the Forms receive eternality pros ta alla, since the Form of
the Eternal receives its eternality pros heauton. Frances considers this solution, but,
for some reason, seems to think it is unimportant. Having made this argument,
it is necessary to flesh out what pros ta alla and pros heauton predication means in
terms of the Forms and of other objects that are not Forms and what saying that a
Form has pros ta alla predication means metaphysically.
According to Plato, the Forms are perfect, eternal, immutable, and simple. If
this is true, there should be an innate uneasiness in saying that Forms participate
among themselves pros ta alla. If the Forms are simple, then it would be more appropriate to argue that, for example, the Form of Justice is eternal not pros ta alla
by participation in the Form of the Eternal, but pros heauton qua its being a Form
in itself. This, however, would simply give rise to a modified version of the Third
Man. Under this version, Fa, Fb, Fc, … are eternal pros heauton and the Form of the
Eternal (FE) is also eternal pros heauton. Therefore, a new set can be formed for
which there should be a new Form (FE1) and so on and so forth ad infinitum. This
solution, then, brings us nowhere.
A possible way to mend the argument so as not to fall into the trappings of
a second Third Man would be to make a distinction between pros heauton predications which are not also self-predications and those that are. Under this view,
all objects in the sensible world are predicated for some property f by pros ta alla
predication, Forms that contain f but are not Ff (i.e. the Form of Virtue is virtuous) are predicated pros heauton by virtue of it being that particular Form or
a Form (so that the Form of Justice is virtuous by virtue of it being the kind of
Form that pertains to virtue and eternal by virtue of being a Form as such), and
the particular Form Ff is predicated pros heauton through itself. This second distinction also works in reverse, since not only is the Form of Justice virtuous, but
the Form of Virtue is just pros heauton by virtue of being the kind of Form which
pertains to justice. This distinction in pros heauton predications, however, requires
some degree of separation from the Platonic corpus in that, although it is not
contradictory to it and works well in explaining the relationship between different Forms, there seems to be no direct evidence in Plato to support the making of
902980_Text.indd 46
4/18/14 2:18 PM
A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF THE THIRD MAN ARGUMENT
39
such a distinction. Therefore, it must be approached with a caveat for those who do
not stray too far from the text and for whom a purely explanatory proof that fits
with the Platonic principles is not sufficient. The solution to this problem, therefore, must be seen as likely but not proven and, ultimately, will have to wait until
the first argument in Section II to be conclusively resolved.
Another principle considered is the idea that F is distinct from F1 in function.
If this is the case, the expanded set every object that has the property f and F itself
bring forth a ‘new Form,’ F1. However, it follows from this that F is not an f, but
rather an f1 and so on and so forth ad infinitum. In this case, if F is, in fact, not an
F but an F1, and it cannot be included in the expanded set, because it is not one
of the things that have the property f. To simply assume that F gets the property
of being f from F1 etc., is to assume that one needs more than one Form for each
property, but this is the conclusion of the argument. Since this is so, to include it
as a suppressed premise makes the argument invalid.10 If the property which F1
instantiates is any different than the property of F, then the argument makes no
sense. If it is the same, then the argument is circular because it assumes what it is
trying to prove. The problem here seems to be that the Forms are seen solely as
regulative and explanatory principles rather than full metaphysical beings as the
Parmenides and Plato’s work at large would argue. This, however, seems to be a
departure from the text of Parmenides and applies only to the extensive papers that
have only recently been written on this issue by current philosophers. It seems,
then, that this solution does not bring us any closer to solving the Third Man.
II. Solving the Third Man Argument
These considered, an argument can be formed which does not rely on subtle
metaphysical principles to solve the Third Man. The most obvious problem with
this argument is that the Forms are not physical, but exclusively immaterial. One
can see throughout the Parmenides that one of the basic dissimilarities between
Socrates and Parmenides is that the latter is a committed materialist, whereas
Socrates is not.11 Though this argument relies on principles that Aristotle, rather
than Plato, formally puts forth.12 As those acquainted with Aquinas should be
familiar with, every angel is its own species since there is no individuating principle to distinguish between two individuals.13 The same principle applies in this
case. Since the Forms are simple, there is no individuating factor to differentiate
between F and F1, since they both instantiate a given property f. By Leibniz’ Law
of Indiscernibles, which states that two things which hold all their properties in
common cannot be numerically distinct, F and F1 must, of necessity be one and
the same Form. Every time a distinction between the two is made, it collapses on
itself since the Forms are immaterial. The infinite regression, then, while possible
in thought, is impossible in reality, since the argument fails to grasp the kind of
902980_Text.indd 47
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
40
thing that a Form is and is therefore invalid.
At this point, a proponent of the Third Man Argument may choose to argue
that the set of all things which have property F (S={x: F(x)}) is inherently inconsistent by appealing to Russell’s paradox. Russell’s paradox argues that a set of
everything is inherently contradictory, because the set would have to be one of
the members of the set, which, according to the Foundation Axiom, would be an
absurdity. The Foundation Axiom says that there cannot be an infinite sequence of
sets each of whose terms is an element of the previous term.14 One might reply,
however, that the set proposed is simply not specific enough, since the Platonic
Theory of Forms makes a clear distinction between the manner in which any
given thing in this world which has a property F is instantiated and the manner in
which F-ness itself is instantiated (i.e. F-ness has the property F perfectly, whereas
any particular object that has F does so imperfectly). Be that as it may, however,
recent developments in set theory make it possible to have a consistent set even
without relying on the distinction between the instantiation of the Forms and the
instantiation of particular objects. Since a Form has the property which it instantiates and, therefore, participates in itself, the expanded set of the Form and all the
objects which it instantiates has to be understood as a Non-Well-Founded set.
Though Russell’s paradox deems the set Ω={Ω} an absurdity,15 Aczel introduces
a variation of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the AFA16 by using which one
can keep the theory of the Forms consistent. The Anti-Foundation Axiom (AFA)
argues that sets should be considered as graphs rather than a collection of elements, where a set “is an abstract obtained by taking a graph G and then associating to each node of x in the graph a set in such a way that the set associated to x is
the set of sets associated to the children of x in G.”17 Peter Schweizer explains the
contribution of this theory as follows:
This object induces an infinite descending chain of membership, but it is
nonetheless hereditarily finite, since each member of the chain has only
one element. ZFC, with the axiom of foundation replaced by the AFA, is
provably consistent relative to the original system. Thus circularity is formally absolved … and the world of ‘hypersets’ is rendered just as axiomatically secure as the cumulative hierarchy.18
By implementing this method, there is a consistent way to understand the Theory
of Forms in terms of Self-Predication and Self-Participation which further dissolves the infinite regression argued for in the Third Man.
III. Differences in Predication Revisited
For those who are not convinced that the distinction between predication
pros heauton and predication pros heauton as self-predication can be applied to
902980_Text.indd 48
4/18/14 2:18 PM
A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF THE THIRD MAN ARGUMENT
41
Platonic metaphysics without altering any principle already in place, the solution
of the second Third Man formulation would have to be solved by appealing to
the principle in Section II that, since the Forms are immaterial, no individuating
principle can be produced for them. Therefore, since here also Ff and Ff 1 cannot
be distinguished by appealing to an individuating principle, they also collapse
back into one another. The Third Man, then, is doomed to fail due to the fact that
Parmenides seems to have a physical conception of the Forms, whereas Socrates
argues that they are immaterial. Whatever the case, one possibility which can be
conclusively be thrown out is that the Forms are predicated pros ta alla in being (for example) eternal, since that would clash with the principle that they are
simple.
IV. Conclusion
In short, the Third Man argument fails to show an infinite regression of the
Forms. Of the three arguments put forth, the argument from differences in predication successfully dissolves the regression if the added principle that there is a
substantive difference between pros heauton predication when the principle in
question is drawn naturally from the Form and pros heauton predication as selfpredication is accepted. If this principle were not accepted, this argument would
have to rely on the argument from lack of an individuating principle in order to
conclusively dissolve the second Third Man. The argument seeking to show that
the Third Man is inherently circular, though very similar to the argument from
lack of an individuating principle, has to be discarded, since it injects a later conception of the nature of the Forms which Plato himself does not share. Ultimately,
the argument from the lack of an individuating principle dissolves the infinite regression since it shows that the there is an additional assumption that Parmenides
makes in forming the argument that Socrates disagrees with. Together with the
implementation of the theory of Non-Well-Founded Sets, this argument shows
that both the expanded set is logically consistent without producing a regression and that the regression is only possible in thought. Having considered that
there are either two or three arguments, depending on whether one accepts the
added pros heauton distinction and the rather provocative titles that recent articles
carry that treat the issue of the Third Man, an account that looks favourably on
the Third Man Argument will have to appeal to more nuanced interpretations in
order to maintain its bite.
1 Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1038b35-1039a2
2 Schweizer, Peter. “Self-Predication and the Third Man.” Erkenntnis 40.1 (1994): 23. <http://
www.jstor.org/stable/20012526>
902980_Text.indd 49
4/18/14 2:18 PM
42
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
3 Ibid.
4 See Phaedo 75c11–d2, 100b6–7 and Republic 476b10, 480a11, in Plato: Complete Works, trans.
John M. Cooper (Indianapolis: Hacket, 1997).
5 Plato, Symposium 210e, Phaedo 100c
6 Schweizer’s article does a good job of pointing out that Wedberg and other have been able to
solve the Third Man Argument, but at the expense of departing from the Platonic text and
compromising Plato’s theory of the Forms. To take that position one would have to assume
either that Plato thought that there was some fallacy in the argument which turns out not to
be so or that he saw a problem with the theory of the Forms which he hoped his successors
would be able to solve. To argue for either of these cases, however, would be to have to make
an inference without any evidence.
7 Meinwald, Constance, “Good-bye to the Third Man,” in The Cambridge Companion to Plato.
Trans. R. Kraut. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992, 365-396.
8 Pelletier, Francis J., and Edward N. Zalta. “How to Say Goodbye to the Third Man.” Noûs
34.2 (2000): 165-202. <http://www.jstor.org/stable/2671980>
9 Frances, Bryan, “Plato’s Response to the Third Man Argument in the Paradoxical Exercise of
the Parmenides,” Ancient Philosophy 16 (1996): 54.
10 Schweizer, Peter, “Self-Predication and the Third Man.” Erkenntnis 40.1 (1994): 27-28.
<http://www.jstor.org/stable/20012526>
11 See, for example, Parmenides 145a-b, among others.
12 For the sake of extreme preciseness, it is Averoes which is accredited, at least in Aquinas, as
coming forth with this central principle, by interpreting Aristotle.
13 Aquinas, St. Thomas. On Being and Essence. Trans. Armand A. Maurer. Toronto: Pontifical
Institute, 1968, 54.
14 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Non-Wellfounded Set Theory, 2.2
15 Schweizer, “Self-Predication and the Third Man,” 38.
16 Aczel, Peter, Non-Well-Founded Sets, Center for the Study of Language and Information,
Stanford University, Lecture Notes Number 14, 1988.
17 Ibid. 2.3.
18 Schweizer, “Self-Predication and the Third Man,” 38.
902980_Text.indd 50
4/18/14 2:18 PM
A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF THE THIRD MAN ARGUMENT
902980_Text.indd 51
43
4/18/14 2:18 PM
Until the middle of the twentieth
century, Nietzsche was associated with
the very ideas that he fundamentally
opposed throughout his active life.
902980_Text.indd 52
4/18/14 2:18 PM
Nietzsche the
Autobiographer
Anthony Cossette
W
ithout a shred of doubt, Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche is a giant among
Western philosophers, not least because of his immense but sometimes
controversial influence upon succeeding generations. He has certainly furnished
this culture with a treasure-chest’s worth of memorable quotations, including
the pithily infamous and now-hackneyed aphorism “God is dead.”1 However,
critically appraising the full scope and force of Nietzsche’s personality and ideas
requires delving into one of his most overlooked but extraordinarily insightful
works: his short autobiography entitled Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What One
Is. For all of its faults, it stands out as a tour-de-force among the canon of memoirs and autobiographies, for it offers nothing other than Nietzsche’s own view
of his life and his works. As Walter Kaufman, the preeminent Nietzsche scholar
of the 20th century, duly noted when introducing Ecce Homo, “Who would not
rather have Shakespeare on Shakespeare, including the poet’s own reflections on
his plays and poems, than the exegeses and conjectures of thousands of critics and
professors?”2 Indeed, more than anything else Nietzsche ever wrote, Ecce Homo
deserves a distinct place within the world’s autobiographical oeuvre simply because
it is a “triumph of style” and offers a range of insights not just on the development
of Nietzsche’s own self-consciousness but, more fundamentally, on the human
condition itself.3
Before attempting to digest what Nietzsche thought about life’s undeniable
complexities, a brief account of his background will be presented in conjunction
with passages from his autobiography so that one can fully understand and appreciate how the development of his philosophy was inextricable from the pivotal
events and influences that surrounded his life. The son of Lutheran Minister Carl
Ludwig Nietzsche and his wife, Franziska Oehler, he was born on October 15,
1844 in the German town of Röcken in modern-day Saxony.4 Whether by coincidence or not, Nietzsche began writing his autobiography Ecce Homo on his fortyfourth birthday, October 15, 1888; on the same day, he inscribed a dedication to
introduce the main work after the preface as a form of thanksgiving to the fateful
role he played in the circumstances of his own life’s unfolding, a characteristic of
45
902980_Text.indd 53
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
46
his perfectly cheerful philosophical outlook:
On this perfect day, when everything is ripening and not only the grape
turns brown, the eye of the sun just fell upon my life: I looked back, I
looked forward, and never saw so many and such good things at once. It
was not for nothing that I buried my forty-fourth year today; I had the
right to bury it; whatever was life in it has been saved, is immortal. . . . How
could I fail to be grateful to my whole life?—and so I tell my life to myself.5
Nietzsche actually had every reason to disparage his own existence because it was
fraught with difficulties and major illnesses that plagued him up until the very
end. A series of protracted ailments threatened to overtake his well-being, but he
fought back and instead chose the path of affirmation and fashioned his “will to
health, to life, into a philosophy.”6
Regarding his parentage, Nietzsche informs the reader that “My father died
at the age of thirty-six.”7 Indeed, records show that his father Carl Ludwig died
in the year 1849 from what was then diagnosed as a “softening of the brain,” a
euphemism for a major mental illness.8 It should be noted here that the death
of his father, as with all people who suffer bereavement from the painful experience of losing one’s relatives or loved ones, must have made an indelible mark on
Nietzsche’s psyche even at such a young age. The lack of a parent whom he never
had a chance to know left him without an instructional figure of his own sex in his
household. Nevertheless, Nietzsche speaks of him with reverence and a large sense
of pride, as his father “had received his pastoral position” from the Prussian King
Frederick William IV, after whom his son Friedrich was named.9 In a subsequent
section of Ecce Homo, Nietzsche again comments on the metaphysical (rather than
actual) relationship with his father by saying, “I am merely my father once more,
and, as it were, his continued life after an all-too-early death.”10 Thus Nietzsche
treats as seminal the continuities that lay between him and his father, whose
legacy his son intends to fully bring to fruition in the form of the written word.
Nietzsche does not say much about his mother other than a few remarks about
her full-blooded German-ness which contrasted sharply with his supposed belief
in his Polish ancestry,11 a claim that turns out to be patently false.12 There is an
extant photograph of Nietzsche standing next to his mother who has her hands
clasped around his right arm, perhaps symbolic of her overprotectiveness (Appendix 1). After her son succumbed to mental illness, she took him under her care
until her death in 1897, and his sister Elizabeth nursed him thereafter until he
died in 1900.13
Toward the end of Nietzsche’s life and especially after his death, the status
of his relationship with his sister remained contentious in the minds of many. As
children and young adults, they were quite close, but as they grew older, Nietzsche
902980_Text.indd 54
4/18/14 2:18 PM
NIETZSCHE THE AUTOBIOGRAPHER
47
“came to realize that [his sister’s] character and outlook were basically opposed to
what he wanted his own to be.”14 When she married a prominent nationalist and
anti-Semite named Bernhard Förster whose ideologies completely and utterly
contrasted with Nietzsche’s own, the bonds that held brother and sister together
for so long were broken apart.15 The philosopher, who stood vehemently opposed
to any strain of anti-Semitism that ran through Europe in his era, especially in his
native Germany, could not restrain himself any longer. He unleashed his fury and
targeted it directly toward his sister in a letter written not too long after her marriage to Bernhard and the couples’ emigration to Paraguay to found a new German anti-Semitic colony there called Nueva Germania; one can unquestionably
feel the arousal of irritation in the letter’s tone and a condemnation of any association of his name with the anti-Semitic movement:
One of the greatest stupidities you have committed—for yourself and for
me! Your association with an anti-Semitic chief expresses a foreignness to
my whole way of life which fills me ever again with ire and melancholy.
. . . It is a matter of honor to me to be absolutely clean and unequivocal
regarding anti-Semitism, namely opposed, as I am in my writings.16
In spite of all of this, after her brother had lost much of his mental faculties,
Elizabeth returned to take care of him and assume custody of all of his writings,
sometimes distorting them to suit her and her husband’s nationalist and antiSemitic viewpoints.17 It is for this reason, and the fact that the Nazis appropriated
the Nietzsche “cult” based on Frau Förster-Nietzsche’s corrupt “corrections” of her
brother’s writings, that Nietzsche’s reputation in the West suffered greatly for the
longest time. Until the middle of the twentieth century, Nietzsche was associated
with the very ideas that he fundamentally opposed throughout his active life. Fortunately, his image has been resuscitated thanks to more scholarly and authentic
editions of his voluminous writings being published in Europe and notable English translations that adhere closely to Nietzsche’s style and original intent appearing in the Anglosphere.18
Apart from his familial troubles and the tainting of his name by others, Nietzsche was grateful that he received the best education one could have in his
time. Indeed, his schooling years were formative and exerted no less of a decisive
influence upon his thinking. As a youth he was educated at the Schulpforta, one of
the most prestigious boarding schools in 19th century Germany.19 Here Nietzsche
began to take up an interest in classical philology, a field that would eventually
land him a professorship at the University of Basel in Switzerland at the young
age of only twenty-four.20 Outside of school, Nietzsche read the writings of the
German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer whom he called “more honest but
gloomy in matters of spirit” and whose philosophical influence on Nietzsche
was profound.21 The young Nietzsche was attracted to Schopenhauer’s essential
902980_Text.indd 55
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
48
doctrines of the primacy of the Will in human action, his advocacy for an ascetic
lifestyle, and his synthesis of Western ideas with Indian philosophy as found in
the Hindu Upanishads. Moreover, Schopenhauer’s skepticism and staunch atheism
led Nietzsche to appreciate him all the more, as Nietzsche’s own attitudes toward
religion were uncompromising, strongly rebuking all forms of organized worship.22
He touches upon this radical distancing of himself from the concept of God in
the second section of Ecce Homo:
I do not by any means know atheism as a result; even less as an event: it is
a matter of course with me, from instinct. I am too inquisitive, too questionable, too exuberant to stand for any gross answer. God is a gross answer,
an indelicacy against us thinkers—at bottom merely a gross prohibition for
us: you shall not think!23
According to Kaufmann, Nietzsche never appeared to experience any sort of “crisis of faith” as an adolescent.24 Not until near the end of his writing career, in the
same period in which he wrote Ecce Homo, did he direct his most sustained attacks
against Christianity. He loosened all inhibitions against the world’s largest religion
by penning The Antichrist, with a title meant to portray the author as “anti-Christian” and, at the same time, “be as provocative as possible.”25
Alongside the Schopenhauerian influence, no one can avoid discussing Nietzsche and his autobiography without mentioning his friendship with and ultimate dissociation from the German composer Richard Wagner. With reluctant
praise, Nietzsche “considered the composer Germany’s greatest living genius.”26
But when Wagner became increasingly nationalistic and anti-Semitic in his outlook and opinions, Nietzsche could no longer remain privy to the developments in
his old friend’s artistic circle and simultaneously hold true to his integrity. Thus he
increasingly forbade himself all possible contact with the goings-on at Bayreuth,
where the annual performances of Wagner’s operas were held.27 In Ecce Homo,
the one reason he “could never forgive Wagner” was “[t]hat he condescended to the
Germans—that he became reichsdeutsch.”28 Elsewhere, Nietzsche often repeats
what he thinks of his fellow compatriots with characteristic irony and acerbic
wit, especially when he discusses questions of health, climate, and nutrition as
metaphors in relation to the development of the self: “The slightest sluggishness
of the intestines is entirely sufficient, once it has become a bad habit, to turn a
genius into something mediocre, something ‘German.’ The German climate alone
is enough to discourage strong, even inherently heroic, intestines.”29 Aside from
these caustic remarks, Nietzsche always admired the true, original spirit of Wagner
and his music, as he writes that “All things considered, I could not have endured
my youth without Wagner’s music. For I was condemned to Germans.”30 In 1888,
during his last year of lucidity, Nietzsche composed two whole books containing both praise and criticism of Wagner and his aesthetic and artistic tastes: The
902980_Text.indd 56
4/18/14 2:18 PM
NIETZSCHE THE AUTOBIOGRAPHER
49
Case of Wagner and Nietzsche contra Wagner. In essence, then, Nietzsche’s relationship with Wagner was more than mundane love-hate; it was the consummation,
at least for Nietzsche as he wrote many years earlier in his first book The Birth of
Tragedy, of identifying the “Dionysian artist . . . with the primal unity, its pain and
contradiction.”31
Ecce Homo itself is a very well-crafted and stylized autobiography despite
Nietzsche’s inability to publish it during his own lifetime, perhaps due to his
incapacitation so soon after writing it as well as the pronouncements present in
his other late writings31 that were certain to stir controversy amongst would-be
readers. Still, little of his work was read while he was still alive anyway, and Nietzsche knew all-too-well how those few who did read his books consistently
misunderstood and clouded them with half-truths and downright lies. Therefore,
the problem of misinterpretation stands at the forefront of his autobiography and
may have been the very reason he decided to embark upon writing it. One can
conceive of the work as his own kind of apology or testimony in front of the jury
of humanity and, specifically, his audience, an appropriate metaphor considering
his posthumous fame. Furthermore, Nietzsche thought of himself as an “artistic
Socrates” without his namesake’s emphasis on reason and Apollonian restraint.33
Just as Socrates in Plato’s dialogue the Apology thought it was “right for me . . . to
defend myself first against the first lying accusations made against me and my followers, and then against the later accusations and later accusers,”34so Nietzsche felt
the time had come for him to “confront humanity with the most difficult demand
ever made of it . . . for I have not left myself ‘without testimony.’”35 At the outset
of Ecce Homo, unfairly indicted and constantly taken out-of-context as an author
and philosopher by the majority of his readership, Nietzsche feels the urgent
need to justify coming up with a defense of his own views by justly affirming his
identity for all time, exclaiming “Hear me! For I am such and such a person. Above
all, do not mistake me for someone else!”36 It is unfortunate how little this demand
was heeded, for the irony of how his own sister bowdlerized his writings after his
mental collapse becomes all the more apparent in light of the above statement.37
His actual views were properly assessed with a decent degree of accuracy only after
his death and the coming of the Second World War. But in his lifetime, Nietzsche
himself was well aware of his own obscurity and untimeliness to the point that,
right from the beginning of Ecce Homo, he believed that “one has neither heard
nor even seen me” and that his fame had not arrived yet as “some are born posthumously.”38 These are certainly prophetic statements concerning the reputation he
would acquire soon after his death.
The structure of Ecce Homo is dependent on Nietzsche’s penchant for irony,
contradiction, and sardonic wit. It is divided into a preface and four distinct sections, all bearing mockingly self-congratulatory designations: “Why I Am So
902980_Text.indd 57
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
50
Wise;” “Why I Am So Clever;” “Why I Write Such Good Books;” and “Why I
Am a Destiny.”39 Nietzsche, of course, did not mean to inflate his own ego with
the christening of these different sections; Nietzsche commentator Thomas Steinbuch warns those who jump to hasty conclusions about Nietzsche’s supposed
pomposity that “if an ideology of affirming self-importance has been found here,
this is only the projection of an authoritarian society’s own obsessive focus on
figures of domination and its need to believe in the monolithic action of authority.”40 Rather, as French philosopher Georges Gusdorf says, Nietzsche as a writer
and, more importantly, as an autobiographer is here straining “toward a complete
and coherent expression of his entire destiny.”41 In other words, no one knows
Nietzsche better than Nietzsche himself.
The very title of the autobiography is a not-so-subtle proclamation of his
stance toward Christianity if one knows him well, neatly borrowed from Pilate’s
words to Jesus in the Gospels and refashioned to suit Nietzsche’s own purposes.
Kaufmann articulates astutely what Nietzsche intended to mean with this title:
“Here is a man! Here is a new, different image of humanity: not a saint or holy
man any more than a traditional sage, but a modern version.”42 In addition to all of
this, the title and the work itself represent, at bottom, a conscious revolt against
idealism and a rebellion against traditional moral injunctions coming from Christianity that exhort man to be something altogether different from what he truly
is. This spirit is best encapsulated in a passage contained within The Twilight of the
Idols, another work written by Nietzsche in the same year as Ecce Homo:
Let us finally consider how naïve it is to say: “Man ought to be such and
such!” Reality shows us an enchanting wealth of types, the abundance of
a lavish play and change of forms—and some wretched loafer of a moralist comments: “No! Man ought to be different.” He even knows what man
should look like, this wretched bigot and prig: he paints himself on the
wall and comments, “Ecce Homo!”43
The subtitle of Ecce Homo, “How One Becomes What One Is” represents
no less of a significant choice on Nietzsche’s part. To attain the supreme goal of
human life, which is self-transformation from the lowest depths to the ultimate
heights of human existence (to the “fullness of life,” as Nietzsche would say),
one should not even have to recall it to consciousness. No other person should
imprint their own imperative or command on the individual; every person is
their own master and commander. Hence, a strong individualism was foremost
in Nietzsche’s mind at the time he was writing his autobiography. Furthermore,
Nietzsche himself is very permissive of every misstep traversed on the path of
life and every mistake or folly defective human beings undeniably commit in one
way or another: “From this point of view even the blunders of life have their own
meaning and value—the occasional side roads and wrong turns, the delays, ‘mod-
902980_Text.indd 58
4/18/14 2:18 PM
NIETZSCHE THE AUTOBIOGRAPHER
51
esties,’ seriousness wasted on tasks that are remote from the task.”44 Nietzsche’s
primary existential task of transforming Schopenhauer’s will to negate all existence into something more positive, a will to affirm reality as it is, represented a
paradigmatic shift in the psychology of motivation. Instead of dwelling on petty
“thoughts and feelings of renunciation and vindictiveness,” Nietzsche thought that
humans should refocus their efforts on unconditional acceptance, “willing that
nothing be otherwise than it is,” the opposite of decadence; only then will the single
individual have the power to become what he or she truly is or wants to be.45 The
paradox Nietzsche formulates here is the expression of gratitude for the life that
is given to us no matter how much inescapable suffering we must bear in our lives
without any hope or prospect of release from it. He of all people practiced what he
preached, so to speak, by his unconditional acceptance of his fate beyond anyone’s
mere imagining; indeed, his “formula for greatness in a human being is amor fati
[love of fate]: that one wants nothing to be different, not forward, not backward,
not in all eternity. Not merely bear what his necessary, still less conceal it—all
idealism is mendaciousness in the face of what is necessary—but love it.”46
The style of Ecce Homo, like all decent autobiographies, is inseparable from
the oddities and quirks of its author. That autobiographical style paints, above all,
a self-portrait, has been established as axiomatic by a number of critics who opine
that the autobiographer “in writing his story artfully defines, restricts, or shapes
his life into a self-portrait.”47 Nietzsche’s own unique style and its literary merits
have been amply discussed and imitated by other writers, even those who are not
philosophers. The linguistic elements of his style act as his own kind of outlet for
conveying complex philosophical ideas and a very unique train of thought. Nietzsche’s development of the aphorism is a notable trait among his writings, for
he epigrammatically condenses into a few words the inherent profundities and
contradictions in life that make his aphorisms difficult to decipher at times. For
instance, multiple interpretations exist for a famous expression of his that has now
become almost proverbial: “Whoever fights monsters should see to it that in the
process he does not become a monster. And when you look long into an abyss, the
abyss also looks into you.”48 Besides wanting his readers to think with subtlety,
Nietzsche’s purpose in employing his own style is “to communicate a state, an inward tension of pathos, by means of signs, including the tempo of these signs” and
to express the “most delightful and daring nuances of free, free-spirited thought.”49
His use of the word “tempo” to describe style is reminiscent of his interest in
music and his insistence that “it be cheerful and profound like an afternoon in
October.”50 But he maintains that making “good style in itself ” a goal of writing
is a “pure folly,” for style without substance or content is meaningless and smacks
of pure idealism in lacking any basis in reality, the likes of which Nietzsche would
not tolerate.51
902980_Text.indd 59
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
52
Nietzsche’s thinking best typifies what one may call a poetic philosophy. Indeed, Nietzsche’s books, with Thus Spoke Zarathustra and Ecce Homo being the
most representative of this kind, are replete with symbols and metaphors in a
type of poetic meter often contained within prose. Nietzsche’s unique contribution to philosophy may be solidifying the equation of philosophy with poetry, or
philosophy and art, or philosophy and music, rather than the stale didacticism of
traditional academic philosophy typically presented in the universities. Ecce Homo
channels the inward expression of Nietzsche’s soul into poesy and is his method
of developing a metaphor of self. This can undoubtedly be accomplished since, as
autobiographical theorist James Olney says, “philosophy, being of the nature of
poetry, is validated in experience in the inner world of thought and emotions, in
the understanding of one’s self.”52 Nietzsche’s metaphor of himself in his autobiography and other writings (for what else could his written corpus be other than
one long autobiography?) hearkens back to a classical notion of divinity, a being
who reckons himself to be a “genius of the heart . . . the tempter god and born
pied piper of consciences whose voice knows how to descend into the netherworld
of every soul,” including his own.53 There is no coincidence, then, that Nietzsche
adopts the name of the founder of Zoroastrianism, Zoroaster or Zarathustra, as
his mouthpiece for communicating states of mind that seem to originate from
“high mountains” which no man ascends or from the deep places of the world
to where no foot descends.54 The ideas Nietzsche presents to the reader through
metaphor, such as the eternal recurrence, the will to power, and the Übermensch,
are meant to connect the familiar elements of life with unfamiliar and frightening
territories that humans are often afraid to tread upon. Ecce Homo, therefore, can
only venture into terra cognita by using a metaphor “through which we stamp our
own image on the face of nature, allow[ing] us to connect the known of ourselves
to the unknown of the world.”55
Other than by examining stylistic considerations, Ecce Homo can be touted as
an epitome of autobiographies by explaining how it fulfills the necessary preconditions of the autobiographical model established previously by the Confessions
of Augustine and Rousseau, both of whom are taken to be “central figures” in the
autobiographical tradition.56 In fact, Ecce Homo goes beyond these requirements by
striving only to seek the truth rather than preach to “improve mankind” or convince people to conglomerate into some sort of ideological sect.57 Religious ideas,
like many moral prejudices, are to Nietzsche mere vagaries of the masses:
[T]here is nothing in me of a founder of a religion—religions are affairs
of the rabble; I find it necessary to wash my hands after I have come into
contact with religious people.—I want no “believers”; I think I am too malicious to believe in myself; I never speak to masses.—I have a terrible fear
that one day I will be pronounced holy: you will guess why I publish this
902980_Text.indd 60
4/18/14 2:18 PM
NIETZSCHE THE AUTOBIOGRAPHER
53
book before; it shall prevent people from doing mischief with me.58
Ecce Homo, however, was not published until eight years after the author’s death,
and it did not prevent his faithful friend in life Peter Gast from proclaiming at
Nietzsche’s funeral, “Holy be thy name to all coming generations.”59 The prohibition against readers not to accept the author’s conclusions without question or
debate is why Nietzsche’s autobiography may be considered more modern than,
say, Augustine’s Confessions. It does attempt to aim for some kind of “truth,” or a
perspective concerning the truth. But as a more-or-less open question, it intentionally leaves the reader pondering whether or not Nietzsche succeeds in this
endeavor. Nietzsche admits and even encourages objections to be raised against any
proposition encountered in his autobiography. This is what Gusdorf meant when
he said that “in autobiography the truth of facts is subordinate to the truth of the
man, for it is first of all the man who is in question.”60 Thus we are here analyzing
more of the man himself rather than any “truths” he happens to be discussing at a
particular point in time. Therefore, Ecce Homo is as appropriate a title as any for an
autobiography of this superior caliber.
Nietzsche’s autobiography does not merely chronicle his life events, although
he does perform this function at various points throughout the book. In fact,
Nietzsche goes so far in the third section of Ecce Homo, “Why I Write Such Good
Books,” as to chronologically self-evaluate each of the major books he has written
throughout the course of his career, beginning with The Birth of Tragedy. According to Jean Starobinski, “every autobiography . . . is a self-interpretation” and Nietzsche’s is no exception.61 Here he situates his first book in the context in which
it was first conceived, when Nietzsche served briefly as a medical orderly in the
Franco-Prussian War of 1870-1871.62 He writes, “taken up with some degree of
neutrality, The Birth of Tragedy looks quite untimely: one would never dream that
it was begun amid the thunder of the Battle of Wörth. Before the walls of Metz,
in cold September nights, while on duty as a medical orderly, I thought through
these problems.”63 That is, he reflected on the mode of tragedy in ancient drama
and poetry just as he was confronting the tragedy of having to tend to wounded
soldiers as they were returning from the front. Therefore, his self-consciousness
as a writer is once again not merely apparent but actual. Not only this, but he is
acutely aware of the general cultural and intellectual trends of his day. He reserves
praise only for a few select authors, such as Stendhal and Fyodor Dostoyevsky.
The first he calls “one of the most beautiful accidents of my life” and the second
he refers to as “the only psychologist, incidentally, from whom I had something
to learn.”64 What Nietzsche thinks of his contemporaries and which of whom he
holds in either high regard or contempt is fascinating in itself and as a source of
literary and philosophical criticism.
In addition to tackling the problem of himself qua himself in his autobiog-
902980_Text.indd 61
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
54
raphy, Nietzsche possessed a keen sense and critical eye for the problems facing
his culture and humanity in general. This brings the reader to Nietzsche’s method
of Kulturkritik as a way of “strengthening” his affirmation of life “in the face of
unending waves of desire for renunciation and revenge that threatened to engulf
him.”65 “Warfare” was Nietzsche’s metaphor of threatening to attack what he often
called decadence, or any ideology or societal milieu which was life-negating or that
obstructed our attempts to overcome our petty weaknesses. Christian morality was
one example of what he thought best exemplified this trend; another was nihilism,
a symptom of the decay of the spirit of individuality and fortitude that strongly
characterizes the Übermensch.66 Furthermore, author Jill Ker Conway’s definition
of a “secular hero” is in close kinship with Nietzsche’s program of cultural critique:
“the forces which drive the action of [the hero’s] life are not the classical fates but
the war of the individual against society.”67 This is only partially true of Nietzsche,
for he accepted both fate and war as prerequisites for living well, as “givens” in
human existence. Nietzsche says of himself that “attacking is one of my basic
instincts” and “the strength of those who attack can be measured in a way by the
opposition they require: every growth is indicated by the search for a mighty opponent—or problem; for a warlike philosopher challenges problems, too, to basic
combat.”68 Thus his warlike sentiment was not really literal so much as philosophical. To warfare’s logical extremes, he took the whole of Western Europe to task
for its sense of entitlement and its positivist insistence that man was “progressing”
as a species: “higher types are indeed attained, but they do not last. The level of
the species is not raised.”69 Of note, he finds no comparison between the man of
modernity and the man of former times:
Mankind does not represent a development toward something better
or stronger or higher in the sense accepted today. “Progress” is merely a
modern idea, that is, a false idea. The European of today is vastly inferior in value to the European of the Renaissance: further development
is altogether not according to any necessity in the direction of elevation,
enhancement, or strength.70
But Nietzsche is hopeful that Renaissance virtu will be found again in the form of
the Übermensch, who says “Yes to life even in its strangest and hardest problems.”71
Nietzsche’s eponymous protagonist in Thus Spoke Zarathustra seems to be confident of the success of man’s endeavor of self-overcoming when he says and then
asks his disciples, “Man is something that shall be overcome. What have you done
to overcome him?”72 According to the doctrine of eternal recurrence, “that is, of
the unconditional and infinitely repeated circular course of all things,” great people
will again walk upon the earth, and mankind will be composed of those who say
“yes” to suffering even in the most extreme cases.73
Through the act of writing his autobiography, Nietzsche manages to unearth
902980_Text.indd 62
4/18/14 2:18 PM
NIETZSCHE THE AUTOBIOGRAPHER
55
features of existence that hitherto humanity has not had the courage to question. He acknowledges how daily existence can be a painful struggle and people
often almost capitulate or give into despair, denying reality as it is. But these are
struggles everyone undergoes. And Nietzsche admires most of all “anyone who
manages to experience the history of humanity as a whole as his own history” or
vice versa.74 Ecce Homo engages in the exploration of the most questionable aspects of human existence and therefore concerns not just Nietzsche but humanity
in general. Thus, Nietzsche’s autobiography, which ostensibly touches upon Man
in the singular, becomes the autobiography of Man in the plural, the plurality of
Men. In this way, “the autobiographical is transformed. It is no longer the writer’s
own experience: it becomes everyone’s. He is no longer writing about himself: he
is writing about life.”75
Having surveyed the field that Nietzsche tills in his autobiography and other
writings, can the reader critique Ecce Homo on its own terms? There is no other answer to that question other than the affirmative. Even though the autobiography
is exceptional among its kind, there are still places where it could have used improvement or even redaction. His tendency to overestimate his significance in the
grand scheme of things may border on egotism, but if one thoroughly acquaints
himself with most, if not all, of Nietzsche’s writings, having read them two or
more times, then this will not be an encumbrance. Nietzsche’s constant references
to his own Thus Spoke Zarathustra can become tiresome to the reader and interrupt the flow of reading and deeply experiencing the autobiography. In addition,
female readers will not be pleased with some sections that appear to be wholly
contemptuous of women. Nietzsche’s apparent misogyny is controversial amongst
many readers, but one may point to other places where he may not be so critical of
the other sex. Interestingly, he never really treated women as inferior in real life; he
befriended many women such as the Russian intellectual Louise von Salomé, in
whom Nietzsche found unrivalled inspiration and whose poem Prayer to Life Nietzsche set to music in a composition for piano and voice entitled Hymnus an das
Leben, meaning “A Hymn to Life.”76 Therefore, the disconnect between some of
his words and his behavior can be best explained by how Nietzsche said of himself
in Ecce Homo, “I am one thing, my writings are another matter.”77
Despite these numerous flaws, is there still a reason to read Nietzsche? The
ultimate answer to this question may depend upon a person’s interests and inclinations, but Nietzsche’s importance and influence in the history of philosophy
cannot be overstated. He was a fascinating individual with equally interesting
ideas worthy of the highest rank; likewise, his peerless wit and intelligence showcases his originality as a thinker. There is a distinctive level of self-awareness and
humanness in his writing, most especially in his autobiography. Nietzsche’s Ecce
Homo encompasses a broad range of experience and insight into human psychol-
902980_Text.indd 63
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
56
ogy. He gave a useful criterion of what it means to have a vision that is relevant
to the scope of autobiography: “Gradually it has become clear to me what every
great philosophy so far has been: namely, the personal confession of its author
and a kind of involuntary and unconscious memoir.”78 Importantly, the most one
can gain from reading Nietzsche is something no individual can take away from
another: self-understanding and personal growth.
Appendix 1:
Wildman, Wesley. “Photograph of Nietzsche with his Mother.” 2010. Profound Atheism. Web. 8 December 2013.
1 Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science: With a Prelude in Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs.
Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Random House, 1974, 181.
2 Nietzsche, Friedrich. Basic Writings of Nietzsche. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Modern
Library, 2000, 657.
3 Ibid., 658.
902980_Text.indd 64
4/18/14 2:18 PM
NIETZSCHE THE AUTOBIOGRAPHER
57
4 Kaufmann, Walter. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. 4th ed. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1974, 22.
5 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 677.
6 Ibid., 680.
7 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 678.
8 Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 22.
9 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 682.
10 Ibid., 684.
11 But Nietzsche commentator Thomas Steinbuch suggests that Nietzsche’s extravagant claim
of being a Pole could be symbolic of the fact that the normal process of German “socialization never fully took hold in him” (40). Indeed, Nietzsche’s criticism of his own nationality
and the German people is practically ubiquitous elsewhere in his writings. See Steinbuch,
Thomas. A Commentary on Nietzsche’s Ecce Homo. Lanham: University Press of America,
1994, 40.
12 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 681; Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 22.
13 Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 56.
14 Ibid., 42.
15 Ibid., 42-43.
16 Quoted in Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 45.
17 Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 14.
18 Ibid., 1.
19 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 695f.
20 Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 26.
21 Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Will to Power. Ed. Walter Kaufmann. Trans. Walter Kaufmann and
R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Random House, 1967, 59.; Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 24.
22 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 735.
23 Ibid., 692-693.
24 Ibid., 693f.
25 Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Portable Nietzsche. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Penguin
Books, 1982, 565.
26 Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 30.
27 Ibid., 34.
28 That is, a German Nationalist; Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 704.
29 Ibid., 696.
30 Ibid., 705.
31 Ibid., 49.
32 For example, The Antichrist.
33 Ibid., 659.
34 Plato, The Apology, in Great Dialogues of Plato, ed. Eric H. Warmington and Philip G. Rouse,
trans. W.H.D. Rouse. New York: New American Library, 1999, 424.
35 Plato. Complete Works. Ed. John M Cooper. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company,
902980_Text.indd 65
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
58
1997, 18a; Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 673.
36 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 673.
37 Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 8.
38 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 673, 715.
39 Ibid., 656.
40 Steinbuch, Thomas. A Commentary on Nietzsche’s Ecce Homo. Lanham: University Press of
America, 1994, 25.
41 Gusdorf, Georges. “Conditions and Limits of Autobiography.” Trans. James Olney in Autobiography: Essays Theoretical and Critical. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980, 35.
42 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 660.
43 Nietzsche, Portable Nietzsche, 491.
44 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 710.
45 Steinbuch, A Commentary, 8.
46 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 714.
47 Howarth, William L. “Some Principles of Autobiography.” New Literary History 5.2 (1974):
365.
48 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 279.
49 Ibid., 721, 230.
50 Ibid., 707.
51 Ibid., 721.
52 Olney, James. Metaphors of Self: The Meaning of Autobiography. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981, 322.
53 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 423.
54 Nietzsche, Portable Nietzsche, 122.
55 Olney, Metaphors of Self, 32.
56 Olney, James. Memory & Narrative: The Weave of Life-Writing. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press, 1998, 217.
57 Nietzsche, Portable Nietzsche, 502.
58 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 782.
59 Ibid., 782f.
60 Gusdorf, “Conditions and Limits,” 43.
61 Starobinski, Jean. “The Style of Autobiography.” Trans. Seymour Chatman. In Olney, Autobiography, 73-83.
62 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 726.
63 Ibid.
64 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 700; Nietzsche, Portable Nietzsche, 549.
65 Steinbuch, A Commentary, 60.
66 Nietzsche, Will to Power, 9.
67 Conway, Jill K. When Memory Speaks: Exploring the Art of Autobiography. New York: Vintage
Books, 1998, 9.
902980_Text.indd 66
4/18/14 2:18 PM
NIETZSCHE THE AUTOBIOGRAPHER
59
68 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 688.
69 Nietzsche, Will to Power, 363.
70 Nietzsche, Portable Nietzsche, 571.
71 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 562.
72 Nietzsche, Portable Nietzsche, 124.
73 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 729-730.
74 Nietzsche, Gay Science, 268.
75 Spender, Steven. “Confessions and Autobiography.” In Olney, Autobiography, 117.
76 Nietzsche, Basic Writings, 752f.
77 Ibid., 715.
78 Ibid., 203.
902980_Text.indd 67
4/18/14 2:18 PM
To deny the doctrine of divine simplicity
is to walk dangerously close to an
anthropomorphic and empty conception of
God as one being among many beings.
902980_Text.indd 68
4/18/14 2:18 PM
Divine Simplicity: The
Centerpiece of Aquinas’
Doctrine on God
Jonathan Phillips
Editor’s Note: The following paper draws extensively from an Aristotelian-Thomistic
background, which is a system that is intricately built on itself. Thus, this paper—which
addresses the concept of Divine Simplicity—cannot be properly understood without
first understanding the arguments which precede it in the Summa theologiae. If this
paper were fully to explain the arguments to defend the premises it assumes—various
metaphysical realities, the existence of God, and so forth—it would be far too long to
publish. When possible, the author has provided references to the arguments in favor of
the assumptions he makes in the course of the paper. The interested reader is encouraged
to examine the works of Edward Feser, a prominent contemporary Thomistic scholar. His
book Aquinas: A Beginner’s Guide is an excellent source of information on this matter
and explains this paper’s metaphysical assumptions in a way that is far beyond what is
possible here.
T
he doctrine of divine simplicity is one of the central aspects of St. Thomas
Aquinas’ thought, without which one can easily descend into a philosophically bankrupt form of anthropomorphic theism. It claims that God1 is supremely,
entirely one, and not composed whatsoever of any parts on any metaphysical
level. It is a consequence of the arguments to establish God’s existence, which
demand that he hold a status of priority above all other things and that he have
dependence on nothing else; thus God cannot depend on something else to join
together various parts to make him what he is. As the first mover and first cause
of all things outside himself, God cannot be causally posterior to any other thing,
since that would require God to be affected by that which has no existence and no
action without God’s own power to create and to sustain. This doctrine has several
important consequences, and it will be beneficial to see how it informs Aquinas’
entire conception of the nature of God.
In order to understand this doctrine, we must first understand what it means
to be composed. The fundamental relationship in Thomistic philosophy is that of
61
902980_Text.indd 69
4/18/14 2:18 PM
62
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
actuality and potentiality.2 When we examine anything existing in the world—a
tree, for example—the tree is said to be actually existing, or existing in a state of
completeness as a tree, as opposed to something in the process of becoming a
tree. But in order for the tree to change and to become something else, we must
acknowledge another aspect of being: potentiality. In the case of the tree, the tree
can potentially become a table if it is cut down and used to build one. Thus the
tree is actually a tree and potentially a table in this example. More generally, the
tree is potentially a multitude of things such as whatever a person could make out
of it or whatever into which it could decay by natural processes.
Furthermore, potentiality is not actuality. If a tree is potentially a table, it has
the capacity to change into a table. But if a tree is actually a table, it is already a
table—and not a tree after all. So, if we were to say that potentiality is actuality,
this would mean that having the capacity to change into a table is the same thing
as being a table, which is false. Potentiality is not nonbeing, or otherwise it would
be impossible for the tree which is potentially a table to become actually a table;
this is because if the capacity or potentiality of the tree to become a table does not
exist at all, then the tree cannot become a table as its capacity to do so does not
exist. Potentiality is therefore a middle ground between nonbeing and actuality.
Actuality is a more fundamental mode of being whereas potentiality is a more
contingent mode of being. Actuality refers to things that have real being, while
potentiality refers to the ability to change, the capacity to come into being. Potentiality requires actuality and depends on it in order to exist; potentiality has no
independent actual existence without actuality. Indeed, the demonstration of the
concept of potentiality above presupposes some actual being, the tree, which possesses the potentiality, the tree’s capacity to change into a table.
According to the doctrine of divine simplicity, God is one in all respects. In
other words, God is not a composite of actuality and potentiality. But if we are
going to admit that in God, there is no such joining, then what is there? These two
concepts describe all modes of being that are possible: something either actually exists or it potentially exists. In order to come to a greater understanding of
what divine simplicity is per se, let us understand that Aquinas argues that God is
purely actual, with no potentiality.3 This is because Aquinas argues that the world,
as a contingent, caused, changing thing, necessarily implies the existence of some
source and ground of being, something which is able to give it existence.4
It will be helpful to recall the general metaphysical point underlying the idea
of divine simplicity: that God is the Supreme Being, the ultimate metaphysical
reality and source of all other reality, and not dependent on anything else for his
existence. Now, if something is composed of parts, then, unless those parts are
joined together, the thing does not exist. It would be nonsensical to say, for example, that a table, which is composed of a surface and legs, could exist without the
902980_Text.indd 70
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIVINE SIMPLICITY: THE CENTERPIECE OF AQUINAS’ DOCTRINE IN GOD
63
legs. Since something that does not exist cannot cause itself, as it cannot perform
any operation without first existing,5 the thing would depend on something else to
join those parts together so the composite being could exist. Therefore, all composite beings require some logically prior agent to join together those things of
which the being is composed.6 This means that any composite being cannot be the
source and ground of all existence since the composite being requires a prior cause
to produce the combination that results in the composite; thus if God were composed of actuality and potentiality, he would require some being to exist before
him—either temporally or metaphysically—in order to join his actuality to his
potentiality, or to bring him, as the composite, into being, serving as the source of
his existence. But this is incoherent given Aquinas’ Five Ways; God is the ultimate
source of existence, so the being which is supposedly prior to God would then be
the true God. This true God would need to be simple rather than composite for
the reasons we have just seen.
If we accept the notion that God is simple, then several important things follow. When we speak of God’s goodness, justice, or power, we are referring to the
same thing considered under different aspects; since there are no parts in God,
God does not “have” things like power or goodness. Rather, God is power and
goodness. While this may appear rather counterintuitive, it is important to understand that God’s attributes are not the same as ours—our attributes are particular
and distinct things which are different from each other, but God’s attributes are
the consequences of his possessing in himself the fullness and plenitude of being.
Thus God is completely good because, in a Thomistic metaphysical analysis, being
and goodness are the same,7 and evil is a lack of goodness and therefore of being.
God is omnipotent because he, as the first being and as pure actuality, enjoys being
to the greatest degree and cannot be limited by any privation of being or any lack
of perfection. God’s attributes, therefore, are not distinct, but all refer equally to
the supreme unity which is God.
One particular dilemma that this doctrine is extraordinarily helpful in resolving is that which is presented in the Euthyphro. Is goodness good because God
wills it, or does God will something because it is good? Both seem to be unacceptable; the first would make goodness an arbitrary standard where God could will
anything to be good, and the second would make a standard of goodness apart
from God, so he would depend on this other standard for judgments of right and
wrong. If this were so, God would not be causally independent of all other things.
Divine simplicity allows for a resolution of this problem: goodness is based in the
divine nature, and God’s goodness is inseparable from and identical to God’s will.
As God cannot change his goodness or being, so he cannot change his will for us;
he always wills the good, in such a way that he cannot ever actively will that we
do some action which does not accord with our nature. Thus what God wills for
902980_Text.indd 71
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
64
us regarding morality is not some arbitrary or contingent desire which he could
change at will. Rather, the case is that God must will that our actions accord with
natural law. This is not to say that God is not still the standard for goodness, since
goodness is determined by the final cause or end of something,8 and since God
is the final cause of all creation, he is the ultimate standard and source of goodness without which nothing is good. But simplicity allows for the recognition that
God’s will is immutable and identical to his goodness, so, as Edward Feser writes,
“what is objectively good and what God wills for us as morally obligatory are really the same thing considered under different descriptions, and ... neither could
have been other than they are.”9
I would like now to examine the doctrine of simplicity from a different angle.
The philosopher Fr. Réginald Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P., writes the following regarding Aquinas’ First Way, the argument from motion or change, to demonstrate
God’s existence:
In a series of essentially subordinate movers [a series of causes in which
each depends on the one before it for its continued operation, so each acts
as an instrument rather than on its own and indeed has no capacity for
causation on its own, as a hand moves a stick which moves a rock which
moves a leaf ] we must finally arrive at one which is its own principle of
motion [change], and which can explain the entity [being] of its own action. But that alone can explain the entity of its action, to which the action
belongs intrinsically, not only as a potency [potentiality], but also as an act
[actuality], and which, consequently, is its own very action, its very activity.
Such a mover is absolutely immobile [unchangeable] in the sense that He
has by and of Himself that which the others acquire by motion.10
This explanation is meant to show that God is pure actuality, unchangeable,
and cannot have any mixture of potentiality. Any potentiality is a potentiality for
something, to change into something, and it could be realized as an action or an
activity of changing into something else or producing some change. And no potentiality has a capacity to actualize itself, because potentiality has an intermediate
character between being and nonbeing—the character of potential being—but
anything which causes or performs actions must be actually existing in order to
operate. But, if God is to terminate the regress of change that forms the basis for
the First Way, he must be able to explain his own activity without reference to
some higher source. This is only possible if God’s activity belongs to him as actual,
not as potential. If it were to belong to him as potential, the question would arise:
how does God operate at all, since operation, if it involves motion from potentiality to actuality, would seem to be dependent on some being to move the potentiality to actuality, as no potentiality can actualize itself ? The notion that God moves
himself to actuality will not solve this problem, because if this motion of moving
902980_Text.indd 72
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIVINE SIMPLICITY: THE CENTERPIECE OF AQUINAS’ DOCTRINE IN GOD
65
himself to operate were also a motion from potentiality to actuality, the same
question would arise regarding that motion: does God have it potentially or actually? Then, if it is granted that God has that motion as actual and is identical to it,
then that aspect of God which is identical to this operation would more accurately
constitute God, whereas the other aspects of “God” which are not identical to his
operation would rather be secondary causes through which God acts.
Consider the following explanation. Suppose God performed the action of
creation. Is the action of creation present in God potentially or actually? If it is
present in God actually, then it is clear that God is his own operation. If it is present potentially, then something must have moved God to perform this operation.
This would either be another being, or it would be another operation from God.
It cannot be another being, since God, by the conclusion of the First Way as the
termination of the causal sequence of change, must be causally prior to every other
being. It would then have to be another operation from God, at which point the
same problem arises: is this operation in God potentially or actually? Each operation that is in God potentially raises this same question of how that operation
comes about. In order to explain the existence of any of these operations, then, we
must arrive at some first operation which is in God actually, and which God is.
The other operations which this one explains are extraneous and not truly part of
God himself, but rather are secondary causes on which and through which God
acts. This is because they are logically posterior to the first mover, the true and
real God, who is his operation. And indeed God is identical to all his operation,
because any operation which is not identical to God would be a secondary cause
through which God acts, as described above. Since God must be identical to his
own operation, it follows that there can be no mixture of potentiality in God. Any
potentiality is a potentiality for some operation, but God is actual and is identical
to all his operation, so God’s operation is actual. Therefore, there can be no potential operation in God, so there can be no potentiality at all in God; God is purely
actual.
The importance of divine simplicity in this conclusion is that it allows a statement in the vein of “God is identical to his operation” to be coherent. It is easy to
imagine that one who is not familiar with the overall Thomistic system might understand this to mean that God is some vague impersonal force, but this is not the
case. God is not merely an operation; rather, God is the supreme reality, and since
there are no parts or composed things in him, he is identical to all of his attributes
and operations. This is not a limiting view of God but rather a more expansive
view; it allows God to exist in a mode that safeguards philosophical theology from
anthropomorphism and from attempts to think of God as a sort of superhuman
being, or one powerful person among other people. So, as Fr. Garrigou-Lagrange’s
explanation of the First Way shows, God is his operation, but he is also his will
902980_Text.indd 73
4/18/14 2:18 PM
66
DIANOIA UNDERGRADUATE PHILOSOPHY JOURNAL
and his power and his intellect. His existence is unlimited, depends on nothing
else for its own being, gives existence to all other beings, and so is the foundation
and first cause for all things.
Thus, as we have seen, simplicity is not merely an abstract consideration regarding some esoteric attribute of God; it is the foundation for our understanding
of God, the universe, and moral living. To deny the doctrine of divine simplicity is
to walk dangerously close to an anthropomorphic and empty conception of God
as one being among many beings. The doctrine’s profound implications range from
metaphysics to morality, and it is one of the greatest achievements of Aquinas’
philosophical investigation into the divine nature. It serves as a fitting centerpiece
for the Thomistic philosophical edifice in its highest ascent to the inexhaustible
mystery of God.
1 Aquinas begins in this philosophical section of the Summa theologiae without admitting
any prior knowledge of God. He proceeds through strictly philosophical methods without
making any reference to Christianity or the Bible, or any divine revelation at all. He makes
passing references to other authors, including Biblical ones, but his argument is independent
of these references.
2 These are sometimes referred to as act and potency, both meaning states of being, not actions
or operations.
3 Unfortunately it is out of the scope of this paper to provide argumentation in defense of
Aquinas’ Five Ways to demonstrate God’s existence, but I assure the reader that many defenses exist and they are strong. Please see the editor’s note for more information.
4 As an aside, the question of whether the world came into being at a certain point in time does
not in any way factor into Aquinas’ arguments for God’s existence.
5 See Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, part 1, question 2, article 3, and Aquinas, De ente et
essentia, chapter 4, as well as Feser, Aquinas, chapter 1, mentioned in the editor’s note.
6 For information on why it would be impossible for an infinite series of composite beings to
join more composite beings together further and further down the chain, see the sources
mentioned above in note 5.
7 This complex metaphysical topic is explored in Aquinas, Summa theologiae, part 1, question 5,
articles 1-6.
8 See above in note 7, especially article 4 of that question.
9 Edward Feser, “God, Obligation, and the Euthyphro Dilemma,” October 26, 2010. <http://
edwardfeser.blogspot.com/2010/10/god-obligation-and-euthyphro-dilemma.html>
10 Garrigou-Lagrange, Réginald. God: His Existence and Nature, vol. 1. Trans. Dom Bede Rose.
Mount Angel: B. Herder Book Co., 1955, 266.
902980_Text.indd 74
4/18/14 2:18 PM
DIVINE SIMPLICITY: THE CENTERPIECE OF AQUINAS’ DOCTRINE IN GOD
902980_Text.indd 75
67
4/18/14 2:18 PM
Author Biographies
Alexander Trimes
Alexander Trimes ’14 is majoring in English and minoring in Philosophy.
He spent the fall term of his junior year studying abroad at Queen Mary,
University of London, and hopes to teach English abroad following graduation. His academic interests include literary and cultural theory, as well
as postmodern literature. As a long-term goal, Alexander plans to further
pursue these interests through graduate study.
Francis Adams
Francis Adams ’15 comes from the small town of Dobbs Ferry, NY, and is
currently pursuing a double major in English and Philosophy. His interests
include literature and philosophy of all kinds as well as the various religions of the world. He plans to pursue graduate studies in some capacity,
but hopes to make some money in the “real world” first—doing what, he
has no idea.
Gjergji Evangjeli
Gjergji Evangjeli ’14 is a senior with a concentration in Philosophy and
Classics. He is interested in Ancient Greek philosophy, especially Plato
and the synthesis of Philosophy and Theology evident in authors like St.
Thomas Aquinas. He is curious about the paradigm shifts that have led
to the philosophical and religious disconnect of most modern Westerners with classical philosophy and religion, particularly Christianity. Gjergji
will be pursuing a 5th Year Master’s at BC next year, and is considering a
Ph.D. afterwards.
Anthony Cossette
Anthony Cossette ’14 is majoring in Psychology and minoring in Philosophy. He is the current president of BC’s chapter of Psi Chi, the National
Honor Society in Psychology, and is involved in a number of other extracurricular activities such as playing Alto Saxophone in the Boston College
Pep Band at hockey and basketball games. His intellectual interests range
from Cognitive Psychology and Neuroscience to History, Philosophy of
Mind, Epistemology, Ethics, and Environmental Science. Anthony plans
on taking a year’s sojourn or more from formal schooling to reassess his
goals and hopes to attend graduate school in the near future.
Jonathan Phillips
Jonathan Phillips ’15 is a junior Philosophy major with an interest in medieval philosophy, particularly that of St. Thomas Aquinas, and in the philosophers who have continued writing in the tradition that he began. He is
especially interested in their methods of arguing for the existence of God.
He intends to go to law school after graduating from Boston College.
902980_Text.indd 76
4/18/14 2:18 PM
Download