GROUP SELECTION AND THE LIMITS TO ALTRUISM Paul H. Rubin Department of Economics and School of Law Emory University Atlanta, GA 30322-2240 Voice: 404-727-6365 Fax: 404-727-4639 Email: prubin@emory.edu Keywords: evolution, altruism, morality, utilitarianism, Marxism, Rawls, fairness. JEL D634 Synopsis: Several evolutionary mechanisms have been identified in the literature that would generate altruism in humans. The most powerful (except for kin selection) and most controversial is group selection, as recently analyzed by Sober and D.S. Wilson. I do not take a stand on the issue of the existence of group selection. Instead, I examine the level of human altruism that could exist if group selection were an engine of human evolution. For the Sober and Wilson mechanism to work, groups practicing altruism must grow faster than other groups. I call altruistic behavior that would lead to faster growth “efficient altruism.” This often consists of cooperation in a prisoner’s dilemma. Altruistic acts such as helping a temporarily hungry or injured person would qualify as efficient altruism. Efficient altruism would also require monitoring recipients to avoid shirking. Utilitarianism would be an ethical system consistent with efficient altruism, but Marxism or the Rawlsian system would not. Discussions of efficient altruism also help understand intuitions about fairness. We perceive those behaviors as “fair” that are consistent with efficient altruism. It is important to understand that, even if humans are selected to be altruistic, the forms of altruism that might exist must be carefully considered and circumscribed. Introduction A major debate in biology and in particular in the study of human evolution is the extent and significance of group selection. Since the work of Williams (1966) it has generally been thought that any form of group selection was impossible because free riding within the group would eliminate the possibility. More recently, Sober and D.S. Wilson (1998) have reignited the debate. They do not propose the old “good of the species” form of group selection as advocated by Wynne-Edwards (1962) and discredited by Williams (1966). Rather, they argue that in some circumstances groups containing more altruists1 would grow faster than groups with fewer altruists, even though the number of altruists within each type of group would decrease over time. If the groups remain isolated, then the standard result would obtain, and the number of altruists in each group and thus in the population would ultimately go to zero. However, if the groups periodically split and reform, then the number of altruists in the population could increase. They also argue that this mechanism would have been particularly important in human evolution, and present some data indicating that human behavior is consistent with their argument.2 I do not want to address the issue of group selection here. Rather, I am going to assume for the purpose of argument that there is group selection of exactly the sort that Sober and Wilson describe. I ask the question, What are the implications of group selection for the analysis of human altruism? This is consistent with Alexander’s (1987, p. 192) argument that “morality tends to mimic the effects of group selection.” Also, it is well known that Darwin (1871) based his views of evolved morality on group selection, although not of the sort discussed by Sober and Wilson. The rationale for this examination is as follows: Analysts have identified several individually based mechanisms for altruism. Some are: reciprocal altruism; kin selection; the willingness of some to punish others for shirking, or for not punishing those who refuse to punish shirkers (second degree punishment; Axelrod, 1997; Boyd and Richerson, 1992; Hirshleifer and Martinez-Coll, 1988); assortment by degrees of altruism, so that more altruistic persons interact with others with the same behaviors; and asymmetric interaction, such as Maynard Smith’s (1982) “bourgeois” strategy, in which the first player to arrive wins the resource.3 Hirshleifer (1999) has a particularly nice GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 2 discussion of alternative mechanisms for evolution of cooperation, or altruism. But while all of these mechanisms are plausible and all would generate some altruism, none are as powerful at generating altruism among non-related individuals as is complete group selection. Therefore, if we can determine the types of altruism that would be favored by group selection, we can understand the limits of altruism. If some suggested form of altruism is not compatible with group selection, then it is unlikely that humans have evolved a preference for this behavior. Of course, the converse may not be true: if some mechanism is consistent with group selection, this does not prove that this mechanism exists unless we are confident that some form of group selection actually occurred or unless we can identify some mechanism consistent with individual selection to generate the behavior. Nonetheless, consideration of group selection will give us an “upper bound” on the level and form of evolved human altruism. The maintained assumption is that any “tastes” for altruism would have evolved and we living humans would have those tastes that would have led to increased fitness of our ancestors in the environment of evolutionary adaptatedness (EEA). We would perceive these tastes as a sense of “right” or morality, but this feeling has evolved. (This point is discussed in many places; see for example Ruse and E.O. Wilson, 1986.) Then humans today can be no more altruistic than it would have paid to be if there was group selection in the EEA because group selection sets the limits for altruism. This general approach to political tastes is explained and amplified in Rubin (2000a). The other point to note is that most agree that the EEA was an environment of intense group competition. Predation by hominids on hominids or by humans on humans was a very important factor in the EEA. Many analysts believe that this selection pressure was responsible for the tremendous increase in intelligence and brain size as our ancestors evolved from an ape like creature to become humans. Thus, in evolutionary times, group size was important. That is, having more individuals in the group up to the limit that could be supported by the existing technology at a given time was a positive externality for each member. This is a consequence of the “balance of power” argument that the purpose of sociality was defense against predators – primarily other hominids (Alexander, 1987). GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 3 Then there are circumstances in which transfers to some individuals would have been in the group interest, and presumably in those circumstances the utility or wellbeing of the recipients would have become an element in the utility functions of the donors. The main point is that in situations where a low cost transfer could save the life of the recipient and enable him to continue to participate in the group defense, or enable her to reproduce other defenders, then transfers would have been desired. There are probably two situations that would have been relevant in the EEA, and moreover which are still relevant today (because we have tastes evolved in the EEA.) These are temporary income shortfalls, which could lead to starvation, and illness or injury, which could lead to death. Both are discussed below. There is another mechanism, in addition to direct competition, that would have favored more efficient preferences. Mobility between groups was often possible in the EEA (as it is today.) Then groups with preferences for more efficient policies would have been richer or more successful (or fit), and in many cases individuals would have voluntarily chosen such groups. This raises the issue of cultural rather than biological selection of preferences. The most useful models of such selection processes allow genes and culture to interact; see Boyd and Richerson (1985). In their model, there is evolutionary interaction between genes and culture. For example, if cultural norms in some group favor some form of altruism, then individuals who most easily adapt to this form of altruism will be more successful in that group. Cultural and genetic evolution can reinforce each other. But in this paper I focus on the genetic part of the process. The analysis here is positive, not normative. I ask what sorts of tastes humans might have for altruism. In designing optimal policies (that is, in undertaking normative analysis) it is possible to choose other policies that may not agree with these tastes. However, decision-makers should be aware of the sorts of constraints under which they operate. If policies are adopted that conflict with these evolved tastes, then there will be some discontent with these policies, and they will be more expensive to implement. There may also be pressure to change the policies. I will from time to time point out situations where current policies agree with or conflict with evolved tastes. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 4 Efficient Altruism The analysis of group selection leads to the notion of efficient altruism. In the Sober and Wilson analysis, groups with altruists grow faster, and this explains the survival of altruism in the population. But only some types of altruism would generate this differential growth rate. Group selection is not an indiscriminate mechanism for generating everything that is called or appears to be altruism, or for indiscriminate “generosity.” Rather, some behaviors that some have called altruistic might actually lead groups that practiced these behaviors (or that had many individuals practicing these behaviors) to grow more slowly. For example, Binmore (1994, p. 259) argues that in a “first best” world (a world with costless enforcement of social contracts) there would be much more generosity than we actually observe. But the argument here is that natural selection could not have generated preferences for such behavior in humans. I call altruism that does lead to increased growth of groups with more such altruists (or that would have done so in the EEA) “efficient altruism.” The general example of such efficient altruism would be cooperation in some variant of a prisoner’s dilemma game. The prisoner’s dilemma is the generic cooperatedon’t cooperate game, where cooperation is efficient for the cooperators jointly in that it leads to greater payoffs for both participants, but non-cooperation is the best strategy for each player. Then some group in which more people played “cooperate” would have greater income and wealth than some group where fewer individuals cooperated, and the population in the more cooperative would grow more quickly. E.O. Wilson (1998, p. 252) relates morality to cooperation in a prisoner’s dilemma; see generally Binmore (1994). Sober and Wilson (1998, Chapter 5) show that most or all societies enforce “social norms.” One important function of such norms is to induce cooperation and reciprocation – that is, to force a cooperative solution to a prisoner’s dilemma like game. Cooperation: Examples One example of efficient altruism would be cooperation in the purchase or creation of public goods. In the EEA, many things that we think of as public goods (roads, public buildings) would not have been meaningful. But law and order – enforcement of rules – would have been a useful goal. Much of the discussion in Sober GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 5 and Wilson and others of rule enforcement (punishment for rule violation) and second level rule enforcement (punishment for not punishing rule violations) may be construed as contribution to a public good. Thus, one form of altruism that may be favored in human populations is providing institutions or mechanisms for enforcement of rules. Rules and rule enforcement would lead to larger incomes or increased survival in groups, and to exactly the sort of differential growth that is required in the Sober and Wilson model. Rule enforcement in universal among humans (Brown, p. 138). Cooperation in productive activities would also be an efficient form of altruism. An example is group hunting. Indeed, Ridley (1996) indicates that big game was the first public good. Cooperation would be to do one’s share even if the activity is dangerous; shirking or non-cooperation would be to free ride and not do one’s assigned task. Then if all cooperate the hunt will be more successful, so this is exactly a prisoner’s dilemma. Groups with hunters who were more cooperative (or, more generally, workers who were more cooperative) would grow faster than others, and so this form or altruism could survive in the EEA in a Sober and Wilson process. Similarly, if group conflict was an issue in the EEA – and most think that such conflict has been an ongoing part of human and even prehuman existence – then contributions to defense or offense would also have been a public good. The main form of this public good would probably have been rewards to individuals, largely young males, who participated in defense or in predation, and there seems to be much evidence that such rewards are in fact forthcoming. Thus, while individuals may have participated in defensive or offensive “military” activities for private motives, the reason that private motives would have been available is because there were public rewards to such participation. Cooperation by young males in offensive or defensive activities (or in their contemporary surrogates, such as gangs or sports) is a form of altruism that would have survived a group selection process. Another form of altruism – one more consistent with the normal usage of the term – would have been food sharing. Food sharing as a form of insurance could again have been a form of efficient altruism. If one person is low on food today (perhaps because a hunt was unsuccessful) he may die. If another shares his food, this will have desirable effects on the group, since it will lead to a larger group size which is useful for protection GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 6 (Alexander, 1987). The prisoner’s dilemma occurs because sharing in such circumstances is efficient for both parties, but the party who first receives the transfer has an incentive to shirk and not reciprocate. Reciprocal altruism (Trivers, 1971) can make this policy privately as well as socially desirable, but in either case it would be an efficient form or altruism. Binmore (1994) points out that reciprocal altruism is another name for the notion in game theory that cooperative solutions can be reached in repeated games – the so-called “folk theorem.” Moreover, some of the rules that the group might efficiently enforce would be rules mandating sharing and reciprocation. A formal analysis of this problem is in Binmore (1994, pp. 212-226). We would expect humans to agree to share food, and food sharing is universal among humans: Brown, 1991, p. 138. But it is important to note that such food sharing would be limited and would occur only in well-defined circumstances. Sharing creates risks of shirking of two sorts. One is not sharing when one is obliged to (the EEA equivalent of tax evasion). The other is shirking in food seeking or production in order to free ride on those who do produce and share (the EEA equivalent of welfare fraud). Kelly (1995, Chapter 5) discusses these issues and shows that sharing, shirking, and detection of shirking all exist among huntergatherers; see also Boehm (1999a). Then food sharing would not be efficient if the recipient were lacking in food because of shirking. In the EEA, societies were relatively small, and monitoring to reduce shirking would have been possible. Rubin (1982) stresses the difficulty in monitoring shirking under current conditions as compared with conditions in the EEA. Cosmides and Tooby (1992) point out that this issue still informs debate on welfare and other contemporary sharing systems. Proponents of such programs stress the random nature of poverty and the role of luck4; opponents stress shirking. Both sides are trying to capitalize on evolved tastes for or against redistribution in particular circumstances. The difficulty is in trying to design a system of transfers in a world where monitoring of recipients to detect shirking is difficult. McGuire (1992) points out that there are mental mechanisms for calculating the appropriate amount of moralistic aggression associated with differing forms and degrees of shirking. In addition to food sharing, assistance to the ill, hurt or injured who would be expected to recover would have been an efficient form of altruism. This is because someone hurt or injured could, upon recovery, again become a useful member of the GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 7 band. Injury was probably much more common in the EEA than today; injury has been falling steadily in historic times, and is lower now than even in our own recent past. Methods of production in the EEA, such as hunting, would have been particularly prone to injury. Even today many view medical care as a “necessity” and are opposed to treating medical care as simply another expenditure item; this may be because such a taste for treating medical care as different could have evolved in the EEA. Moreover, the nature of care in the EEA was probably such that shirking in the form of consumption of additional care would not have been an alternative. This may be why people today think in terms of the amount of medical care “needed” without realizing that the amount of care consumed can be increased if costs are reduced. None of these forms of altruism would have supported providing food or other resources to a non-productive individual who was not expected to become productive, or to a shirker who was expected to continue to shirk. That is, altruism might have supported transfers to a temporarily unlucky individual or to an individual who was temporarily incapacitated through illness or injury. But it would not have supported transfers to someone who would be expected to remain unproductive. (Kin selection mechanisms might have induced family members to provide some support, for example, to the elderly, and there is evidence that children support aged and unproductive parents in hunter gatherer societies, as long as such support does not lead to excessive deprivation for children or grandchildren.) Continual transfers to non-productive individuals would have been a drain on a band and would have reduced the ability to compete with other bands in the EEA. Boehm (1999a; 1999b) indicates that among hunter-gatherers older individuals who cannot walk are often killed or abandoned. Westermarck (1912) has a lengthy discussion of this issue in Volume 1, Chapter 17, and discusses the killing of certain sick persons as well. Binmore (1994, p. 259) asks why it is that people seem to feel less empathy towards schizophrenic homeless persons. These attitudes and behaviors are consistent with the argument here. There is substantial evidence that in hunter-gatherer societies, there was what has been called an “egalitarian ethic.” (Boehm, 1993, 1999b; Knauft, 1991; Wiessner, 1996.) This might seem to imply that we have inherited from our hunter-gatherer ancestors a desire for income transfers and equality of outcome. But careful reading of Boehm GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 8 (especially 1999b) indicates that what was actually involved was a desire not to be dominated; this is consistent with Knauft’s analysis, although Knauft does not state this as directly as does Boehm. That is, individuals who expected to be the lower ranked members of any hierarchy banded together to prevent potential higher ranked members from actually forming a hierarchy. Food sharing (especially of meat) was virtually universal in such societies, but care is taken not to use such sharing to provide excess status or power to successful hunters (Wiessner, 1996). There is no evidence that potentially dominant members wanted to eliminate hierarchies. Rather, individuals wanted to avoid being dominated. Humans still have such preferences. For example, Buchanan and Tullock (1965) provide a theory of constitutions based on this desire. Bentham, Yes; Marx and Rawls, No Three standard philosophical systems that discuss the optimal moral stance for society are utilitarianism (Bentham, 1781/1988), Marxism (Marx, 1888) or, more generally socialism, and the Rawlsian system (Rawls, 1971). Utilitarianism is roughly consistent with the form of altruism that would occur under group selection; the Rawls “difference principle” is not, nor is a communist or socialist system. My analysis here is obviously sketchy and uninformed by academic discussions of moral theory. However, Posner (1999) indicates that such discussions are not very fruitful anyway. E.O. Wilson (1998) argues that moral philosophy is not generally based on empirical biological knowledge. Alexander (1987, p. 145-165) discusses the relationship between moral philosophy and biology as viewed by moral philosophers. He concludes that in general moral philosophers have not paid adequate attention to biology, and have not taken account of biological knowledge. Earlier, Westermarck (1932) had reached a similar conclusion regarding an earlier generation of moral philosophers. There is also a body of literature by biological informed writers applying biological knowledge to moral discourse. Westermarck (1912, 1932) was an early scholar working in this vein, although his writing is impaired by the limited knowledge of biology available when he was writing; for example, he commonly writes of things “useful for the species.” Westermarck does sometimes refer to natural selection (as in the famous discussion of incest avoidance based on youthful propinquity: Westermarck, GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 9 1912, Volume II, Chapter 40) but in general his method of analysis is comparative rather than evolutionary. This may be because the analytical tools needed to derive specific explanations (e.g., theories of kin selection and of reciprocal altruism) were not available. I believe that Alexander (1987) is the best example of this literature, and my writing here and elsewhere is deeply informed by his analysis. Binmore (1994) is also an analysis of similar issues, based on both evolutionary theory and game theory. Boehm (1999b) has a discussion of the evolved human desire to morally justify particular actions. I will refer to this literature from time to time. However, I do not believe that the basic point of this article has been made within this literature. Bentham Something approximating utilitarianism might well be consistent with efficient altruism. Utilitarianism argues for maximizing some function of individual utilities. Utility functions are related to (if not the same as) fitness (Hirshleifer, 1977): we get pleasure from those things that led to increased reproductive success in the EEA and pain from those things that hindered our ancestors’reproductive success (Johnson, 1999). Thus, maximization of the sum of individual utilities would be the equivalent of maximizing group fitness in the EEA, and would have exactly been the result of efficient altruism in a group selection process. This may be why utilitarianism has been a long lived and successful moral theory – it is a theory that is consistent with our evolved moral preferences. Economists use an essentially utilitarian theory in welfare economics. But there is a deep professional belief in the impossibility of “interpersonal comparisons of utility.” That is, economists are unwilling to compare utilities across persons. The argument made here will at least partially solve the problem of interpersonal comparison. That is, , we can in some circumstances make interpersonal comparisons of utility based on efficient altruism. In particular, in those circumstances discussed above, where the potential recipient of altruism can have his life saved by a relatively small transfer, then humans are often willing to make the transfer, and are at least implicitly making an interpersonal comparison. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 10 Posner (1999) indicates that most academic criticisms of utilitarianism proceed by showing that the logical implications of utilitarianism are undesirable if the argument is carried to its logical extremes. But the argument discussed here is that utilitarianism is essentially the result of fitness maximizing preferences within the relevant group. On this reading, any implications of utilitarianism that conflict with fitness maximization for the group (for example, the sadist who gains great utility from torture) are illegitimate extensions of the theory, and should be ignored. Utilitarianism would perhaps be modified to maximization of utility in terms that would have been consistent with fitness maximization for members of the group in the EEA. Of course, we now extend our altruistic preferences beyond the level of the group, so that some fitness maximizing behaviors – for example, massacre of males of neighboring tribes – would no longer be considered consistent with utilitarianism. J.Q. Wilson (1993) and Binmore (1994) among others discuss tendencies to expand the set of humans included within the group. Indeed, Westermarck (1932) makes a similar point. Alexander (1987) discusses utilitarianism. He indicates (p. 88) that “The only time that utilitarianism … is predicted by evolutionary theory is when the interests of the group … and the individual coincide… ” Alexander’s argument differs from that made here in two respects. First, he is discussing the extent to which an individual will behave in a utilitarian manner; I am concerned with utilitarianism as a social philosophy. Second, Alexander is hostile to group selection arguments (although in some of his discussion “generalized reciprocity” acts almost like group selection), and I am proceeding here as if such mechanisms were feasible. If they are not and if there is no individual selection mechanism that will generate some version of utilitarianism, then it may be a difficult philosophy to justify in biological terms. Rawls Consider Rawls. Rawls argues that humans behind a “veil of ignorance” would choose an income distribution system based on the “difference principle.”5 This says that any inequality in income distribution can be justified only if it benefits the worst off individuals in society. By arguing that this is the rule individuals would choose behind the veil, Rawls is arguing that people are exceedingly risk averse. A huge amount has GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 11 been written about Rawls’analysis, and I do not plan a thorough analysis. But note that this principle is not consistent with efficient altruism as defined above. A group adopting this principle would not have increased its fitness. Consider: Group A does not adopt Rawls’principle. All active adult males have a nutritional level of 2500 calories per day except for one individual who obtains 2000 and is somewhat malnourished (but perhaps not in danger of immediate death). Group B begins with the same distribution but adopts the difference principle and redistributes accordingly. The efficiency costs of redistribution (deadweight losses due to “taxation” in the form of forced transfers and shirking in he expectation of receiving the benefits of redistribution) are so high that once the redistributive process has run its course total income falls. As a result, at equilibrium, everyone in the group has a nutritional level of 2100 calories per day. According to Rawls, Group B is morally superior to Group A because the poorest person in B has 2100 calories and the poorest in A has only 2000. But even though Rawls and his disciples may prefer this outcome, it is not the outcome that would be selected in the EEA. Rather, members of Group A would translate their extra nutrition into increased strength or more hand axes and likely massacre the males (at least) in Group B. (Or, in a more benign scenario, all members of Group B except for the original poorest person would migrate to Group A.) In other words, the costs of Rawls’policy is so large that it would not meet the Sober and Wilson criterion for being the outcome of a group selection process, and so it is unlikely that humans have been selected to desire Rawls’preferred outcome. That is, members of Group B would not be our ancestors and their set of tastes would not have survived. We are descended from people or proto-humans with tastes more like those of Group A.6 Moreover, tastes are exactly relevant for analyzing Rawls’analysis, since he asks what people in the original position would choose – an exact question of tastes. Alexander (1987) has a discussion of Rawls. However, he confines his analysis to a discussion of the “veil of ignorance,” arguing that this may be an appropriate construction in a society in which individuals are less able to foresee the positions of their descendents. He does not discuss in detail the hypothesized outcome of the process. Wilson (1998, p. 249) does indicate that Rawls’ “offered no evidence that justice-asfairness is consistent with human nature.” GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 12 Marx A socialist system divorces returns from inputs. Such systems are inefficient and lead to reductions in output. As such, in a highly competitive environment such as the EEA, they could not survive. Indeed, extreme socialist regimes apparently cannot survive even in our relatively more relaxed environment. Moreover, tastes for socialism would not have evolved since those with such tastes would not have done well. Bailey (1992) has shown that efficient definitions of property rights are virtually universal in hunter-gatherers. Brown (1991, p. 139-140) indicates that private property and inheritance are universal among humans. Boehm (1997, p. S117) argues that socialism is a form of altruism but one that is “so very difficult to execute.” The difficulty is associated with its inefficiency, and more generally with evolved preferences that are inconsistent with this social arrangement. Elsewhere Boehm (1999b) argues that Marx failed by ignoring the power of the human desire for dominance. (Other evolutionary based criticisms of Marx are presented in Rubin, 2000b. This argues that Marxism is an error associated with confusion of types of hierarchies. It is also pointed out that Marxism is a form of group selection, with class, or, in neo-Marxism, race, class and gender as the group characteristics.) Fairness Humans have a preference for “fairness.” Trivers (1971) indicates that we feel “moralistic aggression” if we feel that we have been treated unfairly; this is part of the mechanism for policing reciprocal altruism. Westermarck (1912) discusses a similar point, which he calls “moral indignation.” Binmore (1994) argues that our notions of fairness are an equilibrium selection device – a method of selecting a particular Pareto improving equilibrium when many are available. But the concept of fairness is not well defined. Lakoff (1996, pp. 60-61) has an interesting categorization of various views of fairness. He suggests that there are at least 10 ways in which the term can be used: 1) 2) 3) 4) Equality of distribution (one child, one cookie) Equality of opportunity (one person, one raffle ticket) Procedural distribution (playing by the rules determines what you get) Rights-based fairness (you get what you have a right to) GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 13 5) 6) 7) 8) 9) Need-based fairness (the more you need, the more you have a right to) Scalar distribution (the more you work, the more you get) Contractual distribution (you get what you agree to) Equal distribution of responsibility (we share the burden equally) Scalar distribution of responsibilities (the greater your abilities, the greater your responsibilities) 10) Equal distribution of power (one person, one vote) Lakoff does not provide any basis for this list of meanings or intuitions. (Indeed, Carroll, 1999, has recently provided a general critique of Lakoff’s work indicating that the work is not grounded in evolutionary theory, and would be improved if it were.) But it is easy to see that some of Lakoff’s categories are consistent with the evolutionary explanation for altruism that is proposed here. That is, under proper circumstances many of Lakoff’s categories could have been associated with a form of efficient altruism. (Of course, under different circumstances, many of these categories could be mutually inconsistent, which is why economists generally avoid the use of the concept of fairness.) Moreover, the actions associated with many of these concepts are universal among humans (Brown, 1991.) I will briefly consider each. Equality of distribution: This would be consistent with food sharing, which, as discussed above, is sometimes an efficient form of altruism. Some food sharing, although not equality of distribution, is universal among humans (Brown, 1991, p. 138.) Full equality, however, would not be an efficient form of altruism because it would lead to excessive shirking. Equality of opportunity: This would probably have been the norm in the EEA. It would also have served to reduce the power of dominant individuals by reducing their ability to pass on their success to their children. Among mobile hunter-gatherers and their predecessors, hereditary wealth would have been minimal (since the mobile nature of the society meant that wealth in general was minimal), so there would have been a tendency towards de facto equality of opportunity. Today the term is used loosely: no one (in America at least) advocates true equality of opportunity, since this would mean removing all children from their parents at birth and raising them communally. Otherwise, differential parental abilities in child raising will effect children. Moreover, children can of course inherit wealth in our society. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 14 Procedural distribution: At least to some extent, playing by the rules would have been important. Brown (1991, p. 138) indicates that rules are universal among humans and that sanctions for violations are also universal. If the rules are themselves aimed at forcing cooperation in prisoner’s dilemmas and at enforcing reciprocity as Sober and Wilson indicate, then tying income distribution to obeying rules would be efficient. Rights-based fairness: If rights are defined efficiently, then this form of fairness would also be efficient. Private property rights are of course an efficient way to define rights (e.g., Pipes, 1999). Brown (1991, p. 139-140) does indicate that ownership of property and inheritance of property are universal among humans. Bailey (1992) shows that among hunter-gatherers, property rights are generally defined efficiently. To the extent that rights based fairness is a form of property rights based fairness, then we can understand this notion and associated preferences. Need-based fairness: This is consistent with an insurance model of sharing. Those who have a shortfall in a period receive transfers. This will keep them alive as potential fighters when needed. This form of behavior may also be part of a process of reciprocal altruism. Of course, for this form of altruism to be efficient, some monitoring to reduce shirking is needed. Moreover, “need” would be carefully circumscribed, perhaps including only being at risk of or close to immediate death. Scalar distribution: This is an efficient principle of distribution because it provides incentives for work. In many hunter-gatherer societies, the hunter who kills the game has rights to distribute it, subject to various social norms. If this were the pattern in the EEA (and chimpanzees also behave in this way, suggesting that it is an evolutionary old behavior in the hominid line) then it might be an evolved principle of distribution and a form of efficient altruism. Contractual distribution: This would be equivalent to reciprocal altruism, an agreement to return a gift, and would be an efficient method of solving intertemporal prisoner’s dilemmas. A norm of reciprocity is universal among humans (Brown, 1991, p. 139). Of course, today we have third party (court) enforcement of contracts. Equal distribution of responsibility: This principle would have served to constrain dominant individuals in society, and to create more equality. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 15 Scalar distribution of responsibilities: This seems to have been an important principle in hunter-gatherers. Better, more skilled hunters do catch more game even though they are obligated share much of their catch with others. (Kelly, 1995, p. 177179.) Because of this enforced sharing, the willingness of skilled hunters to catch more game is itself somewhat of a puzzle. Kelly provides some hypotheses to explain the behavior, but ultimately the reason seems to be a mystery. Nonetheless, such behavior would be an efficient form of altruism and could be consistent with a group selection model. Of course, today, in a market economy rewards are relatively closely related to effort. Equal distribution of power: As Boehm (1993, 1999b) and Knauft (1991) have argued, in small hunter-gatherer bands, which were probably the most important human and hominid population structure in the EEA and for most of the existence of humans and our immediate ancestors, there is something like a “reverse dominance hierarchy.” This is interpreted to mean that no individual is dominant and decisions are jointly made. Brown (1991, p. 138) indicates that no humans have perfect democracy and none have complete autocracy, so “they always have a de facto oligarchy.” This principle would be associated with reducing the power of dominant individuals, and with Boehm’s “reverse dominance hierarchy.” While many human societies have been centrally run for the benefit of dominant individuals (Betzig, 1986) there seems to be a preference for relatively democratic societies when possible. Thus we see that at least five of Lakoff’s principles are associated with efficiency: procedural distribution; rights based fairness; scalar distribution; contractual distribution; and scalar distribution of responsibilities. Two principles are associated with insurance: equality of distribution and need based fairness. The other three principles, equality of opportunity, equal distribution of responsibility, and equal distribution of power, have the effect of reducing the power of dominants. Our intuitions about fairness seem to be consistent with evolution of tastes in the directions discussed in this paper. Of course, as mentioned above, it is easy to construct examples where these principles conflict with each other. For some examples, equality of opportunity can lead to inequality of distribution, and either procedural distribution or rights based fairness can be inconsistent with need-based fairness. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 16 This list and the discussion may seem trivial. But this is because the notions are so intuitive that it is not easy to see how there could exist alternatives. Consider some potential notions of fairness or morality that no one would endorse: Take from the poor and give to the rich. Cheaters who cheat fellow group members deserve as much as they can get away with. Promising to return a favor and then reneging is moral. Compensation should be inversely related to effort. Good hunters should stay at home and poor hunters should have the responsibility for bringing in game. Each person should do that at which he is worst (has a comparative disadvantage). The least competent person, perhaps a child, should make decisions for the group. Dictatorship is a moral form of government. No good deed should go unpunished.7 Obviously, these are silly principles, and clearly not intuitively “fair” in any sense. But that is the point: they do not seem fair or desirable, and they would have been associated with group and individual death in the EEA. If any of our putative ancestors had beliefs such as these, they did not survive to be our ancestors. We have those intuitive notions of fairness that led to survival, and we still view these behaviors as fair. J.Q. Wilson (1993) also categorizes various measures of fairness: fairness as equity; fairness as reciprocity; and fairness as impartiality. This categorization is less nuanced than that of Lakoff, but consistent with it: reciprocity is the basis of Lakoff’s third, fourth, and seventh principle; equity is consistent with the first, second, and perhaps eighth point. Lakoff does not explicitly mention impartiality, but it is implicit in his analysis. But, unlike Lakoff, Wilson does explicitly relate his notions of fairness to evolved preferences, and in particular to their value in a social species. Indeed, Wilson generally relates his notions of a moral sense to evolution, in a way consistent with the arguments here. Summary and Implications for Further Research I assume for the sake of argument that group selection was involved in human evolution, including evolution of altruistic preferences. Nonetheless, there would still be limits to the amount of altruism that could have evolved. Altruism in contemporary group selection models is associated with faster growth of altruistic groups. This can occur if such altruism leads to cooperation in some prisoner’s dilemma. I call altruism GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 17 that would lead to faster growth “efficient altruism.” A common form of efficient altruism would be saving the sick or injured, or providing food to a hungry or starving person who is down on his luck. But such altruism must also be associated with monitoring the recipient to avoid free riding, for societies that allowed excessive shirking and free riding would not have grown as fast as others and in the highly competitive EEA would not have survived. Utilitarianism as a moral system is approximately consistent with efficient altruism; Marxism or the Rawlsian systems are not. The notions of efficient altruism and of evolved political preferences also help explain human intuitions about fairness. It would be useful to explore the limits of efficient altruism. It would also be useful to understand the relation of efficient altruism to other ethical systems, in addition to those sketched out here. It might also be worth working out the implications of utilitarianism if we understand that utility functions have evolved. From this basis, it might also be possible to derive a more evolutionarily based system of morality. While we might decide to adopt a moral system that is not consistent with our evolved preferences, it is still useful to understand these preferences. For example, if we choose policies that are too inconsistent with these preferences, then costs of enforcing these policies might be very high. Acknowledgments: The author would like to thank Frank Salter and an anonymous referee for helpful comments, while accepting blame for all errors. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 18 References cited Alexander, Richard D. 1987. The biology of moral systems. Aldine de Gruyter, New York. Axelrod, Robert. 1997. The complexity of cooperation: agent-based models of competition and collaboration. Princeton University Press, Princeton, Chapter 3: Promoting Norms. Bailey, Martin J. 1992. Approximate optimality of aboriginal property rights. Journal of Law and Economics. 35:183-198. Barkow, Jerome H., Leda Cosmides and John Tooby. 1992. editors, The adapted mind. Oxford University Press, New York. Bentham, Jeremy (1781/1988), The principles of morals and legislation. Prometheus Books, Amherst, NY. Betzig, Laura L. 1986. Despotism and differential reproduction: a Darwinian view of history. Hawthorne. Aldine de Gruyter, New York. Binmore, Ken. 1994. Game theory and the social contract II: just playing. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Boehm, Christopher. 1993. Egalitarian behavior and reverse dominance hierarchy. Current Anthropology. 14:227-254 (including comments and reply). Boehm, Christopher. 1997. Impact of the human egalitarian syndrome on darwinian selection mechanics. American Naturalist, 150 (Supplement):S100-S121. Boehm Christopher. 1999a. The natural selection of altruistic traits. Human Nature. 10:205-253. Boehm, Christopher. 1999b. Hierarchy in the forest: The evolution of egalitarian behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge. Boyd, Robert and Peter J. Richerson. 1985. Culture and the evolutionary process. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Boyd, Robert and Peter J. Richerson. 1992. Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or anything else) in sizeable groups. Ethology and Sociobiology. 13:171-195. Brown, Donald E. 1991. Human universals. McGraw Hill, New York. Buchanan, James and Gordon Tullock. 1965. The calculus of consent. University of Michigan, Ann Arbor. Carroll, Joseph. 1999. The deep structure of literary representations. Evolution and Human Behavior. 20:159-173. Cosmides, Leda and John Tooby. 1992. Cognitive adaptations for social exchange, in Jerome H. Barkow, Leda Cosmides and John Tooby (1992), editors, The adapted mind. Oxford University Press, New York. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 19 Darwin, Charles. 1871/1981. The descent of man and selection in relation to sex. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Hirshleifer, Jack. 1977. Economics from a biological viewpoint. Journal of Law and Economics. 20:1-52. Hirshleifer, Jack. 1999. There are many evolutionary pathways to cooperation. Journal of Bioeconomics. 1:73-93. Hirshleifer, Jack and J. Martinez-Coll. 1988. What strategies can support the evolutionary emergence of cooperation? Journal of Conflict Resolution, 32: 367-398. Johnson, Victor S. 1999. Why we feel: the science of human emotions. Perseus Books, Reading, MA. Kelly, Robert L. 1995. The foraging spectrum: diversity in hunter-gatherer lifeways. Smithsonian Institution Press, Washington, D.C. Knauft, Bruce. 1991. Violence and sociality in human evolution. Current Anthropology. 32:391-428 (including comments and reply). Lakoff, George. 1996. Moral politics: what conservatives know that liberals don’t. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Marx, Karl. 1888. Manifesto of the Communist party (web edition: Project Guttenberg). Maynard Smith, John. 1982. Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge University Press, New York. McGuire, Michael. 1992. Moralistic aggression, processing mechanisms, and the brain. in Roger D. Masters and Margaret Gruter, eds., The sense of justice: biological foundations of law. Sage Publications, Newbury Park. Pipes, Richard. 1999. Property and freedom. Knopf, New York. Posner, Richard. 1999. The problematics of legal and moral theory. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Rubin, Paul H. 1982. Evolved ethics and efficient ethics. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 3:161-74. Rubin, Paul H. 2000a. The state of nature and the evolution of political preferences. American Law and Economics Review. (In press). Rubin, Paul H. 2000b. Hierarchy. Human Nature (In press). Ruse, Michael and Edward O. Wilson. 1986. Moral philosophy as applied science. Philosophy. 61:173-192. Sober, Elliott and David Sloan Wilson. 1998. Unto others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Trivers, Robert L. 1971. The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology. 46:35-57. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 20 Westermarck, Edward. 1912. The origin and development of the moral idea, (2 Volumes, Second Edition). Macmillan and Co. London. Westermarck, Edward. 1932. Ethical relativity. Harcourt Brace and Co. New York. Wiessner, Polly 1996. Leveling the hunter: constraints on the status quest in foraging societies, in Polly Wiessner and Wulf Schiefenh¬ vel., eds., Food and the status quest: an interdisciplinary perspective. Berghan Books Providence, RI. Williams, George C. 1966). Adaptation and natural selection: a critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Wilson, Edward O. 1998. Consilience: the unity of knowledge. Knopf, New York. Wilson, James Q. 1993. The moral sense. Free Press, New York. Wynne-Edwards, Vero Copner. 1962. Animal dispersion in relation to social behaviour. Hafner Publishing Company, New York. GROUP SELECTION AND ALTRUISM PAGE 21 Endnotes 1 Hirshleifer (1999) indicates that “altruism” is a measure of attitude, and what is relevant is behavior – what he calls “helping behavior.” Here, for consistency with the majority of the literature, I will follow the standard usage, although Hirshleifer’s terminology is more appropriate. 2 Boehm (1999b) also proposes a form of group selection, based on mechanisms different from those suggested by Sober and Wilson. However, the arguments in this paper would apply to Boehm’s mechanism as well. 3 Sober and Wilson define group selection rather broadly, so that any individuals interacting, however briefly, may constitute a “group.” By their definition any of these mechanisms would be a form of group selection. I do not need to address this issue here. 4 Binmore, 1994, p. 259: “It is true that a substantial minority of people on the street are mentally ill, but the majority are just plain unlucky.” No source is given for this assertion. Binmore appears to be an advocate of increased generosity towards street people. 5 I do not discuss the mechanism of the “veil of ignorance” itself. For an elaborate discussion, see Binmore (1994). However, the results of deliberations behind the veil must be hypothetical. This is because we are never behind such a veil. It is also true that different people will intuit different outcomes of such a process – for example, Rawls and myself. Therefore, the notion of the veil is difficult to operationalize. 6 Interestingly, Sober and Wilson (1998, p. 237) discuss Rawls and the difference principle as an example of a moral rule, but do not consider the consistency of this rule with their view of evolved altruism. 7 This last is a stock joke phrase; the joke is in the violation of intuitions about ethics.