Research Article On Intuitionistic Fuzzy Context-Free Languages Jianhua Jin, Qingguo Li,

advertisement
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
Journal of Applied Mathematics
Volume 2013, Article ID 825249, 16 pages
http://dx.doi.org/10.1155/2013/825249
Research Article
On Intuitionistic Fuzzy Context-Free Languages
Jianhua Jin,1,2 Qingguo Li,1 and Chunquan Li2
1
2
College of Mathematics and Econometrics, Hunan University, Changsha 410082, China
College of Sciences, Southwest Petroleum University, Chengdu 610500, China
Correspondence should be addressed to Qingguo Li; liqingguoli@yahoo.com.cn
Received 19 October 2012; Revised 15 December 2012; Accepted 15 December 2012
Academic Editor: Hak-Keung Lam
Copyright © 2013 Jianhua Jin et al. This is an open access article distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License,
which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Taking intuitionistic fuzzy sets as the structures of truth values, we propose the notions of intuitionistic fuzzy context-free
grammars (IFCFGs, for short) and pushdown automata with final states (IFPDAs). Then we investigate algebraic characterization
of intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable languages including decomposition form and representation theorem. By introducing the
generalized subset construction method, we show that IFPDAs are equivalent to their simple form, called intuitionistic fuzzy simple
pushdown automata (IF-SPDAs), and then prove that intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable step functions are the same as those accepted
by IFPDAs. It follows that intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automata with empty stack and IFPDAs are equivalent by classical automata
theory. Additionally, we introduce the concepts of Chomsky normal form grammar (IFCNF) and Greibach normal form grammar
(IFGNF) based on intuitionistic fuzzy sets. The results of our study indicate that intuitionistic fuzzy context-free languages generated
by IFCFGs are equivalent to those generated by IFGNFs and IFCNFs, respectively, and they are also equivalent to intuitionistic fuzzy
recognizable step functions. Then some operations on the family of intuitionistic fuzzy context-free languages are discussed. Finally,
pumping lemma for intuitionistic fuzzy context-free languages is investigated.
1. Introduction
Intuitionistic fuzzy set (IFS) introduced by Atanassov [1–
3], which emerges from the simultaneous consideration of
the degrees of membership and nonmembership with a
degree of hesitancy, has been found to be highly useful in
dealing with problems with vagueness and uncertainty. The
notion of vague set, proposed by Gau and Buehrer [4], is
another generalization of fuzzy sets. However, Burillo and
Bustince [5] showed that it is an equivalence of the IFS and
studied intuitionistic fuzzy relations. Recently, IFS theory
has supported a wealth of important applications in many
fields such as fuzzy multiple attribute decision making, fuzzy
pattern recognition, medical diagnosis, fuzzy control, and
fuzzy optimization [6–10].
In classical theoretical computer science, it is well known
that formal languages are very useful in the description of
natural languages and programming languages. But they are
not powerful in the processing of human languages. For this,
Lee and Zadeh [11] introduced the notion of fuzzy languages
and gave some characterizations, where fuzzy languages took
values in the unit interval [0, 1]. Malik and Mordeson [12–
14] studied algebraic properties of fuzzy languages. They
stated that fuzzy regular languages can be characterized by
fuzzy finite automata, fuzzy regular expressions, and fuzzy
regular grammars. Meanwhile, as one of the generators of
fuzzy languages, fuzzy automata have been used to solve
meaningful issues such as the model of computing with
words [15], clinical monitoring [16], neural networks [17], and
pattern recognition [18]. Also, fuzzy grammars, automata,
and languages tend to the improvement of lexical analysis and
simulating fuzzy discrete event dynamical systems and hybrid
systems [14, 19].
As is well known, quantum logic was proved by Birkhoff
and Von Neumann as a logic of quantum mechanics and
2
is currently understood as a logic with truth values taken
from an orthomodular lattice. To study quantum computation, Ying [20, 21] first proposed automata theory based
on quantum logic where quantum automata are defined to
be orthomodular lattice-valued generalization of classical
automata. More systematic exposition of this theory appeared
in [22, 23]. Moore and Crutchfield [24] defined quantum
version of pushdown automata and regular and contextfree grammars. He showed that the corresponding languages
generated by quantum grammars and recognized by quantum
automata have satisfactory properties in analogy to their
classical counterparts. A basic framework of grammar theory
on quantum logic was established by Cheng and Wang [25].
They proved that the set of lattice-valued quantum regular
languages generated by lattice-valued quantum regular grammars coincides with that of lattice-valued quantum languages
recognized by lattice-valued quantum automata. Then some
algebraic properties of automata based on quantum logic
were discussed by Qiu [26, 27]. To enhance the processing
ability of fuzzy automata, the membership grades were
extended to many general algebraic structures. For example,
by combining the ideas in [20–23] and the idea in Ying’s
another work on topology based on residuated lattice-valued
logic [28], Qiu has primarily established automata theory
based on complete residuated lattice-valued logic [29–31].
And Li and Pedrycz [32] studied automata theory with membership values in lattice-ordered monoids. They showed that
lattice-valued finite automata have more power to recognize
fuzzy languages than that of classical fuzzy finite automata.
Recently, Li [33] studied automata theory with membership
values in lattices, introduced the technique of extended
subset construction to prove the equivalence between latticevalued finite automata and lattice-valued deterministic finite
automata, and then presented a minimization algorithm of
lattice-valued deterministic finite automata. On the basis of
breadth-first and depth-first ways, Jin and Li [34] established
a fundamental framework of fuzzy grammars based on
lattices, which provided a necessary tool for the analysis of
fuzzy automata.
Fuzzy context-free languages, more powerful than fuzzy
regular languages, have also been studied and can be characterized by fuzzy pushdown automata with two distinct
ways and fuzzy context-free grammars, respectively [14, 35].
As a continuation of the work in [29–31], a fundamental
framework of fuzzy pushdown automata theory based on
complete residuated lattice-valued logic has been established
in recent years by Xing et al. [36], and the work generalizes
the previous fuzzy automata theory systematically studied by
Mordeson and Malik to some extent. The pumping lemma
for fuzzy context-free grammar theory in this setting was also
investigated by Xing and Qiu [37].
Using the notions of IFSs and fuzzy finite automata,
Jun [38, 39] presented the concept of intuitionistic fuzzy
finite state machines as a generalization of fuzzy finite state
machines, and Zhang and Li [40] discussed intuitionistic
fuzzy recognizers, intuitionistic fuzzy finite automata, and
intuitionistic fuzzy language. They showed that the languages
recognized by intuitionistic fuzzy recognizers are regular, and
Journal of Applied Mathematics
the intuitionistic fuzzy languages recognized by the intuitionistic fuzzy finite automata and the intuitionistic fuzzy languages recognized by deterministic intuitionistic fuzzy finite
automata are equivalent. Recently Chen et al. [41] utilized the
intuitionistic fuzzy automata to deal with consumers’ advertising involvement when considering the expression of an IFS
characterized by a pair of membership degree and nonmembership degree is similar to human thinking logic with pros
and cons. Due to pushdown automata being another kind of
important computational models [15] and also motivated by
the importance of grammars, languages and models theory
[14], it stands to reason that we ought consider the notions of
intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automata, intuitionistic fuzzy
context-free grammars, and fuzzy context-free languages
because our discussion in this paper will provide a fundamental framework for studying intuitionistic fuzzy set theory
on fuzzy pushdown automata and generators as well. How to
characterize intuitionistic fuzzy context-free languages and
its pumping lemma in this setting becomes open problems;
however, there is no research on the algebraic characterization of intuitionistic fuzzy context-free languages. We
will try to solve the problems in this paper. Additionally,
some examples are given to illustrate the significance of the
results. In particular, Example 35 presented in this paper
will show that intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automata have
more power than fuzzy pushdown automata when comparing
two distinct strings although the degrees of membership of
these strings recognized by the underlying fuzzy pushdown
automata are equal. Investigating intuitionistic fuzzy contextfree languages will reduce the gap between the precision of
formal languages and the imprecision of human languages.
The remaining parts of the paper are arranged as follows. Section 2 describes some basic concepts of IFSs. Section 3 gives the definitions of intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown
automata with two distinct ways and their languages. It
is investigated that, for any intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown
automaton with final states (IFPDA, for short), there is
a cover, which consists of a collection of classical pushdown automata, equivalent to the IFPDA. By introducing
intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable step functions, it is shown
that intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automata with final states
and empty stack are intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable step
functions, respectively, and conversely any intuitionistic
fuzzy recognizable step function can be recognized by an
intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automaton with final states or
empty stack. It follows that intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown
automata with final states and empty stack are equivalent.
Section 4 studies intuitionistic fuzzy context-free grammars
(IFCFGs) as a type of generator of intuitionistic fuzzy
context-free languages (IFCFLs). The notions of intuitionistic
fuzzy Chomsky normal form (IFCNF) and Greibach normal form (IFGNF) are proposed. The results of our study
indicate that IFCFLs generated by IFCFGs are equivalent to
those generated by IFGNFs and IFCNFs, respectively, and
they are also equivalent to intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable
step functions. The algebraic properties of IFCFLs are also
discussed. Section 5 establishes pumping lemma for IFCFLs.
Some examples are then given to illustrate the application
of pumping lemma and the significance of IFCFLs. Finally,
Journal of Applied Mathematics
3
conclusions and directions for future work are presented in
Section 6.
2. Basic Concepts
Definition 1 (see [40]). An intuitionistic fuzzy set 𝐴 in a nonempty set 𝑋 is an object having the form:
𝐴 = {(π‘₯, πœ‡π΄ (π‘₯) , 𝜈𝐴 (π‘₯)) | π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋} ,
(1)
where the functions πœ‡π΄ : 𝑋 → [0, 1] and 𝜈𝐴 : 𝑋 → [0, 1]
denote the degree of membership (i.e., πœ‡π΄ (π‘₯)) and the degree
of nonmembership (𝜈𝐴(π‘₯)) of each element π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 to the set
𝐴, respectively, and the two quantities satisfy the following
inequalities:
0 ≤ πœ‡π΄ (π‘₯) + 𝜈𝐴 (π‘₯) ≤ 1,
∀π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋.
(2)
For the sake of simplicity, we use the notation 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴 )
instead of 𝐴 = {(π‘₯, πœ‡π΄ (π‘₯), 𝜈𝐴(π‘₯)) | π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋}. An intuitionistic
fuzzy set will be abbreviated as an IFS.
Let {𝐴 𝑖 | 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼} be a family of IFSs in 𝑋. Then the infimum
and supremum operations of IFSs are defined as follows:
𝑖∈𝐼
𝑖∈𝐼
(3)
𝑖∈𝐼
0, if 𝑒 = 𝑣
πœˆπ‘–π‘‘ (𝑒, 𝑣) = {
1, if 𝑒 =ΜΈ 𝑣,
(7)
for all (𝑒, 𝑣) ∈ 𝑋 × π‘‹.
Definition 2. Let 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴 ) be an IFS in 𝑋. Then the image
set of 𝐴, denoted as Im(𝐴), is given as
Im (𝐴) = Im (πœ‡π΄ ) ∪ Im (𝜈𝐴 ) ,
(8)
where Im(πœ‡π΄ ) = {πœ‡π΄ (π‘₯) | π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋} and Im(𝜈𝐴 ) = {𝜈𝐴(π‘₯) | π‘₯ ∈
𝑋}.
For any πœ†, πœƒ ∈ [0, 1], πœ† + πœƒ ≤ 1, the (πœ†, πœƒ)-cut set of 𝐴 is
defined as
𝐴 (πœ†,πœƒ) = {π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 | πœ‡π΄ (π‘₯) ≥ πœ†, 𝜈𝐴 (π‘₯) ≤ πœƒ} .
(9)
supp (𝐴) = {π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 | πœ‡π΄ (π‘₯) > 0, 𝜈𝐴 (π‘₯) < 1} .
(10)
𝑖∈𝐼
where ⋁ and β‹€ denote supremum and infimum of real numbers in [0, 1], respectively.
For two IFSs 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴 ) and 𝐡 = (πœ‡π΅ , 𝜈𝐡 ), we say 𝐴 = 𝐡
if πœ‡π΄ = πœ‡π΅ and 𝜈𝐴 = 𝜈𝐡 . In addition, if the IFS 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴) in
𝑋 satisfies the condition that, for any π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋, πœ‡π΄ (π‘₯) + 𝜈𝐴(π‘₯) =
1, then 𝐴 reduces to a fuzzy set in 𝑋. The difference between
intuitionistic fuzzy sets and fuzzy sets is whether the sum
of the degrees of membership and nonmembership of an
element to a set equals one.
An IFR in 𝑋 × π‘Œ is an intuitionistic fuzzy subset of 𝑋 × π‘Œ;
that is, it is an expression 𝐸 given by
𝐸 = {((π‘₯, 𝑦) , πœ‡πΈ (π‘₯, 𝑦) , 𝜈𝐸 (π‘₯, 𝑦)) | π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋, 𝑦 ∈ π‘Œ} ,
(4)
where the mappings πœ‡πΈ : 𝑋 × π‘Œ → [0, 1] and 𝜈𝐸 : 𝑋 × π‘Œ →
[0, 1] satisfy
0 ≤ πœ‡πΈ (π‘₯, 𝑦) + 𝜈𝐸 (π‘₯, 𝑦) ≤ 1,
∀ (π‘₯, 𝑦) ∈ 𝑋 × π‘Œ.
(5)
An IFBR over 𝑋 is an IFS of 𝑋 × π‘‹. Let 𝑃 = (πœ‡π‘ƒ , πœˆπ‘ƒ ) and
𝐸 = (πœ‡πΈ , 𝜈𝐸 ) be IFRs in 𝑋 × π‘Œ and π‘Œ × π‘, respectively. Define
the composition of IFRs, 𝑃 ∘ 𝐸 = (πœ‡π‘ƒβˆ˜πΈ , πœˆπ‘ƒβˆ˜πΈ ) in 𝑋 × π‘, by
𝑦∈π‘Œ
πœˆπ‘ƒβˆ˜πΈ (π‘₯, 𝑧) = β‹€ (πœˆπ‘ƒ (π‘₯, 𝑦) ∨ 𝜈𝐸 (𝑦, 𝑧)) ,
𝑦∈π‘Œ
3. Intuitionistic Fuzzy Pushdown Automata
It is well known that any language accepted by a pushdown
automaton with final states can be accepted by a certain
pushdown automaton with empty stack, and vice versa. As
a natural generalization of pushdown automata, we give the
notions of intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automata with final
states and empty stack, respectively, and then do research
in the algebraic characterization of their intuitionistic fuzzy
recognizable languages including decomposition form and
representation theorem. Note that Σ∗ is the free monoid
generated from the set Σ with the operator of concatenation,
where the empty string πœ€ is identified with the identity of
Σ. And the length of the string πœ” ∈ Σ∗ is denoted by |πœ”|.
π‘π‘˜ = {1, . . . , π‘˜}.
Definition 3. An intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automaton
with final states (IFPDA, for short) is a seven tuple M =
(𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 𝐹), where
(i) 𝑄 is a finite nonempty set of states;
(ii) Σ is a finite nonempty set of input symbols;
(iii) Γ is a finite nonempty set of stack symbols;
πœ‡π‘ƒβˆ˜πΈ (π‘₯, 𝑧) = ⋁ (πœ‡π‘ƒ (π‘₯, 𝑦) ∧ πœ‡πΈ (𝑦, 𝑧)) ,
for all (π‘₯, 𝑧) ∈ 𝑋 × π‘.
if 𝑒 = 𝑣
if 𝑒 =ΜΈ 𝑣,
If supp(𝐴) is finite, then 𝐴 is called a finite IFS in 𝑋.
⋃𝐴 𝑖 = {(π‘₯, β‹πœ‡π΄ 𝑖 (π‘₯) , β‹€πœˆπ΄ 𝑖 (π‘₯)) | π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋} ,
𝑖∈𝐼
1,
πœ‡π‘–π‘‘ (𝑒, 𝑣) = {
0,
And the support set of 𝐴, denoted as supp(𝐴), is defined by
⋂𝐴 𝑖 = {(π‘₯, β‹€πœ‡π΄ 𝑖 (π‘₯) , β‹πœˆπ΄ 𝑖 (π‘₯)) | π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋} ,
𝑖∈𝐼
Furthermore, if 𝑅 is an IFBR over 𝑋, then its reflexive and
𝑛
𝑛+1
= 𝑅𝑛 ∘ 𝑅, 𝑛 ≥
transitive closure is 𝑅∗ = ⋃∞
𝑛=0 𝑅 , where 𝑅
0, and 𝑅0 = 𝑖𝑑 = (πœ‡π‘–π‘‘ , πœˆπ‘–π‘‘ ), that is,
(6)
(iv) 𝛿 = (πœ‡π›Ώ , πœˆπ›Ώ ) is a finite IFS in 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ ;
(v) 𝑍0 ∈ Γ is called the start stack symbol;
(vi) 𝐼 = (πœ‡πΌ , 𝜈𝐼 ) and 𝐹 = (πœ‡πΉ , 𝜈𝐹 ) are intuitionistic fuzzy
subsets in 𝑄, which are called the intuitionistic fuzzy
subsets of initial and final states, respectively.
4
Journal of Applied Mathematics
Definition 4. An intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automaton
with empty stack (IFPDA0 , for short) is a seven tuple N =
(𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 0), where 𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼 and 𝑍0 are the same as
those in IFPDA M, and 0 represents an empty set.
Definition 5. Let M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 𝐹) be an IFPDA.
Define an IFBR on 𝑄 × Σ∗ × Γ∗ , ⊒M = (πœ‡βŠ’M , 𝜈⊒M ) in the form
of
𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž, πœ”, 𝛽) , (𝑝, 𝑒, 𝛼))
Proposition 9. If 𝑓 can be accepted by some IFPDA M =
(𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 𝐹), then 𝑓 is an IFS in Σ∗ , and the image set
of 𝑓 is finite.
Proof. We have the following.
Claim 1 (𝑓 = (πœ‡π‘“ , πœˆπ‘“ ) is an IFS in Σ∗ ).
πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž, πœ”, 𝛽) , (𝑝, 𝑒, 𝛼))
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, πœ€, head (𝛽) , 𝑝, 𝛼 \ tail (𝛽)) ,
{
{
{
if 𝑒 = πœ”, tail (𝛽) ≤ 𝛼
{
{
= {πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, head (πœ”) , head (𝛽) , 𝑝, 𝛼 \ tail (𝛽)) ,
{
{
if 𝑒 = tail (πœ”) , tail (𝛽) ≤ 𝛼
{
{
0,
otherwise,
{
is also finite, where 𝑋∧ = {π‘₯1 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ π‘₯π‘˜ : π‘˜ ≥ 1, π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯π‘˜ ∈
𝑋} ∪ {1}, and 𝑋∨ = {π‘₯1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ π‘₯π‘˜ : π‘˜ ≥ 1, π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯π‘˜ ∈ 𝑋} ∪ {0}.
(11)
πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, πœ€, head (𝛽) , 𝑝, 𝛼 \ tail (𝛽)) ,
{
{
{
if 𝑒 = πœ”, tail (𝛽) ≤ 𝛼
{
{
= { πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, head (πœ”) , head (𝛽) , 𝑝, 𝛼 \ tail (𝛽)) ,
{
{
if 𝑒 = tail (πœ”) , tail (𝛽) ≤ 𝛼
{
{
0,
otherwise
{
for any (π‘ž, πœ”, 𝛽), (𝑝, 𝑒, 𝛼) ∈ 𝑄 × Σ∗ × Γ∗ . Here, for any nonempty string 𝑒 = π‘₯1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ π‘₯𝑛 , 𝑛 ≥ 1, head(𝑒) = π‘₯1 , tail(𝑒) =
π‘₯2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ π‘₯𝑛 , and tail(𝑒) ≤ 𝑒. ⊒∗M is the reflexive and transitive
closure of ⊒M .
If no confusion, we denote ⊒ and ⊒∗ instead of ⊒M and
∗
⊒M , respectively.
Definition 6. Let M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 𝐹) be an IFPDA. Then
we call L(M) an intuitionistic fuzzy language accepted by M
with final states, where L(M) = (πœ‡L(M) , 𝜈L(M) ), πœ‡L(M) , and
𝜈L(M) are functions from Σ∗ to the unit interval [0, 1], and
πœ‡L(M) (πœ”)= ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (𝑝, πœ€, π‘Ÿ)) ∧
πœ‡πΉ (𝑝) | π‘ž0 , 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄, π‘Ÿ ∈ Γ∗ },
𝜈L(M) (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 ) ∨ 𝜈⊒∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (𝑝, πœ€, π‘Ÿ)) ∨
𝜈𝐹 (𝑝) | π‘ž0 , 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄, π‘Ÿ ∈ Γ∗ }
for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ .
Definition 7. Let N = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 0) be an IFPDA0 .
Then we call L(N) an intuitionistic fuzzy language accepted
by N with empty stack, where L(N) = (πœ‡L(N) , 𝜈L(N) ),
πœ‡L(N) and 𝜈L(N) are functions from Σ∗ to the unit interval
[0, 1], and
πœ‡L(N) (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’∗N ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (𝑝, πœ€, πœ€)) |
π‘ž0 ,𝑝 ∈ 𝑄},
𝜈L(N) (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 ) ∨ π‘£βŠ’∗N ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (𝑝, πœ€, πœ€))
π‘ž0 , 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄}
|
for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ .
Lemma 8 (see [33]). Let 𝑙 be a lattice and 𝑋 a finite subset of
𝑙. Then the ∧-semilattice of 𝑙 generated by 𝑋, written as 𝑋∧ , is
finite, and the ∨-semilattice of 𝑙 generated by 𝑋, denoted as 𝑋∨ ,
It suffices to show that 0 ≤ πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) + πœˆπ‘“ (πœ”) ≤ 1, for any
πœ” = 𝑒1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑒𝑖 ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑖 = 1, . . . , 𝑛.
Clearly, πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (𝑝, πœ€, π‘Ÿ)) ∧
πœ‡πΉ (𝑝) | π‘ž0 , 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄, π‘Ÿ ∈ Γ∗ } = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ),
(π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 ,𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž1 ,𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 ,
𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) ∧ πœ‡πΉ (π‘žπ‘› ) |
(π‘ž0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈ 𝑄𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, π‘Ÿ1 , . . ., π‘Ÿπ‘› ∈ Γ∗ },
and πœˆπ‘“ (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 ) ∨ 𝜈⊒∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (𝑝, πœ€, π‘Ÿ)) ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (𝑝) |
π‘ž0 , 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄, π‘Ÿ ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 ) ∨ 𝜈⊒ ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅
𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒ ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨
𝜈⊒ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘žπ‘› ) | (π‘ž0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈
𝑄𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, π‘Ÿ1 , . . . , π‘Ÿπ‘› ∈ Γ∗ }.
On the one hand, 0 ≤ πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) + πœˆπ‘“ (πœ”); on the other
hand, there exists a sequence (π‘ž0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈ 𝑄𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 ,
. . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, π‘Ÿ1 , . . . , π‘Ÿπ‘› ∈ Γ∗ such that πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) = πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) ∧
πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ),
(π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) ∧
πœ‡πΉ (π‘žπ‘› ). Hence πœˆπ‘“ (πœ”) ≤ 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 ) ∨ 𝜈⊒ ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 ,
𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒ ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨
𝜈⊒ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘žπ‘› ).
Therefore, πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) + πœˆπ‘“ (πœ”) ≤ (πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) + 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 )) ∨ (πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž0 ,
πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) + 𝜈⊒ ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 ,
𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ))) ∨ (πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) + 𝜈⊒ ((π‘ž1 ,
𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 ))) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ (πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 ,
𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) + 𝜈⊒ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› ))) ∨
(πœ‡πΉ (π‘žπ‘› ) + 𝜈𝐹 (π‘žπ‘› )) ≤ 1 ∨ 1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 1 = 1.
Claim 2 (Im(𝑓) is finite).
In fact, let 𝑋 = Im(πœ‡πΌ ) ∪ Im(πœ‡π›Ώ ) ∪ Im(πœ‡πΉ ) and π‘Œ =
Im(𝜈𝐼 ) ∪ Im(πœˆπ›Ώ )∪Im(𝜈𝐹 ). Then 𝑋∧ = {π‘₯1 ∧⋅ ⋅ ⋅∧π‘₯π‘˜ | π‘˜ ≥ 1, π‘₯1 ,
. . . , π‘₯π‘˜ ∈ 𝑋} ∪ {1} and 𝑋∨ = {π‘₯1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ π‘₯π‘˜ | π‘˜ ≥ 1, π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯π‘˜ ∈
𝑋} ∪ {0} are finite sets by Lemma 8. Since 𝛿 = (πœ‡π›Ώ , πœˆπ›Ώ ) is a
finite IFS, for any πœ” = 𝑒1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑒𝑖 ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑖 = 1, . . . , 𝑛, there
exists a natural number 𝑑 ∈ 𝑁 such that πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) ∧
πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ),
(π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 ))∧⋅ ⋅ ⋅∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› ))∧
πœ‡πΉ (π‘žπ‘› ) | (π‘ž0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈ 𝑄𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, π‘Ÿ1 , . . . , π‘Ÿπ‘› ∈
Γ∗ } = (π‘Ž10 ∧⋅ ⋅ ⋅∧π‘Ž1,𝑛−1 ∧π‘Ž1𝑛 )∨⋅ ⋅ ⋅∨(π‘Žπ‘‘0 ∧⋅ ⋅ ⋅∧π‘Žπ‘‘,𝑛−1 ∧π‘Žπ‘‘π‘› )), where
π‘Žπ‘–π‘— ∈ 𝑋, 𝑖 = 1, . . . , 𝑑; 𝑗 = 0, . . . , 𝑛. By Lemma 8, (𝑋∧ )∨ is also
finite. Since πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) ∈ (𝑋∧ )∨ for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ , Im(πœ‡π‘“ ) ⊆ (𝑋∧ )∨ .
Hence Im(πœ‡π‘“ ) is a finite subset of [0, 1].
Similarly, it follows that Im(πœˆπ‘“ ) is also a finite subset of
[0, 1].
Therefore, Im(𝑓) = Im(πœ‡π‘“ ) ∪ Im(πœˆπ‘“ ) is finite.
If 𝑓 can be accepted by some IFPDA0 N = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿,
𝐼, 𝑍0 , 0), then, by Definition 7, for any πœ” = 𝑒1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑒𝑖 ∈
Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑖 = 1, . . . , 𝑛, we have πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 )∧
Journal of Applied Mathematics
5
πœ‡βŠ’∗N ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (𝑝, πœ€, πœ€)) | π‘ž0 , 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄} = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) ∧
πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ),
(π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, πœ€)) |
(π‘ž0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈ 𝑄𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, π‘Ÿ1 , . . . , π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ∈
Γ∗ }, and πœˆπ‘“ (πœ”) = β‹€ {𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 ) ∨ 𝜈⊒∗N ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (𝑝, πœ€, πœ€)) | π‘ž0 ,
𝑝 ∈ 𝑄} = β‹€ {𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 ) ∨ 𝜈⊒ ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑧0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∨
𝜈⊒ ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈⊒ ((π‘žπ‘›−1 ,
𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, πœ€)) | (π‘ž0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈ 𝑄𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈
Γ, π‘Ÿ1 , . . ., π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ∈ Γ∗ }.
In a similar manner, it is concluded that the following
must be true.
Proposition 10. If 𝑓 can be accepted by some IFPDA0 N =
(𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 0), then 𝑓 is an IFS in Σ∗ , and the image set
of 𝑓 is finite.
Specially, the IFPDA M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 𝐹) will be
abbreviated as MσΈ€  = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹), whenever Im(𝐼) ⊆
{0, 1} and supp(𝐼) = {π‘ž0 }. Moreover, if Im(𝐼) ∪ Im(𝐹) ∪
Im(𝛿) ⊆ {0, 1} and supp(𝐼) has only one element, then the
IFPDA is a classical PDA.
For two IFPDAs M1 and M2 , we say that they are equivalent if they accept the same intuitionistic fuzzy language.
Proposition 11. Let 𝐴 be an IFS in a nonempty set Σ∗ . Then
the following statements are equivalent:
(i) 𝐴 can be accepted by an IFPDA M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼,
𝑍0 , 𝐹);
(ii) 𝐴 can be accepted by a certain IFPDA MσΈ€  = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ,
ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0 , 𝑋0 , 𝐹󸀠 ), where π‘ž0 ∈ 𝑄󸀠 .
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
Proof. (i) implies (ii). Construct an IFPDA M = (𝑄 , Σ,
ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , 𝐼󸀠 , 𝑋0 , 𝐹󸀠 ) as follows: 𝑄󸀠 = 𝑄 ∪ {π‘ž0 }, ΓσΈ€  = Γ ∪ {𝑋0 },
where π‘ž0 ∉ 𝑄, 𝑋0 ∉ Γ. Define an IFS 𝐼󸀠 in 𝑄󸀠 by
1,
πœ‡πΌσΈ€  (π‘ž) = {
0,
if π‘ž = π‘ž0
if π‘ž =ΜΈ π‘ž0 ,
0, if π‘ž = π‘ž0
πœˆπΌσΈ€  (π‘ž) = {
1, if π‘ž =ΜΈ π‘ž0 .
σΈ€ 
(12)
1,
if π‘ž = π‘ž0
πœˆπΉσΈ€  (π‘ž) = {
𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) , if π‘ž =ΜΈ π‘ž0 .
if π‘ž = π‘ž0
if π‘ž =ΜΈ π‘ž0 ,
(14)
0, if π‘ž = π‘ž0
𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž) = {
1, if π‘ž =ΜΈ π‘ž0 .
It follows that the IFPDA M = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , 𝐼, 𝑋0 , 𝐹󸀠 )
accepts 𝐴.
Similarly, it is easily concluded that the following must be
true.
(i) 𝐴 can be accepted by an IFPDA0 M
Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 0);
=
(𝑄, Σ,
(ii) There exists an IFPDA0 MσΈ€  = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0 , 𝑋0 , 0)
recognizing 𝐴, where π‘ž0 ∈ 𝑄󸀠 .
Define an IFS 𝐹 in 𝑄 by
if π‘ž = π‘ž0
if π‘ž =ΜΈ π‘ž0 ,
1,
πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž) = {
0,
Proposition 12. Let 𝐴 be an IFS in a nonempty set Σ∗ . Then
the following statements are equivalent:
σΈ€ 
0,
πœ‡πΉσΈ€  (π‘ž) = {
πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) ,
(𝑝0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  ((𝑝0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€ 
((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  ((π‘žπ‘›−1 ,
𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) ∧ πœ‡πΉσΈ€  (π‘žπ‘› ) | π‘ž ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , (𝑝0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈
𝑄󸀠𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈ ΓσΈ€  , π‘Ÿ1 , . . . , π‘Ÿπ‘› ∈ ΓσΈ€ ∗ } = ⋁{1 ∧ πœ‡πΌ (𝑝0 )∧
πœ‡βŠ’M ((𝑝0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 ,
𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ),
(π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) ∧ πœ‡πΉ (π‘žπ‘› ) | (𝑝0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈ 𝑄𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . ., 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈
Γ, π‘Ÿ1 , . . . , π‘Ÿπ‘› ∈ Γ∗ } = πœ‡L(M) (πœ”), and 𝜈L(MσΈ€  ) (πœ”) =
β‹€{πœˆπΌσΈ€  (π‘ž) ∨ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  ((π‘ž, πœ”, 𝑋0 ), (𝑝0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  ((𝑝0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ),
(π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅
𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) ∨ πœˆπΉσΈ€  (π‘žπ‘› ) |
π‘ž ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , (𝑝0 , π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈ ΓσΈ€  , π‘Ÿ1 , . . .,
π‘Ÿπ‘› ∈ ΓσΈ€ ∗ } = β‹€{1 ∨ 𝜈𝐼 (𝑝0 ) ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((𝑝0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅
𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž1 , 𝑒2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧1 π‘Ÿ1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝑒3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧2 π‘Ÿ2 )) ∨
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑒𝑛 , 𝑧𝑛−1 π‘Ÿπ‘›−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, π‘Ÿπ‘› )) ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘žπ‘› ) | (𝑝0 , π‘ž1 , . . .,
π‘žπ‘› ) ∈ 𝑄𝑛+1 , 𝑧1 , . . . , 𝑧𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, π‘Ÿ1 , . . ., π‘Ÿπ‘› ∈ Γ∗ } = 𝜈L(M) (πœ”).
Therefore, L(MσΈ€  ) = L(M).
From the construction, it is clearly that MσΈ€  can be
denoted as MσΈ€  = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0 , 𝑋0 , 𝐹󸀠 ).
(ii) implies (i). Suppose the IFS 𝐴 is accepted by the
IFPDA MσΈ€  = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0 , 𝑋0 , 𝐹󸀠 ). Then we construct an
IFS 𝐼 in 𝑄󸀠 by
(13)
Define an IFS 𝛿󸀠 in 𝑄󸀠 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × ΓσΈ€  × π‘„σΈ€  × ΓσΈ€ ∗ by
mappings πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  , πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  : 𝑄󸀠 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × ΓσΈ€  × π‘„σΈ€  × ΓσΈ€ ∗ → [0, 1],
πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  (π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑋0 , 𝑝, 𝑍0 ) = πœ‡πΌ (𝑝), πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  (π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑋0 , 𝑝, 𝑍0 ) = 𝜈𝐼 (𝑝),
πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑧, 𝑝, 𝛾) = πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑧, 𝑝, 𝛾), πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑧, 𝑝, 𝛾) = πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏,
𝑧, 𝑝, 𝛾), where π‘ž, 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄, 𝜏 ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑧 ∈ Γ, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ ; otherwise,
πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  (π‘ž0 , 𝜏, 𝑧, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 0 and πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  (π‘ž0 , 𝜏, 𝑧, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 1.
Then for any πœ” = 𝑒1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑒𝑛 ∈ Σ∗ , 𝑒𝑖 ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑖 =
1, . . . , 𝑛, we have πœ‡L(MσΈ€  ) (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌσΈ€  (π‘ž) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  ((π‘ž, πœ”, 𝑋0 ),
There is especially a simple type of intuitionistic fuzzy
pushdown automata, which is called intuitionistic fuzzy
simple pushdown automata. The definition is given as follows.
Definition 13. An IFPDA M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹) is called
an intuitionistic fuzzy simple pushdown automaton
(IFSPDA) if the image set of 𝛿 is contained in the set
{0, 1}.
Next any IFPDA is proven to be an equivalence of a certain IFSPDA by utilizing the generalized subset construction
method. Noting that an IFS requires that the sum of the
degrees of membership and nonmembership of an element
to a set is no more than the natural number 1. So the proof
technique is to some extent different from the technique of
6
Journal of Applied Mathematics
πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘– , πœπ‘–+1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜+1 , 𝑍𝑖 𝛾𝑖 ), (π‘žπ‘–+1 , πœπ‘–+2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜+1 ,
𝑍𝑖+1 𝛾𝑖+1 )) = 𝑐𝑖+1 > 0,
extended subset construction introduced by Li in [33], and it
is not an easy task to conduct reasoning in the realm of the
modified techniques.
𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘– , πœπ‘–+1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜+1 , 𝑍𝑖 𝛾𝑖 ), (π‘žπ‘–+1 , πœπ‘–+2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜+1 ,
𝑍𝑖+1 𝛾𝑖+1 )) = 𝑑𝑖+1 < 1,
Proposition 14. Let M be an IFPDA. Then there exists an
IFSPDA MσΈ€  such that L(MσΈ€  ) = L(M).
Proof. Let M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹) be an IFPDA. Then we
construct an IFSPDA MσΈ€  = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ, Γ, 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0σΈ€  , 𝑍0 , 𝐹󸀠 ) as follows:
(i) 𝑄󸀠 = 𝑄 × (𝐿 1 − {0}) × (𝐿 2 − {1}), where 𝐿 1 = 𝑋∧ , 𝐿 2 =
π‘Œ∨ , 𝑋 = Im(πœ‡π›Ώ ) ∪ Im(πœ‡πΉ ) and π‘Œ = Im(πœˆπ›Ώ ) ∪ Im(𝜈𝐹 );
(ii) π‘ž0σΈ€  = (π‘ž0 , 1, 0) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 ;
(iii) 𝛿󸀠 = (πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  , πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ) is an IFS in 𝑄󸀠 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ ×
𝑄󸀠 × Γ∗ , where the mappings πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  , πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  : 𝑄󸀠 × (Σ ∪
{πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„σΈ€  × Γ∗ → {0, 1} are given as follows.
For any (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), (π‘žσΈ€  , 𝑐, 𝑑) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , 𝜏 ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑋 ∈
Γ and 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ , πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), 𝜏, 𝑋, (π‘žσΈ€  , 𝑐, 𝑑), 𝛾) = 1,
and πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), 𝜏, 𝑋, (π‘žσΈ€  , 𝑐, 𝑑), 𝛾) = 0 whenever there
exist π‘ŽσΈ€  and 𝑏󸀠 such that πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋, π‘žσΈ€  , 𝛾) = π‘ŽσΈ€  > 0,
πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋, π‘žσΈ€  , 𝛾) = 𝑏󸀠 < 1, 𝑐 = π‘Ž ∧ π‘ŽσΈ€  and 𝑑 =
𝑏 ∨ 𝑏󸀠 . Otherwise, πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), 𝜏, 𝑋, (π‘žσΈ€  , 𝑐, 𝑑), 𝛾) = 0
and πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), 𝜏, 𝑋, (π‘žσΈ€  , 𝑐, 𝑑), 𝛾) = 1;
(iv) 𝐹󸀠 = (πœ‡πΉσΈ€  , πœˆπΉσΈ€  ) is an IFS in 𝑄󸀠 . For any (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 ,
π‘Ž ∧ πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) , if 0 ≤ π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1
πœ‡πΉσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏)) = {
0,
if π‘Ž + 𝑏 > 1,
𝑏 ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) , if 0 ≤ π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1
πœˆπΉσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏)) = {
1,
if π‘Ž + 𝑏 > 1.
(15)
Now, it is claimed that, for any πœ” = 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ∈ Σ∗ ,
πœπ‘– ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑖 ∈ {1, . . . , 𝑛} and for any (π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ) ∈
𝑄󸀠 , 𝑍𝑛 , 𝛾𝑛 ∈ Γ∗ , πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑍𝑛 𝛾𝑛 )) = 1
M
and 𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑍𝑛 𝛾𝑛 )) = 0 whenever the
M
following condition is satisfied.
(P1) There exist π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘›−1 ∈ 𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . . , 𝑍𝑛−1 ∈ Γ and 𝛾1 ,
. . . , 𝛾𝑛−1 ∈ Γ∗ such that π‘Žπ‘› = πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅
πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∧
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, 𝑍𝑛 𝛾𝑛 )) and 𝑏𝑛 =
𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› ,
𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, 𝑍𝑛 𝛾𝑛 )). Otherwise, πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› ,
M
π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑍𝑛 𝛾𝑛 )) = 0 and 𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€,
M
𝑍𝑛 𝛾𝑛 )) = 1.
It is proved by induction. In fact, if |πœ”| = 0, then πœ” =
πœ€, πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 )) = 1 and 𝜈⊒∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž0 , πœ€,
M
𝑍0 )) = 0. Hence πœ‡βŠ’∗M (((π‘ž0 , 1, 0), πœ€, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘ž0 , 1, 0), πœ€, 𝑍0 )) = 1
and 𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  (((π‘ž0 , 1, 0), πœ€, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘ž0 , 1, 0), πœ€, 𝑍0 )) = 0.
M
Suppose the result still holds whenever |πœ”| ≤ 𝑛, 𝑛 ∈ 𝑁.
If |πœ”| = 𝑛 + 1, πœ” = 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜ πœπ‘˜+1 = π‘₯πœπ‘˜+1 and πœπ‘˜+1 ∈ Σ, then
|π‘₯| = 𝑛 and π‘₯ = 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜ .
Next, for any (π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , π‘π‘˜+1 , π›Ύπ‘˜+1 ∈ Γ∗ ,
whenever (P1) is satisfied; that is, there exists a sequence of
states π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘˜ ∈ 𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . . , π‘π‘˜ ∈ Γ, 𝛾1 , . . . , π›Ύπ‘˜ ∈ Γ∗ such that
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘žπ‘˜ , πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ , π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ) = π‘π‘˜+1 > 0,
πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘žπ‘˜ , πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ , π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ) = π‘‘π‘˜+1 < 1,
where 𝛾0 = πœ€, 𝑖 = 0, 1, . . . , π‘˜ − 1.
Let π‘Žπ‘™ = 𝑐1 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ 𝑐𝑙 , 𝑏𝑙 = 𝑑1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑑𝑙 , 𝑙 ∈ {1, . . . , π‘˜ + 1}.
Then
πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘– , π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ), πœπ‘–+1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜+1 , 𝑍𝑖 𝛾𝑖 ), ((π‘žπ‘–+1 , π‘Žπ‘–+1 , 𝑏𝑖+1 ),
πœπ‘–+2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜+1 , 𝑍𝑖+1 𝛾𝑖+1 )) = 1,
𝜈⊒MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘– , π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ), πœπ‘–+1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜+1 , 𝑍𝑖 𝛾𝑖 ),
πœπ‘–+2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜+1 , 𝑍𝑖+1 𝛾𝑖+1 )) = 0,
((π‘žπ‘–+1 , π‘Žπ‘–+1 , 𝑏𝑖+1 ),
πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ ), ((π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ),
πœ€, π‘π‘˜+1 π›Ύπ‘˜+1 )) = 1, and
𝜈⊒MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ ), ((π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ),
πœ€, π‘π‘˜+1 π›Ύπ‘˜+1 )) = 0,
where π‘Ž0 = 1, 𝑏0 = 0, 𝛾0 = πœ€, 𝑖 = 0, 1, . . . , π‘˜ − 1.
By assumption, πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , π‘₯, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœ€, π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ )) =
M
1, 𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , π‘₯, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœ€, π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ )) = 0, and so πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  ,
M
M
π‘₯πœπ‘˜+1 , 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ )) = 1, 𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , π‘₯πœπ‘˜+1 , 𝑍0 ),
M
((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ )) = 0.
((π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ),
πœ€,
Therefore,
πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ),
M
π‘π‘˜+1 π›Ύπ‘˜+1 )) = ⋁{πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ )) ∧
M
πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ ), ((π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ),
πœ€,
π‘π‘˜+1 π›Ύπ‘˜+1 )) | (π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , π‘π‘˜ ∈ Γ, π›Ύπ‘˜ ∈ Γ∗ } = 1 ∧ 1 = 1.
𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ), πœ€, π‘π‘˜+1 π›Ύπ‘˜+1 )) =
M
β‹€ {𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ), πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ )) ∨ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ ,
M
π‘π‘˜ ), πœπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘˜ ), ((π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ), πœ€, π‘π‘˜+1 π›Ύπ‘˜+1 )) | (π‘žπ‘˜ , π‘Žπ‘˜ , π‘π‘˜ ) ∈
𝑄󸀠 , π‘π‘˜ ∈ Γ, π›Ύπ‘˜ ∈ Γ∗ } = 0 ∨ 0 = 0.
For any (π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , π‘π‘˜+1 , π›Ύπ‘˜+1 ∈ Γ∗ , if (P1) is
not satisfied, then it follows that
πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ), πœ€, π‘π‘˜+1 π›Ύπ‘˜+1 )) = 0,
M
𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘˜+1 , π‘Žπ‘˜+1 , π‘π‘˜+1 ), πœ€, π‘π‘˜+1 π›Ύπ‘˜+1 )) = 1.
M
Hence, for any πœ” = 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ∈ Σ∗ , πœπ‘– ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑖 ∈
{1, . . . , 𝑛}, we have πœ‡L(MσΈ€  ) (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› ,
M
𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝛾)) ∧ πœ‡πΉσΈ€  ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 )) | (π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ }
= ⋁{π‘Žπ‘› ∧ πœ‡πΉ (π‘žπ‘› ) | π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘›−1 ∈ 𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . . , 𝑍𝑛−1 ∈ Γ,
𝛾1 , . . . , 𝛾𝑛−1 ∈ Γ∗ , π‘Žπ‘› = πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧
πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ),(π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, 𝛾)), 𝑏𝑛 = 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ),
(π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, 𝛾))} =
⋁{πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ),(π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍1 𝛾1 )(π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› ,
𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, 𝛾)) ∧ πœ‡πΉ (π‘žπ‘› ) | π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘›−1 ∈ 𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . .,
𝑍𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, 𝛾1 , . . . , 𝛾𝑛−1 ∈ Γ∗ } = πœ‡L(M) (πœ”), 𝜈L(MσΈ€  ) (πœ”) =
β‹€{𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝛾)) ∨ πœˆπΉσΈ€  ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› ,
M
Journal of Applied Mathematics
7
𝑏𝑛 )) | (π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝑏𝑛 ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘žπ‘› ) | π‘ž1 ,
. . . , π‘žπ‘›−1 ∈ 𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . . , 𝑍𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, 𝛾1 , . . . , 𝛾𝑛−1 ∈ Γ∗ ,
π‘Žπ‘› = πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ),(π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ),
(π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, 𝛾)), 𝑏𝑛 = 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž1 ,
𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› ,
𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, 𝛾))} = β‹€{𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅
∨𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, 𝛾)) ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘žπ‘› ) | π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘›−1 ∈
𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . . , 𝑍𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, 𝛾1 , . . .,𝛾𝑛−1 ∈ Γ∗ } = 𝜈L(M) (πœ”).
Therefore, L(MσΈ€  ) = L(M).
where πΉπ‘Žπ‘ = {π‘ž ∈ 𝑄 | πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) ≥ π‘Ž, 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) ≤ 𝑏}; the mapping
∗
𝛿󸀠 : 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ → 2𝑄×Γ is given by
Clearly, an IFPDA is a generalization of a classical pushdown automaton (PDA). Next, it will be shown that any
IFPDA can be characterized by a collection of pushdown
automata. To describe the behavior of a pushdown automaton
M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹), we need to introduce the concept
of instantaneous description. An instantaneous description is
a three-tuple (π‘ž, πœ”, 𝛾) ∈ 𝑄 × Σ∗ × Γ∗ , which means that the
automaton is in the state π‘ž and has unexpended input πœ” and
stack contents 𝛾. An instantaneous description represents the
configuration of a pushdown automaton at a given instant. To
introduce the transition in a pushdown automaton in terms of
instantaneous descriptions, we define ≻M as a binary relation
on 𝑄 × Σ∗ × Γ∗ . We say (π‘ž, π‘Žπœ”, 𝑍𝛾) ≻M (𝑝, πœ”, πœŽπ›Ύ) if 𝛿(π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑍)
contains (𝑝, 𝜎), where 𝑝, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, π‘Ž ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, πœ” ∈ Σ∗ , 𝑍 ∈ Γ,
and 𝛾, 𝜎 ∈ Γ∗ . Furthermore, we define ≻∗M as the reflexive
and transitive closure of ≻M . Then the language accepted by
M with final states is defined as
for all π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] with π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1, for all πœ” ∈ Σ∗ , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ .
πœ‡π‘“π‘† (πœ”) = ⋁{π‘Ž ∈ [0, 1] | Mπ‘Žπ‘ accepts πœ”, Mπ‘Žπ‘ ∈ 𝑆} = ⋁{π‘Ž ∈
[0, 1] | π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ , (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = ⋁{π‘Ž ∈
[0, 1] | πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) ≥ π‘Ž, 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) ≤ 𝑏, (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), 𝛾 ∈
Γ∗ } = ⋁{π‘Ž ∈ [0, 1] | πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) ≥ π‘Ž, (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), π‘ž ∈
𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = ⋁{πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) | πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, π‘ž ∈
𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = πœ‡π‘“ (πœ”) = πœ‡L(M) (πœ”), πœˆπ‘“π‘† (πœ”) = β‹€{𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] |
Mπ‘Žπ‘ accepts πœ”, Mπ‘Žπ‘ ∈ 𝑆} = β‹€{𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ ,
(π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] | πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) ≥
π‘Ž, 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) ≤ 𝑏, (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝑏 ∈
[0, 1] | 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) ≤ 𝑏, (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } =
β‹€{𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) | πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } =
πœˆπ‘“ (πœ”) = 𝜈L(M) (πœ”).
Therefore, 𝑓𝑆 = L(M) = 𝑓.
Conversely, suppose 𝑓 can be recognized by a cover
L (M) = {πœ” ∈ Σ∗ | (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗M (𝑝, πœ€, 𝛾) , 𝑝 ∈ 𝐹, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } .
(16)
𝑆 = {Mπ‘Žπ‘ | Mπ‘Žπ‘ = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , πΉπ‘Žπ‘ ) ,
Definition 15. A collection of classical pushdown automata
with final states
𝑆 = {Mπ‘Žπ‘ | Mπ‘Žπ‘ = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , πΉπ‘Žπ‘ ) ,
0 ≤ π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1, π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] }
(17)
is called a cover if the following conditions hold:
For a cover 𝑆, its recognized intuitionistic fuzzy language
𝑓𝑆 = (πœ‡π‘“π‘† , πœˆπ‘“π‘† ) in Σ∗ is given by
πœ‡π‘“π‘† (πœ”) = ⋁{π‘Ž ∈ [0, 1] | Mπ‘Žπ‘ accepts πœ”, Mπ‘Žπ‘ ∈ 𝑆},
πœˆπ‘“π‘† (πœ”) = β‹€{𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] | Mπ‘Žπ‘ accepts πœ”, Mπ‘Žπ‘ ∈ 𝑆}, for
all πœ” ∈ Σ∗ .
Theorem 16. Let 𝑓 be an IFS in Σ∗ . Then 𝑓 can be accepted
by an IFPDA if and only if 𝑓 can be recognized by a cover 𝑆.
Proof. If 𝑓 can be accepted by an IFPDA, then there exists an
IFSPDA M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹) such that M accepts 𝑓 by
Proposition 14. Next we construct a cover
0 ≤ π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1, π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] } ,
Clearly, the cover 𝑆 is well defined.
Next, we will show that 𝑓 can be recognized by the cover
𝑆. In fact, we have
(π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 )≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾) if and only if πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 ,
πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1,
0 ≤ π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1, π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] } .
(18)
(19)
Then we construct an IFSPDA M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, πœ‚, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹),
where πœ‚ = (πœ‡πœ‚ , πœˆπœ‚ ) is an IFS in 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ ,
and the mappings πœ‡πœ‚ , πœˆπœ‚ : 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ → {0, 1}
are defined as
1,
πœ‡πœ‚ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = {
0,
(i) π‘Ž1 ≤ π‘Ž2 and 𝑏2 ≤ 𝑏1 imply πΉπ‘Ž2 𝑏2 ⊆ πΉπ‘Ž1 𝑏1 ;
(ii) 𝐹01 = 𝑄.
𝑆 = {Mπ‘Žπ‘ | Mπ‘Žπ‘ = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , πΉπ‘Žπ‘ ) ,
𝛿󸀠 (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍) = {(𝑝, 𝛾) | πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 1, 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈
Γ∗ }, for all (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍) ∈ 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ.
if (𝑝, 𝛾) ∈ 𝛿󸀠 (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍)
otherwise,
0, if (𝑝, 𝛾) ∈ 𝛿󸀠 (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍)
πœˆπœ‚ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = {
1, otherwise,
(20)
for any (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) ∈ 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ .
𝐹 = (πœ‡πΉ , 𝜈𝐹 ) is an IFS in 𝑄, where πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) = ⋁{π‘Ž ∈ [0,
1] | π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ } and 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) = β‹€{𝑏 ∈ [0, 1]π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ }, for all
π‘ž ∈ 𝑄. Then L(M) = 𝑓𝑆 . In fact, for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ ,
πœ‡L(M) (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) | πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, π‘ž ∈
𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = ⋁{⋁{π‘Ž ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ } | πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”,
𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = ⋁{π‘Ž ∈ [0, 1] |
π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ , πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } =
⋁{π‘Ž ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ , (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } =
⋁{π‘Ž ∈ [0, 1] | Mπ‘Žπ‘ accepts πœ”, Mπ‘Žπ‘ ∈ 𝑆} = πœ‡π‘“π‘† (πœ”),
𝜈L(M) (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) | πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄,
𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{β‹€{𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ } | πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”,
𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž ∈ πΉπ‘Žπ‘ ,
8
Journal of Applied Mathematics
(π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝑏 ∈ [0, 1] | Mπ‘Žπ‘
accepts πœ”, Mπ‘Žπ‘ ∈ 𝑆} = πœˆπ‘“π‘† (πœ”).
Therefore, the IFSPDA M accepts 𝑓.
Theorem 16 shows that every IFPDA is equivalent to a
certain cover; however, the cover may have infinite classical
pushdown automata elements. Is there a finite cover who
is equivalent to the IFPDA? To solve the problem, we
introduce the notion of an intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable
step function as follows.
Definition 17. An IFS 𝐴 over Σ∗ is called an intuitionistic
fuzzy recognizable step function if there are a finite natural number 𝑛 ∈ 𝑁, recognizable context-free languages
L1 , . . . , L𝑛 ⊆ Σ∗ , and (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ∈ (0, 1]×[0, 1) with 0 ≤ π‘Žπ‘– +𝑏𝑖 ≤
1 for 𝑖 = 1, . . . , 𝑛 such that
𝑛
𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴) = ∐ (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1Li ,
(⋆)
𝑖=1
where 1Li = (πœ‡1L , 𝜈1L ) represents the intuitionistic characi
i
terized function of L𝑖 , 𝑖 = 1, . . . , 𝑛, that is,
1,
πœ‡1L (πœ”) = {
i
0,
0,
𝜈1L (πœ”) = {
i
1,
if πœ” ∈ L𝑖
if πœ” ∉ L𝑖 ,
(21)
if πœ” ∈ L𝑖
if πœ” ∉ L𝑖 .
And the equation (⋆) means that the following equations
hold:
𝑛
πœ‡π΄ (πœ”) =⋁ π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1L (πœ”) ,
𝑖=1
i
𝑛
𝜈𝐴 (πœ”) =β‹€ 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1L (πœ”) ,
𝑖=1
i
(22)
∗
∀πœ” ∈ Σ .
Noting that the family of all the intuitionistic fuzzy
recognizable step functions over Σ∗ is denoted by Step𝐢(Σ).
Proposition 18. Let MσΈ€ 1 = (𝑄1 , Σ, Γ1 , 𝛿1 , π‘ž01 , 𝑍01 , 𝐹1 ) be an
IFPDA. Then the language recognized by MσΈ€ 1 is an intuitionistic
fuzzy recognizable step function over Σ∗ , that is, L(MσΈ€ 1 ) ∈
Step𝐢(Σ).
Proof. By Proposition 14, there is an IFSPDA M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ,
𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹) equivalent to MσΈ€ 1 .
Let 𝑅 = {(πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž), 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž)) | π‘ž ∈ 𝑄} \ {(0, 1)} = {(π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) |
𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ }, π‘π‘˜ = {1, . . . , π‘˜}. Put 𝐹𝑖 = {π‘ž ∈ 𝑄 | πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) =
π‘Žπ‘– , 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) = 𝑏𝑖 }, for all 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ . Then we construct a PDA
M𝑖 = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹𝑖 ), where the mapping 𝛿󸀠 : 𝑄 × (Σ ∪
∗
{πœ€}) × Γ → 2𝑄×Γ is defined by
𝛿󸀠 (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋) = {(𝑝, 𝛾) | πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 1, 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈
Γ∗ }, for all (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋) ∈ 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ.
Then L(M𝑖 ) = L𝑖 = {πœ” ∈ Σ∗ | (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗M𝑖 (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾),
π‘ž ∈ 𝐹𝑖 , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ }.
Therefore, for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ , we have πœ‡L(MσΈ€ 1 ) (πœ”) = πœ‡L(M) (πœ”)
= ⋁{πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) | πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } =
⋁{π‘Žπ‘– | πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) = π‘Žπ‘– , 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) = 𝑏𝑖 ,
𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = ⋁{π‘Žπ‘– | (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗M𝑖 (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), π‘ž ∈ 𝐹𝑖 ,
𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = ⋁{π‘Žπ‘– | πœ” ∈ L(M𝑖 ), 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } = ⋁𝑖∈π‘π‘˜ π‘Žπ‘– ∧
πœ‡1L(M ) (πœ”), and 𝜈L(MσΈ€ 1 ) (πœ”) = 𝜈L(M) (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) | 𝜈⊒∗M ((π‘ž0 ,
i
πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 0, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝑏𝑖 |
πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) = π‘Žπ‘– , 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) = 𝑏𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈
π‘π‘˜ , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝑏𝑖 | (π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ) ≻∗M𝑖 (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾), π‘ž ∈ 𝐹𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ ,
𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ } = β‹€{𝑏𝑖 | πœ” ∈ L(M𝑖 ), 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } = ⋀𝑖∈π‘π‘˜ 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1L(M ) (πœ”).
i
So L(M) = βˆπ‘–∈π‘π‘˜ (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1Li .
Proposition 18 shows that the set of the languages recognized by all the IFPDAs is a subset of Step𝐢(Σ). In fact,
Step𝐢(Σ) is also a subset of the set of the languages recognized
by all the IFPDAs. We will prove the decomposition form in
the following.
Theorem 19. Let 𝐴 be an IFS over Σ∗ . Then the following
statements are equivalent:
(i) 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ);
(ii) there is an IFPDA M such that 𝐴 = L(M);
(iii) there is an IFSPDA M such that 𝐴 = L(M).
Proof. (i) implies (iii). Suppose 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ). Then there is
a finite natural number 𝑛 ∈ 𝑁, recognizable context-free
languages L1 , . . . , L𝑛 ⊆ Σ∗ , and (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ∈ (0, 1] × [0, 1)
with 0 ≤ π‘Žπ‘– + 𝑏𝑖 ≤ 1 for 𝑖 = 1, . . . , 𝑛 such that 𝐴 =
(πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴) = βˆπ‘›π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1Li . Let L𝑖 be recognized by a PDA
M𝑖 = (𝑄𝑖 , Σ, Γ𝑖 , 𝛿𝑖 , π‘ž0𝑖 , 𝑍0𝑖 , 𝐹𝑖 ), and 𝑄𝑖 ∩𝑄𝑗 = 0 whenever 𝑖 =ΜΈ 𝑗,
𝑖, 𝑗 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 .
Next, construct an IFSPDA M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹)
as follows: 𝑄 = ⋃𝑛𝑖=1 𝑄𝑖 ∪ {π‘ž0 }, Γ = ⋃𝑛𝑖=1 Γ𝑖 ∪ {𝑍0 }, where
π‘ž0 ∉ ⋃𝑛𝑖=1 𝑄𝑖 , 𝑍0 ∉ ⋃𝑛𝑖=1 Γ𝑖 . 𝛿 = (πœ‡π›Ώ , πœˆπ›Ώ ) is an IFS over
𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ , where the mappings πœ‡π›Ώ , πœˆπ›Ώ :
𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ → {0, 1} are defined by πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 ,
πœ€, 𝑍0 , 𝑝, 𝛾) = 1 and πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 , 𝑝, 𝛾) = 0 if (𝑝, 𝛾) = (π‘ž0𝑖 ,
𝑍0𝑖 ), 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 ; πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = πœ‡π›Ώπ‘– (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) and πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž,
𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = πœˆπ›Ώπ‘– (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) if 𝑝, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄𝑖 , 𝑍 ∈ Γ𝑖 , 𝛾 ∈ Γ𝑖∗ ,
𝜏 ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 . Otherwise, πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 0 and
πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 1.
𝐹 = (πœ‡πΉ , 𝜈𝐹 ) is an IFS in 𝑄, where
πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž0 ) = ⋁ {π‘Žπ‘– ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝐹𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } ,
𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž0 ) = β‹€ {𝑏𝑖 ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝐹𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } ,
πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) = {
π‘Žπ‘– ,
0,
if π‘ž ∈ 𝐹𝑖
if π‘ž ∉ 𝐹𝑖 ∪ {π‘ž0 } ,
(23)
𝑏 , if π‘ž ∈ 𝐹𝑖
𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) = { 𝑖
1, if π‘ž ∉ 𝐹𝑖 ∪ {π‘ž0 } .
Therefore, for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ , we have
πœ‡L(M) (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) ∧ πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) | π‘ž ∈
𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ },
𝜈L(M) (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈⊒∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) | π‘ž ∈
𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ }.
Journal of Applied Mathematics
9
If πœ” = πœ€, then πœ‡L(M) (πœ€) = (πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 )) ∧
πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž0 )) ∨ (⋁{πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ€, 𝑍0𝑖 )) ∧ πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž0𝑖 ) | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈
𝑄𝑖 , 𝑍0𝑖 ∈ Γ𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 }) = πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž0 ) ∨ (⋁{πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž0𝑖 ) | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝑄𝑖 , 𝑍0𝑖 ∈
Γ𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 }) = ⋁{π‘Žπ‘– ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝐹𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } =
⋁𝑛𝑖=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1L (πœ€); 𝜈L(M) (πœ€) = (𝜈⊒∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 )) ∨
i
𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž0 )) ∧ (β‹€{𝜈⊒∗M ((π‘ž0 , πœ€, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ€, 𝑍0𝑖 )) ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž0𝑖 ) | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝑄𝑖 ,
𝑍0𝑖 ∈ Γ𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 }) = 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž0 )∧(β‹€{𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž0𝑖 ) | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝑄𝑖 , 𝑍0𝑖 ∈ Γ𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈
𝑁𝑛 }) = β‹€{𝑏𝑖 ∈ [0, 1] | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝐹𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } = ⋀𝑛𝑖=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1L (πœ€). If
i
πœ” ∈ Σ∗ \ {πœ€}, then πœ‡L(M) (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ”, 𝑍0𝑖 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) ∧
πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝑄𝑖 , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ , π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } = ⋁{πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝑄𝑖 ,
𝛾 ∈ Γ𝑖∗ , π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 , πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ”, 𝑍0𝑖 ),(π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1} =
⋁{π‘Žπ‘– | π‘ž ∈ 𝐹𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 , πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ”, 𝑍0𝑖 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, 𝛾 ∈ Γ𝑖∗ } =
⋁{π‘Žπ‘– | πœ” ∈ L𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } = ⋁𝑛𝑖=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1L (πœ”), 𝜈L(M) (πœ”) =
i
β‹€{𝜈⊒∗M ((π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ”, 𝑍0𝑖 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) ∨ 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž)|π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝑄𝑖 , 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ , π‘ž ∈
𝑄, 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } = β‹€{𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) | π‘ž0𝑖 ∈ 𝑄𝑖 , 𝛾 ∈ Γ𝑖∗ , π‘ž ∈ 𝑄, 𝑖 ∈
𝑁𝑛 , πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ”, 𝑍0𝑖 ),(π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1} = β‹€{𝑏𝑖 | π‘ž ∈ 𝐹𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈
𝑁𝑛 , πœ‡βŠ’∗M ((π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ”, 𝑍0𝑖 ), (π‘ž, πœ€, 𝛾)) = 1, 𝛾 ∈ Γ𝑖∗ } = β‹€{𝑏𝑖 | πœ” ∈
L𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } = ⋀𝑛𝑖=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∨ 𝜈1L (πœ”).
i
(iii) implies (ii): obviously.
(ii) implies (i): it is concluded by Proposition 18.
Next, we will discuss the characterization of IFPDA0 .
Proposition 20. Let M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 0) be an IFPDA0 .
Then there is a special IFPDA0 MσΈ€  = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0σΈ€  , 𝑋0 , 0)
equivalent to M.
Proof. Given M, we construct an IFPDA0 MσΈ€ 
(𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0σΈ€  , 𝑋0 , 0) as follows:
Firstly let us show that, for any πœ” = 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ∈ Σ∗ , πœπ‘– ∈
Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑖 ∈ {1, . . . , 𝑛}, π‘žπ‘› ∈ 𝑄,
πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ) , ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ) , πœ€, 𝑋0 ))
M
1,
={
0,
𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ) , ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ) , πœ€, 𝑋0 ))
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
0,
={
1,
(P2) there exist π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘›−1 ∈ 𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . . , 𝑍𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, 𝛾1 ,
. . . , 𝛾𝑛−1 ∈ Γ∗ , s.t. π‘Žπ‘› = πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍1 𝛾1 ))∧πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 ))∧
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, πœ€)) > 0
and 𝑏𝑛 = 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∨
𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨
𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, πœ€)) < 1.
In fact, if (P2) is satisfied, then let πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘– , πœπ‘–+1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍𝑖 𝛾𝑖 ), (π‘žπ‘–+1 , πœπ‘–+2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑖+1 𝛾𝑖+1 )) = 𝑐𝑖 , 𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘– , πœπ‘–+1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑖 𝛾𝑖 ),
(π‘žπ‘–+1 , πœπ‘–+2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑖+1 𝛾𝑖+1 )) = 𝑑𝑖 , 𝑖 = 0, 1, . . . , 𝑛 − 2, where
𝛾0 = πœ€. We have
Obviously, 𝛿󸀠 = (πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  , πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ) is a finite IFS in 𝑄󸀠 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) ×
Γ × π‘„σΈ€  × ΓσΈ€ ∗ .
Next, we show L(MσΈ€  ) = L(M).
πœ”, 𝑍0 𝑋0 ),
((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ),
𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝜈⊒MσΈ€  ((π‘ž0 , 1, 0),
𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 )) = 0,
πœ”, 𝑍0 𝑋0 ),
((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ),
𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝜈⊒MσΈ€  (((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ), 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž2 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 , 𝑑0 ∨
𝑑1 ), 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 𝑋0 )) = 0,
..
.
(2) 𝛿 = (πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  , πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ) is an IFS in 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ ,
where the mappings πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  , πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  : 𝑄󸀠 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × ΓσΈ€  × π‘„σΈ€  ×
ΓσΈ€ ∗ → [0, 1] are defined by
σΈ€ 
πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  ((π‘ž0 , 1, 0),
𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 )) = 1,
πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ), 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž2 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 , 𝑑0 ∨
𝑑1 ), 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 𝑋0 )) = 1,
σΈ€ ∗
(i) πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  ((𝑝0 , 1, 0), πœ€, 𝑋0 , (π‘ž0 , 1, 0), 𝑍0 𝑋0 )
=
1,
πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ((𝑝0 , 1, 0), πœ€, 𝑋0 , (π‘ž0 , 1, 0), 𝑍0 𝑋0 ) = 0;
(ii) πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), 𝜏, 𝑋, (π‘žσΈ€  , π‘Ž ∧ π‘ŽσΈ€  , 𝑏 ∨ 𝑏󸀠 ), 𝛾) = 1
and πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), 𝜏, 𝑋, (π‘žσΈ€  , π‘Ž ∧ π‘ŽσΈ€  , 𝑏 ∨ 𝑏󸀠 ), 𝛾) =
0 whenever πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋, π‘žσΈ€  , 𝛾) = π‘ŽσΈ€  > 0 and
πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋, π‘žσΈ€  , 𝛾) = 𝑏󸀠 < 1, for all (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 ,
𝜏 ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€}, 𝑋 ∈ Γ, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ ;
(iii) if 0 ≤ π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1, then πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, 𝑋0 , (π‘ž, π‘Ž,
𝑏), πœ€) = π‘Ž and πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, 𝑋0 , (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€) = 𝑏.
If π‘Ž + 𝑏 > 1, then πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, 𝑋0 , (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€) =
0 and πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, 𝑋0 , (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€) = 1;
(iv) In other cases, πœ‡π›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), 𝜏, 𝑋, (𝑝, 𝑐, 𝑑), 𝛾) = 0
and πœˆπ›ΏσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), 𝜏, 𝑋, (𝑝, 𝑐, 𝑑), 𝛾) = 1.
if (P2) is satisfied
otherwise,
where the condition (P2) is the following:
=
σΈ€ 
(24)
M
(1) 𝑄󸀠 = 𝑄2 × (𝐿 1 \ {0}) × (𝐿 2 \ {1}), where 𝑄2 = 𝑄 ∪ {𝑝0 },
ΓσΈ€  = Γ ∪ {𝑋0 }, 𝐿 1 = 𝑋∧ , 𝐿 2 = π‘Œ∨ , 𝑋 = Im(πœ‡π›Ώ ), π‘Œ =
Im(πœˆπ›Ώ ), and π‘ž0σΈ€  = (𝑝0 , 1, 0);
σΈ€ 
if (P2) is satisfied
otherwise,
πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ 𝑐𝑛−2 , 𝑑0 ∨ 𝑑1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑑𝑛−2 ),
πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) = 1,
𝜈⊒MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ 𝑐𝑛−2 , 𝑑0 ∨ 𝑑1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑑𝑛−2 ),
πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) = 0.
Hence πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 ) ≥ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  ((π‘ž0 ,
M
1, 0), πœ”, 𝑍0 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ), 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘ž1 ,
𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ), 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž2 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 , 𝑑0 ∨ 𝑑1 ), 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ,
𝑍2 𝛾2 𝑋0 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ 𝑐𝑛−2 , 𝑑0 ∨
𝑑1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑑𝑛−2 ), πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) = 1,
𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) ≤ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  ((π‘ž0 , 1, 0), πœ”,
M
𝑍0 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ), 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  (((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ), 𝜏2
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž2 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 , 𝑑0 ∨ 𝑑1 ), 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 𝑋0 )) ∨
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘›−1 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ 𝑐𝑛−2 , 𝑑0 ∨ 𝑑1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑑𝑛−2 ),
πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) = 0.
Since πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) ≤ 1 and
M
𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) ≥ 0, πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ),
M
M
10
Journal of Applied Mathematics
((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) = 1 and 𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ),
M
πœ€, 𝑋0 )) = 0.
If (P2) is not satisfied, then we assume πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  ,
M
πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) > 0.
So there at least exist π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘›−1 ∈ 𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . . , 𝑍𝑛−1 ∈ Γ,
𝛾1 , . . . , 𝛾𝑛−1 ∈ Γ∗ , s.t. πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  ((π‘ž0 , 1, 0), πœ”, 𝑍0 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ),
𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘ž1 , 𝑐0 , 𝑑0 ), 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 𝑋0 ),
((π‘ž2 , 𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 , 𝑑0 ∨ 𝑑1 ), 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 𝑋0 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  (((π‘žπ‘›−1 ,
𝑐0 ∧ 𝑐1 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ 𝑐𝑛−2 , 𝑑0 ∨ 𝑑1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑑𝑛−2 ),πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 𝑋0 ),
((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) > 0.
Hence π‘Žπ‘› = πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∧
πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 ,
πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, πœ€)) > 0 and 𝑏𝑛 = 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∨
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈⊒M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› , 𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ), (π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, πœ€)) < 1.
It contradicts with the assumption. So πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ),
M
((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 ) = 0 if (P2) is not satisfied. In a similar
way, it is easily concluded that 𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› ,
M
𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 ) = 1 if (P2) is not satisfied.
Secondly, for any πœ” = 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› ∈ Σ∗ , πœπ‘– ∈ Σ ∪ {πœ€},
𝑖 ∈ {1, . . . , 𝑛}, πœ‡L(MσΈ€  ) (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€,
M
𝑋0 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, πœ€)) | (π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› ,
𝑏𝑛 ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 } = ⋁{πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž0 , πœ”, 𝑍0 ), (π‘ž1 , 𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘ž1 ,
𝜏2 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍1 𝛾1 ), (π‘ž2 , 𝜏3 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘› , 𝑍2 𝛾2 )) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡βŠ’M ((π‘žπ‘›−1 , πœπ‘› ,
𝑍𝑛−1 𝛾𝑛−1 ),(π‘žπ‘› , πœ€, πœ€)) | π‘ž1 , . . . , π‘žπ‘› ∈ 𝑄, 𝑍1 , . . . , 𝑍𝑛−1 ∈ Γ, 𝛾1 ,
. . . , 𝛾𝑛−1 ∈ Γ∗ } = πœ‡L(M) (πœ”).
Similarly, 𝜈L(MσΈ€  ) (πœ”) = 𝜈L(M) (πœ”).
Hence L(MσΈ€  ) = L(M).
Remark 21. Proposition 20 presents an equivalence of an
IFPDA0 . In particular, due to the underlying truth-valued
domain being an IFS, the proof technique used in Proposition 20 is to some extent different from the technique of
extended subset construction in [33]. Moreover, Proposition 20 plays an important role in proving the fact that any
language recognized by an IFPDA0 is an intuitionistic fuzzy
recognizable step function.
Proposition 22. Let M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 0) be an IFPDA0 .
Then the language recognized by M is an intuitionistic fuzzy
recognizable step function over Σ∗ , that is, L(M) ∈ Step𝐢(Σ).
Proof. Let M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 0) be an IFPDA0 . Then
there is a special IFPDA0 MσΈ€  = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  , 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0σΈ€  , 𝑋0 , 0) constructed by Proposition 20, which is equivalent to M. For any
(π‘Ž, 𝑏) ∈ (𝐿 1 \ {0}) × (𝐿 2 \ {1}) with 0 < π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1, construct a classical PDA with empty stack Mπ‘Žπ‘ = (𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  ,
σΈ€ σΈ€ 
, π‘ž0σΈ€  , 𝑋0 , 0), where 𝑄󸀠 , Σ, ΓσΈ€  , π‘ž0σΈ€  , and 𝑋0 are the same as
π›Ώπ‘Žπ‘
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ ∗
σΈ€ σΈ€ 
: 𝑄󸀠 × Σ × ΓσΈ€  → 2𝑄 ×Γ is
those in MσΈ€  , and the function π›Ώπ‘Žπ‘
defined by
σΈ€ σΈ€ 
((𝑝0 , 1, 0), πœ€, 𝑋0 ) = {((π‘ž0 , 1, 0), 𝑍0 𝑋0 )};
(i) π›Ώπ‘Žπ‘
σΈ€ σΈ€ 
((π‘ž, 𝑐, 𝑑), 𝜏, 𝑋) = {((π‘žσΈ€  , 𝑐 ∧ 𝑐1 , 𝑑 ∨ 𝑑1 ), 𝛾) | 𝑐1 =
(ii) π›Ώπ‘Žπ‘
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋, π‘žσΈ€  , 𝛾) > 0, 𝑑1 = πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋, π‘žσΈ€  , 𝛾) < 1, π‘žσΈ€  ∈
𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ };
σΈ€ σΈ€ 
(iii) π›Ώπ‘Žπ‘
((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, 𝑋0 ) = {((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€)};
σΈ€ σΈ€ 
((π‘ž, 𝑐, 𝑑), 𝜏, 𝑋) = 0 in other cases.
(iv) π›Ώπ‘Žπ‘
Then for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ , we have πœ‡L(M) (πœ”) = πœ‡L(MσΈ€  ) (πœ”)
= ⋁{πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) ∧ πœ‡βŠ’MσΈ€  ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ),
M
πœ€, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, πœ€)) | (π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 } = ⋁{π‘Žπ‘› |
(π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 , 0 < π‘Žπ‘› + 𝑏𝑛 ≤ 1, πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ),((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ),
M
πœ€, 𝑋0 )) = 1} = ⋁{π‘Žπ‘› | (π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ ((π‘žπ‘› , π‘Žπ‘› , 𝑏𝑛 ), πœ€, πœ€), π‘žπ‘› ∈
𝑄} = β‹π‘Ž∈𝐿 1 \{0} π‘Ž ∧ πœ‡1L(M ) (πœ”), and 𝜈L(M) (πœ”) = 𝜈L(MσΈ€  ) (πœ”)
ab
= β‹€{𝜈⊒∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) ∨ 𝜈⊒MσΈ€  ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€,
M
𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, πœ€)) | (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 } = β‹€{𝑏 | (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏) ∈
𝑄󸀠 , 0 < π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1, πœ‡βŠ’∗ σΈ€  ((π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ), ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, 𝑋0 )) =
M
1} = β‹€{𝑏 | (π‘ž0σΈ€  , πœ”, 𝑋0 ) ≻∗Mπ‘Žπ‘ ((π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏), πœ€, 𝑋0 ), (π‘ž, π‘Ž, 𝑏) ∈ 𝑄󸀠 }
= ⋀𝑏∈𝐿 2 \{1} 𝑏 ∨ 𝜈1L(M ) (πœ”).
ab
Therefore L(M) ∈ Step𝐢(Σ).
Theorem 23. Let 𝐴 be an IFS over Σ∗ . Then the following
statements are equivalent:
(1) 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ);
(2) 𝐴 is accepted by a certain IFPDA0 M.
Proof. (i) implies (ii). Suppose 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ). Then there are
a finite natural number 𝑛 ∈ 𝑁, recognizable context-free
languages L1 , . . . , L𝑛 ⊆ Σ∗ , and (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ∈ (0, 1] × [0, 1)
with 0 ≤ π‘Žπ‘– + 𝑏𝑖 ≤ 1 for 𝑖 = 1, . . . , 𝑛 such that 𝐴 =
(πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴) = βˆπ‘›π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1Li . Let L𝑖 be recognized by PDA
M𝑖 = (𝑄𝑖 , Σ, Γ𝑖 , 𝛿𝑖 , π‘ž0𝑖 , 𝑍0𝑖 , 0), and 𝑄𝑖 ∩ 𝑄𝑗 = 0 whenever 𝑖 =ΜΈ 𝑗,
𝑖, 𝑗 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 .
Next, construct an IFPDA0 M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 0) as
follows: 𝑄 = ⋃𝑛𝑖=1 𝑄𝑖 , Γ = ⋃𝑛𝑖=1 Γ𝑖 ∪ {𝑍0 }, and 𝐼 = (πœ‡πΌ , 𝜈𝐼 )
are an IFS over 𝑄, defined by πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0𝑖 ) = π‘Žπ‘– , 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0𝑖 ) = 𝑏𝑖 ,
𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 ; otherwise πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž) = 0 and 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž) = 1. 𝛿 = (πœ‡π›Ώ , πœˆπ›Ώ ) is
an IFS over 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ , where the mappings
πœ‡π›Ώ , πœˆπ›Ώ : 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ → {0, 1} are defined by
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ€, 𝑍0 , π‘ž0𝑖 , 𝑍0𝑖 ) = 1 and πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0𝑖 , πœ€, 𝑍0 , π‘ž0𝑖 , 𝑍0𝑖 ) = 0, 𝑖 ∈
𝑁𝑛 ; πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 1 and πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 0 if 𝑝, π‘ž ∈ 𝑄𝑖 ,
𝑍 ∈ Γ𝑖 , 𝛾 ∈ Γ𝑖∗ , 𝜏 ∈ Σ, 𝑖 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 and (𝑝, 𝛾) ∈ 𝛿(π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍).
Otherwise, πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 0 and πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 1.
Then 𝐴 = L(M) = βˆπ‘›π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1Li .
(ii) implies (i). It is concluded by Proposition 22.
One can see that IFPDAs and IFPDAs0 are equivalent to
a type of intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable step functions over
a set, respectively, by Theorems 19 and 23. Therefore, IFPDAs
and IFPDAs0 are equivalent in the sense that they accept or
recognize the same classes of intuitionistic fuzzy languages.
That is to say, the following statement is true.
Corollary 24. For any IFPDA M, there is an
IFPDA0 MσΈ€  equivalent to M. For any IFPDA0 MσΈ€  , there
is an IFPDA M equivalent to MσΈ€  .
4. Intuitionistic Fuzzy Context-Free Grammars
As a type of generator of intuitionistic fuzzy context-free
languages, the notion of intuitionistic fuzzy context-free
Journal of Applied Mathematics
grammars is introduced in the section. Then the relationship
between intuitionistic fuzzy context-free grammars, IFPDAs,
IFPDAs0 , and intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable step functions
is discussed. The algebraic properties of intuitionistic fuzzy
context-free languages are investigated finally.
Definition 25. An intuitionistic fuzzy grammar is a system
𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼), where
(i) 𝑁 is a finite nonempty alphabet of variables;
(ii) 𝑇 is a finite nonempty alphabet of terminals and 𝑇 ∩
𝑁 = 0;
(iii) 𝐼 is an intuitionistic fuzzy set over 𝑁;
(iv) 𝑃 is a finite collection of productions over 𝑇 ∪ 𝑁,
and 𝑃 = {π‘₯ → 𝑦 | π‘₯ ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ 𝑁(𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ ,
𝑦 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ , πœ‡πœŒ (π‘₯ → 𝑦) > 0, 𝜈𝜌 (π‘₯ → 𝑦) < 1},
where 𝜌 = (πœ‡πœŒ , 𝜈𝜌 ) is an IFS over (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ × (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ ,
πœ‡πœŒ (π‘₯, 𝑦), and 𝜈𝜌 (π‘₯, 𝑦) mean the membership degree and
the nonmembership degree that π‘₯ will be replaced by 𝑦,
respectively, denoted by πœ‡πœŒ (π‘₯, 𝑦) = πœ‡πœŒ (π‘₯ → 𝑦), 𝜈𝜌 (π‘₯, 𝑦) =
𝜈𝜌 (π‘₯ → 𝑦).
For 𝛼, 𝛽 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ , if π‘₯ → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑃, then 𝛼𝑦𝛽 is said to
be directly derivable from 𝛼π‘₯𝛽, denoted by 𝛼π‘₯𝛽 ⇒ 𝛼𝑦𝛽, and
define πœ‡πœŒ (𝛼π‘₯𝛽 ⇒ 𝛼𝑦𝛽) = πœ‡πœŒ (π‘₯ → 𝑦), 𝜈𝜌 (𝛼π‘₯𝛽 ⇒ 𝛼𝑦𝛽) =
𝜈𝜌 (π‘₯ → 𝑦).
If 𝛼1 , . . . , π›Όπ‘š are strings in (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ and 𝛼1 → 𝛼2 ,
. . . , π›Όπ‘š−1 → π›Όπ‘š ∈ 𝑃, then 𝛼1 is said to derive π›Όπ‘š in 𝐺, or,
equivalently, π›Όπ‘š is derivable from 𝛼1 in 𝐺. This is expressed
by 𝛼1 ⇒∗𝐺 π›Όπ‘š or simply 𝛼1 ⇒∗ π›Όπ‘š . The expression 𝛼1 → 𝛼2 →
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ → π›Όπ‘š is referred to as a derivation chain from 𝛼1 to π›Όπ‘š .
An intuitionistic fuzzy grammar 𝐺 generates an intuitionistic fuzzy language L(𝐺) = (πœ‡πΊ, 𝜈𝐺) in the following
manner. For any πœƒ = πœ”π‘› ∈ 𝑇∗ , 𝑛 ≥ 1, πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (πœ”0 ) ∧
πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | πœ”0 ∈ 𝑁, πœ”1 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈
(𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ }, and 𝜈𝐺(πœƒ) = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (πœ”0 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨
𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | πœ”0 ∈ 𝑁, πœ”1 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ }.
πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) and 𝜈𝐺(πœƒ) express the membership and nonmembership degree of πœƒ in the language generated by grammar
𝐺, respectively. Obviously, L(𝐺) = (πœ‡πΊ, 𝜈𝐺) is well defined.
In fact, for any πœƒ = πœ”π‘› ∈ 𝑇∗ , 𝑛 ≥ 1, there is the strongest
σΈ€ 
⇒
derivation from πœ”0 to πœ”π‘› , that is, πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1σΈ€  ⇒ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ⇒ πœ”π‘›−1
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
⇒
πœ”π‘› , such that πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) = πœ‡πΌ (πœ”0 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”π‘›−1
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
πœ”π‘› ). So 𝜈𝐺(πœƒ) ≤ 𝜈𝐼 (πœ”0 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ),
and πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) + 𝜈𝐺(πœƒ) ≤ πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) + 𝜈𝐼 (πœ”0 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1σΈ€  ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨
σΈ€ 
⇒ πœ”π‘› ) = (πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) + 𝜈𝐼 (πœ”0 )) ∨ (πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) + 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1σΈ€  )) ∨
𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1
σΈ€ 
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ (πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) + 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1
⇒ πœ”π‘› )) ≤ (πœ‡πΌ (πœ”0 ) + 𝜈𝐼 (πœ”0 )) ∨ (πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”0 ⇒
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
πœ”1 ) + 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1 )) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ (πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”π‘›−1
⇒ πœ”π‘› ) + 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1
⇒
πœ”π‘› )) ≤ 1.
For any intuitionistic fuzzy grammars 𝐺1 and 𝐺2 , if
L(𝐺1 ) = L(𝐺2 ) in the sense of equality of intuitionistic fuzzy
sets, then the grammars 𝐺1 and 𝐺2 are said to be equivalent.
For any intuitionistic fuzzy grammar 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼), if
Im(𝐼) = Im(πœ‡πΌ ) ∪ Im(𝜈𝐼 ) = {0, 1} and supp(𝐼) = {𝑆}, then 𝐺
is also written as 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝑆).
11
Proposition 26. Let 𝐴 be an IFS over 𝑇∗ . Then the following
statements are equivalent:
(i) 𝐴 is generated by a certain intuitionistic fuzzy grammar
𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼);
(ii) 𝐴 is generated by a certain intuitionistic fuzzy grammar
𝐺 = (𝑁󸀠 , 𝑇󸀠 , 𝑃󸀠 , 𝑆).
Proof. (i) implies (ii). Let 𝐴 be generated by an intuitionistic
fuzzy grammar 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼). Then we construct an
intuitionistic fuzzy grammar 𝐺󸀠 = (𝑁󸀠 , 𝑇󸀠 , 𝑃󸀠 , 𝑆) as follows:
𝑁󸀠 = 𝑁 ∪ {𝑆}, 𝑆 ∉ 𝑁; 𝑇󸀠 = 𝑇, 𝑃󸀠 = 𝑃 ∪ 𝑃1 , where 𝑃1 = {𝑆 →
π‘ž | π‘ž ∈ supp(𝐼), πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 → π‘ž) = πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž), 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 → π‘ž) = 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž)}.
Next we show that L(𝐺󸀠 ) = L(𝐺). In fact, 𝐺󸀠 =
σΈ€ 
(𝑁 , 𝑇󸀠 , 𝑃󸀠 , 𝐼󸀠 ), where 𝐼󸀠 is an IFS over 𝑁󸀠 , πœ‡πΌσΈ€  (𝑆) = 1, πœˆπΌσΈ€  (𝑆) =
0; πœ‡πΌσΈ€  (π‘ž) = 0 and πœˆπΌσΈ€  (π‘ž) = 1 when π‘ž ∈ 𝑁.
For any πœƒ = πœ”π‘› ∈ 𝑇∗ , 𝑛 ≥ 1, πœ‡πΊσΈ€  (πœƒ) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌσΈ€  (πœ”0 )∧πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”0 ⇒
πœ”1 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | πœ”0 ∈ 𝑁󸀠 , πœ”1 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁󸀠 ∪
𝑇󸀠 )∗ } = ⋁{πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒ πœ”1 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”1 ⇒ πœ”2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒
πœ”π‘› ) | πœ”1 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁󸀠 ∪ 𝑇󸀠 )∗ } = ⋁{πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒ π‘ž) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (π‘ž ⇒
πœ”2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | π‘ž ∈ 𝑁, πœ”2 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪
𝑇)∗ } = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (π‘ž ⇒ πœ”2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | π‘ž ∈
𝑁, πœ”2 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁∪𝑇)∗ } = πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) and πœˆπΊσΈ€  (πœƒ) = β‹€{πœˆπΌσΈ€  (πœ”0 )∨
𝜈𝜌 (πœ”0 ⇒ πœ”1 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | πœ”0 ∈ 𝑁󸀠 , πœ”1 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈
(𝑁󸀠 ∪ 𝑇󸀠 )∗ } = β‹€{𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒ πœ”1 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”1 ⇒ πœ”2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒
πœ”π‘› ) | πœ”1 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁󸀠 ∪ 𝑇󸀠 )∗ } = β‹€{𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒ π‘ž) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (π‘ž ⇒
πœ”2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | π‘ž ∈ 𝑁, πœ”2 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } =
β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (π‘ž ⇒ πœ”2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | π‘ž ∈ 𝑁,
πœ”2 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } = 𝜈𝐺(πœƒ).
Hence L(𝐺󸀠 ) = L(𝐺).
(ii) implies (i), obviously.
Definition 27. (1) An intuitionistic fuzzy grammar 𝐺 = (𝑁,
𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼) is called context-free (IFCFG, for short) if it has only
productions of the form 𝐴 → πœ” ∈ 𝑃 with 𝐴 ∈ 𝑁 and πœ” ∈
(𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ . And the language L(𝐺), generated by the IFCFG
𝐺, is said to be an intuitionistic fuzzy context-free language
(IFCFL).
(2) An IFCFG 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝑆) is called an intuitionistic
fuzzy Chomsky normal form (IFCNF) if it has only productions of the form 𝐴 → 𝐡𝐢 ∈ 𝑃 or 𝐴 → π‘Ž ∈ 𝑃 or 𝑆 → πœ€,
where 𝐴, 𝐡, 𝐢 ∈ 𝑁, 𝐡 =ΜΈ 𝑆, 𝐢 =ΜΈ 𝑆 and π‘Ž ∈ 𝑇. (3) An IFCFG
𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝑆) is called an intuitionistic fuzzy Greibach
normal form (IFGNF) if all the productions are of the form
𝐴 → π‘Žπ‘₯ ∈ 𝑃 or 𝑆 → πœ€, where 𝐴 ∈ 𝑁, π‘Ž ∈ 𝑇, and π‘₯ ∈
(𝑁 \ {𝑆})∗ . (4) An IFCFG 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼) is called a simpletyped intuitionistic fuzzy context-free grammar (IFSCFG) if
𝑃 = {𝐴 󳨀→ π‘₯ | 𝐴 ∈ 𝑁, π‘₯ ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ , πœ‡πœŒ (𝐴 󳨀→ π‘₯) = 1} .
(25)
Proposition 28. Let 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼) be an IFCFG and
L(𝐺) = (πœ‡πΊ, 𝜈𝐺) be the intuitionistic fuzzy context-free
language generated by 𝐺. Then the image set of L(𝐺) is a finite
subset of the unit interval [0, 1].
Proof. Let 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼) be an IFCFG. Then Im(πœ‡πœŒ ) and
Im(𝜈𝜌 ) are finite. For any πœƒ = πœ”π‘› ∈ 𝑇∗ , 𝑛 ≥ 1, there exist
12
Journal of Applied Mathematics
natural numbers 𝑑, 𝑙 such that πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (𝑆) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒
πœ”1 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”1 ⇒ πœ”2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | 𝑆 ∈ 𝑁,
πœ”1 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } = (π‘Ž10 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅∧ π‘Ž1𝑛−1 ∧ π‘Ž1𝑛 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ (π‘Žπ‘‘0 ∧
⋅ ⋅ ⋅∧π‘Žπ‘‘π‘›−1 ∧π‘Žπ‘‘π‘› ) and 𝜈𝐺(πœƒ) = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (𝑆)∨𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒ πœ”1 )∨𝜈𝜌 (πœ”1 ⇒
πœ”2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (πœ”π‘›−1 ⇒ πœ”π‘› ) | 𝑆 ∈ 𝑁, πœ”1 , . . . , πœ”π‘›−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } =
(𝑏10 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑏1𝑛−1 ∨ 𝑏1𝑛 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ (𝑏𝑙0 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑏𝑙𝑛−1 ∨ 𝑏𝑙𝑛 ), where
π‘Žπ‘–π‘˜ ∈ Im(πœ‡πΌ ) ∪ Im(πœ‡πœŒ ), π‘π‘—π‘˜ ∈ Im(𝜈𝐼 ) ∪ Im(𝜈𝜌 ), 𝑖 ∈ {1, . . . , 𝑑},
𝑗 ∈ {1, . . . , 𝑙}, π‘˜ ∈ {0, 1, . . . , 𝑛}. Let 𝑋 = Im(πœ‡πΌ ) ∪ Im(πœ‡πœŒ ) and
π‘Œ = Im(𝜈𝐼 ) ∪ Im(𝜈𝜌 ). Then 𝑋 and π‘Œ are finite subsets of the
interval [0, 1]. (𝑋∧ )∨ and (π‘Œ∨ )∧ are also finite by Lemma 8.
Since πœ‡πΊ(πœƒ) ∈ (𝑋∧ )∨ and 𝜈𝐺(πœƒ) ∈ (π‘Œ∨ )∧ for any πœƒ ∈ 𝑇∗ ,
we have Im(πœ‡πΊ) ⊆ (𝑋∧ )∨ and Im(𝜈𝐺) ⊆ (π‘Œ∨ )∧ . Hence
Im(L(𝐺)) = Im(πœ‡πΊ) ∪ Im(𝜈𝐺) is finite.
Proposition 29. Let 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝑆) be an IFCFG. Then
L(𝐺) ∈ Step𝐢(𝑇).
Proof. Let 𝑋 = Im(πœ‡πœŒ ) and π‘Œ = Im(𝜈𝜌 ). Then 𝑋 and π‘Œ have
finite elements because 𝑃 is a finite collection of productions
over 𝑇 ∪ 𝑁. Suppose 𝐿 1 = 𝑋∧ and 𝐿 2 = π‘Œ∨ . Then 𝐿 1 and 𝐿 2
are finite by Lemma 8. For any (π‘Ž, 𝑏) ∈ (𝐿 1 \ {0}) × (𝐿 2 \ {1}),
0 ≤ π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1, we construct a classical context-free grammar
σΈ€ 
, 𝑆󸀠 ) as follows:
πΊπ‘Žπ‘ = (𝑁󸀠 , 𝑇, π‘ƒπ‘Žπ‘
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
𝑁 = 𝑁 × (𝐿 1 \ {0}) × (𝐿 2 \ {1}), 𝑆󸀠 = (𝑆, 1, 0) ∈ 𝑁󸀠 , π‘ƒπ‘Žπ‘
consists of the form:
→
𝐷1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ π·π‘˜ whenever πœ‡πœŒ (𝐴
(1) (𝐴, π‘Ž1 , 𝑏1 )
𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜ ) > 0 and 𝜈𝜌 (𝐴 → 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜ ) < 1, where
𝐷𝑖 = {
(πœπ‘– , π‘Ž2 , 𝑏2 ) ,
πœπ‘– ,
if πœπ‘– ∈ 𝑁
if πœπ‘– ∈ 𝑇
→
(26)
𝑖 = 1, . . . , π‘˜; π‘Ž2 = π‘Ž1 ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝐴 → 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜ ) and 𝑏2 =
𝑏1 ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝐴 → 𝜏1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœπ‘˜ );
(2) (𝐴, π‘Ž1 , 𝑏1 ) → π‘₯ whenever π‘Ž ≤ π‘Ž1 ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝐴 → π‘₯) and
𝑏 ≥ 𝑏1 ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝐴 → π‘₯), for all 𝐴 ∈ 𝑁, π‘₯ ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ .
Then L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘ ) = {πœ” ∈ 𝑇∗ | 𝑆󸀠 ⇒∗πΊπ‘Žπ‘ πœ”} = {πœ” ∈ 𝑇∗ | π‘Ž ≤
πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒1 ⇒ 𝑒2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”), 𝑏 ≥ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒
𝑒1 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒1 ⇒ 𝑒2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”), 𝑒1 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪
𝑇)∗ }.
Next it suffices to show that L(𝐺) = ∐(π‘Ž, 𝑏) ⋅ 1L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘ ) , that
is, πœ‡πΊ(πœ”) = β‹π‘Ž∈𝐿 1 \{0} π‘Ž ∧ πœ‡1L(𝐺 ) (πœ”) and 𝜈𝐺(πœ”) = ⋀𝑏∈𝐿 2 \{1} 𝑏 ∨
π‘Žπ‘
𝜈1L(𝐺 ) (πœ”), for all πœ” ∈ 𝑇∗ .
π‘Žπ‘
σΈ€ 
Suppose πœ‡πΊ(πœ”) = π‘Žπ‘˜ > 0. Then there exist 𝑒1σΈ€  , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1
∈
∗
σΈ€ 
σΈ€ 
(𝑁 ∪ 𝑇) such that π‘Žπ‘˜ = πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒1 ⇒ 𝑒2σΈ€  ) ∧
σΈ€ 
⇒ πœ”). Put 𝑐 = 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1σΈ€  ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒1σΈ€  ⇒ 𝑒2σΈ€  ) ∨
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒𝑛−1
σΈ€ 
⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒𝑛−1
⇒ πœ”). Then 𝑐 < 1 and πœ” ∈ L(πΊπ‘˜π‘ ).
Therefore, πœ‡πΊ(πœ”) ≤ β‹π‘Ž∈𝐿 1 \{0} π‘Ž ∧ πœ‡1L(𝐺 ) (πœ”) and 𝜈𝐺(πœ”) ≥
π‘Žπ‘
⋀𝑏∈𝐿 2 \{1} 𝑏 ∨ 𝜈1L(𝐺 ) (πœ”) for any πœ” ∈ 𝑇∗ . In addition,
π‘Žπ‘
β‹π‘Ž∈𝐿 1 \{0} π‘Ž ∧ πœ‡1L(𝐺 ) (πœ”) = ⋁{π‘Ž ∈ 𝐿 1 \ {0} | πœ” ∈ L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘ )} ≤
π‘Žπ‘
⋁{πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒1 ⇒ 𝑒2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”) | πœ” ∈
L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘ ), 𝑒1 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁∪𝑇)∗ } ≤ ⋁{πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 )∧πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒1 ⇒
𝑒2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”) | 𝑒1 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } = πœ‡πΊ(πœ”),
𝜈𝐺(πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒1 ⇒ 𝑒2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒
πœ”) | 𝑒1 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } ≤ β‹€{𝑏 ∈ 𝐿 2 \ {1} | 𝑏 ≥
𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 )∨𝜈𝜌 (𝑒1 ⇒ 𝑒2 )∨⋅ ⋅ ⋅∨𝜈𝜌 (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”), 𝑒1 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈
(𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } ≤ β‹€{𝑏 ∈ 𝐿 2 \ {1} | 𝑏 ≥ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒1 ⇒
𝑒2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”), π‘Ž ≤ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒1 ⇒
𝑒2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”), 𝑒1 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } = β‹€{𝑏 ∈
𝐿 2 \ {1} | πœ” ∈ L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘ )} = ⋀𝑏∈𝐿 2 \{1} 𝑏 ∨ 𝜈1L(𝐺 ) (πœ”).
π‘Žπ‘
It is concluded that πœ‡πΊ(πœ”) = β‹π‘Ž∈𝐿 1 \{0} π‘Ž ∧ πœ‡1L(𝐺 ) (πœ”) and
π‘Žπ‘
𝜈𝐺(πœ”) = ⋀𝑏∈𝐿 2 \{1} 𝑏 ∨ 𝜈1L(𝐺 ) (πœ”), for all πœ” ∈ 𝑇∗ .
π‘Žπ‘
Proposition 29 states that any language recognized by an
IFCFG is an intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable step function,
where the proof technique is constructive. Next we will
show that the set consisting of all the intuitionistic fuzzy
recognizable step functions coincides with that of languages
recognized by IFCFGs.
Theorem 30. Let 𝐴 be an IFS over 𝑇∗ . Then the following
statements are equivalent:
(1) 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(𝑇);
(2) There is an IFCFG 𝐺 such that 𝐴 = L(𝐺);
(3) There is an IFSCFG 𝐺 such that 𝐴 = L(𝐺).
Proof. (1) implies (3). Let 𝐴 = βˆπ‘˜π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1L𝑖 , where π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ∈
[0, 1], π‘Žπ‘– + 𝑏𝑖 ≤ 1, 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ , and L1 , . . . , Lπ‘˜ ⊂ 𝑇∗ are
classical context-free languages. Suppose L𝑖 is generated by
a context-free grammar 𝐺𝑖 = (𝑁𝑖 , 𝑇, 𝑃𝑖 , 𝑆0𝑖 ) and 𝑁𝑖 ∩ 𝑁𝑗 = 0
whenever 𝑖 =ΜΈ 𝑗. Then we construct an IFSCFG 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝐼)
as follows: 𝑁 = β‹ƒπ‘˜π‘–=1 𝑁𝑖 , 𝑃 = β‹ƒπ‘˜π‘–=1 𝑃𝑖 , 𝐼 = (πœ‡πΌ , 𝜈𝐼 ) is an IFS
over 𝑁, where the mappings πœ‡πΌ , 𝜈𝐼 : 𝑁 → [0, 1] are defined
by πœ‡πΌ (𝑆0𝑖 ) = π‘Žπ‘– , 𝜈𝐼 (𝑆0𝑖 ) = 𝑏𝑖 ; πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž) = 0 and 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž) = 1 whenever
π‘ž ∈ 𝑁 \ {𝑆0𝑖 | 𝑖 = 1, . . . , π‘˜}.
Next, we show 𝐴 = L(𝐺) = βˆπ‘˜π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1L𝑖 . In fact, for
any πœ” = 𝑒𝑛 ∈ 𝑇∗ , πœ‡πΊ(πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (𝑆) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒1 ⇒
𝑒2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”) | 𝑆 ∈ 𝑁, 𝑒1 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } =
⋁{πœ‡πΌ (𝑆0𝑖 ) | 𝑆0𝑖 ⇒∗𝐺𝑖 πœ”, 𝑆0𝑖 ∈ 𝑁, 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } = ⋁{π‘Žπ‘– | πœ” ∈ L𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈
π‘π‘˜ } = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1L (πœ”) and 𝜈𝐺(πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (𝑆) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 ⇒ 𝑒1 ) ∨
𝑖
𝜈𝜌 (𝑒1 ⇒ 𝑒2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒ πœ”) | 𝑆 ∈ 𝑁, 𝑒1 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈
(𝑁 ∪ 𝑇)∗ } = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (𝑆0𝑖 ) | 𝑆0𝑖 ⇒∗𝐺𝑖 πœ”, 𝑆0𝑖 ∈ 𝑁, 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } = β‹€{𝑏𝑖 |
πœ” ∈ L𝑖 , 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1L (πœ”).
𝑖
Hence L(𝐺) = (πœ‡πΊ, 𝜈𝐺) = βˆπ‘˜π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1L𝑖 = 𝐴.
(3) implies (2). It is true obviously since an IFSCFG is a
special IFCFG by Definition 27.
(2) implies (1). It is straightforward by Propositions 26
and 29.
Theorem 31. Let 𝐴 be an IFS over Σ∗ . Then the following
statements are equivalent:
(1) 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ);
(2) there is an IFPDA M such that 𝐴 = L(M);
(3) there is an IFPDA0 M such that 𝐴 = L(M);
(4) there is an IFCFG 𝐺 such that 𝐴 = L(𝐺);
(5) there is an IFCNF 𝐺 such that 𝐴 = L(𝐺);
(6) there is an IFGNF 𝐺 such that 𝐴 = L(𝐺).
Journal of Applied Mathematics
Proof. (1) implies (5). Let 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ). Then suppose 𝐴 =
βˆπ‘˜π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1L𝑖 , where π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ∈ [0, 1], π‘Žπ‘– + 𝑏𝑖 ≤ 1, 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ , and
L1 , . . . , Lπ‘˜ ⊂ Σ∗ are classical context-free languages.
If supp(𝐴) = {πœ€}, then we construct an IFCNF 𝐺 = (𝑁,
Σ, 𝑃, 𝑆) as follows: 𝑁 = {𝑆}, 𝑃 = {𝑆 → πœ€ | πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 → πœ€) =
πœ‡π΄ (πœ€), 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 → πœ€) = πœ‡π΄ (πœ€)}. Clearly, L(𝐺) = 𝐴.
If supp(𝐴) \ {πœ€} =ΜΈ 0, then there is a Chomsky normal form
grammar 𝐺𝑖 = (𝑁𝑖 , Σ, 𝑃𝑖 , 𝑆0𝑖 ) such that L(𝐺𝑖 ) = L𝑖 \ {πœ€},
for any L𝑖 with L𝑖 \ {πœ€} =ΜΈ 0, 𝑖 = 1, . . . , π‘˜. Let 𝑁𝑖 ∩ 𝑁𝑗 = 0
whenever 𝑖 =ΜΈ 𝑗. Then we construct an IFSCFG 𝐺 = (𝑁, Σ, 𝑃, 𝐼)
according to the method constructed by Theorem 30, where
𝑁 = β‹ƒπ‘˜π‘–=1 𝑁𝑖 , 𝑃 = β‹ƒπ‘˜π‘–=1 𝑃𝑖 , 𝐼 = (πœ‡πΌ , 𝜈𝐼 ) is an IFS over 𝑁, and
the mappings πœ‡πΌ , 𝜈𝐼 : 𝑁 → [0, 1] are defined by πœ‡πΌ (𝑆0𝑖 ) = π‘Žπ‘– ,
𝜈𝐼 (𝑆0𝑖 ) = 𝑏𝑖 ; πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž) = 0 and 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž) = 1 whenever π‘ž ∈ 𝑁 \ {𝑆0𝑖 |
𝑖 = 1, . . . , π‘˜}. Next, we construct an IFCNF 𝐺󸀠 = (𝑁󸀠 , Σ, 𝑃󸀠 , 𝑆)
as follows:
(i) 𝑁󸀠 = 𝑁 ∪ {𝑆}, 𝑆 ∉ 𝑁;
(ii) 𝑃󸀠 = 𝑃 ∪ 𝑃󸀠󸀠 , where 𝑃󸀠󸀠 has the productions in the
form of
(𝐸1) 𝑆 → πœ€ with πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 → πœ€) = πœ‡π΄ (πœ€), 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 → πœ€) =
πœ‡π΄ (πœ€) whenever πœ€ ∈ supp(𝐴);
(𝐸2) 𝑆 → 𝐡𝐢 with πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 → 𝐡𝐢) = πœ‡πΌ (𝑆0𝑖 ) and
𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 → 𝐡𝐢) = 𝜈𝐼 (𝑆0𝑖 ) whenever 𝑆0𝑖 ∈ supp(𝐼)
and 𝑆0𝑖 → 𝐡𝐢 ∈ 𝑃𝑖 , 𝑖 = 1, . . . , π‘˜;
(𝐸3) 𝑆 → 𝛼 with πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 → 𝛼) = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (𝑆0𝑖 ) | 𝑆0𝑖 ∈
supp(𝐼), 𝑆0𝑖 → 𝛼 ∈ 𝑃𝑖 , 𝑖 = 1, . . . , π‘˜} and 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 →
𝛼) = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (𝑆0𝑖 ) | 𝑆0𝑖 ∈ supp(𝐼), 𝑆0𝑖 → 𝛼 ∈ 𝑃𝑖 , 𝑖 =
1, . . . , π‘˜} whenever 𝑆0𝑖 ∈ supp(𝐼) and 𝑆0𝑖 → 𝛼 ∈
𝑃𝑖 , 𝑖 = 1, . . . , π‘˜.
Then we have L(𝐺󸀠 ) = (πœ‡πΊσΈ€  , πœˆπΊσΈ€  ) = 𝐴. In fact, for any πœ” ∈
Σ , if πœ” = πœ€, then πœ‡πΊσΈ€  (πœ€) = πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆 → πœ€) = πœ‡π΄ (πœ€) and πœˆπΊσΈ€  (πœ€) =
𝜈𝜌 (𝑆 → πœ€) = 𝜈𝐴(πœ€); if πœ” =ΜΈ πœ€, then πœ‡πΊσΈ€  (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆⇒𝐺󸀠 𝑒1 ) ∧
πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒1 ⇒𝐺󸀠 𝑒2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒𝐺󸀠 πœ”) | 𝑒1 , 𝑒2 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁󸀠 ∪
Σ)∗ } = ⋁{πœ‡πΌ (𝑆0𝑖 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑆0𝑖 ⇒𝐺𝑖 𝑒1 ) ∧ πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒1 ⇒𝐺𝑖 𝑒2 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧
πœ‡πœŒ (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒𝐺𝑖 πœ”) | 𝑒1 , 𝑒2 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪ Σ)∗ , 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } =
∗
⋁{π‘Žπ‘– | πœ” ∈ L(𝐺𝑖 ), 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1L (πœ”) and πœˆπΊσΈ€  (πœ”) =
𝑖
β‹€{𝜈𝜌 (𝑆⇒𝐺󸀠 𝑒1 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒1 ⇒𝐺󸀠 𝑒2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒𝐺󸀠 πœ”) |
𝑒1 , 𝑒2 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁󸀠 ∪ Σ)∗ } = β‹€{𝜈𝐼 (𝑆0𝑖 ) ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑆0𝑖 ⇒𝐺𝑖 𝑒1 ) ∨
𝜈𝜌 (𝑒1 ⇒𝐺𝑖 𝑒2 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝜌 (𝑒𝑛−1 ⇒𝐺𝑖 πœ”) | 𝑒1 , 𝑒2 , . . . , 𝑒𝑛−1 ∈ (𝑁 ∪
Σ)∗ , 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } = β‹€{π‘Žπ‘– | πœ” ∈ L(𝐺𝑖 ), 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∨ πœ‡1L (πœ”).
𝑖
(1) implies (6), similarly. The proof is omitted.
(5) implies (4), (6) implies (4), obviously, since IFCNF
and IFGNF are special IFCFGs respectively.
(1), (2), (3), and (4) are equivalent mutually by Theorems
19, 23, and 30.
Theorem 31 states that IFCFLs, the set of intuitionistic
fuzzy languages recognized by IFPDA and the set of intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable step functions, coincide with
each other. Next we discuss some operations on the family
of IFCFLs.
Let 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴) and 𝐡 = (πœ‡π΅ , 𝜈𝐡 ) be IFSs over Σ∗ ,
πœ†, πœƒ ∈ [0, 1], and 0 ≤ πœ† + πœƒ ≤ 1. Then the operations of union,
scalar product, reversal, concatenation and Kleene closure are
defined, respectively, by
13
(i) 𝐴 ∪ 𝐡 = (πœ‡π΄∪𝐡 , 𝜈𝐴∪𝐡 ), πœ‡π΄∪𝐡 (πœ”) = πœ‡π΄ (πœ”) ∨ πœ‡π΅ (πœ”),
𝜈𝐴∪𝐡 (πœ”) = 𝜈𝐴 (πœ”) ∧ 𝜈𝐡 (πœ”);
(ii) (πœ†, πœƒ)𝐴 = (πœ† ∧ πœ‡π΄ , πœƒ ∨ 𝜈𝐴), (πœ† ∧ πœ‡π΄ )(πœ”) = πœ† ∧ πœ‡π΄ (πœ”),
(πœƒ ∨ 𝜈𝐴 )(πœ”) = πœƒ ∨ 𝜈𝐴(πœ”);
(iii) 𝐴−1 = (πœ‡π΄−1 , 𝜈𝐴−1 ), πœ‡π΄−1 (πœ”) = πœ‡π΄ (πœ”−1 ), 𝜈𝐴−1 (πœ”) =
𝜈𝐴 (πœ”−1 );
(iv) 𝐴𝐡 = (πœ‡π΄π΅ , 𝜈𝐴𝐡 ), πœ‡π΄π΅ (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡π΄ (πœ”1 ) ∧ πœ‡π΅ (πœ”2 ) |
πœ”1 πœ”2 = πœ”}, 𝜈𝐴𝐡 (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐴 (πœ”1 ) ∨ 𝜈𝐡 (πœ”2 ) | πœ”1 πœ”2 = πœ”};
(v) 𝐴∗ = (πœ‡π΄∗ , 𝜈𝐴∗ ), πœ‡π΄∗ (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡π΄ (πœ”1 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡π΄ (πœ”π‘˜ ) :
π‘˜ ≥ 1, πœ” = πœ”1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœ”π‘˜ }, 𝜈𝐴∗ (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐴 (πœ”1 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨
𝜈𝐴 (πœ”π‘˜ ) : π‘˜ ≥ 1, πœ” = πœ”1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœ”π‘˜ } for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ ,
where πœ”−1 represents the reversal of πœ”, that is, if πœ” =
πœ”1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœ”π‘˜ , then πœ”−1 = πœ”π‘˜ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœ”1 , for all πœ” ∈ Σ∗ .
Theorem 32. (1) The family Step𝐢(Σ) is closed under the
operations of union, scalar product, reversal, concatenation,
and Kleene closure. That is, 𝐴 ∪ 𝐡, (πœ†, πœƒ)𝐴, 𝐴−1 , 𝐴𝐡, 𝐴∗ ∈
Step𝐢(Σ), for any 𝐴, 𝐡 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ), πœ†, πœƒ ∈ [0, 1], 0 ≤ πœ† + πœƒ ≤ 1.
(2) Let β„Ž : Σ∗1 → Σ∗2 be a homomorphism. If 𝐴 ∈
Step𝐢(Σ2 ), then β„Ž−1 (𝐴) = 𝐴 ∘ β„Ž ∈ Step𝐢(Σ1 ). (3) Let β„Ž : Σ∗1 →
Σ∗2 be a homomorphism. If β„Ž satisfies, for 𝜏 ∈ Σ, β„Ž(𝜏) =ΜΈ πœ€,
and 𝑔 = (πœ‡π‘” , πœˆπ‘” ) ∈ Step𝐢(Σ1 ), then β„Ž(𝑔) = (πœ‡β„Ž(𝑔) , πœˆβ„Ž(𝑔) ) ∈
Step𝐢(Σ2 ), where πœ‡β„Ž(𝑔) (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡π‘” (𝛼) | β„Ž(𝛼) = πœ”, 𝛼 ∈ Σ∗1 },
πœˆβ„Ž(𝑔) (πœ”) = β‹€{πœˆπ‘” (𝛼) | β„Ž(𝛼) = πœ”, 𝛼 ∈ Σ∗1 } for any πœ” ∈ Σ∗2 .
Proof. (1) Let 𝐴, 𝐡 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ). By Definition 17, we can
assume 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴 ) = βˆπ‘˜π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1L𝑖 , 𝐡 = (πœ‡π΅ , 𝜈𝐡 ) =
βˆπ‘›π‘—=1 (𝑐𝑗 , 𝑑𝑗 ) ⋅ 1M𝑗 , where all L𝑖 and M𝑗 are classical contextfree languages, 0 ≤ π‘Žπ‘– + 𝑏𝑖 ≤ 1, 0 ≤ 𝑐𝑗 + 𝑑𝑗 ≤ 1, π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 , 𝑐𝑗 , 𝑑𝑗 ∈
[0, 1], 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ , and 𝑗 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 . With respect to the union, we
have 𝐴 ∪ 𝐡 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ). That is, 𝐴 ∪ 𝐡 = (πœ‡π΄∪𝐡 , 𝜈𝐴∪𝐡 ) =
(πœ‡π΄ ∨ πœ‡π΅ , 𝜈𝐴 ∧ 𝜈𝐡 ), πœ‡π΄∪𝐡 (πœ”) = πœ‡π΄ (πœ”) ∨ πœ‡π΅ (πœ”) = (β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧
πœ‡1L (πœ”)) ∨ (⋁𝑛𝑗=1 𝑐𝑗 ∧ πœ‡1M (πœ”)), 𝜈𝐴∪𝐡 (πœ”) = 𝜈𝐴(πœ”) ∧ 𝜈𝐡 (πœ”) =
𝑖
𝑗
(β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1L (πœ”)) ∧ (⋀𝑛𝑗=1 𝑑𝑗 ∨ 𝜈1M (πœ”)), for all πœ” ∈ Σ∗ .
𝑖
𝑗
With respect to the scalar product, for each (πœ†, πœƒ) ∈
[0, 1]×[0, 1], 0 ≤ πœ†+πœƒ ≤ 1, we have (πœ†, πœƒ)𝐴 = (πœ†∧πœ‡π΄, πœƒ∨𝜈𝐴 ),
(πœ† ∧ πœ‡π΄)(πœ”) = πœ† ∧ πœ‡π΄ (πœ”) = πœ† ∧ (β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1L (πœ”)) =
𝑖
β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 ((πœ† ∧ π‘Žπ‘– ) ∧ πœ‡1L (πœ”)), (πœƒ ∨ 𝜈𝐴)(πœ”) = πœƒ ∨ 𝜈𝐴(πœ”) = πœƒ ∨
𝑖
(β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1L (πœ”)) = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 (πœƒ ∨ 𝑏𝑖 ) ∨ 𝜈1L (πœ”), for all πœ” ∈ Σ∗ .
𝑖
𝑖
By Definition 17, (πœ†, πœƒ)𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ). For the reversal
−1
operation, L−1
∈ Σ∗ | πœ” ∈ L𝑖 }, and L−1
𝑖 = {πœ”
𝑖 is a context-free language because L𝑖 is a context-free language,
𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ . For any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ , πœ‡π΄−1 (πœ”) = πœ‡π΄ (πœ”−1 ) = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧
πœ‡1L (πœ”−1 ) = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1L−1 (πœ”),𝜈𝐴−1 (πœ”) = 𝜈𝐴(πœ”−1 ) = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨
𝑖
𝑖
𝜈1L (πœ”−1 ) = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1L−1 (πœ”), that is 𝐴−1 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ). For the
𝑖
𝑖
operation of concatenation, since πœ‡π΄π΅ (πœ”) = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 ⋁𝑛𝑗=1 (π‘Žπ‘– ∧
𝑐𝑗 ) ∧ πœ‡1L M (πœ”), 𝜈𝐴𝐡 (πœ”) = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 ⋀𝑛𝑗=1 (𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝑑𝑗 ) ∨ 𝜈1L M (πœ”), for
𝑖
𝑗
𝑖
𝑗
all πœ” ∈ Σ∗ , where the elements of the family set {L𝑖 M𝑗 | 𝑖 ∈
π‘π‘˜ , 𝑗 ∈ 𝑁𝑛 } are also context-free languages since L𝑖 and M𝑗
are context-free languages. Hence 𝐴𝐡 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ).
14
Journal of Applied Mathematics
For the Kleene closure, 𝐴∗ = (πœ‡π΄∗ , 𝜈𝐴∗ ) is defined by
πœ‡π΄∗ (πœ”) = ⋁{πœ‡π΄ (πœ”1 ) ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ πœ‡π΄ (πœ”π‘˜ ) : π‘˜ ≥ 1, πœ” = πœ”1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœ”π‘˜ },
𝜈𝐴∗ (πœ”) = β‹€{𝜈𝐴 (πœ”1 ) ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝜈𝐴(πœ”π‘˜ ) : π‘˜ ≥ 1, πœ” = πœ”1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ πœ”π‘˜ } for
any πœ” ∈ Σ∗ . Since 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ), we assume that the IFSPDA
M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹) accepts 𝐴 by Theorem 19. Let 𝑅 =
{(πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž), 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž)) | π‘ž ∈ 𝑄} \ {(0, 1)} = {(π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) | 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ }. Then
𝐴 = βˆπ‘˜π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1L𝑖 , where L𝑖 is accepted by a PDA M𝑖 =
(𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿󸀠 , π‘ž0 , 𝑍0 , 𝐹𝑖 ), the mapping 𝛿󸀠 : 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ →
∗
2𝑄×Γ is defined by 𝛿󸀠 (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋) = {(𝑝, 𝛾) | πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋, 𝑝, 𝛾) =
1, 𝑝 ∈ 𝑄, 𝛾 ∈ Γ∗ }, for all (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑋) ∈ 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ, and
𝐹𝑖 = {π‘ž ∈ 𝑄 | πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž) = π‘Žπ‘– , 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž) = 𝑏𝑖 }, for all 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ .
For any nonempty subset 𝐽 of the set {1, 2, . . . , π‘˜}, we can
assume that 𝐽 = {𝑖1 , . . . , 𝑖𝑠 }. Let π‘Ÿπ½ = π‘Žπ‘–1 ∧ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∧ π‘Žπ‘–π‘  , 𝑑𝐽 =
𝑏𝑖1 ∨ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∨ 𝑏𝑖𝑠 , and L(𝐽) = ⋃𝑝1 ⋅⋅⋅𝑝𝑠 L+𝑝1 L+𝑝2 L∗𝑝1 L+𝑝3 (L𝑝1 ∪
L𝑝2 )∗ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ L+𝑝𝑠−1 (L𝑝1 ∪ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∪ L𝑝𝑠−2 )∗ L+𝑝𝑠 (L𝑝1 ∪ ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ ∪ L𝑝𝑠 )∗ ,
where 𝑝1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ 𝑝𝑠 is a permutation of {𝑖1 , . . . , 𝑖𝑠 }, and L(𝐽) takes
unions under all permutations of {𝑖1 , . . . , 𝑖𝑠 }. Hence L(𝐽)
is a context-free language. It is easily verified that 𝐴∗ =
(∐0 =ΜΈ 𝐽⊆π‘π‘˜ (π‘Ÿπ½ , 𝑑𝐽 )⋅1L(𝐽) )∪((πœ‡π΄ (πœ€), 𝜈𝐴(πœ€))⋅1{πœ€} ). Therefore, 𝐴∗ ∈
Step𝐢(Σ).
(2) If 𝐴 ∈ Step𝐢(Σ2 ), then 𝐴 = βˆπ‘˜π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1L𝑖 , where π‘Žπ‘– ,
𝑏𝑖 ∈ [0, 1], π‘Žπ‘– + 𝑏𝑖 ≤ 1, 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ , and L1 , . . . , Lπ‘˜ ⊂ Σ∗2 are
classical context-free languages. Since β„Ž : Σ∗1 → Σ∗2 is a
homomorphism, πœ‡β„Ž−1 (𝐴) (πœ”) = πœ‡π΄βˆ˜β„Ž (πœ”) = πœ‡π΄ (β„Ž(πœ”)) = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧
πœ‡1L (β„Ž(πœ”)) = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1β„Ž−1 (L ) (πœ”), and πœˆβ„Ž−1 (𝐴) (πœ”) = πœˆπ΄βˆ˜β„Ž (πœ”) =
𝑖
𝑖
𝜈𝐴(β„Ž(πœ”)) = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ πœ‡1L (β„Ž(πœ”)) = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1β„Ž−1 (L ) (πœ”), where
𝑖
𝑖
πœ” ∈ Σ∗1 , β„Ž−1 (L𝑖 ) = {πœ”1 ∈ Σ∗1 | β„Ž(πœ”1 ) ∈ L𝑖 }, 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ , and the
elements of the set {β„Ž−1 (L𝑖 ) | 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ } are classical contextfree languages. Hence β„Ž−1 (𝐴) = 𝐴 ∘ β„Ž = βˆπ‘˜π‘–=1 (π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ) ⋅ 1β„Ž−1 (L𝑖 ) .
And so β„Ž−1 (𝐴) ∈ Step𝐢(Σ1 ). (3) If β„Ž(𝜏) =ΜΈ πœ€, for all 𝜏 ∈ Σ, and
𝑔 = (πœ‡π‘” , πœˆπ‘” ) ∈ Step𝐢(Σ1 ), then πœ‡π‘” (πœ”) = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧ πœ‡1L (πœ”),
𝑖
πœˆπ‘” (πœ”) = β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ πœ‡1L (πœ”), for any πœ” ∈ Σ1 , where π‘Žπ‘– , 𝑏𝑖 ∈ [0, 1],
𝑖
π‘Žπ‘– + 𝑏𝑖 ≤ 1, 𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ , L1 , . . . , Lπ‘˜ ⊂ Σ∗1 are classical context-free
languages. Since β„Ž : Σ∗1 → Σ∗2 is a homomorphism, β„Ž(L𝑖 ) =
{β„Ž(πœ”) ∈ Σ∗2 | πœ” ∈ L𝑖 } is also a classical context-free language,
𝑖 ∈ π‘π‘˜ . For any π‘₯ ∈ Σ∗2 , πœ‡β„Ž(𝑔) (π‘₯) = ⋁{πœ‡π‘” (𝛼) | β„Ž(𝛼) = π‘₯} =
⋁{β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧πœ‡1L (𝛼) | β„Ž(𝛼) = π‘₯} = β‹π‘˜π‘–=1 π‘Žπ‘– ∧πœ‡1β„Ž(L ) (π‘₯), πœˆβ„Ž(𝑔) (π‘₯) =
𝑖
𝑖
β‹€{πœˆπ‘” (𝛼) | β„Ž(𝛼) = π‘₯} = β‹€{β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1L (𝛼) | β„Ž(𝛼) = π‘₯} =
β‹€π‘˜π‘–=1 𝑏𝑖 ∨ 𝜈1β„Ž(L ) (π‘₯). Hence β„Ž(𝑔)
𝐢
Step (Σ2 ).
𝑖
=
𝑖
(πœ‡β„Ž(𝑔) , πœˆβ„Ž(𝑔) )
∈
5. Pumping Lemma for IFCFLs
In this section, we mainly discuss the pumping lemma for
IFCFLs, which will become a powerful tool for proving a
certain intuitionistic fuzzy language noncontext-free.
Theorem 33. Let 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴) be an IFCFL over Σ∗ . Then
there exists a finite natural number 𝑛 such that for any 𝑧 ∈ Σ∗
with 𝑛 ≤ |𝑧|, there have 𝑒, 𝑣, 𝑀, π‘₯, 𝑦, 𝑒1 , 𝑣1 , 𝑀1 , π‘₯1 , 𝑦1 ∈ Σ∗
such that 𝑧 = 𝑒𝑣𝑀π‘₯𝑦 = 𝑒1 𝑣1 𝑀1 π‘₯1 𝑦1 , |𝑣𝑀π‘₯| ≤ 𝑛,
|𝑣1 𝑀1 π‘₯1 | ≤ 𝑛, |𝑣π‘₯| ≥ 1, |𝑣1 π‘₯1 | ≥ 1, and πœ‡π΄ (𝑒𝑣𝑖 𝑀π‘₯𝑖 𝑦) ≥
πœ‡π΄ (𝑒𝑣𝑀π‘₯𝑦),𝜈𝐴 (𝑒1 𝑣1𝑖 𝑀1 π‘₯1𝑖 𝑦1 ) ≤ 𝜈𝐴(𝑒1 𝑣1 𝑀1 π‘₯1 𝑦1 ), for all 𝑖 ≥ 0.
Proof. Let 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴) be an IFCFL over Σ∗ . Then there
is an IFCNF 𝐺 = (𝑁, 𝑇, 𝑃, 𝑆) who accepts 𝐴. According to
Proposition 29, L(𝐺) = ∐(π‘Ž, 𝑏) ⋅ 1L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘ ) , where (π‘Ž, 𝑏) ∈
(𝑋∧ \ {0}) × (π‘Œ∨ \ {1}), 𝑋 = Im(πœ‡πœŒ ), π‘Œ = Im(𝜈𝜌 ), 0 ≤ π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≤ 1
σΈ€ 
and the classical context-free grammar πΊπ‘Žπ‘ = (𝑁󸀠 , 𝑇, π‘ƒπ‘Žπ‘
, 𝑆󸀠 )
is shown in the proof process of of Proposition 29. Let 𝐺 have
π‘š variables. That means, |𝑁| = π‘š. Choose 𝑛 = 2π‘š . Next,
suppose |𝑧| ≥ 𝑛, πœ‡πΊ(𝑧) = π‘Ž0 > 0 and 𝜈𝐺(𝑧) = 𝑏0 < 1. Then
there exist π‘π‘˜ ∈ π‘Œ∨ \ {1} and π‘Žπ‘™ ∈ 𝑋∧ \ {0} with 0 < π‘Ž0 + π‘π‘˜ ≤ 1
and 0 < π‘Žπ‘™ + 𝑏0 ≤ 1 such that 𝑧 ∈ L(πΊπ‘Ž0 π‘π‘˜ ) ∩ L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘™ 𝑏0 ).
By pumping lemma for context-free languages, there are
𝑒, 𝑣, 𝑀, π‘₯, 𝑦 ∈ Σ∗ satisfying 𝑧 = 𝑒𝑣𝑀π‘₯𝑦, |𝑣𝑀π‘₯| ≤ 𝑛 and
|𝑣π‘₯| ≥ 1 such that 𝑒𝑣𝑖 𝑀π‘₯𝑖 𝑦 ∈ L(πΊπ‘Ž0 π‘π‘˜ ), for all 𝑖 ≥ 0. Then
πœ‡π΄ (𝑒𝑣𝑖 𝑀π‘₯𝑖 𝑦) ≥ πœ‡π΄ (𝑒𝑣𝑀π‘₯𝑦) for any 𝑖 ≥ 0 since πœ‡π΄ (𝑒𝑣𝑖 𝑀π‘₯𝑖 𝑦) =
β‹π‘Ž∈𝑋∧ \{0} π‘Ž ∧ 1L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘ ) (𝑒𝑣𝑖 𝑀π‘₯𝑖 𝑦) ≥ π‘Ž0 .
Similarly, there are 𝑒1 , 𝑣1 , 𝑀1 , π‘₯1 , 𝑦1 ∈ Σ∗ satisfying 𝑧 =
𝑒1 𝑣1 𝑀1 π‘₯1 𝑦1 , |𝑣1 𝑀1 π‘₯1 | ≤ 𝑛 and |𝑣1 π‘₯1 | ≥ 1 such that
𝑒1 𝑣1𝑖 𝑀1 π‘₯1𝑖 𝑦1 ∈ L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘™ 𝑏0 ), for all 𝑖 ≥ 0. Then 𝜈𝐴(𝑒1 𝑣1𝑖 𝑀1 π‘₯1𝑖 𝑦1 ) ≤
𝜈𝐴 (𝑒1 𝑣1 𝑀1 π‘₯1 𝑦1 ) for any 𝑖 ≥ 0 since 𝜈𝐴 (𝑒1 𝑣1𝑖 𝑀1 π‘₯1𝑖 𝑦1 ) =
⋀𝑏∈π‘Œ∨ \{1} 𝑏 ∨ 1L(πΊπ‘Žπ‘ ) (𝑒1 𝑣1𝑖 𝑀1 π‘₯1𝑖 𝑦1 ) ≤ 𝑏0 .
Next, let us look at an example to negate an intuitionistic
fuzzy language to be an IFCFL.
Example 34. Let 𝐴 = (πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴 ) be an IFS over 𝑇∗ . The
mappings πœ‡π΄ , 𝜈𝐴 : 𝑇∗ → [0, 1] are defined by
0.5,
0,
if 𝑧 = π‘Žπ‘– 𝑏𝑗 π‘π‘˜ (𝑖 < 𝑗 < π‘˜) ,
otherwise,
0.3,
𝜈𝐴 (𝑧) = {
1,
if 𝑧 = π‘Žπ‘– 𝑏𝑗 π‘π‘˜ (𝑖 < 𝑗 < π‘˜) ,
otherwise,
πœ‡π΄ (𝑧) = {
(27)
where 𝑖, 𝑗, and π‘˜ are natural numbers.
Suppose 𝐴 is an IFCFL. Then there exists a certain IFCNF
𝐺 such that L(𝐺) = 𝐴. For constant 𝑛, put 𝑧 = π‘Žπ‘› 𝑏𝑛+1 𝑐𝑛+2 .
Hence, πœ‡π΄ (𝑧) = πœ‡L(𝐺) (𝑧) = 0.5 and 𝜈𝐴(𝑧) = 𝜈L(𝐺) (𝑧) = 0.3.
Let 𝑧 = 𝑒𝑣𝑀π‘₯𝑦, where |𝑣𝑀π‘₯| ≤ 𝑛 and |𝑣π‘₯| ≥ 1. If 𝑣𝑀π‘₯
does not have 𝑐’s, then 𝑒𝑣3 𝑀π‘₯3 𝑦 has at least 𝑛 + 2π‘Ž’s or 𝑏’s;
if 𝑣𝑀π‘₯ has at least a 𝑐, then it has not an π‘Ž since |𝑣𝑀π‘₯| ≤ 𝑛.
And so 𝑒𝑀𝑦 has π‘›π‘ŽσΈ€  s, but no more than 2𝑛 + 2𝑏’s and 𝑐’s in
total, that is, |𝑒𝑀𝑦| ≤ 𝑛 + 2𝑛 + 2. Therefore, it is impossible
that 𝑒𝑀𝑦 has more 𝑏’s than π‘Ž’s and also has more 𝑐’s than 𝑏’s.
By calculation, we have πœ‡π΄ (𝑒𝑀𝑦) = 0 and 𝜈𝐴 (𝑒𝑀𝑦) = 1. No
matter how 𝑧 is broken into 𝑒𝑣𝑀π‘₯𝑦, we have a contradiction
with Theorem 33. Therefore, 𝐴 is not an IFCFL.
The following example will show that intuitionistic fuzzy
pushdown automata have more power than fuzzy pushdown
automata when comparing two distinct strings although the
degrees of membership of these strings recognized by the
underlying fuzzy pushdown automata are equal.
Journal of Applied Mathematics
15
Example 35. Let Σ = {0, 1}. Then 𝐿 = {πœ”1πœ”−1 | πœ” ∈ Σ∗ } ⊆ Σ∗
is clearly a context-free language but not a regular language by
classical automata theory, where πœ”−1 represents the reversal of
the string πœ”. Given an IFPDA M = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, 𝛿, 𝐼, 𝑍0 , 𝐹) and
a fuzzy pushdown automaton N = (𝑄, Σ, Γ, πœ‚, 𝜎0 , 𝑍0 , 𝜎1 ). Put
𝑄 = {π‘ž0 , π‘ž1 , π‘ž2 }, Γ = {𝑍0 , 0, 1}, an IFS 𝛿 = (πœ‡π›Ώ , πœˆπ›Ώ ) in 𝑄 × (Σ ∪
{πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ is defined by
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 0, 𝑍0 , π‘ž0 , 0𝑍0 ) = 0.7, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 0, 𝑍0 , π‘ž0 , 0𝑍0 ) =
0.2,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 𝑍0 , π‘ž0 , 1𝑍0 ) = 0.6, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 𝑍0 , π‘ž0 , 1𝑍0 ) =
0.3,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 0, 0, π‘ž0 , 00) = 0.3, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 0, 0, π‘ž0 , 00) = 0.6,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 0, 1, π‘ž0 , 01) = 0.3, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 0, 1, π‘ž0 , 01) = 0.5,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 0, π‘ž0 , 10) = 0.5, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 0, π‘ž0 , 10) = 0.4,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž1 , 0, 0, π‘ž1 , πœ€) = 0.6, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž1 , 0, 0, π‘ž1 , πœ€) = 0.3,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž1 , 1, 1, π‘ž1 , πœ€) = 0.5, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž1 , 1, 1, π‘ž1 , πœ€) = 0.35,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 𝑍0 , π‘ž1 , 𝑍0 ) = 1, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 𝑍0 , π‘ž1 , 𝑍0 ) = 0,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 0, π‘ž1 , 0) = 1, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 0, π‘ž1 , 0) = 0,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 1, π‘ž1 , 1) = 1, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž0 , 1, 1, π‘ž1 , 1) = 0,
πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž1 , πœ€, 𝑍0 , π‘ž2 , 𝑍0 ) = 1, πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž1 , πœ€, 𝑍0 , π‘ž2 , 𝑍0 ) = 0.
Otherwise πœ‡π›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 0 and πœˆπ›Ώ (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) = 1
for (π‘ž, 𝜏, 𝑍, 𝑝, 𝛾) ∈ 𝑄 × (Σ ∪ {πœ€}) × Γ × π‘„ × Γ∗ .
The IFSs 𝐼 = (πœ‡πΌ , 𝜈𝐼 ) and 𝐹 = (πœ‡πΉ , 𝜈𝐹 ) in 𝑄 are defined
by πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž0 ) = 1, 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž0 ) = 0, πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž1 ) = πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž2 ) = 0, 𝜈𝐼 (π‘ž1 ) =
πœ‡πΌ (π‘ž2 ) = 1, πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž2 ) = 1, 𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž2 ) = 0, πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž0 ) = πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž1 ) = 0 and
𝜈𝐹 (π‘ž0 ) = πœ‡πΉ (π‘ž1 ) = 1.
And set πœ‚ = πœ‡π›Ώ , 𝜎0 = πœ‡πΌ , and 𝜎1 = πœ‡πΉ .
By computing with the strings, 010, 111, 01110, 10101,
0011100, and 1011101∈ Σ∗ , we have
πœ‡L(M) (010) = 𝑓N (010) = 0.6, 𝜈L(M) (010) = 0.3,
πœ‡L(M) (111) = 𝑓N (111) = 0.5, 𝜈L(M) (111) = 0.35,
πœ‡L(M) (01110) = 𝑓N (01110) = 0.5, 𝜈L(M) (01110) =
0.4,
πœ‡L(M) (10101) = 𝑓N (10101) = 0.3, 𝜈L(M) (10101) =
0.5,
=
πœ‡L(M) (0011100)
𝜈L(M) (0011100) = 0.6,
𝑓N (0011100)
=
0.3,
πœ‡L(M) (1011101)
=
𝜈L(M) (1011101) = 0.5.
𝑓N (1011101)
=
0.3,
This implies that 111 is better than 01110 because the
degree of nonmembership of 𝜈L(M) (111) is smaller than the
𝜈L(M) (01110)’s although the degrees of membership of the
fuzzy context-free languages 𝑓N (01110) and 𝑓N (111) are
equal. Comparing the above five strings, 010 is the best and
0011100 is the worst.
languages. Firstly, the notions of intuitionistic fuzzy pushdown automata (IFPDAs) and their recognizable languages
are introduced and discussed in detail. Using the generalized
subset construction method, we show that IFPDAs are equivalent to IFSPDAs and then prove that intuitionistic fuzzy
step functions are the same as those accepted by IFPDAs.
Furthermore, we have presented algebraic characterization of
intuitionistic fuzzy recognizable languages including decomposition form and representation theorem. It follows that
the languages accepted by IFPDAs are equivalent to those
accepted by IFPDAs0 by classical automata theory. Secondly,
we have introduced the notions of IFCFGs, IFCNFs, and
IFGNFs. It is shown that they are equivalent in the sense
that they generate the same classes of intuitionistic fuzzy
context-free languages (IFCFLs). In particular, IFCFGs are
proven to be an equivalence of IFPDAs as well. Then some
operations on the family of IFCFLs are discussed. Finally
pumping lemma for IFCFLs has been established. Thus,
together with [38–40], we have more systematically established intuitionistic fuzzy automata theory as a generalization
of fuzzy automata theory.
As mentioned in Section 1, IFS and fuzzy automata theory
have supported a wealth of important applications in many
fields. The next step is to consider the potential application
of IFPDAs and IFCFLs such as in model checking and
clinical monitoring. Additionally, many related researches in
theories, such as IFPDAs based on the composition of t-norm
and t-conorm and the minimal algorithm of IFPDAs, will be
studied in the future.
Acknowledgments
The authors would like to thank the editor and the anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments that helped
to improve the quality of this paper. This work is supported by National Science Foundation of China (Grant no.
11071061), 973 Program (2011CB311808), and Natural Science
Foundation of Southwest Petroleum University (Grant no.
2012XJZ030).
References
[1] K. T. Atanassov, “Intuitionistic fuzzy sets,” Fuzzy Sets and Systems, vol. 20, no. 1, pp. 87–96, 1986.
[2] K. T. Atanassov, Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets: Theory and Applications, vol. 35, Physica, Heidelberg, Germany, 1999.
[3] K. Atanassov, “Answer to D. Dubois, S. Gottwald, P. Hajek, J.
Kacprzyk and H. Prade’s paper: terminological difficulties in
fuzzy set theory: the case of intuitionistic fuzzy sets,” Fuzzy Sets
and Systems, vol. 156, no. 3, pp. 496–499, 2005.
[4] W. L. Gau and D. J. Buehrer, “Vague sets,” IEEE Transactions on
Systems, Man and Cybernetics, vol. 23, no. 2, pp. 610–614, 1993.
6. Conclusions
[5] P. Burillo and H. Bustince, “Vague sets are intuitionistic fuzzy
sets,” Fuzzy Sets and Systems, vol. 79, no. 3, pp. 403–405, 1996.
Taking intuitionistic fuzzy sets as the structures of truth
values, we have investigated intuitionistic fuzzy context-free
languages and established pumping lemma for the underlying
[6] Z. Chen and W. Yang, “A new multiple criteria decision making
method based on intuitionistic fuzzy information,” Expert
Systems with Applications, vol. 39, no. 4, pp. 4328–4334, 2012.
16
[7] V. Khatibi and G. A. Montazer, “Intuitionistic fuzzy set versus
fuzzy set application in medical pattern recognition,” Artificial
Intelligence in Medicine, vol. 47, no. 1, pp. 43–52, 2009.
[8] Z. Pei and L. Zheng, “A novel approach to multi-attribute
decision making based on intuitionistic fuzzy sets,” Expert
Systems with Applications, vol. 39, no. 3, pp. 2560–2566, 2012.
[9] Q. S. Zhang, H. X. Yao, and Z. H. Zhang, “Some similarity
measures of interval-valued intuitionistic fuzzy sets and application to pattern recognition,” International Journal of Applied
Mechanics and Materials, vol. 44–47, pp. 3888–3892, 2011.
[10] Q. S. Zhang, S. Y. Jiang, B. G. Jia, and S. H. Luo, “Some
information measures for interval-valued intuitionistic fuzzy
sets,” Information Sciences, vol. 180, no. 12, pp. 5130–5145, 2010.
[11] E. T. Lee and L. A. Zadeh, “Note on fuzzy languages,” Information Sciences, vol. 1, no. 4, pp. 421–434, 1969.
[12] D. S. Malik and J. N. Mordeson, “On fuzzy regular languages,”
Information Sciences, vol. 88, pp. 263–273, 1994.
[13] D. S. Malik and J. N. Mordeson, Fuzzy Discrete Structures,
Physica, New York, NY, USA, 2000.
[14] J. N. Mordeson and D. S. Malik, Fuzzy Automata and Languages:
Theory and Applications, Chapman & Hall/CRC, Boca Raton,
Fla, USA, 2002.
[15] M. S. Ying, “A formal model of computing with words,” IEEE
Transactions on Fuzzy Systems, vol. 10, no. 5, pp. 640–652, 2002.
[16] F. Steimann and K.-P. Adlassnig, “Clinical monitoring with
fuzzy automata,” Fuzzy Sets and Systems, vol. 61, no. 1, pp. 37–
42, 1994.
[17] C. L. Giles, C. W. Omlin, and K. K. Thornber, “Equivalence
in knowledge representation: automata, recurrent neural networks, and dynamical fuzzy systems,” Proceedings of the IEEE,
vol. 87, no. 9, pp. 1623–1640, 1999.
[18] G. F. DePalma and S. S. Yau, “Fractionally fuzzy grammars
with application to pattern recognition,” in Fuzzy Sets and Their
Applications to Cognitive and Decision Processes, L. A. Zadeh, K.
S. Fu, K. Tanaka, and M. Shimura, Eds., pp. 329–351, Academic
Press, New York, NY, USA, 1975.
[19] D. W. Qiu, “Supervisory control of fuzzy discrete event systems:
a formal approach,” IEEE Transactions on Systems, Man, and
Cybernetics B, vol. 35, no. 1, pp. 72–88, 2005.
[20] M. S. Ying, “Automata theory based on quantum logic. I,”
International Journal of Theoretical Physics, vol. 39, no. 4, pp.
985–995, 2000.
[21] M. S. Ying, “Automata theory based on quantum logic. II,”
International Journal of Theoretical Physics, vol. 39, no. 11, pp.
2545–2557, 2000.
[22] M. S. Ying, “A theory of computation based on quantum logic.
I,” Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 344, no. 2-3, pp. 134–207,
2005.
[23] M. S. Ying, “Quantum logic and automata theory,” in Handbook
of Quantum Logic and Quantum Structures, K. Engesser, D.
M. Gabbay, and D. Lehmann, Eds., pp. 619–754, Elsevier,
Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2007.
[24] C. Moore and J. P. Crutchfield, “Quantum automata and
quantum grammars,” Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 237, no.
1-2, pp. 275–306, 2000.
[25] W. Cheng and J. Wang, “Grammar theory based on quantum
logic,” International Journal of Theoretical Physics, vol. 42, no. 8,
pp. 1677–1691, 2003.
[26] D. W. Qiu, “Automata theory based on quantum logic: some
characterizations,” Information and Computation, vol. 190, no.
2, pp. 179–195, 2004.
Journal of Applied Mathematics
[27] D. W. Qiu, “Notes on automata theory based on quantum logic,”
Science in China, vol. 50, no. 2, pp. 154–169, 2007.
[28] M. S. Ying, “Fuzzifying topology based on complete residuated
lattice-valued logic. I,” Fuzzy Sets and Systems, vol. 56, no. 3, pp.
337–373, 1993.
[29] D. W. Qiu, “Automata theory based on complete residuated
lattice-valued logic,” Science in China, vol. 44, no. 6, pp. 419–
429, 2001.
[30] D. W. Qiu, “Automata theory based on complete residuated
lattice-valued logic. II,” Science in China, vol. 45, no. 6, pp. 442–
452, 2002.
[31] D. W. Qiu, “Pumping lemma in automata theory based on
complete residuated lattice-valued logic: a note,” Fuzzy Sets and
Systems, vol. 157, no. 15, pp. 2128–2138, 2006.
[32] Y. M. Li and W. Pedrycz, “Fuzzy finite automata and fuzzy
regular expressions with membership values in lattice-ordered
monoids,” Fuzzy Sets and Systems, vol. 156, no. 1, pp. 68–92,
2005.
[33] Y. M. Li, “Finite automata theory with membership values in
lattices,” Information Sciences, vol. 181, no. 5, pp. 1003–1017, 2011.
[34] J. Jin and Q. Li, “Fuzzy grammar theory based on lattices,” Soft
Computing, vol. 16, no. 8, pp. 1415–1426, 2012.
[35] H. Y. Xing, “Fuzzy pushdown automata,” Fuzzy Sets and
Systems, vol. 158, no. 13, pp. 1437–1449, 2007.
[36] H. Y. Xing, D. W. Qiu, and F. C. Liu, “Automata theory based on
complete residuated lattice-valued logic: pushdown automata,”
Fuzzy Sets and Systems, vol. 160, no. 8, pp. 1125–1140, 2009.
[37] H. Y. Xing and D. W. Qiu, “Pumping lemma in context-free
grammar theory based on complete residuated lattice-valued
logic,” Fuzzy Sets and Systems, vol. 160, no. 8, pp. 1141–1151, 2009.
[38] Y. B. Jun, “Intuitionistic fuzzy finite state machines,” Journal of
Applied Mathematics & Computing, vol. 17, no. 1-2, pp. 109–120,
2005.
[39] Y. B. Jun, “Intuitionistic fuzzy finite switchboard state
machines,” Journal of Applied Mathematics & Computing, vol.
20, no. 1-2, pp. 315–325, 2006.
[40] X. W. Zhang and Y. M. Li, “Intuitionistic fuzzy recognizers and
intuitionistic fuzzy finite automata,” Soft Computing, vol. 13, no.
6, pp. 611–616, 2009.
[41] T. Y. Chen, H. P. Wang, and J. C. Wang, “Fuzzy automata based
on Atanassov fuzzy sets and applications on consumers’ advertising involvement,” African Journal of Business Management,
vol. 6, no. 3, pp. 865–880, 2012.
Advances in
Operations Research
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Advances in
Decision Sciences
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Mathematical Problems
in Engineering
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Journal of
Algebra
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Probability and Statistics
Volume 2014
The Scientific
World Journal
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
International Journal of
Differential Equations
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Volume 2014
Submit your manuscripts at
http://www.hindawi.com
International Journal of
Advances in
Combinatorics
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Mathematical Physics
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Journal of
Complex Analysis
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
International
Journal of
Mathematics and
Mathematical
Sciences
Journal of
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Stochastic Analysis
Abstract and
Applied Analysis
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
International Journal of
Mathematics
Volume 2014
Volume 2014
Discrete Dynamics in
Nature and Society
Volume 2014
Volume 2014
Journal of
Journal of
Discrete Mathematics
Journal of
Volume 2014
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Applied Mathematics
Journal of
Function Spaces
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Optimization
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Hindawi Publishing Corporation
http://www.hindawi.com
Volume 2014
Download