HD28 .M414 ot^misy no. 3VI ^^ .^.y^Wrt*- ALFRED P. WORKING PAPER SLOAN SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT Un intertemporal rrererences in Uontinuous Time: The Case of Certainty* Ayman Hindy, Chi-fu Huang, and David Kreps March 1991 MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 50 MEMORIAL DRIVE CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS 02139 WP// 3311 On Intertemporal Preferences in Continuous Time: The Case of Certainty* Ayman Hindy, Chi-fu Huang, and David Kreps March 1991 WP# 3311 On Intertemporal Preferences in Continuous Time: The Case Ayman of Certainty* Hindyl Chi-fu Huang* and David Kreps^ March 1991 To appear in Journal of Mathematical Economics Abstract DifTerent topologies on the space of certain consumption patterns in a continuous time setting are discussed. A family of topologies which give an economically reasonable sense of closeness and have an appropriate intertemporal flavor is suggested. The topological duals of our suggested topologies are essentially spaces of Lipschitz contin- uous functions. Any utility functional whose felicity function at any time t depends on the consumption at that time and is not linear in it is not continuous in any one of our topologies. A clciss of utility functionals that are continuous in the suggested topologies and that capture the intuitively appealing notion that consumptions at nearby dates are almost perfect substitutes is provided. We then give necessary and sufficient conditions for a consumption plan to be optimal for this class of utility functionals. We demonstrate our general theory by solving in closed form the optimal explicitly consumption problem for a particular utility function. The optimal solution consists of a (possible) initial "gulp" of consumption, or an initial period of no consumption, followed by consumption at the rate that maintains a constant ratio of wealth to an index of past consumption experience. 'This paper merges results reported in two earlier papers, a paper with the same title by Huang and Kreps and a paper titled "OplimaJ Consumption with Intertemporal Substitution I: The Case of Certainty" by Hindy and Huang. The authors would like to thank Peter Diamond, Darrcll DufTie, Oliver Hart, Hua He, John Heaton, Larry Jones, Andreu Mas-Colell, Scott Richard, Tong-sheng Sun, Jean-luc Vila, Thaleia Zariphopoulou, and the anonymous referees for comments. Itzhak Katznelson told us about Orlicz Spaces. 'Graduate School of Business, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305 'Sloan School of Management, Massachusetts Institutes of Technology, Cambridge, MA 02139 ^Gradu ate School of Business, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305 M.I.T. AUG LIBRARIES 1 5 1991 RK;fj\/Fn Summary Introduction and 1 Introduction and 1 Consider an economic agent 1 Summary who from time lives consumption commodity consumable to time Suppose there 1. any time between zero and one. at We is a single ask the fol- lowing questions: First, how might we represent the agent's consumption pattern over his lifetime? Second, if we A'+ denote the space of possible consumption patterns, what let an appropriate topology on X+; that "closeness" with the appropriate intertemporal flavor and which mathematically? Third, what form is one which gives an economically reasonable sense of is, will equilibrium prices take tinuous linear functional? Fourth, what is agent whose preferences are continuous in is if relatively well-behaved they are given by a con- the optimal consumption-savings behavior of an such a topology? There are '"standard" answers to these questions. Consumption patterns are represented by a function c:[0, 1] — where 3f+, such consumption patterns c{t) u topology. In addition, prices Preferences are represented by U(c) q. the felicity function of the individual and y{t) is consumption is at time t. Two they are close as functions; say, in c(t) are '"close" if some L^ the sup-norm topology or in appropriate value of c{i) represents the rate of and = come from Z', for the f^ u(c{t),y{t)J)dt, some functional where of the consumption rates. ^ A This a generalized version of the Ryder and Heal [1973] preferences analyzed by Magill is typical example is y(t) = y{t) + Jq 0(t,s)c{s)ds for some functions y(t) and 6{t,-). [1981]. We at are dissatisfied with these standard answers. one time should be something of a substitute for Basically we consumption feel that consumption at other, near-by times. Consequently, prices for consumption at close-by times should be approximately the same. These, however, are not the properties of the above standard answers. find answers to the questions of the previous paragraph that and retain, at the will for economic analysis. Readers familiar with the literature on commodity differentiation, Colell [1975] and Jones [1981, 1984] will at this point rightly of signed measures on the weak topology. A thus set out to conform to these intuitions, same time, mathematical properties important questions are readily available in this literature. Take the We example, Mas for think that the answers to our commodity space to be the space equipped with the topology of weak convergence, or simply [0, 1] consumption pattern is represented by a measure on right-continuous increasing function where the value of this function at time cumulative consumption from time as well as gulps are allowed. to time Then t. [0, 1] t or by a denotes the In this representation, continuous injestion as long as the agents' preferences are continuous in the weak topology and satisfy a strong monotonicity property equilibria exist with prices that are continuous functions of time. Preferences continuous in the weak topology treat nearby consumptions as close substitutes and equilibrium prices are continuous functions of time, all one caveat. When functional. the questions A we raised above seem to have been answered!. There merely continuous function the felicity function is is is, however, not, in general, a reasonable representation of a function only of c and (, we have the standard time-additive utility Introduction and 1 Summary 2 consumption and asset prices over time. continuous function can be nowhere differentiable - take, for example, a Brownian A motion sample path. In is fact, most continuous functions are nowhere perhaps not so counter-intuitive when time is question. When prices for consumption should be continuous functions of time. This differentiable. not the characteristic of the commodity in the commodities are indexed by time, our intuition certainly suggests that We also think that more should be true. Prices should not fluctuate over time in a nowhere differentiable fashion.^ In particular, model. we think that interest rates should exist in a reasonable economic intertemporal This condition equivalent to the requirement that prices for consumptions be is This additional requirement absolutely continuous functions of time. commodity results of the We begin in what makes the is differentiation literature unsatisfactory for our purposes. Section 2 with a formulation of the consumption set and consumption space. For the set of feasible consumption patterns, we use the space of positive, increasing, right continuous functions on [0,1], denoted A'+.^ For given x G A'+ and the cumulative consumption from time zero to time t t £ [0,1], x{t) denotes under consumption pattern In x. order to speak of net trades, the space of consumption bundles, or the commodity space, the linear span of A'+. Denoted A', this [0, 1] is is the space of functions of bounded variation on that are right-continuous. The space A' comes equipped with a number of topologies, any of which could conceiv- ably serve our purposes. In order to investigate their suitability, we construct in Section 3 a "wish we list" of properties for a suitable topology. Our wish mind give useful mathematical properties, keeping in do optimization, and conduct equilibrium desirable economic properties. The analysis. discussion here list comes two in that, in the end, we parts. First, will Second, and more important, is want to we list the heart of this paper in terms of economics; essentially, we are giving our intuition concerning when different consumption patterns should be "close". Once we have our wish done in Section 4. We list, we can see how well the standard topologies fare. This is many norm The weak quickly look at the topologies induced by the total variation and the Skorohod topology and show that these two topology has is we of the properties fail rather substantially. desire, and, indeed as we mentioned above, a substantial literature on economies where the commodity space is there the space of signed measures, endowed with this topology; see Mas-Colell [1975] and Jones [1981, 1984]. But, we mentioned above, the weak topology has too large a topological see, lacks a certain uniform property that we find appealing. as We turn instead, in Section will use for 5, to dual, and, as we will a family of norm topologies. For this introduction, we one representative member of this family, given by the norm I G X; the topology induced by this norm is ||ar|| = /q |a-(i)|d<-|-|a:(l)| denoted hereafter by T. We will show ^Prices for consumption will in general fluctuate in a nowhere differentiable fashion in a model with uncertainty due to temporal resolution of uncerttiinty. See, for example, We weak nondecreasing, and so forth. will use relations throughout. Huang [1985]. For example, negative means nonpositive, increasing means forth. If the relation is strict, we will use strictly negative, strictly increasing, and so The Consumption 2 that, Consumption Space Set and on A'+, these norm topologies are 3 weak topology. topologically equivalent to the all However, preferences continuous and uniformly proper, a concept due to MasColell [1986] discussed in section 2, in any of the proposed topologies exibit a trade-off property which we find appealing. This property is essantially that agents tolerate delaying or advancing increasingly larger quantities of consumption for decreasingly shorter periods of time. contrast, preferences continuous and uniformly proper in tolerance for this kind of intertemporal substitution. have all the properties we the weak topology The norm fail In to exhibit we introduce topologies from the point of view of economic intuition and, find desirable in addition, they are mathematically very well behaved. For example, preferences continuous in these topologies In Section 7, admit continuous numerical representations. we turn to the characterization of the topological dual spaces for our In particular, the dual to (A', T), denoted, hereafter, as A'*, topologies. Lipschitz continuous functions. In this section, we also confirm some the space of is desirable mathematical properties of the dual spaces, notably that the duals are vector lattices in the order duals and the order intervals are weakly compact. Section 8 gives necessary and sufficient conditions for a consumption pattern to be optimal for a class of An model. continuous in our topologies utility functions optimal consumption plan in a consumption-savings in genercd will be periodic even if the felicity function has an infinite slope at zero. Whether one should consume at a given time depends on the relation between ones wealth and a weighted average of past consumption. solution for a particular utility function is provided in Section 8.3. Finally, A all closed form proofs are in the appendix. There are three companion papers to this. Mas-Colell and Richard [1991] does the hard work of establishing existence of equilibrium for economics based on our, and other, Hindy and Huang [1990a, 1990b] generalize and extend our analysis to models topologies. where there is uncertainty and temporal resolution of that uncertainty, and they consider some of the standard models the impact of our topology on The Consumption 2 and Consumption Space Set Consider an economic agent who from time zero to time one. This agent can consume lives a consumption commodity at any time during his the agent tive consume only consumption positive is finite. life-time consumption from time zero to time X is if x(<) increasing, limits x{t~) = it is span. It is t. : [0,1] Note that — > 5f, with x{t) denoting the cumulative this representation absolutely continuous and in discrete lumps \ims-\tx(s) and xif^) avoid complications, is we natural to require that consumption pattern can be represented by a = permits consumption if a:{<) is has the following two properties. First, for each possible kind of discontinuity To life amounts of the consumption good, and that the cumula- Thus a positive increasing real-valued function x at "rates" theory of finance. in the lim,|tx(5) exist and are t 6 discontinuous. [0, 1], finite. As both unilateral Second, the only a jump. shall further assume that x is right-continuous: lim^if x{s) — 2 x{t), for all That 6 [0,1). t Consumption Space Set and The Consumption is, if the agent consumes a nontrivial stocl< consumption commodity during the time at time To sum t.* we up, 4 he in fact interval (t~ ,1"^), The set [0, 1]. of such functions denoted by X+. Throughout the paper, Xr is, of the consumes x{t'^) — x{t~) will represent the agent's life-time consumption pattern by a positive increasing right-continuous real-valued function x on is amount for r G [0,1] will denote the indicator function of Xr represents a unit gulp of consumption at time That [r, 1]. Also, scalars will be denoted by r. a,b,... Let X denote the linear span of X+, which functions of bounded variation defined on X in the usual way: xi refer to is a X > 12 if x^ We Our agent X+ = will (x - j/)"*" + y, xi if use x+ > x(0) X2 if 0, > and > on induces orders xi - 0:2 G -Y+ consumption We \ {0}. set. will Note that A' to denote the positive (increasing) = then x+(0) x(0). Then we can with inf(x,j/) defined similarly. be assumed to have preferences over a complete and transitive binary relation >: preferences are increasing: Vxi,X2 G A'+, xi the direction of xq: Vx G A'+ and Va special role played by xo here. > X+ as the agent's X, we also use the convention that define sup(x,2/) the space of right continuous real- valued The cone X+, and to For x G lattice, in the usual fashion. [0,1]. X2 £ commodity space and as the part of X. - is It the direction of which preference > 0, would is x on X+. A'+ We that are given mathematically by will assume throughout that these + x^ >: ^i; that they are strictly increasing in + axo >- x. The reader may be put off by the suffice to assume that there is some x G X+ \ {0} always strictly increasing, although condition and our uniform properness assumption, to be discussed shortly, in below (c) would need to be modified accordingly. For the analysis of Mas-Colell and Richard [1991], one would wish to use the social endowment Moreover, we the topology T in place of xo- will assume that there relativized to X+. is given a linear topology T on A'; with T"^ denoting Preferences are assumed to be continuous in uniformly proper with respect to T. Continuity of preferences standard and needs no justification. in a fixed topology Uniform properness, on the other hand, standard. This condition, introduced by Mas-Colell [1986], is The merely recall his definition: 1 (Mas Colell) Preferences respect to a linear topology if we will X+, v £ V , = will and a T-open neighborhood and scalar a > 0, x - ax' + av assume that preferences are uniformly proper with respect to particular choice of x* we A'+ are said to be uniformly proper with there exists a vector x' G A'4. of the origin such that, for every x G In fact, T '^ x. for the xo-^ V/ < 0. We will continue to use *Here we have used the convention that x{t) = i(l) V< > 1 and i{t) = throughout, so that the value of any i € A' for arguments greater than one or less than zero always well defined. *As we mentioned earlier, our use of xo in this special role is purely to ease exposition. Any x' g X+ this convention is T y on fairly not so commodity reader should consult Mas-Colell [1986] for further commentary. Here, space. V is is and shown there to be intimately related to the existence of equilibria for economies with an infinite dimensional Definition T"*" A Wish 3 A 3 List for Wish 5 r List for What properties do First, we want T T we want for the topology T? The to be well behaved of desiderata list mathematically. Ideally, T comes two parts. in should be a locally convex, metric topology, and A' should be complete and separable under this metric. we wish to invoke uniform properness wish for T and undertake optimization for Also, since our agents, we will In order to apply the equilibrium existence results of to be a linear topology. Mas-Colell [1986], one would wish that the lattice operations are continuous with respect to T, or (even) that {A',A'+,T) forms a much too hope to Banach when we come upon economic for, and Richard [1991] allow us to weaken But lattice. this, as it will considerations. Happily, Mas-Colell desideratum substantially: this turn out, will be We want the will order intervals to be weakly compact and the topological dual to be a vector lattice in the order dual.^ The second and more substantial part of our wish list concerns the economics of the situation. Our intuition suggests that certain consumption streams ought to be close, and we will look for a topology on A' that accomodates this intuition. Consider the following requirements, phrased in terms of properties of y. Two (a) patterns of consumption that have almost equal cumulative consumption at every point in time should be close. h Xn y for all n implies x y We t. = The idea of this metric X any other path y that e up and to the point {t,x{t)). Hence X is within With (b) this If e To do so, the Prohorov metric. For x and y in p{x, y) moving n implies y if is inf{f > x(< : + e) depicted in Figure lives entirely left and down y within is e y consumption of a in also regarded as insignificant. known metric on A^, is for all sup(g[o,i] \xn{t) - x{t)\ = + 1; e > the y{t) > 0, then x.' consumption between i„ and x must be small wish to weaken this so that shifts amounts of time are limn^oo if and y y Xn y, In (a), differences in cumulative time Formally, at every fixed size across small we begin by introducing a well A.)., let -()-(}. x(t neighborhood of a consumption path e within a "sleeve" around x that is determined by and to the right (c in each direction) from x at every of x, then at every time of the total consumption under y at t, the total consumption under some time no more than f away from t. we can pose our second requirement: p(xn,x) implies y ^ y as n — < GO, then Xn y y for all n implies x y y, and y y Xn for all n x.^ 1*^0 could be used instead. ^For the definition of a vector lattice and the order dual, see Schaefer (1974). ^The astute reader will notice that this rules out the standard model where felicity of consumption rates, unless felicity reader will also note that (a) is linear. We will could be said more compactly demonstrate as: T utility is the integral of this explicitly in section 6. The relativized to .\'+, denoted T'^ should be no stronger than the sup norm topology relativized to A'+. *Or: T'*' should be no stronger than the weak topology on A'+ generated by the space of continuous functions on [0, 1]. A Wish 3 Our T List for 6 economic consideration sharpens (b) somewhat. The idea final amount shift of a given great consequence in terms of preference. Suppose that increasingly larger may amount of consumption across a small in (b) is that the of time should not be of we imagine instead the shift of an amount of consumption over a decreasingly smaller period of time. It help to give a concrete example: Consider comparing the consumption patterns anXi/2 and anX(n+i)/2ni where a„ is a strictly positive scalar. As n goes to infinity, the shift in time grows small (and so, in particular, p(anXi/2i«nX(n+i)/2n) ~^ 0)i but if a„ grows with n, the amount for a„ to shifted go to grows large. wish to assert that, a priori, enough so that the difference infinity slowly To be more negligible uniformly. We precise, it should be possible terms of preference becomes in we know, by the presumed strict monotonicity of Xo that Xo + anXi/2 ^ a„Xi/2- ^^ wish to assert that the "added utility" from \o eventually compensates for the shift of On from 1/2 to {n + l)/2n, if a„ goes to infinity sufficiently slowly. For example, we might insist that, if a„ is o{n) (i.e., an/n -* 0), >- in the direction then the growth in a„ order to come relative to the growth in the Or we might slow enough. is require that a„ is o{n^'^), or o(lnn), in to the desired conclusion that the shift in consumption through time amount amount of consumption shifted. But there shifted such that, if some is the shift in time is is small "sufficiently slow" rate of small, the change in utility is small. To measure what is meant by a "sufficiently slow" rate of are given a concave, continuous, strictly increasing function /i(0) p{z) = = and \n{z + — fJ,{n) 1). By a-nlp{n) —* 0, or On we = oo as n — /i growth, we suppose that we : [0,oo) For examples, think of n(z) oo. ^ = [0,oo), such that z^^^ for p > "slow growth" of a sequence of numbers a„ relative to p o{p{n)). Note that linear growth is 1, or meant the fastest "slow growth" that is are willing to contemplate, since p must be concave. In general, we pose the following condition. (c) For fixed and as above, {j/„(l)} are Xn n, p + Xoy if {xn) and {y„} are two sequences of claims with both o{p{n)), and (ii) p{yn^Xn) < l/n, then for all (i) {x„(l)} sufficiently large Vn- Note that the condition depends on the when p{z) = We fixed p. It becomes stronger the faster p grows, p is given uniformly for all agents in the economy; it enters as part of the data of the economy under consideration. But we do not wish to prespecify what rate p is "slow enough." We only suppose that some "slow so it is strongest enough" rate can be specified z. in are imagining that a particular economic application.^ 'it has been said to us that this condition is not very natural - how would one discover what is the appropriate function p for a given population of consumers? We suggest the following. First, for a given consumption path i, let N,{x) denote the set of x' G A'+ that are within f of i in the Prohorov metric. We suggest that a natural property for consumer preferences I "delayed and lowered by Nt(x) is sleeve drawn around is That is, in is: For each i € terms of figure 1, X+, the >;-worst element of the worst consumption pattern in the one admits to this structural at the end of section 6, if added to that representation), then we can ask of a given consumer: Take any path x would be the lower-right boundary of the sleeve. property (which, we observe, some impatience f". will hold for the sort of representation If we suggest Three Candidate Topologies 4 7 Three Candidate Topologies 4 Several topologies on the space of functions of bounded variation have been extensively analyzed by mathematicians. In this section, we ask how each of these do wish terms of our in list. For the space of functions of bounded variation, a mathematically natural norm For x £ A', the total variation of x, denoted by TV(a;), variation: /J |di(<)lvariation (The L^ norm on consumption rates in norm on cumulative consumption.) Note well that we topological vector lattice with A'+ the positive cone,^° then norm at least as strong as the total variation topology. well mathematically, aside from lack of separability, economic wish Xn given by (a), In the first place, (a) list. = k/n a;„(<) for e {(k / we should have x„ converging norm. In the same way (b) is if - l)/n,k/n] and x to x, but (of + need to have a topology will But while performs this topology in terms of our consumption patterns = given by x(t) course) we do |3-(0)| to have A' be a performs miserably it total just the total is we hope violated: Consider the is TV(x) = is the standard models is According to t. not, in the total variation when the underlying time space is a have the sort of economic qualities we desire. violated. Total variation, continuum, measures time much too finely to Consider next the Skorohod metric originally introduced on the space of functions which are right-continuous and have finite Let A denote the class of = A e A, then A(0) strictly increasing, and A(a) = strictly positive scalars ( for and sup^gfQ that (A', \x{X{t)) ji - y(t)\ (RCLL). This metric left limits For x,y e 1. continuous mappings of X, which there exists < (. It is defined as follows:'^ define S{x,y) to be the in A : X X X —^ R+ itself. If infimum of those a A such that supj^rg can be shown that S onto [0, 1] ij |A(<) — t\ < e a metric, and is a separable metric space. 5") is Moreover, this metric does possess some of the economic qualities that we desire. Since two consumption patterns that are metric, (a) we define i„(0 = by !„(<) = a:„ 1 Unhappily, (b) satisfied. is for > < (n close in the sup + for / < 1/2, is not In particular, difference x«„ it =J> t G [1/2, (n The Skorohod topology Xt does not approach zero. frequently used on A' We is still — is + l)/2n], and also not very well Xt in this topology = k. if <„ — /, their continue our search. the topology of weak convergence denoted by denoting convergence in this topology. Let C[0, X € A'+ with z{a) for if (so (b) should apply), but Xn does l)/2n, then p(x„,Xi/2) -^ not a linear topology. Whereas Xt„ One other topology %,, with note, in this regard, that comes to exploiting the linear structure of the space of consumption claims. it is — are close under the Skorohod We i„(0 = 2n{t - 1/2) not approach Xi/2 in the Skorohod topology. behaved when norm satisfied. 1] be the space of continuous Suppose you possess this path. What is the most you are willing to have this path Now what path x if in compensation we give you an additional xo up front? "delayed and lowered" by, minimizes this amount, over all paths with z(a) = it? (For preferences with representations as at the end of 6, this optimization problem is tractible.) Finally, how does this amount change as k increases? The section answer to this question, of course, gives us /i. '"which we would want if we were to rely on the existence result of Mas Colell [1986] "a good reference is Billingsley (1968, p???). A 5 Family of Norm Then x^ functions on [0,1]. /eC[0,l] x if and only => if -* Jq_ f(t)dx(t) for Jq_ f(t)dxa(t) all 12.13 Recall that the separable 8 Topologies weak topology Holmes (cf. is a linear, Hausdorff, locally convex topology. [1975, exercise 22c]). It is It is metrizable on A'+ by precisely the Prohorov metric (hence has a countable neighborhood base and sequential), but is it is not metrizable on X. point of view of economic desiderata, the From the Preferences continuous in the weak topology on X+ weak topology obey (a) and will quite an attractive candidate, except for being non-metrizable on all is well behaved: (b). Altogether, of A'. It it is has the further virtue of having been thoroughly analyzed in the economics literature, e.g., in Mas-Colell and Jones [1981, [1975] 1984]. Preferences that are continuous and uniformly proper in the weak topology need not be behaved well terms of in Fix some preferences: (RecjJl that /i(oo) That A is, = /z, oo any fixed function ^, however. This is and consider the continuous function f{t) = (c), for is assumed.) Define linear preferences by x preferences are given by evaluating consumption fortiori, y = a:„ is \/Ji{n)Xo and = j fd{Xn + Xo) Roughly put, "shadow ?/„ = l quite an impact, if + prices" for that amount = — 0. shadow ^J^)< j fdyn A consumption amount We is is still at times just after we norm C[0, rise very quickly. shift is should become negligible, but we have picked around zero quickly enough so that the prespecified Norm Topologies too strong along the time dimension. 1] time zero too much.^'' '^Integrals here are defined from '"'if strictly of consumption from time zero to time \/n has have discussed three possible topological structures on total variation is increases quickly enough. Condition (c) holds that there prices (given by /) to rise Family of it = ^fiy)il + 2y/lU^)). that the slow-enough-increase must be prespecified, and slow-enough-increase 5 j fdx > f fdy. by /. plans at the "prices" given But, for every n, a slow enough increase in the amount shifted so that the is 1. \/^4")Xi/n- Note that x^ and yn qualify in terms of l/x//x(n) a result, shifting an increasing the point of (c) i( + strictly positive. (c). In particular, Xn(a)/fi{n) As y 2y/l/n{l/t) continuous and uniformly proper in the weak topology, and is increasing because / Consider y so even for linear 0- to 1, A'. The Skorohod topology does so that /(O)i(O) enters as a bv the sup norm, then the weak topology The topology generated by is better, term in the integral. weak* topology of A' generated first just the byC[0,l]. '*For any continuous function /, and for preferences defined from / as in the example, we can find a rate ^l that grows slowly enough so that (c) would be satisfied for these preferences and for /i. Thus the order of quantifiers in (c) is all important - /i must be picked first, and then, what we have shown, there function are "nice" for this ft. (i.e., linear) preferences continuous and uniformly proper in the weak topology that violate (c) A 5 but Norm Family of violates (b) it 9 Topologies and is The topology not linear. of weak convergence except that preferences continuous and uniformly proper we In this section, (c). will norm introduce a family of in is quite suitable, weak topology may the violate topologies which will be free of all these defects. To do this, the Musielak [1983] is reader must be introduced to the notion of an Orlicz space, for which an accessible reference. To make this paper close to self-contained, we give a very quick introduction here, adequate for, To begin, consider the case where the that we defined the following norm on X: and told terms of our particular application. in = function n{z) z^'^, for some p > Imagine 1. i/p = Mv Since our functions x are all of From standard Banach space logical linear space. It is I + \x{t)\Ut \x{\)\^ Jo bounded theory, variation, it is clear that all these integrals exist. it is clear that (A', worth noting, perhaps, that X || a separable normed topo- ||p) is be complete will not in this norm: Consider, for example, the sequence of right-continuous, bounded variation functions i„ that are indicator functions of [l/2n, l/(2n - U [l/(2n - 1)) 2), l/{2n - 3)) U ... U [1/2, 1]. These are Cauchy and converge to the obvious measurable function, but what they converge to has unbounded variation and is not right-continuous. A'+, however, This norm has the right "flavor" for • II in lip (c) as well, for the case /i(z) is = complete. Roughly put, z^/p. trades off differences in consumption paths in time and in amounts, where differences amounts are scaled by being consumption paths then the difference What, circle in then, do 0(1 /n) is in the power p. time dimension and Hence if the difference in two o{'n}l^) in the space dimension, small.*^ is we do X, denoted raised to the if /i(z) is not of the form 2^/p? For /x define rj = /x"^ and the unit C,,, as C„ = {xe X : C v{Ht)\)dt + 7?(|x(l)|) = 1}. Jo The convexity measuring all of r/ ensures that this unit circle is appropriately shaped to be a "gauge" for other vectors x: Define, for x other than i positive scalar a that satisfies ||a:||,, is xja G C,,. It well defined. Moreover, for /x(z) definition of the norm. With Proposition {X,\\ 1 [[,,) is operations defined in Section = = 0, ||x||^ to be the unique strictly takes a proof, but because of the continuity of z^l^, this definition is r/, equivalent to the standard this definition: a separable 2, normed topological linear space. With the order order intervals are weakly compact in each of these topolo- gies. We omit the proof for the first assertion of this proposition as of the theory of Orlicz spaces; see Musielak [1983, theorem a proof of the second assertion. ''See Proposition 4 for an exact statement. 1.5]. it is a simple application In the appendix, we provide A 5 Family of Norm 10 Topologies Note that a countable dense set of (A', • || ||^) the set of piecewise linear functions that is change their values at rational time points and have rational right-hand derivatives. These Thus the space functions are absolutely continuous. dense (AM| in norm the ||r,) ||,, Fixing n and the corresponding the we topology relativized to A'+ Tjj the topology induced by 77, denoted by 7^, and is ||^ || denoted by T^+. For the special case where n{z) is = z^l^, use notation such as Tp. The following basic results are established in the appendix. Proposition 2 For any is is by consumption at rates. • || of absolutely continuous functions - any consumption pattern can be approximated arbitrarily closely in /i and corresponding weaker than both the Skorohod and rj, T\ is no stronger than which in turn Tj,, total variation topologies. The first part of this proposition is fairly more than linearly, large differences in intuitive. Since 7; is convex, Note that, the dimension of space. topologies, the lattice operations are most definitely not continuous topological vector lattice. For example, Xi/2-X(n+i)/2n ~ tends to accentuate, it and (A', in our norm 7^) is not a 0- but the corresponding positive parts (or negative parts, or absolute values) do not converge. We will be looking complete, transitive, continuous 7^, for some on A'+ that are given by a binary relation y that for preferences prespecified We tf. T^ the in will topology, and uniformly proper with respect to continue to assume that y increasing as before. is following results establish that we Proposition 3 Preferences that are continuous with respect to Moreover, Xj^ is >: separable under preference relation y T^ , T^ satisfy (a) and hence every continuous (complete and omitted. and (h). transitive) on A'+ admits a continuous numerical representation. ately implies the satisfaction of (a). is The are looking for the "right" thing given our desiderata. Satisfaction of (b) follows as a simple corollary to Proposition 5, which in turn proof is The The separability of A'+ follows standard lines existence of a numerical representation is immedi- and the standard given continuity and separability - see, for example, Fishburn [1970]. Proposition 4 Fix ing as above, fi and the corresponding and 7^ uniformly proper rj. Suppose that y is for the specific choice x' T^ continuous, = \o. Then y increassatisfies (c). In the appendix, in Tr,. Thus for we prove one technical any neighborhood V — x„ = y„ must not stand This leaves open one on X+? It is with respect to 7^ But: is + a:„, in the relation issue: clear from the x„ and of the origin, the definition of uniform properness to xo j/„ fact: If How do y ?/„ - Xn j/„ are as in (c), then is -|- the topologies Xn- T^ ^ eventually inside V. Apply to conclude that, eventually, Xo to \o y^- x^ That does + a;„ - Xo + it. compare with the weak topology example of Section 4 and Proposition 4 that uniform properness stronger than uniform properness with respect to the weak topology. 1 6 On the Standard Models and the 7^ Topologies Proposition 5 For any ft and T^ rj, is 1 weak topology on topologically equivalent to the X+. Hence we reaffirm (the obvious): Uniform properness is not just a topological property on X^. On C the Standard Models and the 7^ Topologies The standard models of preferences for consumption through time assume that preferences are defined over consumption in rates and are given by a numerical representation of either the time-additive form U{x)= [ u{x'{t),t)dt, Jo or the non-time-additive form U(x)= where x' of The x'. denotes the first f\ix'{t),y{t)j)dt, (1) derivative of cumulative consumption x, and y is some functional The non-time-additive form [1973] by Magill [1981], who used time-additive form needs no further explanation. Ryder and Heal includes, for example, a generalization of = yit)+ I yit) 9{t,s)x'{s)ds, Jo for some real-valued functions y and 6, and a special case of Magill [1981], the so-called habit-formation model, recently analyzed by Constantinides [1990] and Sundaresan [1989] when 0{t,s) = e~^*'~'' for all 5 < < and zero elsewhere. Preferences so given are not defined for consumption other than at rates (where x is not absolutely continuous), but we might consider the following procedure for extending preferences to general x: Find a sequence of absolutely continuous Xn that approximate x, and then define U{x) = lim„_oo U{Xn), hoping that the limit of the approximating sequence a:„. We will it is well defined want preferences to be sense of approximation had better be no weaker than remarked that is T^ T^ continuous, so the convergence - and we have already possible to approximate arbitrarily closely, in terms of by absolutely continuous x„. Hence and independent T^ , any x G A'+ program does have some hope of working. this It will only work, though, in very special cases: Proposition 6 Suppose that preferences on A'+ are represented by f/(i)= f\{x'{t),yit),t)dt the utility function (2) Jo for some (jointly) continuous function u, for X, all absolutely continuous consumption paths where y{t) = yit)+ / Jt-ki{t) 0ii,s)dx{t-s) (3) 12 7 Duality for some continuous function y, preferences are continuous in any (for T^ point of this explicitly is that = and + a(y,t)z (i(y,t), is is x'. If these where a and every point felicity at /? are that converge in 7^ to a;„ Indeed, ar„ converges to x in time depends in in the literature), not continuous. In the proof of the above proposition, not linear in 0. t. when the marginal a sequence of consumption patterns and consumption paths on the consumption rate at that time (a case of great interest the utility function u{x',y,t) ki, k2, relativized to absolutely continuous , then u must have the form u{z,y,t) t]), jointly continuous functions of y The and nontrivial continuous functions we constructed while t/(i„) /* U{x) a: norm the sup if topology, so any treatment of preferences for consumption through time that asked for property (a) would not admit the standard models felicity at is any time is in the literature. The reason should be clear: Unless marginal independent of the consumption rate at that time, consuming steadily not well approximated in the standard models by consumption at quickly varying rates. Yet the cumulative consumption paths of such patterns, and thus the corresponding be made close What in sort of [1984, p. 525], y, can the sup norm. model might then be used to replace the standard model? Following Jones we make the that the marginal felicity be one where the is following proposal: too sensitive to felicity at time t is The problem with the standard models is current consumption. A more apt model would derived only from a functional of the recent past consumption and possibly the nearby future consumption; and the current consumption contributes to the current felicity only through this functional. Proposition 7 Let u{z,t) and continuosly be jointly continuous differentiable in its first argument. Then W(x)= / u{y{t),t)dt Jo for all X+, X e and k^ such from zero, is continuous in that either k\ is and some The form T^ , where y(t) a constant or ki is is defined in (3) for differentiable function 9, with bounded derivative. given in the above proposition does indicate the sort of "intertemporal substi- tution of consumption at near-by times" that motivated this study. for this 7 form to represent uniform proper preferences Other conditions, which we leave zero. some functions ki bounded away differentiable with derivative is for y{t) to for interested readers, One sufficient condition be bounded away from can also be generated,. Duality For the duration of this section, we assume that some pair /x and 77 as in Section 5 has been fixed. Mas-Colell and Richard [1991] tells us that it will be possible to establish existence of equilibrium in economies where preferences are increasing and uniformly proper in our 7 13 Duality topology we can if establish that the topological dual forms a vector lattice in the order drawn from the order dual. Moreover, equilibrium prices for these equilibria will be Hence our aim in this section is to characterize the topological dual space of (A", 7^), which we denote by A'^, and to verify that A'^ does form a vector lattice in the More important, we will show that A'* is composed of absolutely continuous marks the topological time. This As a consequence, X^ is 7^, the whole of A', %, order dual. functions of and the weak topology. Although is weaker than the weak topology. a proper subset of the space of continuous functions and does not contain any function that Our between distinction X+, on topologically identical on dual. not absolutely continuous. is analysis here will be simple applications of the duality results developed in Musielak However, the reader should note that A' [1983, section 13] for Orlicz spaces. subspace of an Orlicz space, and thus A'^ is a much is a proper smaller space than the topological dual of an Orlicz space. Before proceeding, a definition Definition 2 an is t] N -function is if = lim = supfrs — T)*(s) Theorem and only Let 1 if t] be an r](r) N and : r = lim ztoo Z ziO Putting in order. > 0], tj* function and the conjugate function oft]. is <^ oo. Z A" : — » 3? a linear functional. an absolutely continuous function f on there exists (l)(x) = [ f{t)dx{t) Vi 6 [0, 1] Then <j> E. X^ if so that A', JOwith f £ L^ , where Z"* = {y: f' V'illvimdt v'il\y{t)\) -- + as j ^ 0+}, Jo and T]' is the conjugate ofr]. In addition, in the above representation, functional Thus, if if and only f T/ is a positive linear positive. is satisfy derivatives. A'* contains functions include ri(z) = \\y\\r,' all < oo. Since Lipschitz continuous functions the Lipschitz continuous functions. z^ with p > continuous functions whose derivatives if is an TV function. A"* can be identified with absolutely continuous functions whose derivatives y Now what 4> r] is 1. In these cases. A'* lie in L' with asymptotically linear and thus course the linear case show immediately that r]{z) = \z\. Arguments is - + - = have bounded Note that examples of is 1. not an TV function? This includes of identical to those used to prove in the linear case AT* is N composed of absolutely Theorem 1 the space of absolutely continuous function with bounded derivatives - exactly the space of Lipschitz continuous functions. For t? that is 14 Optimization 8 asymptotically linear, one quickly shows that 7^ The the space of Lipschitz continuous function. is Thus equivalent to T\. following theorem, whose proof A'^ is is also omitted, records this fact. Theorem 2 Let be asymptotically linear in that 7/ lim z—>oo for some Then scalar a. G A'^ 4> if (f>{x) ^ and only = = a > 0, z f if f{t)dx{t) X £X Jofor some Lipschitz continuous function f . In addition, (j) is and only positive if if is f positive. Given that any it is 77 must be asymptotically for all 77. Note that and limj^oo vi^) = 00, if 7? is not an N function, Thus Theorems 1 and 2 have completely characterized X^ convex with linear. 77(0) = equilibrium prices for consumption are representated by an absolutely if continuous function of time, f{t), the interest rate exists for almost -f'{t)/f(t) at time The all t and is equal to t. following proposition shows that Proposition 8 For any the space rj, X^ X* is is a lattice in the order dual. a lattice in the order dual. Optimization 8 we formulate In this section the optimal consumption problem for an agent whose prefer- ences are continuous in our topologies. This agent also has a preference for final wealth. Formally, the agent's preferences on A'+ x S?+ are represented by the functional f\iy{t),t)dt + V{w{l+)), Jo where y{t) = 2/(0-)e-^' + /' 6-^('-')dx(0 (4) Jo- > and at time 1. The function u satisfies the conditions of Proposition 7 and in its first argument, and with y{0~) > 0,and where V w{l'^) denotes the agent's wealth after consumption continuous, strictly concave, and increasing. an exponentially weighted average of past consumption and of general y's defined in (3). Higher values of consumption and The w{0). single less t, /? is strictly concave Note that y is a special case of the family imply higher emphasis on the recent past emphasis on the distant past consumption. consumption good At any time is is the numeraire and the agent starts at time with wealth he allocates his wealth, w(t), between consumption and investment in , , Optimization 8 a 15 with instantaneous rate of return rislcless asset any consumption pattern We sup / 6A'+ xex ^0 Note that w(i) A straint. a is . a continuous function of time. For r{t), denote the times of jumps of i. + V(w(l'^)) dw{t) - w{t)r{t)dt w{t^) = i£;(r,) w{t) > 0, - will dx(t) fort G - Ai(r,) = f3[dx(t) y(n) = y(T^ - + ) y{t)dt] /3Ax(r,) r,+i) (t,, for all t forallr,-, for dy{t) hrt G G t (5) [0,1], (7-,,r,+i) for alH forallr,. continuous function and (5) left clear that at is u{y(t),t)dt consumption pattern x G A'+ that wealth w{0) It is policy . investigate the optimal consumption decision of the agent: s.t. initial x, Ti,T2,. is just the intertemporal budget con- satisfies the budget constraint (5) with the simply called budget feasibie. any time t, given u;(i) and y(t~), the subsequent optimal consumption independent of past decisions. Thus, {w{t),y{t~)) are, using the terminology of dynamic programming, the "state variables" for the above dynamic choice problem. thus define the "indirect utility function" or the "value function" J{w(t),y(t~ supremand of the agent's optimization program starting from w and dynamics of t ),t) as We the given {w{t),y{t~)) and the y described in (5) and (6). Heuristic Derivation of Necessary Conditions 8.1 We now use heuristic arguments to derive a set of necessary conditions for a consumption pattern x to be optimal.^^ These conditions will imply that an optimal consumption pattern can have gulps only at The reader approach = 0. After = t 0, consumption occurs only when pjy — will see that the following derivations deviate Jw somewhat from the standard dynamic programming. This occurs because consumption other than in feasible, and, is < more important, the standard Bellman's equation will at rates be linear in the "control" and hence the standard arguments are unapplicable. Suppose x' is be (w'{t), y'{t~ in w w and and (a) all y. an optimal consumption pattern, and for )) G t [0, 1]. Assume the corresponding state variables J is finite and differentiable Let Juj{w,y,t) and Jy{w,y,t) denote the partial derivatives of J with respect to y, respectively. Along the optimal solution, J should Bellman Optimality Principle times let that the value function < < < r < : The Bellman optimality principle'^ implies that for 1 J{w'{t),y'{t-),t) = j\iy'{s),s)ds + Jiw-iT),y'{T-),T). '*These heuristic arguments can be made formal. The reader '^See, for example, satisfy the following conditions: Fleming and Rishel [1975, p.??]. is (7) refered to Blaquiere [1985] for details. Optimization 8 Form this, 16 immediate that J{w'{t),y'(t~ it is times of the jumps of x'. This is so as the ),t) is jumps of x* contribute only through their contribution to y' and at the jump to the integral of a continuous function of time even at moment to the agent's satisfaction jump of a the contribution of the felicities is zero. For brevity of notation, we will use J(t) to denote J(w'{t),y'(t~),t) and similarly use w Jw{t) and Jy{t) to denote the partial derivatives oi J{t) with respect to (b) Continuous Marginal Value of rates, the marginal value of r' + Ai y Along the optimal : 6 < y, respectively. policy, given the interest must be equal to the marginal [0, 1) , '^'^' value of eeJ> in . w and units of wealth at time € and units of wealth at time " x' will be called for to change w' and y'. t + At That A< > for small is, or else some changes we must have JAt)^ = 7^(< + AOfer^'^(^)'^\ Letting At Along the same thus Jw{t) is Similarly, at t we 0, [ Thus Jw{t) must be right-continuous on we show that Jwit) must be left-continuous on (0, arguments, get Ju,(t) line of continuous on must be equal to its — -|- is (c) » ' implies, as <• f if increase in y(t~) felicity function on {t,t + + Jy{t + Uy{y'{s),s)ee-^^'-'+^'Us -f At] and to At)€e-^^'. (9) [0,1). The Jy{t)€e-^^^ (10) 0, that : By the hypothesis that _ y'(t) is r(t) is continuous in continuous on some time interval ^^ in {t — At, ' uyiy t -\- A/), then, as At — (t),t). a time interval over which x' has no "gulps", (9) implies, as At ^dAll = -Uy(y'{t),t) + 0y{t). 'We t, (8) - and Hence, left- 0. dJJt) Next note that and is,^* Uy{y'is),s)ee-f^^'-'1ds Dynamics of Marginal Values At — 1] established by noting that Jy{t-At)e= At — At. That ( we conclude that Jy{t) must be right-continuous on 0, continuity o{ Jy{t) letting principle, a marginal value of marginal contribution to the / [0,1). [0, 1]. Jy(t)e=r and Ju,(<"'"). by the Bellman optimality the value function at time Letting At = (8) use Uy(y,t) to denote the partial derivative of « with respect to y. — 0, that • 0, . Optimization 8 17 Also note that at = < Times (d) Appropriate an interval (r,, t-,+i ) Jw(a) = V'{w(a)) and Jy(a) = 1, "Gulps" for when our : 0. Applying Bellman's optimality principle solution prescribes consumption at rates, in (7) on we get the following for alK G (r.,r,+i) Bellman's equation: m^ix{u{y'{t),t) + lw[r{t)w'{t)-x'{t)] + lyf3[x'{t)-y'{t)] + Jt} = (11) Note that the Bellman equation sumption rate that = i'(0 6[0,oo] x'it) The Bellman equation, for (r some — e,r e + > 0. = oo when l^{t) - > , when J^,(t) - 0Jy{t) = , when 7^{t) - 0Jy[i) By 0. PJyi''') < 0. . - PJyii) continuity, Jw{t) be negative on {t will Hence our candidate policy should prescribe a jump moment l3Jy(T) = on r, when at r - (,t for all points Since this cannot happen as there can only be a countable e). - < Suppose that we prescribe a "gulp" our policy might prescribe a "gulp" only at a that 7u;(r) f3ly{t) therefore, suggests that a "gulp" of consumption might be prescribed any moment r when JwiT) - Jw(t) - f3Jy(T) < Hence, the con- x'{t). satisfies (11) is given by: x'{t) at consumption rate linear in the is number + e) t G of jumps, this particular interval, such 0. at No "Gulps" after = time r > 0. Note that by at any one moment. This, together with the continuity of the marginal values of (e) t Now : suppose that our policy right continuity of x', a "gulp" of size calls for A we cannot have two successive jumps w and y, are differentiable functions of time, this implies that Jw{t) — implies that there are two strictly positive numbers fi,f2 such that: JUi)-0Jy{t)>O 7w{t)-0yit) = when O PJy{t) is decreasing just to the left t on Jw{t)-fiJyit)>0 Assuming that J\v and Jy (r-ei,r), on = T, (r,r + €2). of r and increasing just to the right of r. This condition, however, cannot hold for any size of jump A. i,From the dynamics of Jw and Jy, we get that: |[7.(r+) But by strict /?7,(r+ )] - j^yUr) - PJyir)] = concavity of the felicity (3[uy{y'{T) + /3A,r) - «,(j/-(r),r)] function in y, this last quantity is . (12) negative. Hence, if di[Jw — /3</y] were negative just before the jump, it would be strictly negative just after the jump, thus violating the condition that Jw - 0Jy be increasing just after a "gulp". Note that our analysis possibly at < = is not valid for and i = I. A < = gulp at and t = 1, / = 1, thus x' does not have any gulps, except however, cannot derive any consumption satisfaction from it is clearly sub-optimal since the agent and the final wealth is aJso reduced. Optimization 8 18 All the above leads us to conclude that x' should take the form of a possible "gulp" at t = followed by periods of consumption mixed with periods of no consumption. 0, should prescribe a jump Ai*{0) at < = 0, jump should maximize then the size of the value function immediately after the jump. That is, the jump If size Aa;'(0) we the should solve the following problem max J(u;(0) iFrom the order condition, first initial possible at times of jump at < = f, we then know + j/(0~) /3e,0+). that J^i^"^) = fiJyi^'^)- Moreover, after the 0, the following condition should be satisfied for all t G (0, 1]; no consumption: + lwr{t)w\t) -ly^y'{t) + u{y'{t),t) lt = (13) Q, together with A(0-7^(0<0, and at the times when consumption occurs we must have at rates, [7^(0 - /37,(0]x*'(0 = More generally, (14) 0. (15) consumption only occurs when J w{t) - PJy(t). strategy of no consumption is sub-optimal and hence uiy'(t),t) The necessary conditions on value function should at all During these times the + Jwr{t)w'(t) - lydy'it) + 7, < 0. (16) J can be expressed more compactly by stating that the times satisfy the following differential inequality: max|u(j/,0 + Jyjwr{t) Besides this differential inequality, it is - Jy(3y + clear that Jt, (iJy J must - J^,] = also satisfy 0. (17) two boundary condi- tions: J{w,y,l) J(0,j/,0 The first of The second =V(w) and =f,'u{y€-0i'-'),s)ds-\-V{O). these boundary conditions follows because at is i = 1 no consumption is , , ^ ' optimal. a consequence of the positive wealth constraint - when the agent's wealth reaches zero, he must henceforth refrain from consumption. We will show in the following section that the differential inequality plus the ary conditions are almost sufficient for optimality. readers familiar with dynamic programming. are allowed, standard results in We two bound- This deserves some commentary for observe that if only consumption rates dynamic programming show that the Bellman equation, together with the appropriate boundary conditions, are not only necessary but also cient. suffi- This occurs because the optimal consumption rates would be functions of J. Readers unfamiliar with dynamic programming are referred to Fleming and Rishel (1975, pp.??), for example, for a readable account. In our case, however, consumption does not have to be Optimization 8 19 at rates. Hence optimal consumption may not be readily determined once we know J turns out that the sufficient conditions for optimality include additional conditions optimal policy beyond those imposed on J . It on the These additional conditions are obtained from . the preceeding heuristic analysis. Sufficiency 8.2 We provide two results. conditions (18), theorem in is First, we show an upper bound which we show that if that the solution to (17), with the boundary on the value function J . Second, we give a verification a consumption pattern x* satisfies certain conditions, then the life-time utility derived from x' is given by the solution of (17) and (18). Hence and x' coincides with the upper bound on Proposition 9 Assume that there exists a differentiable function [0, 1] — Si ' of time, U {-oo}, concave in that solves (17) with utility w and the is J optimal. J'{w,y,t):^^ X J?+ X whose partial derivatives are continuous functions y, Then boundary conditions (18). J(ti;(0), j/(0~),0) < J-(ti;(0),j/(0-),0). As we mentioned almost sufficient may J' is in that The problem above. before, the differential inequality is, they produce a function that bounds the value function J from of course, that a budget feasible consumption pattern that attains not exist. Note that this at rates is not a problem in the standard models as consumption and the consumption pattern that produces J* can be calculated as a function of J', and thus J' = J for a consumption pattern x' to attain J'. occur only at Theorem and the boundary conditions are < = . The following verification theorem gives a set of conditions sufficient In particular, they stipulate that gulps can and afterwards, consumption occurs only 3 Let J' satisfy the conditions of Proposition a budget feasible consumption pattern x' , which is 9. at times where J^ (0, 1], with a possible Ai'(O), and whose associated state variables are w'(t),y'{t~), such that for f^\jl{w\y\t) - (ij;{w\y\t)]dx'{t) ^Jy- Suppose further that there exists continuous on u{y\t) + j:w'r{t)-j;Py' + j; = = and = for all t jump £ (0,1]: (19) all e>0, (20) and J-{wiO),y(0-),0) = J'{w(0) - Ax'{0),yiO-) Then J{w{0),y{0~),0) = J'{w{0),y{0~),Q) and x' 8.3 /?Ax'(0),0). (21) optimal consumption pattern. Example To demonstrate how policy, is the + to use the verification theorem in constructing an optimal consumption we provide a closed form solution for the optimal consumption problem in an infinite 20 Optimization 8 horizon economy with a constant interest rate °° This departure from our calculations. Our The agent seeks to maximize 1 -e-''y{trdt I given u;(0) and j/(0~) and where y{t) r. a given by equation (4). is We take horizon setup in earlier sections finite topologies generalize in a standard way to is a < 1 and S > 0. for tractability of this infinite horizon measure, m, that economy by replacing the Lebesgue measure on [0,oo) with a finite continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure. For example, we can take Tn{A) e~^^dt for r. all Lebesgue measureable sets A. We for this case, which is simpler than in the case of finite horizon separable in time and in {w,y). With a value function should have the form e~^^J{w,y) at time differential inequality oo) specified above satisfy [0, Simplicity follows from the observation that the programs, needs a minor modification. is for t some function Q independent off. The second boundary condition J(0,t/) = r first boundary condition in (18) and simply assert that f a a{aii needs modification as there We the agent does not have a preference for final wealth. reader, Then the boundary condition this is = lime-*'j(«;(O,J/(r)) 0, (22) in (18) simplifies to = e-'^l-iye-l'^'-'^r ds Jo The J. becomes I. is abuse of notation, the slight maxi :\^ + J^wT-JyPy-6J,l3Jy-jAJ = which = we advocate. the notion of continuity that value function absolutely leave the details to the reader but one can easily show that the agent's preferences for consumption on The verification theorem is -\- is (23) c) no date and, hence, final again leave the details to the replaced by 0, (24) t\oo Readers famiUar with for all budget-feasible policies. infinite horizon programs would rec- ognize this as a "transversality condition". We wiU show that the key feature of the solution to average past consumption A:', w y. If then the optimal behavior increases and y declines till is starts with -'t^ the ratio strictly greater consumption, reducing id a critical ratio the agent starts at time zero with to invest at the rate which keeps the ratio is — all - fc', and increasing reaches k' . From then strictly less w than If, on, the agent consumes on the other hand, the agent then the optimal behavior j/, Jj'^J. of wealth the wealth in the riskless asset and wait while equal to k' forever. than > /:* to bring is to take a "gulp" of ^ immediately to k' gulp, the optimal consumption occurs at the rate that keeps the ratio ^ . Following this equal to k' forever. To ensure existence of a solution, we make the following assumption. This assumption guarantees, among other things, that the value function will be concave. 8 21 Optimization Assumption 6 Now we the problem satisfy The parameters of 1 + 00 > > ar 6 0, First preceed as follows. we the policy of consumption that keeps "Y^ > it, and investigate equal to ^ or after a period of no consumption such a policy, denoted J''{w,y), Proposition 10 J''{w,y) is A; The k. an initial "gulp" if agent's life-time utility from of the sufficient conditions for optimahty: A ky ^ if if {S . forever, after '^^ A= r given by: j''{w,y)= where - 6 the A:-ratio consumption policies: all > rjo^ < if many satisfies - a)P > (1 - a/3(^))~' - (<^ + and B = a/3)~^ {S ^ < ^ > — y Jt k - a0{^))~^- Furthermore, j'' is continuous, concave, has continuous first derivatives and satisfies yl + rwJt-PyJ^-SJ'' = o Jt-PJ' = together with the boundary condition (23) However, there This is fc-ratio policy is and if (25) the transversality condition (24)- j'' satisfies exactly one k so that ^<k, ^>k, if the diflferential inequality of (22). then the optimal policy: Proposition 11 Let ^ + (!-«) — ar and note that k' by Assumption > follows that the k' -ratio policy The is 1. j''' the optimal solution for the agent's problem. reader can easily verify that k* associated J^' is is the unique ratio with the property that the twice continuously differentiable over the whole We summarize of size domain {w,y). the solution in the following proposition. Proposition 12 The optimal initial gulp satisfies the differential inequality (22). It then solution A = ^^^^^^ [{S - is to consume + ar)«;(0) at rate c(t) - -fi^wit), after an (^ + (1 - a))j/(0-)] , if ^^ > k' , or 1 after a period of It is interesting to starts with the who no consumption of length same compare initial this t' = log 3q<, ' "^^^ , if "^o^ < '^'*- consumption policy to that adopted by a consumer who wealth w{0) and the same past consumption experience j/(0~) seeks to maximize: Jo a 9 22 References where c{t) is the consumption rate at t and we assume that can be easily verified that his optimal consumption rate > ar and 6 1 - a > 0. It a linear function of his wealth: is c{t)='-f^w{t). The propensity consume to additive preferences. is consume c{t) when rw{t), and hence wealth; see figure 3. start if his A wealth is 6 = An r. his wealth at agent with time-additive preferences any time will be a constant equal to his consumer with non-time additive preferences, however, by consuming a "gulp" of and then keep the with time-additive and non-time- for agents However, the quantity of consumption and the trajectory of wealth are different. Consider the case = same the level of his size *"*"' ;^0 —K if his wealth is will initial will either too high relative to J/(0~), wealth constant forever, or he will wait for t' = ^^r^ log yZl , too low relative to j/(0~), and then start consuming the interest on his wealth forever. The parameter mines the which controls the rate of "decay" of previous consumption, deter- (3, size of the initial "gulp" or the length of the initial waiting period, level of the subsequent constant wealth. The higher the value of the initial gulp, if /3, and hence the the smaller the size of the solution calls for a "gulp", and the shorter the initial waiting period, in case the solution entails a waiting period. This is an intuitive result since a higher /? implies that past consumption experience has "smaller" effect on current, and hence total, satisfaction. Therefore, cumulate wealth, the effect of j/(0~) period before the ratio calls for an initial when the optimal ^ reaches "gulp", higher and hence the "gulp" contributes P choose solution entails an initial waiting period to ac- decays faster with higher its critical value. /? means that the (3 Similarly, leading to shorter waiting when the optimal effect of the less to future satisfaction. solution "gulp" will decay faster Therefore, agents with higher smaller initial "gulps". References 9 Banach Lattices and Positive Operators, Springer- Verlag, 1. Schaefer, H., 2. P. Billingsley (1968), New 3. Berlin, 1974. Convergence of Probability Measures, John Wiley and Sons, York. A. Blaquiere (1985), "Impulsive Optimal Control with Finite or Infinite Time Hori- zon", Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications 46. 4. G. Constantinides (1990), "Habit Formation: Puzzle", Journal of Political 5. P. Economy A Resolution of the Equity Premium 98, 519-543. Fishburn (1970), Utility Theory for Decision Making, John Wiley and Sons, New York. 6. W. Fleming and Springer- Verlag. R. Rishel (1975), De(erm/n/s(/c and Stochastic Optimal Control, 9 23 References 7. A. Hindy and C. sumption: A Huang (1990a), On Intertemporal Preferences for Uncertain Con- Continuous Time Approach, Sloan School of Management, Massachusetts Institute of Technology. 8. A. Hindy and C. Huang (1990b), Optimal Consumption and Portfolio Rules with Local Substitution, Graduate School of Business, Stanford University. 9. C. Huang, Information Structure and Equilibrium Asset Prices, Journal of Economic Theory 35:33-71, 1985. 10. R. B. Holmes (1975), Geometric Functiona.1 Analysis and its Applications, Springer- Verlag, Berlin. 11. L. Jones (1981), Commodity Differentiation in Economic Modelling, Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley. 12. L. Jones (1984), "A Competitive Model of Product Differentiation", Econometrica 52, 507-530. 13. M. Magill (1981), 14. A. Mas "Infinite Colell (1975), Horizon Programs", Econometrica 49, 679-711. "A Model of Equilibrium with Differentiated Commodities", Journal of Mathematical Economics 15. A. Mas Colell ( 1986), 2, 263-296. "The Price Equilibrium Existence Problem in Topological Vector Lattices", Econometrica 54, 1039-1053. 16. Mas in Vector Lattices", Journal of Economic Theory 17. J. 18. Colell and S. Richard (1991), "A to the Existence of Equilibria 53, 1-11. Musielak (1983), Orlicz Spaces and Modular Spaces, Springer- Verlag, Berlin. H. Ryder and G. Heal (1973), "Optimal Growth with Intertemporally Dependent Preferences", 19. New Approach A. Review of Economic Studies 40, 1-31. Sundaresan (1989), "Intertemporally Dependent Preferences and the Volatility of Consumption and Wealth", Review of Financial Economics 2, 73-89. S. A 24 Proofs Appendix A Proofs Fix a continuous, strictly increasing and convex function rj from [0,oo) to [0,oo) with = and 77(00) = 00. Define /,,(x,a), for x £ and a £ (0,oo), by X 77(0) f\i\x{t)\/a)dt Jv ix,a)= + r,{\xil)\/a). Jo Since functions x are of bounded variation, the integral and certainly well defined for every x is a. We record a Lemma A A lemma first. sequence {x„} in X converges to zero in • \\ \\r, if and only if, for every scalar = 0. > 0, lim„ Ir,{xn,a) Proof. See Musielak [1983, theorem a 1.6]. I 1. We want to show that order intervals are weakly compact. In sequential compactness in the norm topology itself. The proof follows standard lines, and so we will provide only a sketch. For X* > X, let / be the order interval [a;.,i']. We will assume that i. = 0, this is without loss of generality because all of our topologies are linear. Let Q be any countable dense set of points in [0, 1) that excludes all points of discontinuity of x*. Proof of Proposition fact, we can show Now X E I if and only if a: is nondecreasing and x' — x \s nondecreasing. Let {in} be any sequence out of/. By the usual diagonalization procedure, we can produce a function y such that, along a subsequence (which we will hereafter not bother to mention), lim„ Xn{t) = y{t) at all arguments t £ Q. Since each x„ is nondecreasing, so is y. Define a function x by x{t) = limsjtj/(<) for t £ [0,1), where the limit is taken over sequences converging to t from (strictly) above along the set Q and x{l) = limni„(l). Since y is nondecreasing, so is X. Moreover, y is right continuous (and has left limits) by construction. Clearly lim„a:n(0 = a;(<) at all points t that are not points of discontinuity of i - that is, for almost every t. And lim„i„(l) = i(l) by construction. Since all the x„ and x are bounded above by x'(l), we can apply dominated convergence and Lemma A to conclude that i„ approaches x in 7^. We are done once we show that x* > x > 0. We have already remarked that x is nondecreasing (i.e., x > 0). So let us carefully sketch the other half: If i'(0 - x{t) < — then right continuity of both functions implies that we can find values q > from Q such that x'{q) — x{q) < x'{q') - x{q'). (The case of < = 1 is left to the reader.) By increasing q' slightly to be some q" < q \i need be (if q' is a point of x'{t') x{t') for t > t' , q' discontinuity of x, this gives x*{q) large n, x'{q) - Xn{q) < x'{<f') Proof of Proposition - We — y{q) Xniq"). < x'{q") - y{q") for q > 9". Hence I Which is a contradiction. for sufficiently note first that for any rj, %, is topologically equivalent to Ta,, for any scalar a. Hence, without loss of generality, we can assume that 7^(1) = 1. Note that this implies, by the convexity of 7/, that Ti(r) > r for all r > 1. Now it is evident that Hence, if for fixed 77 (with q{l) = 1) we let 77i(r) = max{|r|,7/(r)} 111' fo'' l^'i \\v ^ (which is convex as it is the maximum of two convex functions), we have that T is no stronger than 7^, for any 77. The proof of the first part of Proposition 2 is thus shown if we show that, for any 7/, 7^ is equivalent to T^,. Of course, Ti, can be no stronger, so we only II II , 2. A 25 Proofs For this use Lemma A: If ar„ — T^, then !„ — need to show that if x„ — 7^, 7^, — 0. Suppose that for some fixed a, /,„(in,a) does not go then for every a > 0, /,,(a;„,a) to zero - look along some subsequence where the limit exceeds 4/M for some integer M. Now ljj[Xn,(i) can be written as the sum of three terms: > . J 7?(l„(0/a)l{|x„(t)|/a>l}<^< + ViXn{t)/a)l{\^^(t)\/a<\}dt J + 77(i„(l)/a). Pick n large enough so that the is positive, each must go to zero in n. term is less than 1/M. If the second is to go to zero, since tj is strictly positive except at the argument zero, we can find n large enough so that the Lesbesgue measure of the And for the third term to go to zero, it is 1 > Xn{t)/a > 1/A/} < 1/M. set {t G [0,1] necessary that, for n large enough, x„(l)/a < 1/M. Picking n large enough so that all this happen at once, when we expand /^, (x„,a) in analogous fashion, we will find that (i) the first term in the sum is less than 1/A/, since it is identical with the first term above, (ii) the third term is less than 1/M, directly from our selection of n, and (iii) the second term is less than 2/A/, when we overestimate T]i(Xnit)/a) in the second term with the function that is 1/A/ if the argument is less than 1/A/ and 1 is the argument is between 1/A/ and 1. Since this is so for all n above some level, we contradict the supposition. Next we must show that, for any ry, T,, is no stronger than the total variatio n and Skorohod topologies. Since total variation is a (linear) norm topology, it suffices to show in total that if i„ —» in total variation, then i„ — %,. Apply Lemma A - if Xn — variation, then the same is true for Xn/a for any scalar a > 0. The total variation norm And dominated is larger than the sup norm, so the same must be true in the sup norm. convergence gives the result. As for the Skorohod topology, Billingsley [1968, page 123, problem 2] states the result for the L^ norm topology, which immediately gives the result for T. For general 77, note that if Xn -^ x in the Skorohod topology, then for n sufficiently large, sup, |x„(/)| < sup( \x{t)\ + 1/n. Fixing any a, then, and evaluating Ir,{xn - x,a), we know that the arguments of t) will be bounded above by K/a = 2sup( |x(/)|/a + 2/(an). Convergence of /,,(in - x,a) to zero, then, follows immediately if Ii{Xn — x,a) converges to zero, where /] means the integral using the function r]*{t) = t in place of rj, since we can overestimate r)(r) with rT)(K/a). Convergence of /i(x„ - x,a) to zero follows from the I problem in Billingsley, and we are done. Since each term first : Proof of Proposition 4. We need T^. Fixing a scalar Xn - Vn — > that an upper bound on /,,(a:„ - j/„,a) to a is show that > 0, if x„ and ?/„ are as in the (2.3), then the techniques employed just above show ^7?((3a;„(l) + 2)/a) + 7?((x„(l) - j/„(l))/a). The second term vanishes for any a since a;„(l) - j/n(l) < pi^n^Vn) < 1/"- And the first term vanishes for any a: By assumption, Xn(l)//i(n) -^ 0, and thus (3x„(l) + 2)/(an(n)) -^ 0. Hence for any e there is A^, such that for all n > N,, (3x„(l) + 2)/a < €^l(n). Apply T] to both sides (t; is monotone), and use the shape of 77, for f < 1 to conclude that I r;((3x„(l) + 2)/a) < r]{(fi{n)) < (r](n{n)) - en, for all n > N,. Proof of Proposition 5. In A'^., the weak topology is described by the Prohorov metric. Accordingly, the topology is sequential, and it suffices to show that a sequence is convergent in one of the two topologies if and only if it is convergent in the other. Suppose first that sufficiently large so that x„ — X in Tr,. Fix f > 0, and, applying Lemma A, pick Ir,{xn - x,() < € ioT n > N. We claim that this implies that p(x„,i) < e. For if not, then there exists some t such that x„(/ -\- () + ( < x(/) or such that x„(< - f ) - f > x{t). Suppose that the former is true, and suppose further that t e[0,l- t]. See figure Al. In calculating /^(xn - x,f), when we integrate 7/((x„(<) - x{t))() over [t,t + e], the integrand exceeds N 7/(1) = 1. (Recall that 77(1) = 1 is wlog.) Hence the integral is at least f, a contradiction. If A 26 Proofs (summed) term in /,,(i„ - x,c) will exceed 1, again a contradiction. The case where, for some t, Xn(t — () — (> x{t) is handled similarly. Conversely, suppose that i„ — x in the weak topology. Fix a constant a > 0. We will show that /,,(x„ - x,a) -* 0, so that !„ — i T^ follows by Lemma A. If p(a:„,x) —* 0, t > I then - Iti(1) > and the f, We zero in n. m, let ^ Now in Ir,{xn,a) converges to we can bound /q t/ f ^"' '~^^ '' j dt above by fmax{x{k/Tn),Xn{k/Tn)} — m\n{x{{k—l)/Tn),Xn{{k—\)/m)} ° ^ "^ibTi x{t term need, therefore, only be concerned with the first (integral) term. For a given N{m) be sufficiently large so that for n > N{m), p(xn,x) < 1/m. Recalfing that both i„ and x are nondecreasing, 1 last 1(1)1 —^ 0, so that the final immediate that |a;„(l)- it is integer - then x(l) €, since p(x„,ar) — 1/m) - 1/m, < 1/m, max{a;(<),i„(<)) < x(t + 1/m) + 1/m and min{x(<), !„(<)} > summation given is bounded above by so the fx{{k+l)/m)-x{{k-2)/m) + 2/m\ Jli, 1 -SH ) -a i,From the shape of?; (convex, equal to zero at zero, and increasing), this in turn is bounded above by /y. J_ argument of For fixed a, the assertion. I Proof OF Proposition f, y G 5f+ and i l)/m)-x((A:-2)/m) + 2/m \ ^ x((fc+ 6 [0, 1] 6. Suppose not. By joint continuity, there such that w((r + r)/2, + 2\ upper bound vanishes with m, proving our fixed, so this is rj / 3x(l) 1 j/, ^ t) exists two scalars r and + u(f, y, t)/2. Without loss u{r,y,t)/2. By joint continuity u{r, y, t)/'2 of generality, assume that u({r + f)/2,y,t) > u(r, y, /)/2 + again, there exists e > and some interval / containing /, and some interval A containing y such that u((r + f)/2,w,s) - e > u{r,w,s)/2 + u(f,w,s)/2 for all s G / and w £ A. Consider a sequence of absolutely continuous consumption patterns constructed as follows: Off of /, consume the pattern m{s), to be described shortly, in each a;„. On /, subdivide / into 2n equal sized intervals, and consume at rate r on the even subintervals and f on the odd. This sequence of consumption patterns converges in the Prohorov metric to the consumption pattern x that has x'{s) = m(s) off/ and x'{s) = {r + f)/2 on /. Choose Tn{s) A for all 5 G [0,1]. Note that this is always feasible. By Proposition 5, Xn -* X in T^. Proposition 7 shows that lim„_oc /o^ u{x',yn,t)dt = /q u(x',y,t)dt. But for such that y{s) 6 any j/„, we have: u{x',yn,t)dt> / Jo Taking limits of both sides as n u(x',y,t)dt = J' is not continuous in T^. u{x'^,yr„t)dt — oo, / u(x',yn,t)dt lim » we + eX{I). get: + f-^(/), > lim / u{x'yn,t)dt-\-(X{I). "-*°° Jo n-'oo Jo Hence U{x) > lim„_oo t^(^n) V I Jo where A(/) Finally, note that if is the Lebesgue measure of /. Thus = a{y,t)r + f3{y,t) for {z,y) 6 u{z,y,t) - A 27 Proofs (0,oo) X (0,oo) and if u is a and jointly continuous, then /3 must be continuous functions. I 1. We prove the necessity part of the assertion first. Suppose that using the Hahn-Banach theorem continuous linear functional on A'. We extend to L'' to be a linear functional continuous in %,. Denote this extension still by 4>. Musielak [1983, theorem 13.17] shows that 4> can be represented as Proof of Theorem (j!) a is Ti, (f> f\it)y{t)dt <i>(z)= + zil)yil) (26) Jo for some y Now fix L^ €. . X e X Since i . is we can a right-continuous bounded variation function, use integration by parts to rewrite 4>(x) as follows. First, define f(t) = y(l) = [0, 1]. Note that / is absolutely continuous with f'{t) - -y{t) and /(I) V? e + /( j/(l). y(s)ds Then integration by parts gives [\(t)y(t)dt + x{l)y{l) = - I x(t)df{i) + x{\)f(\)= [ f(t)dx{t). Jo- Jo Jo We have thus proved the only if part as x e A' is an arbitrary element of A'. Next we turn to the sufficiency part. First reversing the above integration by parts to show that can be written as (26) with a y 6 L'^' Musielak [1983, corollary 13.14] then shows that is continuous in %j. . <t> <f) The last assertion is obvious. I Proof of Proposition 7. Fix a topology T^. Let x„ be a sequence of consumption plans that converge to x in T^. Assume, without loss of generality, that sup„ ||A'n||^ < oo. First observe that x„ -+ if a; in T^, then lim n— oo Now we consider yjl) - [ i„ /' |xn(0 ^x - in T. Hence, x{t)\ dt + |x„(l) - x{l)\] = (27) 0. Jo y{t) = fl^ki(!) ^(^'^) ('^^"C " ^) " '^^^^ " Integrating by parts, ^'^^- get: yn{t)-y{t) = -(xn{klit))-x{k^it)))0{tJ-ki{t))- (Xr,{t-S)-X(t-S)]e2{t,s)ds, / (28) where ^2(^«) denotes the partial derivative of ^(<,s) with respect to its second argument. But since both Q and its derivative are bounded, the left-hand side in (28) is bounded by Mi|x„(^-i(<)) - a:(/:i(0)l + ^h[ll \in{i - s) - x(< - s)\dsl where M, and Ah are two constants. iFrom , we can this, easily conclude that lim„_oo [/o IVnit) - y(OI dt is less than or equal toMi\imn^oo[lo\xAt)-x{t)\dt]+M2\irn^-.oo[!o!o\''n(t-s)-x(t-s)\dsdt\,mthecase when x(t - ki{t) is s)\dsdt y{t)\di - 0. a constant, , ^lim„_oo[/o kn(0 - in the case when < ci < \k[{t)\ x(0|<^i] < Ci- + M2lim„_oo[/o /o l^nit - s) In both cases, lim„_oo[/o IVnCO - This follows from (27) and the uniform convergence theorem applied to the inside intergral in the second term of the previous expression. A 28 Proofs Now y. It consider the convergence of u(j/„). First, assume that u is Lipschitz continuous in then follows that |u(j/n) — w(y)| < a|j/„ — y\, where a is independent of y. It then - u{y)\dt follows that lim„_,oo[/o |w(!/n) < alim„^oo[/J \yn{t) - y{t]\d.t = 0. It then U{xn) converge to U{x). Next consider the case when u is merely continuously differentiable in y. For every integer m, define Um{y) = u(^)X[o,i] + '^(y)^[^<y<m] + w('")X[m,oo)- For a fixed m, the follows that function u^ is Lipschitz continuous in y, and hence the arguments in the previous paragraph show that Um{Xn) converge to Um{x), where ZVm(i) is defined exactly as U{x), except that u is replaced by Um- Now fix x and the corresponding y. Let A = {t E. [Q,\]:u(y[t)J) > 0} and let A'^ = [0, 1] \ A. Note that either A or A'^ might be of measure zero. It is — oo. clear that u,n(t/(<),0 converge monotonically to u{y{t),t) on both A and A'^ as Applying the monotone convergence theorem, we conclude that Um[^) = J^ "m(2/(0' ^^ + — oo. It then follows that: Jac Ujn{y{t),t)dt converge to ZV(ar) as m m = lim U{xn) lim Hm{Xn) = lim Hm{x) = H{x). Proof of Proposition 8. Theorems 1 and 2 establish that the cone defining the order dual corresponds to nonnegative functions /. Hence in the order dual, the join of / and g (for f,g £ X* in the obvious embedding) would be given by max{/,5}, and the meet by min{/,g}, these being taken pointwise. Now the absolute value of the derivative of max{f,g] for absolutely continuous / and g is (almost everywhere) less than |/'| + \g'\. Thus if f,g G X*, maoi{f,g} and ni'm{f,g} are also elements of X^. This completes the proof. I Proof of Proposition 9. Assume that the agent adopts a budget feasible consumption pattern x with associated wealth w and y. For convenience of notation, we at times denote J'(w{t),yit-),t),J:;,iw{t),yit-),t),j;{w{t),y{t-),t),3indJ^{wit),y{t-),t)hyJ'it),j;^{t), Jy{t), and Jt{t), respectively. J^u{y{s),s)ds + E. We have + r{w{t),y{r),t) = /,V' {J'js)rw{s)ds - J^uiy{s),s)ds J;(5)(ii(5) + + riw(0),yiO-),0) + j;{s)0idx{s) - y{s)ds) + Y:,{j'ir,^) - J:{s)ds), (29) where the equality follows from fundamental theorem of calculus and we have set tq = 0. Note that the boundary conditions for J* ensure that the left-hand expression is the correct expression of utility even for consumption plans that exhaust all the wealth before time 1. By the hypothesis that J* is concave in its first two arguments, we know that r{rn - J'ir,) < J'jTiXwiT^) - wir,)) Substituting this into (29), while noting that w{r^) + j;(r.)(y(r,) - - w{t) = x(t~) - 2/(7")). x(t), gives rl u{y{s),s)ds j: < + J'{w{t),y{t-),t) J'{w{0)MO-),0) + f\uiyis),s) + J'Js)wis)Tis) - j;{s)0y{s) + J:{s)]ds Jo + j\l3J;{s)-J'Js)]dx{s)<J'iwiO),y(0-)^0), J'{r,)) A 29 Proofs where the second inequality follows from the hypothesis that the integrands are negative I and I is increasing. Proof of Th EOREM arguments With the hypotheses added 3. in addition to the ones Proposition in identical to those used to prove the proposition prove this theorem. Proof of Proposition 9, I Suppose that - > 10. to bring the ratio immediately to k k. The size of the initial "gulp" required = (w ky)/{\ + /3k) and we define J^{w,y) = A is J^{w - A,y + /3A). Concavity of J^ in both it? and y follows from assumption 1, and the rest of the proposition can be easily verified by direct computations. For the transversality < condition note that for any point {w{t),y{t~)), j''(w{t),y(t~)) 7. Noting that any for 7/3e*~*'''°"'''u>(0), feasible policy, y{t~) < the transversality condition follows. Proof of Proposition ^ - bJ^' < /Sy we only need - if > r < k' to prove that and <0 - if . y inequality, consider any point x = {w,y) such that w be the point on the intersection of the line w — k*y first to Figure 2, let a < y PJ^' -Jt' y To prove the some constant e~^* J^(w(t),y{t~)) I 11. In light of Proposition 10, ^a + j'^rW - Jf 7j/(<~)", for and hence /3iy(0)e''', -« through the point x with slope 7^ = the boundary w = k'y, to which one would jump line passing In > k*y. Referring and the straight words, other a is the point on one starts at x. By construction, = = J^'{a). Let f{w,y) + Jt'rw- J^' (3y, and note that f(a) - 6j'''{a) = 0. J'^'ix) Applying the fundamental theorem of calculus along the straight line connecting a and x, we obtain f{x) - f{a) = j^(f^dw + fydy). Noting that along the line connecting a and if ^ we have dy = —fidw, and that du; > in the direction from a to is sufficient to conclude that fw — 0fy < X, yl + Q Computing for k' = f^, - Pfy in j^\^.j^'py^sj'' <o " the region w> x_, then follows that it ->r. if y k*y, the reader can easily verify that /„, - fSfy < ^^p^. To prove the second w < k'y. We can write 0J!:' inequality, consider the function J^* = - fiJy' in the region where where y^-'gi^) /3 r where A is assumption 1, hence g{z) dg dz ] 00 &s z derivative of 9, A(S + r a/?) +P ] ^ r + a/? /3 Note that 5(1) = given in proposition 10. Computing the + /? 0, and that 00. we get _«±h5 /J_ _ U- a(3 \ + aP k'(r+3)) k'{r + (3)J 6 d -ar) ziP + r) 0(6 1 + ^J -^^ > 0, by A ^° Proofs Substituting k' in the expression for for 2 > 1. It . then follows that J^' J5b 194 - ^, we conclude I3J^' > that ^a 0, for all = for 2 = 1, and that points {w, y) such that w< ^> k'y. I Date Due f -^^i. t99A F»-0® Lib-26-67 Mil 3 TOflO UBRARieS 00711512 3