tA e "> o/ TEC^. ALFRED P. WORKING PAPER SLOAN SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT AUCTIONS WITH RESALE MARKETS: AN EXPLORATORY MODEL OF TREASURY BILL MARKETS Sushil Bikhchandani and Chi-fu Huang June 1988 Revised June 1989 WP # 3070-89-EFA MASSACHUSETTS TECHNOLOGY 50 MEMORIAL DRIVE CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS 02139 INSTITUTE OF AUCTIONS WITH RESALE MARKETS: AN EXPLORATORY MODEL OF TREASURY BILL MARKETS Sushil Bikhchandani and Chi-fu Huang June 1988 Revised June 1989 WP # 3070-89-EFA SEP 1 2 1989 RECEIVED AUCTIONS WITH RESALE MARKETS: AN EXPLORATORY MODEL OF TREASURY BILL MARKETS* Sushil Bikhchandani^and Chi-fu Huang^ June 1988 Revised June 1989 Abstract This paper develops a model of competitive bidding with a resale market. The primary market is of resale. modelled as a common- value auction, in which bidders participate After the auction the winning bidders sell for the purpose the objects in a secondary market and the buyers on the secondary market receive information about the bids submitted in the auction. The effect of this information linkage between the primary auction and the secondary market on bidding behaviour in the primary auction is examined. The auctioneer's expected revenues from organizing the primary market as a discriminatory auction versus a uniform-price auction are compared, and plausible sufficient conditions under which the uniform-price auction yields higher expected revenues are obtained. example of our model, with the primary market organized the U.S. Treasury bill *We thank John Cox An as a discriminatory auction, is market. bill auctions and Margaret Meyer for helpful Chemical Bank for answering many of our questions on the organization of Treasury bill auctions. We would also like to acknowledge helpful comments from seminar participants at City College of New York, Princeton, Stanford and UCLA. The second author is grateful for support under the Batterymarch Fellowship Program. ^Anderson Graduate School of Management, University of California, Los Angeles, CA 90024 02139 'Sloan School of Management, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, conversations. We for kindling are grateful to our interest Chiang Sung in Treasury of the MA Introduction 1 1 Introduction 1 One of the major achievements of economic theory in the past decade has been a deeper understanding of the conduct and design of auctions. Recent surveys of the literature on McAfee and McMillan auctions are (1987), Milgrom (1987), and Wilson account for a large volume of economic and financial ment uses a sealed-bid auction to sell activities. The U.S. U.S. Treasury Department uses a sealed-bid auction to Many Interior Depart- mineral rights on federally owned properties. Auction houses regularly conduct auctions of antiques, jewelry, and works of dollars. (1988). Auctions Treasury sell Every week the art. worth bills billions of other economic and financial transactions, although not explicitly conducted as auctions, can nevertheless be thought of as implicitly carried out through auctions; see, example, an analysis of sales of seasoned new issues for the market for corporate control in One for seasoned new issues. resale, the auction will be among all This for sale. One may argue Thus it is that common-value with the the participating bidders.' in Parsons and Raviv (1985), and is that there exist active resale or (1986). feature often shared by such financial activities secondary markets for the objects and Tiemann true, for when resale price being the that an auction with a resale market is common Weber (1982a) common-value However, there are situations that make existing theory inapplicable. Treasury bills valuation might be argued that the theory of common- value auctions developed by Wilson (1969), and Milgrom and The observation example, for Treeisury there exists the possibility of is A is applicable. certainly true. case in point is auctions. bill In Treasury bill auctions, there are usually participate in the weekly auction. They submit competitive about forty bidders or primary dealers who These primary dealers are large financial institutions. sealed bids that are price-quantity pairs. Others, usually indi- vidual investors, can submit noncompetitive sealed bids that specify quantity (less then a prespecified maximum). The noncompetitive bids, usually small in quantity, always win. The primary dealers compete for the remaining bills in a discriminatory auction. the demands bidder down, are met the bills of the bidders, starting with the highest price are allocated. The winning competitive bidders pay the 'An auction is After the auction, the Treasury department announces common-value if is, until all unit price they submitted. All the noncompetitive bidders pay the quantity-weighted average price of competitive bids. That all the winning some summary participating bidders do not value the objects for sale differently. ^ Introduction 1 statistics • 2 about the bids submitted. These include amount total tender received; amount accepted; • total tender - • highest winning bid; • lowest winning bid; • quantity weighted average of winning bids; and • the split between competitive and noncompetitive bids. The Treasury bills are then delivered to the winning bidders and can be resold at an active secondary market. Since primary bidders are large institutions, they tend to have private information about the term structure of interest rates thai in the is better than the information possessed by investors secondary markets. The primary dealers submit bids information that is in the auction based on both publicly available at the time, and their private information. The buyers on the resale market have access only to public information, including information revealed by the Treasury about the bids submitted in the auction. To the extent that bids submitted reveal the private information of the primary dealers, the resale price in the secondary market will be responsive to the bids. This creates an incentive for the primary dealers to signal their private information to the secondary market participants. This information linkage between the actions taken by the bidders in the auction and the resale price in existing models of common-value auctions and In Section 2, we develop is is absent the primary focus of this paper. a model of competitive bidding with a resale market. The primary dealers or bidders are risk-neutral and have private information about the true value of the objects. random We variables, assume that the bidders' private signals and the true value are i.e., affiliated roughly speaking, higher realizations of a bidder's private signal imply that higher realizations of the true value, and of the other bidders' private signals, are more likely. prices paid After the auction the auctioneer publicly announces by the winning bidders, for some information example) about the auction. The winning bidders ^For an analysis of bidding with a resale market when the valuations of the bidders are see Milgrom (1987). (the common knowledge, Introduction 1 then 3 the objects in the secondary market, at a price equal to the expected value of the sell object conditional on all public information.^ Although the primary motivation of many institutional details, demand bidders And we do model which are absent. most one unit is the Treasury bill market, there are For instance, we require that competitive of the object, instead of being allowed to choose quantity. not model the effect of any forward contracts, and close substitutes (such as \ast week's Treasury we at this bills) owned by primary bidders on focus on one aspect of the Treasury bill market their bidding strategies. In this paper — the informational linkage of the resale market and the primary auction. The results of this paper may also be helpful in analyzing other types of auctions with resale markets, such as art auctions, in by Van Gogh is auctioned at a price which bidders have correlated values. much In section 3 we analyze discriminatory auctions. It is tions for the existence of a unique symmetric is model in Nash equilibrium We provide sufficient condi- in nondecreasing strategies Milgrom and Weber (1982a) where bidders participate purpose of consumption and there for the in future. assumed that the winning bids and the highest losing bids are revealed at the end of the auction. in the auction. Unlike the a painting higher than expected, then one might expect and other paintings by Van Gogh to be sold at higher prices this If is no resale market, the not sufficient for the existence of an equilibrium. higher than those derived in Milgrom and Weber affiliation The equilibrium bids property alone we obtain axe (1982a), because primary bidders have an incentive to signal. A kets key insight gained from the theory of common-valuation auctions without resale mai- is that the greater the sale) revealed in duction in the amount of information (about the an auction, the greater the expected revenue if Any for the auctioneer. uncertainty about the true value weakens the winners' curse which causes the bidders to bid more aggressively. Thus affiliated true value of the objects for the auctioneer hats in re- turns private information with the bidders' valuations, he can increase his expected revenue by precom- mitting to announcing his private information before the auction. market and there When there exists an incentive for the bidders to signal, the auctioneer the bidders' incentive to signal and thus decrease his expected revenue if is may a resale reduce he announces his ^Riley (1988) investigates a model in which conditional upon winning, each bidder's payment depends all the bids submitted. In our model, the expected value for each primary bidder depends on the bids upon submitted. 1 Introduction 4 private information. Sufficient conditions for the public announcement of the auctioneer's private information to increase his expected revenue are provided. and In Sections 4 5 we consider a uniform-price auction, that rule for determining the winning bidders is identical to the one in is an auction in which the the discriminatory auction, but the winning bidders pay a uniform price equal to the highest losing bid. The existence of an equilibrium depends in part on the kind of information about the auction publicly revealed by the auctioneer. If, as we assumed for discriminatory auctions, the announced then we show by example that there may are exist an incentive winning bids for the bidders to submit arbitrarily large bids in order to deceive the secondary market buyers. Bidders in a discriminatory auction do not have such an incentive since, upon winning, they must pay what they bid. However, a symmetric Nash equilibrium always exists auction, provided that only the price paid by the winning bidders is in the uniform-price announced (and thus bidders have no incentive to signal). Next, we turn The key to the question of the auctioneer's revenues. the theory of auctions without resale markets mentioned above is from insight gained Without also useful here. resale markets, uniform-price auctions yield higher revenues than discriminatory auctions, since in the former the price is linked to the information of the highest losing bidder. When there are resale markets in which the buyers draw inferences about the true value from the bids and the winning bids are announced, there same direction. Namely that in a is an additional factor which works uniform-price auction it is cheaper to bid high to signal a high realization of private information, since conditional does not pay what he bids. Therefore, in greater We when in in in the order upon winning a bidder our model as well, uniform-price auctions result expected revenues for the auctioneer, when there exists an equilibrium. also provide plausible sufficient conditions the primary auction by winning bidders is is under which the auctioneer's revenues organized as a uniform-price auction and only the price paid announced is greater than under a discriminatory auction when the winning bids are announced. Section 6 contains concluding remarks. All proofs are in an appendix. The revenue maximizing mechanism for selling Treasury bills was a subject of debate in the early 1960s. Friedman (1960) proposed that the Treasury should switch from a discrim- inatory auction to a uniform-price auction for the sale of Treasury bills. that uniform-price auctions would induce bidders to reveal their true man Apart from the demand fact curves, Fried- asserted that discriminatory auctions encouraged collusion and discouraged smaller 2 The model 5 bidders from participating. Both Goldsein (1960) and Brimmer (1962) disputed Friedman's contention. Smith (1966), on the basis of a mathematical model, concluded that uniformprice auctions yield greater revenues. in that Unlike Smith's model, our model each bidder's beliefs about the others' bids are confirmed we model in game-theoretic is an equilibrium, and the information linkage between the primary auction and the secondary market. Like Smith, our analysis provides support for Friedman's proposal that the Treasury bill auction should be uniform-price. The model 2 Consider a common-value auction competitive bids The in Treasury bill true value of the objects is in which n risk-neutral bidders (the dealers who submit auctions) bid for k identical, indivisible objects, with n same the for all the bidders, and is unknown to them > k. at the time they submit bids. Each bidder privately observes a signal about the true value, based on which he submits a we indicate bid. We cissume that there are no noncompetitive bids. In Section 6 how noncompetitive bids can be incorporated in our model. assume that each bidder demands The primary (or is allowed) at most one unit of the object. dealers' interest in the objects being auctioned of resale in the secondary market. We market buyers that they would prefer to For instance, the primary bidders week's Treasury we bills, sell may may have sufficiently lower resell the Treasury solely for the purpose than the valuations of the the objects rather then consume them. capital constraints so that unless they sell this not be able to participate in next week's auction. Since, as primary bidders make positive expected will establish, prefer to they is assume that the primary dealers' personal (con- sumption) valuations of the object are always resale Throughout we bills at their profits in the auction, they expected value conditional on all publicly might known information. If instead one assumes that the primary bidders' personal value of the object szLme level as that of the resale buyers, then primary bidders is the object and their privately when at the the private information of the winning not revealed after the primary auction, the primary bidders will never the expected value of the object conditional on sell if if all is known information their expected value is is strictly less all public information greater than the resale price, and will always than the resale price. sell Therefore the resale market buyers will make strictly negative expected profits and the resale market will break down. 2 The model 6 Hence we preclude this possibility. For similar reasons we assume that primary bidders can participate in the resale market only as sellers, not as buyers. After the auction the auctioneer publicly announces some information about the auction. For simplicity we assume that that the winning bids and the highest losing bid submitted in the auction are publicly announced. In the case of the uniform-price auction, there exist an equilibrium we when also analyze uniform-price auctions the price paid by the winning bidders We may become is not the winning bids are not announced and only announced. some additional information about the value allow the possibility that for sale may the winning bids are revealed at the end of the auction. Therefore, if of the objects publicly available after the bids are submitted, but before the opening of the secondary market. The k winners in the primary auction then risk-neutral buyers on the secondary markets. The buyers on the objects to sell the secondary markets do not have access to any private information about the true value. They infer what they can from the information released by the auctioneer about the primary auction, and any other publicly available information. Thus, regardless of the secondary market auction or a posted price market conditional on The n all — the resale price will be the expected value of the object is a random variable, V i = 1,2, ...,n. Each bidder . observes a private signal, X,, about the true value. Let becomes public except after the auction when otherwise the true value, that example when — an publicly available information.^ risk-neutral bidders will be indexed by being auctioned mechanism BlVlP] , ^ The has a P denote true value of each object common prior on P V, and any other information that over but before the resale market meets. stated, that given is, P = V is i We will assume, the bidders' signals are not uninformative about E[V\Xi,X2, ,^„,P]. If this condition is violated, for our model reduces to the usual common-value auction without a resale market. Let f{v,p,x) denote the joint density function of {Xi,X2, .,Xn). [p,p] X [x, It is assumed that / i]" be the support of/, where V , P, and the vector of signals symmetric i]" denotes the n-fold product of [x,x]. in the we do not rule out the possibility that the support of the either from above or from below. Further, *The participants n arguments. Let is [z, it is Icist random assumed that all variables the is random X= [v,v\ X Note that unbounded variables in risk neutral. In the case of Treasury bill primary bidder that pays say $1 in 182 days will be E[m|/], where denotes the random marginal rate of substitution between consumption 182 days from now and that of today and where I denotes the information revealed by all the bids submitted. This true value will be the secondary market price whether or not the secondary market participants are risk neutral. in the secondary market do not have to be auctions, the "true" value of a m bill for a Discriminatory auction 3 this model are affiliated. 7 That is, for ail x, x' G [^,^1", v, v' E and {v,v], e p, p' {p,p], f{iv,p,x) V {v',p',x'))f{{v,p,x) A {v',p'y)) > fiv,p,x]f{v',p',x'), where V denotes the componentwise maximum, and A denotes the componentwise mini- mum. Affiliation is said to be strict if H is an increasing function of is if an increasing^ function then c,, d,. for other implications of affiliation. the above inequality E[H{V ,P,Xi,X2, The reader We referred to is at X is c, and for all c, ,(i, £ the right-hand derivative and at x assume that {V ,P,Xi, a.ny d,, . strictly increasing in and c,- [x,x], < in X,- < d,, H if n] is G l,...,n] contin- is continuously that if H is Moreover, we shall strictly increasing in Xi,thenE[H{V,P,Xi,X2,...,Xn)\ci < Xi < d, for all Ci,di = di, t 7^ 1] is \x,x). Discriminatory auction 3 In a discriminatory auction, the bidders the auction. that when A bidding game Weber winning bidder pays the price that he or she bids. In symmetric Nash equilibrium with among the primary dealers. in when the motive which the buyers know some or would and thus signal is we show strictly increasing strategies in the is of the primary bidders all of their bids (or a their private information. in Milgrom and not sufficient for the existence of a Nash This is to resell in a secondary summary their bids), there exists an incentive for the primary bidders to bid value this section Unlike the auctions examined (1982a), the affiliation property alone equilibrium. Intuitively, market submit sealed bids and the k highest bidders win the bidders' private signals are infoTmation complements^, in a sense to be defined later, there exists a statistic based on more than they otherwise because, by affiliation, the resale is responsive to the bids submitted to the extent the bids reveal the private information received by the primary bidders. If each bidder's incentive to signal increeises with his information realization, then there exists an equilibrium is < i the left-hand derivative. is i di, Milgrom and Weber (1982a) with the convention that the derivative ..,A''„) are strictly affiliated so o{{V,P,Xi,...,X„),say Affiliation implies that < Xi < further assume for simplicity that uously differentiable then 'E\H{V ,P,Xi, X^, ..,Xn)\ci differentiable in is strict. ...,Xn)\ci in strictly increasing strategies. It the information complementarity of the bidders' signals with respect to the true value that ^Throughout this paper, we will use weak relations. For example, increasing means nondecreasing, means nonnegative, etc. If a relation is strict, we will say, for example, strictly increaaing. 'The reader will see that our notion of information complementarity is different from that in Milgrom and Weber (1982b) positive Discriminatory auction 3 8 ensures that the bidders' incentive to signal increases with their information realizations and enables them to secondary markets participant's exists a unique beliefs are monotone, also show that if a sense to be defined, then there in symmetric equilibrium. model where bidders participate In a We sort themselves in a separating equilibrium. in an auction for final consumption of the objects, Milgrom and Weber (1982a) show that the auctioneer's expected revenue can be increased if he precommits to truthfully reporting his private information about the objects for sale before the auction, provided that his private information is affiliated with the bidders' pri- vate information. This follows since by publicly announcing his information, the auctioneer introduces an additional source of affiliation among the primary bidders' private informa- tion and thus weakens the winners' curse. Hence the bidders compete more aggressively and the expected result selling price not necessarily true. is portion of the bid submitted by a bidder incentive to signal to the resale market participants. is model with a increased. However, in our is A If market resale is this attributed to hia the auctioneer's private information a "substitute" for the bidders' information, announcing that information will reduce the This responsiveness of the resale price to the bidders' information. incentive for the bidders to signal and other hand, bidders', it is cause the expected selling price to the auctioneer's private information Thus game. it is is is symmetric symmetric.^ I's Note that Bidder i's strategy in its last is denoted 6, : point of view. at the time observes his private information Xi. [x,x\ Thus — 9?. increasing and differentiable strategies, . . , 6) n arguments, The the this is a symmetric analysis from the other bidders' when bidder 1 submits his bid, he only a strategy for bidder We order necessary conditions for an n-tuple (6,..., . On natural to investigate the existence of a symmetric Ncish equilibrium. examine the game from bidder viewpoint (6, fall. a "complement" to that of the is always beneficial for the auctioneer to announce his private information. the hypothesis that /(v,p,x) We may turn reduces the Existence of a symmetric Nash equilibrium 3.1 By when in I is a function of Xi. begin our analysis by deriving the 6) to be a when buyers in the Nash equilibrium first- in strictly secondary market believe that are the strategies followed in the bidding. ^To simplify the analysis we arbitrarily assume throughout that in case of a tie the winner is not chosen randomly. Rather, bidder 1 is declared the winner. This assumption is inconsequential. The equilibrium strategy will remain unchanged if we assume that in case of a tie, the winner(s) is (are) chosen from the tied bidders at random. Discriminatory auction 3 9 Since buyers in the secondary market do not have access to private information about the true value, the resale price is earlier, to simplify the analysis prices paid by winning bidders that bidders = t 2, . . . submits a bid equal to (i.e., Then r''(6-i(6),y'i,...,n,P) public information. all the winning bids) and the highest losing bid.* Suppose bidder if conditional on we assume that the auctioneer announces the ,n adopt the strategy 6. ofV the expectation As mentioned =e\v 1 bidder b, 1 receives information wins with a bid b Xi = x and the resale price will be X, = b-'{b),b-HKy^)),---,f>-\biY,),P\ Xi = b-\b),Y,,...,Y,,p], where b~^ denotes the inverse^ of Note that if P= common- value V, r'^[b~^{b),Yi, . and Yj b . . the j-th order statistic of {X2, is = ,Yk,P) . . ,Xn). V, and our model reduces to an ordinary auction without a resale market. Define v^[x',x,y)^-E[r'^{x',Yu...,n,P)\Xi By our hypothesis about strict affiliation, both and v r = x,n = (2) y]- are strictly increasing in each of arguments (provided that given P, the bidders' signals are not uninformative about their V). The expected profit for bidder ^ n'{b\x) 1 when Xi = x and he submits B[{r'{b-'{b)Si,---,y.,P)-b)l^,^i^y^^}\x^ a bid equal to b = x] = E [e [[r'{b-\b),Yu...,n,P) - b) l{,>i^Y,)y\Xi,n] \x, = E [{v'{b-'{b),XuY,) - = / b) 1{,>S(K0}|^1 = ^] is = x] . {v'{b-\b),x,y)-b)f,{y\x)dy, JX where the second equality follows from the law of iterative expectations, the conditional density function of y^ given Xi. Taking the first and fk{y\x) denotes derivative of n'^(6|z) with respect to b gives ^n^ = (v^(6-'(6),x,6-'(6)) - b) h{b-Hb)\x){b'{b-'{b)))-^ - F,{b-Hb)\x) + {b'{b-'{b)))-'fp'Ki{b-\b),x,y)My\x)dy, where b'{x) is the derivative of 6(1), Ft(t/|i) given Xi, and vf 'if some is is the conditional distribution function of Yk the partial derivative of v'^ some function of of the other losing bids, or with respect to its first them, are also announced all argument. For the results remain unchanged. *If 6 that < lie in b{z) then fc~'(fc) the range of 6. = i and if 6 > 6(r) then 6"'(ii) = 1. Thus we only need to consider values of b Discriminatory auction 3 [b,. . all be a Nash equilibrium, ,b) to . when 10 bidders t = 2, bidders adopt . . . , That b. necessary that 6 be a best response for bidder it is n adopt strategy is, b and the must be zero when relation (3) = ^^[^j(^) = {A^,x,x) Rearranging (4) gives 6(x) = (v (i,i,x) -fc(i))-— v'^ —-+ vi(i,i,y)-— / Jx if 6(x) profit [x,x]; and (ii) b[x) has to be positive < t; (i, X, x), = — dy. (5) ^k[^\^) = E[y|j^i = x,n-y]. Besides (5), there are two other necessary conditions that 1 - F,{x\x) and the law of iterative expectations, v''(x,x,y) Vi e b{x): an ordinary differential equation: Note that, by the definition of b{x), = 6 6(i)) A(i|x)(6'(x))-i rk{x\i) bidder 1 market participants believe that resale Condition u'^(x, x, x). in equilibrium. Condition (i) (ii) b (6) must satisfy: (i) v (x, x, x) > follows since expected profit for follows then by slightly increasing the bid to 6(i) from + e (i) and the when Xi = x, fact that expected can be raised from zero to some strictly positive amount. The solution to (5) with the boundary condition 6(x) 6(x) = v^{x,x,x) - = v'^[x,x,x) is r L{u\x)dt{u) + Jxr J^dL{u\x), (7) hW^) Jx where =exp{-i:^ds}, L(u|x) =v<^(u,u,u), t{u) = H^) Note that will show profit to V , L{ii\x) in and what is *^i (8) ("' "' y) A(y|")'^y- t(u) are increcising functions of u and thus are meaisures on follows that b{x) of (7) also satisfies condition under the hypothesis that {Xi, and Ix . , . . (i), [x, i]. We maximizes expected Xn, P) are information complements with respect strictly increasing. Definition 1 Random respect to another variables, (Zi, random T variable ^\\ aziOZj . . Zm), are said to be information complements with if ""' ' , . >0, ^i^j,Vzu...,Zm, where 4,{zu...,Z^)=E\f\Zi = Zu---,Zm = Zm\- 3 Discriminatory auction 11 Thus, the random variables to V of Xi (A'l, . . . ,Xn, P) are information complements with respect the marginal contribution to the conditional expectation of if larger the higher the realization of any other is tarity condition is . , . or P. This information . . , . . Zm) random if . (T, Zi, . . . , Zm) . , . is Zm) complements with are information give three examples of strictly affiliated complemen- if <^(2i, Thus are information complements. Zm) are multivariate normally distributed, then [Zi, We of a higher realization by a large class of distributions. For example, satisfied linear in the 2,'s, then (Zi, respect to T. Xj V" variables that also satisfy the information complementarity condition. Example g{t,zi, sume that . . 1 Let [T, Zi, , . Zm)- Let E~^ that S exists d^ln g/dtdzi > ,Zm) . . . multivariate normally distributed with density function be variance-covariance matrix of these random variables and as- be the and has and d^ strictly negative off-diagonal elements. g/dzidzj > In ber (1982a) then implies that {f,Zi,..., is linear in the Zi [Zi, 's, Zm) , . . . for Zm) are information Besides the multivariate normally distributed gamma 2 Let Zi, i = 1, distribution given . , . . T= ( m ^ The \A = n^ rf^'^r^e-^'/' ) ( ifZi « 0, t > 0, and T is is T. a large class of an example. and distributed according the > 0, . gamma function. Let \/T also be distributed according to distribution with a density Ml/0 = ^(')'"^~^^' '^'>0' I otherwise, I where 7 > {T,Z\, T is to otherwise, I where a > Milgrom and We- variables, there following easily verified Since E[f\Zi, ...,Zm] complements with respect independent conditional on be 1 of is t: gi[Zi\t) gamma Theorem j. random distributions with linear conditional expectations. Example i are strictly affiliated. It . . . and a > , Zm) 0. Using Theorem <"£ strictly affiliated. 1 of -F"ri7 7 t,^! lZi,...,Zm\ 1 Thus {Zi, . . . Milgrom and Weber (1982), one Direct computation yields - £i=i:?Li_^ma + 7 — 1 ,Zm) are information complements with respect to T. verifies that 3 Discriminatory auction 12 Note that the prior distribution of T "conjugate distributions" of gamma in Example distribution; see 2 is an element of the family of DeGroot (1970, Chapter 9). Other distributions with linear conditional expectations can be constructed similarly. Interested readers should consult Ericson (1969) The following example gives Example 3 Let Zi, i = 1,2,. . . and DeGroot random ,m; independent conditional on be with density is otherwise. y Weber (1982) implies > d^ \T\gi{z{\t)/dzidt It is easily verified that also T otherwise, [ The density ofT (1970). variables that are strict information complements. Theorem Vz,t € (0,1). 1 of Milgrom and The same theorem that p, satisfies the strict affiliation inequality. shows that ,x_ ,, ^ , p(i,zi,Z2,...,Zm)-| ( is strictly affiliated. for alii :^j £ The ifae following otherwise Direct com.putation yields = [,Z2...,Zm) ='E\T\Zi for zi,Z2,...,2m t72i,22,...,2,.,<e(o,i) /»(onr=i 5.(2.10 Zi,Z2 = = Z2,...,Zm Zm\ = Finally, one can also verify that d^(p[zi, Z2, (0)1)- . , Zm)/dzidzj > (0,1). lemma is a direct consequence of the definition of information comple- mentarity. All proofs are in an appendix. Lemma 1 Suppose that {Xi,. Then Vi{x,x',y) v"* is strictly with respect to The its first . . ,X„, P) are information complements with respect increasing in x' 6 to V. where vf denotes the partial derivative of y, argument. following proposition shows that with respect to V, then and if (A'l, . of (7) satisfies condition , . . A'„, (i), P) are information complements that is, t; (i,x,x) > b{x) Vi 6 [x,x]. . Discriminatory auction 3 Proposition V. Then 13 1 Suppose that (A'l, v'^{x,x,x) > b{x), Vi € . , . P) are information complements with respect A'„, . and [z, r] the inequality is strict for x > x, where to b is defined in (7). A resale is corollary of Proposition 1 is that b is strictly Thus our assumption that increasing. market buyers can invert the primary bids to obtain the bidders' signal realizations justified. Corollary 1 The strategy b defined in (7) Before proceeding, we first is strictly increasing. lemmas that record two are direct consequences of the defi- nition of affiliation. Lemma 2 Lemma 3 Let (Milgrom and Weber (1982a)) x' > x > y. Then fjk(y|i)//t(y|i) Fk{y\x')/Fi,{x\x') is decreasing in x. < Fk{y\x)/ Fk{x\x). That is, the distribution function Fic{-\x')/ Fk{x'\x') dominates the distribution function Fk{-\x) / Fic{x\x) in the sense of first order stochastic The main Theorem 1 result of this section The n-tuple dominance. is discriminatory auction provided that [Xi, spect to Nash equilibrium of the ,Xn, P) are information complements with re- (6,..., 6), with b as defined in (7), is a . . . V When bidders in the discriminatory auction participate only for the purpose of con- sumption, Milgrom and Weber (1982a) have identified a symmetric Nash equilibrium with a bidding strategy 6^(z) where L{u\x) and identified in = t{u) are as defined in (8). Theorem 1 is - v''(x,x,i) strictly higher Jx r L{u\x)dt{u), The bidding than A uu b (9) strategy for the purpose of resale for every x G {x,x] by an amount equal to Discriminatory auction 3 14 the magnitude of which depends on v^ ted bid.^° It is , the responsiveness of the resale value to the submit- between the resale value and the bids submitted by this informational link bidders in the discriminatory auction that gives the bidders an incentive to signal. since the b is strictly increasing, the resale Of course, buyers can invert the bids announced by the auc- tioneer to obtain the private information of the bidders and, as in Ortega-Reichart (1968) and Milgrom and Roberts (1982), It is in equilibrium no one gets deceived. worth emphasisng that the primary bidders benefit better informed about the true value. relevant information in Xi,X2, . . bidders and the expected price(s) P "informativeness" of for instance, the resale market buyers are if P = or V' if F "centains" all the X„,, then there would be no signalling incentive for the , . If, in the auction would be lower. One might expect to increase with the length of the time period the between the end of the primary auction and the start of the resale market. Next we establish that the symmetric equilibrium metric equilibrium if secondary market buyers identified above is the unique sym- monotonicity condition. The beliefs satisfy a beliefs of the secondary market buyers about the bidders' private information are said to be monotone they are nondecreasing in the bids submitted. For instance, if market buyers believe that bidder when bidder 1 bids I's private information lies in the secondary if the interval [xj(6),i"(6)] then the monotonicity condition on beliefs would imply that x[{-) and b, i"(-) are nondecreasing functions. ^^ Since bidders with higher realizations of their private information would expect higher resale prices, it is natural to expect them to bid more. Therefore monotonicity of beliefs seems to be a natural restriction to impose. Of course, when bids are in the range of the equilibrium bidding strategies, beliefs are obtained by inverting the bidding strategies. Since a symmetric equilibrium and as shown below when is game with symmetric a natural focal point in a players, the only symmetric equilibrium in nondecreasing strategies (6,..., 6) is the resale buyers' beliefs are monotone, we equilibrium will use this when comparing expected revenues between a discriminatory auction and a uniform-price auction. Theorem b is 2 If the secondary market buyers have monotone as defined in (7), is the beliefs then (6, 6,..., 6), where unique symmetric equilibrium in nondecreasing strategies. '"If P = V there is no signalling motive and the equilibrium strategy is as specified in (9), since r''() = V and thus tif (•) = and h{) = 0. Also, when P is "very informative" about V the signalling motive is weak. For example if we let P„ = V + €„ where £„ is, say, uniformly distributed on [— ^, ^] then as n increaaes the resale price becomes less responsive to the players' bids and in the limit the incentive to signal disappears. "In the symmetric equilibrium with z'i(6) = x'{b) = r'(6). For of 6 Theorem > 1, 6(1), x\{b) the resale buyers beliefs are = xt{b) = x, and for b < monotone 6(1), i',(6) (since = itC-) b is = increasing) Z- — 3 Discriminatory auction 15 Public announcement of the auctioneer's information 3.2 Suppose that the auctioneer has private information about V, represented by a random We variable Xq. impact of announcing Xq before the auction on the will consider the expected selling price. Let b[-;xo) be a symmetric equilibrium bidding strategy conditional on Xq b = Xq. It is assumed that and wins then the {b;xo)]Xo) . . . = increasing and differentiable in x. ^e[v\x, = r\b-xo),Yu. ,n,P]Xo) If bidder 1 bids . . ,n,P,Xo = xo] , Putting b. u;''(i',i,y;xo) it is is resale price in this case will be p''Cb~\b;xo),Y\, where b(b 6(-;xo) =E [p^{x' ,Yu ,Yk, = x,n = y,^o = P;xo)\Xi ^o] , straightforward to show that b{x;xo) must satisfy V{x;xo) = °. {rv'^{x,x,x;xo) -b{x;xo)) j! ^t(2;|x;xoJ , ' , + u)f{x,x,y; Xo)fk{y\x-xo)dy. / = where /t(y|x;xo) denotes the conditional density of Y\ given Xi addition, the boundary condition b[r,xo) to (10) with this = 6(i;io) boundary condition it;'^(x,i,x;xo) - / = (10) Jx x and Xq = xq. In The solution -dL{u\x;xo), / Jx fk(u\u;xo) (11) w'^ [x, x, x; xq) must be satisfied. is L{u\x;xo)dt[u;xo) + Jx . .' where L{u\x;xo) = exp<^-/ t(u;xo) = uj /i(u;xo) = — -ds\, (u,u,u;xo), w'}{u,u,y;xo)fk{y\u;xo)dy. / Jx Next, we define conditional information complements. Definition 2 Random ditional on random variables, [Z\, variable Y . , . . Zm), "re said with respect to d^4>{zi,...,zm,y) to be information complements con- random variable w-^ W • T if W OZiOZj where 4>{zi,...,Zm,y) = 'E\f\Zi = Zi,...,Zm = Zm,Y = y] . Discriminatory auction 3 If V , {Xi, A'2, . . . , 16 Xn, P) are information complements conditional on Xq with respect to then a proof identical to that of Theorem equilibrium strategy. This Proposition 2 The is shows that 1 b defined in (11) . the resale . . ,Xn,P) a symmetric stated without proof in the following proposition. n-tuple (b{-;xo), . . are information market participants Xq = xq, provided complements conditional on Xq with respect complements with respect to ,Xn,P) as {X\,X2,- Our main V to and believe that all the bidders follow strategy 6(-;io). Note that the existence of an equilibrium does not depend on whether (XcXi, are information Nash ,b{-;xo)), withb{-;xo) as defined in (11), is a . equilibrium of the discriminatory auction when the auctioneer announces that [Xi, is V . . ,X„,P) . complements conditional on Xq with respect to V. are information be that the expected result in this subsection will . There exists a Nash equilibrium as long selling price under the policy of always reporting A'o cannot be lower than that under any other reporting policy provided that [Xo,Xi,. in the . . ,Xn,P) are information next proposition, that 6(1; zq) Proposition 3 Suppose are information that complements with respect to V .^^ We first show, a increasing function of xq. is {V ,Xo,Xi,. complements with respect .. ,Xn,P) to are affiliated V. Then b{x,Xo) is and that {Xq, Xi, ... ,Xn,P) an increasing function of XQ. The main Theorem result of this section is 3 Suppose that {V ,Xo,Xi, are information . . . ,Xn, P) are complements with respect information cannot lower, and may to V . A affiliated and that (A'o, Ai, . , . . X„,P) policy of publicly revealing the seller's raise, the expected revenue for the seller in a discrimi- natory auction. Given Proposition Theorem Huang 16), is the proof of theorem 3 mimics that of 3, omitted. The interested reader is Milgrom and Weber (1982a, referred to Bikhchandani and (1988) for details. Theorem in iQ. and 3 When depends {Xo,Xi,. critically . . '^Note that this assumption existence of Nash equilibrium. on the fact that under its hypothesis 6(1; xq) is increeising ,Xn, P) are not information complements, 6(r;io) may not be is stronger than the conditional information complementarity required for 4 17 Uniform-price auction an increasing function of This in may turn xq, and revealing Xq may reduce the bidders' incentive to lower the expected revenue for the seller even though (>Yo,Xi,. . . signal. ,Xn,P) are affiliated. 4 Uniform-price auction In a uniform-price auction the bidders The the auction. price they pay is submit sealed bids and the k highest bidders win equal to the {k l)st highest bid. Initially -f- we obtain a candidate for a symmetric Nash equilibrium under the assumption that after the auction the auctioneer reveals the winning bids and the highest losing bid, that winning bidders. We first If is, the price paid by the any of the lower bids are also revealed, our results remain unchanged. obtain strategies that satisfy first-order necessary conditions for a symmetric Ncish equilibrium. Next we show that when there exists a symmetric equilibrium in the uniform-price auction, the auctioneer's expected revenues at this equilibrium are greater than at the symmetric equilibrium of the discriminatory auction. this result is as follows. From The intuition behind the theory of auctions without resale markets compared with a discriminatory auction, a greater amount of information is we know that revealed during a uniform-price auction. This weakens the winners' curse in the uniform-price auction and results in greater revenues for the auctioneer. In addition when the resale markets are informationally linked, as in our model, the primary auction and cheaper to submit higher it is bids in the uniform-price auction in order to signal to the resale market buyers. This in turn further increases the expected revenues from uniform-price auctions. However, the second of these two factors price paid by a bidder conditional can result in in very responsive to the bids submitted there we show by example and P is is uniform-price auction the cis a uniform-price auction. may exist an incentive and upset any purported equilibrium. that this in a upon winning does not increase nonexistence of equilibrium arbitrarily large bids — the fact that his bid If is increased the resale price for the bidders to — is submit In the last part of this section indeed possible, and more generally show that when )t = 1, a constant there does not exist any Nash equilibrium in strictly increasing pure strategies. Uniform-price auction 4 Necessary conditions for a symmetric equilibrium 4.1 As each primary bidder's strategy in the discriminatory auction, the real Suppose that line. If all [bo, bo, ... when buyers differentiable strategies, fco- 18 other bidders use strategy a bid equal to b, then bidder if 1 a function from [x,x\ to in strictly increasing the secondary market believe that in bo, is Nash equilibrium bidder 1 receives information wins the resale price =E r"{6o-i(6),n,...,n,P) to) is a , Xi = all and bidders use x and submits is V\X, = bo'{b),boHbo{Yi)), . . .,boHho{n),P] = E v\xi = bo\b),Yi,...,n,P]. r" is strictly increasing in all its arguments. Note that r"(-) auction, the expected resale price conditional on v"(6o-i(6),i,y) By strict affiliation, v" is =E Xi and Yk = If bidder 1 wins the is [r"(6o-i(6),y,,...,n,P)|Xi strictly increasing in its r'^(-). = x,n = (13) v] arguments. From the definition of v it follows that v"{x',x,y) We show below that 6o U Xi = n"(6|x) is (14) = v^{x,x,x) + -^ (15) as defined in (8). X and bidder = 1 bids b, his expected profit is E[(r"(6o^(6),F,,...,n,P)-6o(n))l^i>,„(y,)}|Xi = i] = E [e [(r"(6o-^(6),yi,...,n,p) - 6o(n)) i{6>6„(fo}|^i'^*J 1^^ = E [(v"(6o^(6), A'i,n) / Jx Taking the Vi',i,y. v {x',x,y) must be given by the following equation: bo{x) where h{x) — first - 6o(n)) l{6>6o(n)}|^i = '-^^ = ^1 (v"(6o'(6),x,y)-6o(y))A(y|x)(iy. derivative of n"(6|i) with respect to {v"{boHb),^,l>o'{b)) - b) b =^ (16) gives hibo\b)\x]{b'o{bo\b)))-' (17) + mbo\b)))-' jf^'\:nboHb),x,y)Uy\x)dy, 4 Uniform-price auction where 6o(i) its first the derivative of bo[x) and n" is argument. For (17) be zero 19 when b = = 6[,(a;) That ^"'(/ l the partial derivative of v" with respect to be a Nash equilibrium, (60, •••.^o) to bo[x). is necessary that relation it is is, 'n ={v"(x,x,x)-bo(x))h{x\x) ^ + /|t;!j'(i,i,y)A{y|i)(iy. where we use the eissumption that 60(1) is 60 is In a uniform-price auction without resale markets Milgrom and Weber (1982a) show that the symmetric Nash equilibrium bidding strategy auctions, the bidding strategy 60 which depends on is strictly higher is fc"(i) than = As v"[x, x, x). 6", for every x v", the responsiveness of the resale value to the G in discriminatory (1,1], by an amount submitted bid. Revenue comparison with the discriminatory auction 4.2 Next we show that when there tion, Rearranging terms implies that strictly increasing. as defined in (15). symmetric equilibrium exists a in the uniform-price auc- generates strictly greater expected revenues than the symmetric equilibrium of the it discriminatory auction.^' Theorem 4 When (60. ,^0) " a symmetric Nash equilibrium in the uniform-price auction, the expected revenues generated at this equilibrium are strictly greater than the expected revenue 4.3 symmetric equilibrium of at the PossibiUty of nonexistence of equiUbrium In this subsection we may of the bidders illustrate the possibility that strong signalling incentives lead to nonexistence of a pure strategy ning bids are announced max{A'i,X2, sity of the discriminatory auction. V . . . . ,Xn, P} Although in a is a sufficient statistic of (Ari,vf2, in this we uniform-price auction. First • Nash equilibrium when winpresent an example in which ,Xn, P) for the posterior den- example the random variables are only weakly illustrates the difficulties that arise when the resale price is on the part affiliated, it very responsive to the winning bids. to that in Theorem 2 establishes that 60 is the only candidate for a symmetric when the resale market buyers have monotone beliefs. This remark also applies to the symmetric equilibrium we will obtain in Section 5. '^An argTiment Bimilar equilibrium 4 Uniform-price auction Example 20 4 Suppose that prior marginal density ofV all the is uniform on Let {bi,b2, . . our attention Let [0,V^]. = Y;[V\Xi,X2,...,X„,P] uniform with support V ,Xn,P}- BlVlZ]. Clearly, the resale price ,bn) be a candidate to The random variables {Xi, X2, [0, l]. Z = ma\{Xi,X2, E[V\Z] > Z E[V\Z=l] = 1. Nash equilibrium, with Xi = It is readily < 6,(X,) it is . , . confirmed that and (19) strictly increasing. < . their conditional den- will be equal <o EjV'lZ], 6, Then x. and , - weakly undominated strategies and thus bidder I's expected payoff when he bids b and The after a uniform-price auction. are independent conditional on are identically distributed, sity is announced bids are 1. We limit Let n"(6|i) be easily verified that if x <x then < n"(6i(x)|x) n"(6i(i)|i), (20) since if bidder 1 bids bi{i), he will always win whenever he would have with a bid 0/61(1) and pay same the others' bid is price. whenever the k-th highest bid of the In addition he will also win in {bi{x),bi{x)). Moreover, since bi is strictly increasing, (19) implies that the resale price if he bids 61(1) is equal to one which is at least as large as the resale price if he wins with a bid 0/61(1). The inequality in (20) is strict as long as there is a nonzero probability that the k-th highest bid is in the interval (61(1), 61(1)). Thus which the only candidate at least Nash equilibrium appears one of the bidders, say bidder bid sufficiently low so that they never win, 1, and to be a somewhat degenerate one always bids one, and at least n the n — k lowest bid bidder 1 always maximizes his profits by bidding one. But is if there is — k in bidders low enough so that any strictly positive cost of participating in the auction (such as an entry fee or a bid preparation cost) then the n — k bidders who never win Next we show that ii k = at this equilibrium will not participate in the auction. 1 and if P is totally uninformative about V , then there does not exist a symmetric Nash equilibrium in strictly increasing strategies. Essentially there is when only one object, and no other information becomes public after the auction, there exists a large incentive for the bidders to responsive to the winning bid. submit high bids, since the resale price is very Xn, P) Uniform-price auction without signalling 5 Proposition 4 Suppose and bid = that k 1 the highest losing bid are and 21 P that announced is V independent of . there does not exist a Then if the winning Nash equilibrium in strictly increasing strategies. However, there exist other examples is uniform on strategy and Xi [0,1] = to bid 6o(x) is for uniform on is which an equilibrium then [V',!], Whether there v"(i,i,i). t;i(-,-,-) exists. = 0, For instance if V' and the equilibrium exist intuitive sufificient conditions under which an equilibrium exists remains an open question. Uniform-price auction without signalling 5 Since there exists a possibility of nonexistence of equilibrium in a uniform-price auction with signalling, we analyze uniform-price auctions when in this section are not announced. Thus the bidders do not have an incentive to information, since they win their bids are not revealed. incentive, by we if are able to show that this uniform-price auction discussed in Section the Treasury 5.1 bill 3. We in at least the winning bids signal their private Even without the signalling two scenarios the expected revenue generated higher than that generated by the discriminatory auction is believe that the scenario first is a plausible one for the case of market. when the winning Existence of a symmetric Nash equilibrium bids are not announced We show below that there exists a symmetric Nash equilibrium difFerentiable strategies, {b' ,b' all bidders use information 6*. Xi = , . . . ,b'), Suppose that bidders x, when buyers i = 2, . . in strictly increeising bidder If b. and secondary market believe that n adopt the strategy , . and submits a bid equal to in the 1 6*, bidder 1 wins the resale price receives is = b[v\xi >n,n,p], where Zj is the j-th order statistic of {Xi, X2, that the signals are identically distributed, r" If bidder 1 . . is . ,Xn)- The equality follows from the fact strictly increasing in both its arguments. wins the auction, the expected resale price conditional on V^ and Xi t}"(i,y) = E [f"(n,P)LVi = x,y% = yl . is 5 Uniform-price auction without signalling By strict affiliation, 0" bids b, his is 22 strictly increasing in its expected profit arguments. Thus, = E 1 is H E[(f"(n,p)-6-(y',))i{,>,.(^^,j|xi = n"{6|x) Xi = x and bidder \{ z] [e [(f"(n,p) - 6*(n)) i(.>t.(n)}|^i.n] |^i = E[(e"(Xx,n)-6'(n))i{,>,.(^^)}|xi = = x] i]. (21) Define 6*(i) Note that Theorem b' is strictly increasing. 5 The n-tuple {b',b' = We show ... ,6') is a t)"{i,i). (22) that [b',b', Yk,yk]- We show model an equilibrium. is in the uniform-price auction price paid by winning bidders in a = that the price paid by winning bidders in the uniform- greater than this. This is ,6*) participate for the purposes of consumption isEiVjA'i lemma the next in price auction in our . bidders follow the strategy 6*. all the Milgrom and Weber (1982a) have shown that the when bidders . Nash equilibrium provided that resale market buyers believe that uniform-price auction . is true even though the primary bidders do not have a signalling motive. Lemma 4 With probability one, the price paid by winning bidders in tion with a resale market is a uniform-price auc- greater than that in a uniform-price auction without resale markets (in which the bidders participate for consumption). That is b'{Y,)>E[v\Xi = Y,,Y,] with probability one. The "true value" of the object for the primary bidders is the resale price. Thus, additional information becomes available after the auction, that winners' curse on the primary bidders would expect the bids Lemma P is 5 weakened. Since there primary auction to increase when in the independent o( {V ,X\,X2,. is . ,Xn)). This is proved in is P is constant, that is P is if no constant, the no signalling motive, one is constant (or when P is the next lemma. With probability one, the bids in the uniform-price auction in the auction) if strictly increase when when no additional information (other than about the bids submitted becomes public after the auction. Uniform-price auction without signalling 5 Revenue comparison with the discriminatory auction 5.2 We 23 obtain two sets of sufficient conditions under which the expected revenues generated at the symmetric equilibrium of the uniform-price auction obtained in the previous subsection, are greater than the expected revenues at the symmetric equilibrium of the discriminatory auction of Section The The 3. first set seems plausible following theorem states that if for the case of Trecisury bill auctions. the public information, P, is not very informative about the true value of the objects, the uniform-price auction generates higher expected revenue than the discriminatory auction. Theorem [x,x] X 6 There [p,p\, M exists a scalar > such that if df"{y,p)/dp < M for y,p E all then the uniform-price auction without signalling generates strictly higher ex- pected revenue than the discriminatory auction with signalling, at their respective symmetric equilibria. In words. on the Theorem 6 says that the ex post public information if resale price conditional on the information released then the auctioneer's expected revenue winning bids are not announced. This is is 1:00pm every Monday. The market comes into arrives little impact One would expect is no signalling when eispect in the auction, bids are submitted before bill results of the auction are play. has higher in the uniform-price auction even true even though there uniform-price auction. In the case of the Treasury resale P from the uniform-price auction, announced around 4:30pm and the that any public information that normally V between 1:00pm and 4:30pm would not be very informative about conditional on the results of the earlier auction. The following theorem gives an alternative scenario under which once again the uniform- price auction generates higher revenues. Essentially the bidders Theorem such that is says that if the signalling motive of not strong, then the uniform-price auction generates higher expected revenue. 7 Suppose that [V ,Xi, if it dr'^{x,yi,. . . . , . . A'„) are strictly affiliated. ,yk,p)/dx < M for all x,yi, ... ,yk,p There exists a scalar € [z,!]*"*"^ x M> [£,p], then the uniform-price auction without signalling generates strictly higher expected revenue than the discriminatory auction with signalling, at their respective symmetric equilibria. A scenario where Theorem informative about the true value 7 is applicable V Then . is when the the impact of public information Xi on the resale price P is very will be small Concluding remarks 6 when bidder 1 Treasury auctions. bill 24 wins. This scenario, however, does not seem to be plausible in the case of Concluding remarks 6 This paper which ric is an exploratory study of competitive bidding when there exists a resale market is informationally linked to the bidding. Nash equilibrium in We discriminatory auctions have shown that there exists a symmet- when winning bids and the highest losing bid are announced provided that the relevant variables are affiliated and are information complements. This monotone is the only symmetric equilibrium beliefs. If his will increase his information is when expected revenue by precommitting to announce his private information We know before the auction. little about the general impact of the ex post information the signalling motive of bidders. For the case of Treasury since we believe that very little additional information short time period between the closing of the Treasury resale market. is the resale market buyers have complementary to that of the bidders, the auctioneer A related question which whether there is bill markets this is becomes publicly available bill in the auction and the opening of the of greater importance for Treasury exist plausible scenarios in P on not important bill auctions which the auctioneer can increase expected revenue by announcing his private information after the auction (and before the secondary markets convene) rather than before the auction. These warrant further investigation. We tion it established the possibility of nonexistence of an equilibrium in a uniform-price auc- when winning bids are announced. However, when there exists a symmetric equilibrium, generates greater expected revenues than the symmetric equilibrium in a discriminatory We auction. auction showed that there also when only for the bidders. exists a the highest losing bid Two is symmetric Nash equilibrium announced, so that there is in a uniform-price no signalling incentive scenarios are provided where the uniform-price auction without sig- nalling generates strictly higher expected revenue for the auctioneer than the discriminatory auction. Some implications of our model deserve attention. First, competitive bids in common knowledge bidders and k price. +j it is eaisy to incorporate non- our model, provided the total amount of noncompetitive bids, before the auction. objects, j of The preceding We j, is can model the primary auction as one with n which are awarded to noncompetitive bidders at the average analysis remains unchanged. The expected profits of the noncom- 6 Concluding remarks petitive bidders 25 positive and equal to the ex ante expected profits of the competitive is minimum and maximum bidders. There tive bid, which may be the reason that resale market buyers do not buy Treasury is a prespecified through noncompetitive bids; and it rnay also explain why quantity for each noncompetibills competitive bidders do not sub- mit only noncompetitive bids while avoiding (presumable costly) information collection.^* Second, the fact that ex ante expected profits of the bidders when P is average price in the auction is strictly less uniform-price auctions without signalling, in expectation, the comparision has been empirically documented by in section 3.1, the primary bidders benefit about the true value, since it if uninformative about Cammack This feature of the weekly Treasury are traded among bill is V'') implies that than the resale price. This (1986). Third, as pointed out decreases the bidders' signalUng incentive. There are several possible extensions of our model. bill. strictly positive (except in the resale market buyers are better informed the primary bidders submit price-quantity pairs and Treasury is First, in the Treaisury bill auction, demand more than one unit of the missing in our model. Second, two weeks before the conduct auction, forward contracts of the Treasury bills to be auctioned the primary bidders. The relationship among the forward prices, bids submitted, and the resale price needs to be investigated. Third, there exists a wide variety of close substitutes of Treasury bills carried as inventories by primary bidders. These close substitutes may have the weekly auction. a significant effect on the interplay between the forward markets and We hope to investigate some of these issues in our future research. '*By renormalizing the units, we can aasume that each competitive bidder demands exactly This allows uj to keep the prespecified maximum demand of noncompetitive bidders than that of competitive bidders. units. m > 1 or zero at a level less , 7 Appendix 26 Appendix 7 Proof of Lemma The l: - (n joint density of (V'.P.A'i,?^!, ...,¥„_!) is l)!/(v,p,iiyi,...,yn-i)l{„i>v2>... >„„_,}• As a consequence, the conditional density of given {P,Xi,Yi,. V' . . ,^,,-1) is f{v,P,x,yi,...,yn-i) '^"^'^^•^'"-'>- f{p,x,yu...,y.-i) Thus {P,Xi,Yi, which fj (i, j/i , information complements. Let rf denote the derivative of ....,Yk) are defined in (l), with respect to is . . . , j/jt , p) is = and strictly increasing function of i' PROOF OF Proposition v'{x, X, x) By = 1, first = /| L{u\x) {vfiu, u, u) rx L[u\x)dt{u) , . . A'„, x' ,Y, = y]- implies, by affiliation, that vf{x,x',y) is a - rx j^^dL{u\x) + viiu, u, u) + viiu, u, u) - ^) (23) dn. P) are information complements with respect Vi(u, u,u) > Vi(u,ti,y) for y < u. Jx Fk[n\u) Next note that Vj". = r'^ then easily verified that write b{x) . , It is I y. - the hypothesis that [Xi, Lemma We i: j/y E[Tf{x,Yi,...,n,P)\Xi Milgrom and Weber (1982a) then 5 of argument. a strictly increasing function of p, vf{x,x',y) Theorem its first It to V and follows that Fk{u\vL) Substituting this relation into (23) gives v'^{x,x,x) - b{x) Note that the above inequality affiliation. r L{u\x) (v^(u,u,ti) + vi{u,u,u)) du > > is strict for x € {x,x] since Vj > and 0. ^3 > by strict I Proof of Corollary have v'^{x,x,x) - b{x) > noting that vf > 0. I l: We Vx > will z. show that The proof b'{x) is > O Vi > z. From Proposition completed by inserting this in (5), 1 we and Appendix 7 27 Proof of Lemma By 3: affiliation we have P > for a, x' > x f,{a\x')h{^\x) < A(a|x)A(/3|x')- Thus > for X y f j^ h{a\x')h{^\x)dad^ < P jjk{a\x)h[fi\x')dadp, which is equivalent to Fi(yjx')(n(i|i) - F,(y|x)) < Fk[y\x)[F,{x\x') - F,(y|x')). Rearranging terms gives < Fk[y\x) - Fkx\x) ^*(vl^') Fk{x\x') • I Proof of Theorem 0- an'^(6(x')|x') ^j Let l: _ - < x' Recall from (4) that x. (^,(,^^-lJ^(,^,^(ld(,,,^ Fk[x\x)\{v (x ,x ,x) v>y^)) ^ r' < d( / AM^ -oyx) ^ h> ( .>\ fk{y\x') , \ ^ / /.r^'U 6(x)) {h\x')r'F,{x'\x')({A-\-,A-K^'))^^^.-y{x') l'k[x'\x) \ < (6'(x'))-^F.(x'|x') , r' d( UAx\ X, x') I - K^'))Wir\ - ^'(^') !k{y\x) J \ ^ ffc(x'|x')an'^(6(x')|x) dh Ft(i'|x) where the first inequality follows from Proposition second inequality follows from 6(x') that < b[x), his ^^^ ' ^ ^' since n''(6(z)ix) Lemma 3. That is, 1, Lemma 1, and Lemma when X\ = x and bidder 2, 1 and the bids 6 = expected profit can be raised by bidding higher. Similar arguments show < = for x' > x. for all x, have thus shown that 6(x) is As a consequence, n''(6|i) we have n'^(6(i)'x) > is maximized for all x the best strategy for bidder 1 > x, by at 6 = h{x). Finally, strict affiliation. when he observes X\ — x, We when Appendix 7 bidders i = 28 2,3, bidders follow . , . . n follow Proof of Theorem Suppose 2: ing strategies. Therefore 6, Weber (1982a), and when the resale market participants believe that 6, the all I 6. Theorem (6^,6, ,...,6,) asymmetric equilibrium is difFerentiable almost everywhere. is proof 14, the complete once we establish that is nondecreas- in Thus, as in Milgrom and b, must be strictly increasing and continuous. Hence b, must satisfy the differential equation (5) and the only solution to this First, 6,(i) = c, is 6 of (7). suppose that Vi G not strictly increasing. That 6, is The [ia,i(,]. resale price bi the is random bidder =E r'{b,Bi,...,Bk,P) where if is affiliated with all the other random the conditional expected resale price =E v'{b,x, 0) Affiliation and monotone nondecreasing in all = + Prob{bidder 1 [lo,!*], both number 1 £i the second expression slightly > A'l market buyers implies that = 1 r' and when Xi = x G c,bi = v' are [xa,Xi\, i] = c}E (24) [(t;'(c, Aj, B*) - c) left after those who bid more than who c = l^^^^jJAi is a x\ , the tie is have been assigned bid Since b,[x) c. and the probability of the event {Bk = c} = strictly is We must have v'{c,Xa,c) > c else a bid bs{xa) = c = x^. Therefore, by strict affiliation, for any xq E (which depends on xq) such that v'{c,Xo,c) > c xq, there define c is in (24) is strictly positive for more when Xi = we v wins of bidders (including bidder 1) when nondecreasing, Bi is Analogous to being declared a winner given that there this probability results in negative profits there exists = wins|Bt the /-th order is Bu...,Bk,P)\Xi = x,Bk = 0]. b,{x) positive (and strictly less than one). (Xfl.ij] 1 E[(v'(c,A'i,B,)-c)l^e^<,j|A'i objects divided by the , ,b,{Xn))- Since 6, . arguments. The expected profit for bidder expectation of the number of objects Vi € bidder beliefs of the resale where the probability of bidder c, if [r'(6, and he submits an equilibrium bid n'{c\x) = b,Bi,...,Bk,P] variables in the model. ij such that b is variable which denotes bidder I's bid and B/ statistic of the others equilibrium bids, {b,{X2), < there exist Xa wins with a bid 1 \y\^bi is, is x a discontinuous = xq. jump If instead of c + Thus ci. bidder in his probability of 1 bids winning Appendix 7 since Bk if v'{c' xq, = > •) , 29 bidder c, v'{c, xq, now win with will 1 Vc' •), > Since beliefs are monotone, probability one. Therefore, there exists c. > £2 such that a bid of tj(xo) leads to greater expected profits than 6,(zo)- This contradicts our assumption that 6, equilibrium strategy. Therefore Next suppose that Since 6, b,{xci). of v'{b,x,0) small enough b,[x') = and b, and can be inverted we b,{y) = = B[[v'{x^,xj,n)-b,{x,))l^y^^^^y\Xi < E = n{b,{xd-€)\xd), - €,Xd,Yk) - [(t;'(id which contradicts our assumption that 6,(id) We record a technical z > lemma 6 (Milgrom and for which all (i) > p[x) (t(z) b,{xd - (ii) x^] = ^"^J an equilibrium bid. is b,{xd) can be ruled out similarly. < a{z) implies p'{z) I 3. (1982a)) Let p{z) anda{z) p[z) = l{yj<xj-f}|^i £)j before proving Proposition Weber and b{x; Xo) If v' implies that for > be differentiable functions (^'{z). Then p[z) > a{z) for X. Proof of Proposition we can show follows > possibility that limjji^fcj(i) Lemma Then, the continuity of /?. < will write v'{x' ,x,y) instead > U'{b,{xd)\x^) The an strictly increasing. has a discontinuity at xj. Consider the case where limiji^ ^ai^) b, strictly increasing is where € must be 6, + ^2 is from 3: =w that 6(i;io) Lemma 6. we have that Let xo < (z, x, > By x'q. x]Xo) > b{x; x'q) =w implies b (i;xo) ^{x-jx'q) we know affiliation > (i, x, x; x'q) b {x;Xq), . then the proposition Suppose that b{x;xo) < 6(i;io). As generalizations of Lemmeis 1, both y and xq, Fk{y\x; io)//it(y|i; iq) 2, and is decreasing in iq, and that Fk{-\x;xo)/Fie[-\x\xo) dominates Fii{-\x;x'q)/ Fk{-\x;x'Q) in the 3, sense of first Vr 6(i;io)\ u;f (i, i', y; iq) is increasing in degree stochzistic dominance. Then = ^ > Id, (^ {x,x,x;xo) \ f (u; r+/f u^jJ,(x, z, y; xq) 77"^ >,^fk{x\x;xo) b{x;xo))-p-;—^ ^iklx|x;ioJ If l^ , b{x;xQ), ^ / ray I'k(x\x;xo} —-—jr+ /' t^i(x, Jx I'k(x\x;xQ) = Jx A(x|x;x'o) ^, u (x,x,x;xo)-6(x;xo))— d, fk{y\x;xQ) , »x/*(y|£i^jdy x, y; Xq) I'k[x\x,xo) 7 Appendix 30 which was to be shown. I Proof of Theorem that of Milgrom and Proof. 3: Weber (1982a, Given Proposition Theorem 3, the proof of theorem 3 mimics 16). Define W{x,z) which is =E \b{x;Xo)\Yk the expected price paid by bidder ditional on bidder = winning when X\ 1 z and by the hypothesis that Xq and ^i are 1 when < i,Xi = z] , the auctioneer publicly reveals Xq, con- and bidder affiliated, 1 bids as Xi = if W2{x,z) > 0. By Proposition x. 3 Note that, by symmetry, the expected revenue for the seller under the policy of publicly reporting Xq is k times E[b{Xi;Xo)\{Yk<Xi}] = E < XuX,] \{n < Xi}] [e [b{XuXo)\n = E[w{XuXi)\{n<X,}], where the equality follows from the law of iterative expectations and the second from first the definition of the seller is W . On the other hand, without reporting Xo, the expected revenue for k times E If we can show [1982, Lemma W{x,x) > that Note 2]. W = E [b{r, = E [w{x, = E [e [v\Xo, Xi = Now we we b[x) then We are done. Xo)\Yk < strategy b{z] Thus W{z,x) •), Xq but his at 2 = a; will Milgrom and Weber Xi - x] = x,n = will x] i] in <x,Xi = x] b{x). after observing optimal choice = will utilize Xo)|n = x,Xi = X, x; v[x,x,x) X, claim that W{x,x) < b{x) implies dW{x,x)/dx prior to learning • that by the law of iterative expectations, first {x, i) [6(Xi)|{n < :^i}] Xi = he z = have to satisfy the x, > b {x). Note first that if bidder 1, were to commit himself to some bidding x, since b{x;xo) is first order condition optimal when Xq = xq. 7 Appendix 31 Then h{x) = (v + i,i,i)-6(z)) < where the W{x,x) < The first equality follows from (6), the b{x), —-rdy vi{i,i,y)-— inequality follows from the hypothesis that first Proof of Theorem 4: Milgrom and Weber [1982, Lemma fact that W2{x,x) > when bidders 0. I 2]. Let P"(z) denote the expected price paid by bidder uniform-price auction, conditional upon winning, use strategy 60 and 1 in Xi = a x. is P"(z) ^ /^o(y)| L If / and the second inequality follows from (25) and the assertion then follows from That rk{x\x) + {v{x,x,x)-W{x,x)) dy vx{x,x,y) / Jx i'k[^\x) dy '""'--' '-' ^7^'ili^"when bidders P'^{x) denotes the corresponding expected price use strategy 6 in a discrim- inatory auction then /^(x) = h{x) (27) i, X (t^'(y,y,y) My) + 77^)d^yix) , bo{y)dL{y\x) where the (14). first (28) equality follows from using integration by parts on (7) Note that L{u\x) and ^*rr increasing, the proof is complete in the sense of first-order, that are probability distributions on if is, we can show ^*)^l| < L[u\x), Vy. Jx ^k[s\x) we have , . r [z, i]- Then since 6o(y) is that jr^/^LS stochastically dominates L[u\x) Since J, and the second from n f k{s\x) ^ Appendix 7 32 Therefore Fkiy\x) _ „ Proof of Proposition where bj, t = 6, = j 1,2, that >—> [x,x\ : . . , . i, bidder price that bidder Lemma 6, 2. I We show that will bidder j, uses strategy if market buyers believe that each bidder t uses strategy has an incentive to deviate from bi[Xi). In fact 1 I's profits are faces = Si Since fk{s\s) Let (61,62,. ..,6„) be a candidate for Nash equilibrium 4: resale 1 r A(«l^) 'FITm'^^^ Fk[s\x) Hy\x) are strictly increasing. n then bidder when Xi = The 5R and the 2,3, ... ,n / jy , = where the inequality follows from r , P{"^^ Fk{x\x) we minimized at a bid of 61(1). max{62(X2), 63(^3),..., 6„(X„)}. Xi and Bi are strictly increasing, and Bi are strictly affiliated is atomless. if We bidder 1 6 is*^ r''{b-\b),Bi) The expected 6,-, show is assume, for simplicity, that By has a density function. The expected resale price wins with a bid equal to will profit for bidder n"(x'|z) 1 = if =-E[v\Xy = b-'{b),Bi] Xi = x and he bids 6i{i') is E[(r"(x',5i)-Bi))l^,^(^,)>^,j|Xi = x] ^'"^^\r"{x'J)-0)g{^\x)d0, h b where Xi = b X. = min{62(i),63(z), The , . . 6„(z)}, and g{-\x) is the conditional density of Si given first-order necessary condition for 61 to be ^5^^! Ox' , 'x' where . =x an equilibrium strategy is ={r-{xM{x))-b,[x))g{h,{x)\x)+ r^'\ux,0)g{0\x)d0 = O^ Jh r" (i,^) denotes the derivative of r" with respect to its first argument. '^Here we assume that the identity of the winning bidder is also disclosed. In our earlier analysis, since restricted attention to symmetric equilibria, such an assumption was not necessary. we Appendix 7 Let i' > 33 X. Then by strict affiliation = (r"(i',fci{x'))-6i(x'))g(fci(x')Ix') < g{h,{x')\J) ^(r"(x',fci(x')) - + |^''*'Vr(^'.^M/3kV/3 6i(x')) + 1^'''^ ^ rr(x',^) ci^ ^^^|^J,^^|^^ g(6i(x')|x') an(x'|x) ax' <,(6i(x')ix) Similarly, we can show < that, for x' x, ox' Thus for any x £ [x, x], n"(x'|x) achieves a global Proof of Theorem Given that bidders 5: n"(6|x) where /t(y|x) is 3,..., 2, ^'\o"(x,y) Proof of Lemma 4: From 6-(n) if I x! we can rewrite (21) as if the definition of h' is x > y. we is positive and only he uses the strategy 6*. have, (29) Since, by strict affiliation, v" in (29) maximized when he wins bidder Vs profits are maximized' 6', = - t)"(y,y))A(y|x)dy, both arguments, the integrand I's profits are at x' n use the conditional density of Yk given Xi. strictly increasing in Thus bidder f =. minimum if if if and only if {Xi > Vt}. Therefore I V* 7^ i, = E[E[y|xi>n,n,p]|xi = n,n] > E[E[i/|xi = n,n,p]|A-i = n,n] = E[^|xi = n,n], where the inequality follows from strict affiliation, and the equality from the law of expectations. Note that the strict inequality above zero probability event. I Proof of Lemma Let affiliated Then random 5: variable, b' and '*If an equality when Y^ be the equilibrium bidding strategy let 6* when = x, iterative which is a P is a strictly P is constant. be the equilibrium bidding strategy when since E[E[vlxi > n,n]\xi,n] = first is P is independent of Xi, or if an equilibrium. is no post-auction public information, then C" is constant in its an expected profit greater than zero. However, (b',...,b') remains there argument and no bid gives bidder t ny\xi > n,n], 7 Appendix 34 we have =E[E V\Xi>Y,,Y,]\Xy = = E[y Xi>x,Yk = x\ = E[V^ Zk+i =x], b;{x) where the Next, x,Yi, = x] (30) last equality follows since the signals are identically distributed. when x y^x, = E{E[v\Xi>Y,,Yk,P]\Xi = b'{x) = E[B[v\z,+ uP]\Zk = x,Y, x,Z,+ i = = x] x] = B{E{v\Zk+uP]\Zk+i=x] = E[v\z,^i^x] = where the first equality follows since the signals are identically distributed, the inequality from strict affiliation, the from (30). becomes an When x equality. = second equality from the definition of x, which Thus the Proof of Theorem to K{x), 6: is Zic, and the last equality a zero probability event, the above strict inequality assertion of By symmetry, lemma is proved. I the expected revenue for the auctioneer n times the unconditional expected payment of bidder 1. Let .ff" and R"^ is equal denote the expected revenue of the auctioneer under uniform-price auction and under discriminatory auction, respectively. Then R" = nxE[6*(n)l{;^.>yJ = kxE[b-{Y,)\Xi>Yk], R' = nxE[6(Xi)l{;e.>yJ = kxE[b{Xi)\Xi>Yk]. Note that the total unconditional expected profits for bidders in equilibrium for the uniform- price auction and for the discriminatory auction are, respectively, nxE[(f"(n,P)-6-(n))l(x,>n}] = A: xE \v\Xi > Yk] - R", E , Appendix 7 35 and = n X E [{r'{X,,Yu.. A:x E [k|Xi > ,¥,, n] - P) - fc*(^i))l{x,>n}] i?"^. Thus, before bidders receive their private information, the two auctions are constant-sum games between the auctioneer and the bidders, with total payoff equal tokxY, \v\Xi '>Y]A. Putting f"(n) = EfT/|xi>n,nl, easily seen that it is E [f''[Yk,p) - f"(n)|^i > n,nj = o, and hence Efr"(n,p)-f"(n)|xi>nl=o. Thus R° = kxY. [f"(n)|xi > n] > i?"* = A: [mx^Ixi > n] X since the (unconditional) expected profit of a bidder in a discriminatory auction strictly positive by R [z,i] X [p,p], is We strictly positive. then .R" > R*^. will show that P is finite. if > f"(n,p)-M{p-P) > f«(n)-M(p-p), from the assumption of strict inequality follows Then df^[y,p)/dp < First note that by affiliation df''{y,p)/dp f"(n,P) where the always = [R" — for all y,p G strict affiliation. For ease of exposition, we assume that the support of )/[k[p — p)) is > M 0. strict affiliation. f"(n)-f"(n,p)<(ir-fl'^)A, and thus = -E[f"(n,p)|xi = n,n] -b'in) < [R" -R')/k~f"{Y,). Taking expectation of the above expression conditional on {Xi > Yt} gives ^" = it X E f6*(yfc)|A'i > Yk] > R'^, M Thus Hence , 7 Appendix 36 which was to be shown. Proof of Theorem {V ,Xi,X2, esis that D = kxB I From Milgrom and Weber 7: ,Xn) are . = n,n] [e [^|i-i strictly afiRliated, > \xi n]-kxE it (1982a, Theorem [v\xun = [e 15) and the hypoth- follows that Xi] - j{Xi)\xi > n] > o, the theorem is where r L{u\x)dt{u), J{x)= and where Let t{u) and L{u\x) are as defined M = D/[kE[Xi\Xi we true. First from recall > Yk]). Lemma in (8).^^ We now show that with M as defined, 4 that, with probability one, 6*(n)>E[y|Xi = n,n]Therefore, E[6*(n)i^i > n] > B[E[v\x, = n,n]i^i > n] and k X E[6*(n)|Xi >n]-kx E[E [v\XuYk = X,] - J{X,)\Xi > Y,] > D. (31) Next note that E [v|Xi,n = where A'l] - J[X,) = h j/i, - K{Xi), defined in (7) and 6 is and where h{u) and L{u\x) are dr'^{x, fc(Xi) . . . , yk,p)/dx < M /*(u|u) Next the hypothesis that as defined in (8). for all i, yi, . . . , yjk,p implies that MXkX k X K{x) < x. Hence Jfc X E > n] < D. [ii'(A'i)|i'i (32) Substituting (32) into (31) gives fc X E which was to be shown. '''Note that to prove this [6*(n)|A-i > n] > p{z) > a(z) for all z > X E [6(Xi)|xi > n] I we also need a technical p{z) and ct{z) be differentiable functions for which Then fc i. (i) lemma that is slightly different from Lemma 6: Let > u(i) and (ii) p{z) < <t(z) implies p'{z) > (7'{z). p{z) The reader should convince herself/himself that this is indeed true. 8 References 37 8 1. S. Bikhchandani and C. Huang (1988), Auctions with resale markets: Treasury 2. bill markets, working paper, E. Commack Treasury bill 4. M. DeGroot 5. W. A model of UCLA. A. Brimmer (1962), Price determination Review of Economics and 3. References in the United States Treasury bill market, Statistics 44, 178-183. (1986), Evidence on bidding strategies and the information contained in auctions, working paper. University of Chicago. Optimal (1970), Ericson (1969), A Statistical Decisions, note on the posterior mean McGraw Hill, New York. of a population mean, Journal of the Roysil StatisticeJ Society 31, pp. 332-334. 6. M. Friedman 7. H. Goldstein (1960), Political 8. R. (1960), Economy McAfee and J. A Program for Monetary The Friedman proposal Stability, New for auctioning York, 63-65. Treasury bills. Journal of 70, 386-392. McMillan (1987), Auctions and bidding. Journal of Economic Lit- erature, 25, 699-738. 9. P. Milgrom (1987), Auction theory, in Advances of the Fifth World Congress of the Econometric Cambridge University 10. P. Milgrom and J. in Economic Theory, Proceedings Society, edited by Truman Bewley, Press. Roberts (1982), Limit pricing and entry under incomplete infor- mation: an equilibrium analysis, Econometrica 50, 443-459. 11. P. Milgrom and R. Weber (1982a), A theory of auctions and competitive bidding, Econometrica 50, 1089-1122. 12. P. Milgrom and R. Weber (1982b), The value of information in a sealed-bid auction. Journal of Mathematical Economics 10, 105-114. 13. A. Ortega-Reichart (1968), Models of Competitive Bidding under Uncertainty, Ph.D. dissertation, Stanford University. 8 References 14. J. 38 Parsons and A. Raviv (1985), Underpricing of seasoned issues, Journal of Financial Economics 14, 377-397. 15. J. Riley (1988), Ex post information in auctions, forthcoming in Review o{ Economic Studies. 16. J. Tiemann (1985), Applications of auction games in mergers and acquisitions: The white knight takeover defense, mimeo. Graduate School of Business Administration, Harvard University. 17. V. Smith (1966), Bidding theory and the Treasury nation increase 18. R. bill prices? bill Review of Economics and auction: Does price discrimi- Statistics 48, 141-146. Wilson (1969), Competitive bidding with disparate information, Management Sci- ence 15, 446-448. 19. R. Wilson (1988), Strategic analysis of auctions, working paper. Graduate School of Business, Stanford University. V(^l <^^\ Date Due NO 12*90 FEB 2 8?^ MIT LIBRARIES DUPL 3 TOflD 1 D0577M31 7