Reviews/Comptes rendus Self-Employed Workers Organize: Law, Policy and Unions by Cynthia J. Cranford, Judy Fudge, Eric Tucker and Leah F. Volko. McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2005. Traditionally, self-employment has been synonymous with individual entrepreneurship and has resided outside the ambit of labour law and collective representation. There is, however, another class of self-employed worker that often shares more in common with an employee than entrepreneur. These are individuals who differ dramatically from the ideal selfemployed type, since they do not employ anyone else but themselves, own very little in the way of capital, offer their labour exclusively to a single contracting party, and exercise little control over their own production. In what sense can someone like this, lying between the status of an employee and entrepreneur, be defined appropriately? Do these small-scale selfemployed workers require special labour protection? If so, what should it look like? If not, how does one facilitate the collective organization of these workers, while at the same time preventing their vulnerability to other techniques for restructuring the employment relationship (i.e., contracting out)? These are the central questions of Self-Employed Workers Organize: Law, Policy and Unions, and it is no accident that Cynthia Cranford, Judy Fudge, Eric Tucker and Leah Volko are the ones doing the asking. All four bring a wealth of experience and first-hand knowledge of the difficulties facing workers in what has come to be known as the “precarious employment sector.” This is a book that the authors have clearly been burning to write. Just pages in, we are told that “in some small way, this book contributes to self-employed workers efforts to better their conditions by telling the stories of their struggles.” What follows is part case study — four case study chapters written by each of the authors — and part general analysis. In the co-written introduction, the authors bring us face to face with four groups of workers — newspaper deliverers, rural route mail 339 couriers, personal care givers, and professional editors. Despite outward differences in their work and social status, all four are described as sharing two important characteristics: their employment relations diverge from the norm that has served as the lynchpin of Canadian labour law throughout the postwar period (i.e., the full-time permanent employee) and each of these groups has tried to use the law to obtain collective bargaining rights, but in each instance, their self-employed status was a contentious legal issue. The two synthesis chapters that bookend this study nicely situate the specific cases in the broader context of self-employment work; illustrating the problems of distinguishing between employees and the self-employed for the purposes of labour protection. The authors are nevertheless unequivocal when it comes to stating their conclusions. Despite the difficulties noted above, workers caught in between the world of paid work and entrepreneurship should have access to collective representation. The authors readily admit, however, that this is not the only solution for workers lying in the grey zone between employee and entrepreneur. Though “there are pressing sociological, normative and policy reasons for extending bargaining rights to these groups of workers” the authors maintain that there is no single workplace representation model that meets the needs of all the self-employed workers highlighted in the book. So, rather than offering a neatly packaged legislative solution, the book emphasizes the “plurality of representational forms and mechanisms” needed for achieving the protections granted to workers in similar situations. For some, the case-study route taken to arrive at these conclusions may be akin to a maddeningly difficult slalom run. Economists would no doubt like to sink their teeth into the introductory and concluding chapters, where the synthesis and policy recommendations reside. But once readers start in on the first of the case studies, Eric Tucker’s fascinating study of Toronto Star newspaper carriers, they will no doubt be hooked. The authors should be CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, VOL . XXXII, NO . 3 2006 340 Reviews/Comptes rendus commended for maintaining the individual interest of each of their respective cases, while at the same time enforcing a common structure, in which they describe the socio-economic context of the workers in question, the history collective representation at work, the legal framework and barriers that they have confronted in trying to organize collectively. As someone interested in labour markets but with no formal legal background, this format proved invaluable. There are, of course, perils in using detailed case studies as the lynchpin for a book, especially those cases that are based on informant interviews and detailed legal analyses of decisions — namely, that the non-specialist reader often does not care about the material as much as the authors do. This problem does not afflict the book as a whole, but when it does, it can be rough going. For example, when Tucker writes about the British Columbia carriers’ drive to organize, he lists all ten factors that the labour board raised as relevant to the determination of the carriers’ employment status. This one unbroken paragraph takes up an entire page. For non-experts, this listing would be no more illuminating here than it would be in context. And this is in the first chapter, an early place to potentially lose readers. Happily, as each of the cases gathers its own steam, all four authors take full control of the material. Fudge’s analysis, in chapter 2, of rural mail carriers, is typically poignant and illuminating. Who would have thought that prior to 2004, nearly 6,000 rural mail couriers used their own vehicles instead of Canada Post trucks to deliver mail and if injured were not entitled to compensation benefits. In the end they were organized, but Fudge is under no illusions that this is THE model for other groups to follow: “Rural route mail workers are … fortunate: they work for a single corporation that has a highly CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE organised workforce [and] the lion’s share are represented by a militant union committed to organising all the workers in the sector.” Such conditions are clearly not present within the personal-care sector, the subject of Cranford’s chapter 3 study. The chapter ends with three regulatory scenarios that could emerge as a means of protecting personal-care workers. No simple solutions are to be found here. The final case in chapter 4, that of freelance editors, was perhaps the most interesting, if only because as an author, the editor’s work is often the most crucial function of the book publishing business (this is why authors still use publishers rather than the Internet to publish their work). Yet, increasingly it seems, publishers subcontract the work to a host of freelance editors, where work is often sporadic and low paid. It is often said that passion is the enemy of precision. Yet, in this instance, the authors have generated a precisely worded and passionately argued case for the need to look at the world of self-employment as it is — complex and multi-layered but with the possibility of improvement for those workers most weakened by the particularities of their employment situation and the vagaries of ill-equipped legal protection. This is an informative and valuable book for researchers and policymakers alike. So in the spirit of the non-standard work covered in this volume, I would advise prospective readers of SelfEmployed Workers Organize to approach it unconventionally, beginning with either the introduction or conclusion, then skipping to any of the cases that seem personally of most interest and then starting in earnest from there. RAFAEL GOMEZ, Glendon College, York University and Institute of Management, London School of Economics POLITIQUES , VOL . XXXII , NO. 3 2006 Reviews/Comptes rendus The Companies We Keep: Corporate Governance for a Democratic Society by Allan C. Hutchinson. Irwin Law Inc., 2005. “The inherent vice of capitalism is the unequal sharing of blessings; the inherent virtue of socialism is the equal sharing of misery.” Winston Churchill Much like a handyman who sees a crack in the plaster and decides it is time to tear down the house, Allan Hutchinson observes recent corporate scandals and decides that we are in dire need of a new model for the corporation. It is the maintained thesis of the text that individual acts of turpitude are merely a symptom of the current conception of corporations as legal entities engaged in the pursuit of maximizing the wealth of shareholders. This conception not only leads to malfeasance on the part of corporate officers, but also harms society in general. Hutchinson leads with scandals to get our attention but then quickly tells us not to look too long upon them as the true problems are structural and the damage corporations do stems from their very nature, is not isolated to shareholders, and is societal in scope. Therefore, changes to corporate governance must examine the activities and the very existence of corporations in an “encompassing social and political context.” The central tenet of the book is that the concentration of power in corporations inhibits the progress of democracy. The terms democracy, democratic well-being, democratic society, and other variants on this theme are scattered throughout the book. What is less clear is the meaning of the word as employed by Hutchinson. We are asked to consider democracy as “appreciated in its most noble sense.” There are several clues as to what this means. Democratic advancement is found in making “the corporation work in the broader public interest and for the greater good of society.” We are told that democracy demands that all Canadians “share in the 341 fortunes and misfortunes of the community.” Democracy demands a reduction in the gap between the governed and their governors. Hutchinson returns to the term “gap” and with deft legerdemain switches democratic advancement to reducing gaps in living standards and wealth. One feels lost in Wonderland as democracy means what the author chooses it to mean. Hutchinson graciously allows that corporations are not the root of all evil. Reading the text though might lead a reader to conclude that while not all, certainly most evil can be laid at the feet of corporations. Hutchinson seeks to harness the productive capacity of corporations while reigning in what he sees as “regressive effects.” One step on this path is to “realize” corporations are not the private property of shareholders. This is akin to harnessing your neighbour’s horse after it’s been fed. It is also interesting that the focus is on large corporations. You would not want to hitch your wagon to a fledgling company lest you share more misfortune than fortune. In the distinction between large and small corporations we see that it is not the corporate form that is objectionable, but rather the assets of successful corporations that are desirable. The ability of the state to direct the resources of corporations rests on the premise that corporations are creatures of the state and rely on the state for their existence and the rule of law that protects their markets. The same can be said for other state sanctioned economic actors: doctors, lawyers, dentists, taxi operators, and barbers. Given the coercive power of the state, all economic actors benefit from the rule of law and therefore the state has the right to direct all economic output. If they come first for the corporations, who will speak? It is with a gnostic’s certainty of divine revelation that Hutchinson plants guideposts for the New Model Corporation. Outright confiscation of productive resources is to be avoided because absent an entrepreneurial class output falls off. Rather, this class and the contributors of capital need to be har- CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, VOL . XXXII, NO . 3 2006 342 Reviews/Comptes rendus nessed. The sharing rule that will keep them productive is nowhere mentioned. However, Hutchinson thinks that allowing stakeholders (a broadly-defined group of actors whose lives are affected by the corporation to some degree) board representation will be one step in ensuring corporations act to further society’s well-being. Individuals have utility functions and homogeneous groups may have highly correlated utility functions. Society does not have a utility function and a board trying to represent society’s desires will resemble Babel. Hutchinson envisions a board with members representing the shareholders, workers, and the public. Setting aside the overt taking of shareholder rights, the concept of public constituency directors is interesting. A corporate governance commission whose provenance is unclear will maintain lists of acceptable public constituency directors. This clerisy of wellmeaning individuals will let us know what is good for us. CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE Hutchinson’s justification for societal representation in the oversight of corporations rests on the facts that corporations are large, ubiquitous, and creatures of the state. His prescriptions for wealth redistribution and worker empowerment emanate from the waste heap of failed collectivism. His faith in government directives and the kindness of strangers is touching, but is hardly a sound basis for public policy. I began with a quote from Winston Churchill. Let me end by paraphrasing him. Capitalism is the worst way to run an economy except all those other methods that have been tried from time to time. MARK R. HUSON, Pocklington Professor of Private Enterprise, University of Alberta School of Business POLITIQUES , VOL . XXXII , NO. 3 2006 Reviews/Comptes rendus Governing with the Charter: Legislative and Judicial Activism and Framers’ Intent James B. Kelly. Vancouver: UBC Press, 2005. Wow! What a breath of fresh academic air! Canadians, once informed by this truly remarkable study, will never be able to view their 1982 Charter of Rights and Freedoms the same way. Finally, an intellectually rigorous, superbly comprehensive, and lucidly written analysis of the Cabinet’s, the Department of Justice’s, the Supreme Court’s, and Parliament’s coordinated governance concerning all Charter rights. Kelly’s stupendously revisionist Governing with the Charter calls into question the very raison d’être for Canada’s ongoing, misleading, and terribly ruinous civil war between the Calgary-based Charterphobes and the largely central Canadian Charterphiles. Twenty-five years after the 1982 Charter, a great many of Canada’s political leaders, academics, and journalists still do not understand the full scope of the political and constitutional “revolution” that is Trudeau’s primary legacy (Behiels 2003). Section 52 of the Charter stipulates that the “Constitution of Canada is the supreme law of Canada.” The Charter is the very heart of the people’s dimension of our constitution. At all times, it should function seamlessly under the coordinated guardianship of the executive, legislative, and judicial branches of governance. It is time to lay to rest the hoary myth of parliamentary supremacy as well as the newly-propagated myth of judicial supremacy, both of which are the stock-in-trade of the Charterphobes. Judicial review has always been at the very centre of Canadian federal governance as Ottawa, the provinces, and corporate Canada pursued their respective interests and interpretations of the British North America Act, 1867. Our misconstrued Charter wars and misguided attacks on Canada’s Supreme Court are not new. Ross Lambertson’s remarkable Repression and Resistance: Canadian Human Rights Activists, 1930– 1968 and Christopher MacLennan’s tightly crafted Toward the Charter: Canadians and the Demand for a National Bill of Rights, 1929–1960 analyze the 343 largely unsuccessful struggles of ordinary working men and women for a meaningful application of their limited British-Canadian civil liberties. Their myriad civil libertarian and human rights organizations failed to achieve their goal, an entrenched Charter of Rights and Freedoms. Why? No doubt partly because the movement was weak and divided. But the central explanation resides in the Charterphobic character of Canada’s British-Canadian political, social, economic, and legal élites who controlled our governance system at all levels until the 1960s. Prime Minister Diefenbaker’s precisely choreographed statutory 1960 Bill of Rights was never intended to usher in a genuine civil and human rights revolution. Its British-Canadian framers’ focus was exclusively on protecting largely theoretical British civil liberties by curtailing executive tyranny; that is, the federal Cabinet, in the hopes of restoring and embellishing the mythic golden-age of parliamentary supremacy. Diefenbaker ensured that his Bill of Rights did not mandate the Supreme Court to carry out substantive judicial review of existing laws. Nor could it invalidate new federal laws if Parliament sent the message that it clearly intended its legislation to override the very narrow traditional civil liberties outlined in his Bill. Indeed, one can argue that Diefenbaker’s goal was to prevent the far more comprehensive conception of human rights, as expressed in the American and French designed 1948 United Nations Declaration of Human Rights, from taking root in Canada’s “conservative” political and judicial cultures and parliamentary system. Diefenbaker’s ill-conceived attempt to stem the rising tide of the human rights movement was a dramatic failure. Why and how did an increasing majority of Canadians from all regions, social classes, and religious and ethnic backgrounds come together during a concerted twenty-year campaign to achieve a genuine rights revolution culminating in an entrenched Charter of Rights and Freedoms? Kelly’s study, unlike those of Lambertson and MacLennan, does not attempt to provide a comprehensive analysis of the rights revolution from the bottom up. This CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, VOL . XXXII, NO . 3 2006 344 Reviews/Comptes rendus task is left for other Charter scholars to undertake. Vaguely aware of emergent human rights movement, Kelly considers it of secondary importance. This is unfortunate because he weakens his own thesis. Widespread social changes strengthened immeasurably the scope and depth of Canada’s human rights movement and this process had a profound impact on a small but significant minority of Canada’s emerging social, political, and legal élites who aided and abetted this movement. Philip Girard’s groundbreaking Bora Laskin: Bringing Law to Life (2005) bears witness to this important phenomenon. Kelly emphatically rejects the court-centred approach that has dominated the debate. He rightly shifts the overly narrow and highly misleading focus of the overly polemical academic and public debates from the Supreme Court to all the political actors responsible for framing and then implementing the Charter. The core theme of Governing with the Charter centres on deciphering and analyzing the comprehensive legislative activism — primarily executive and bureaucratic — that was generated to serve as a counterweight to the clearly intended and anticipated judicial activism inherent in the Charter, the people’s package of the Constitution Act, 1982. Kelly analyzes the evolving nature of the intent of the Charter’s central framers, Trudeau’s Cabinet and senior Justice and PCO mandarins, and the MPs and Senators on the Special Joint Committee. Hounded constantly by the anti-Charter premiers since the early 1970s, the framers began with a weak Charter but then radicalized the document quite dramatically once Trudeau gained the upper hand in his political and judicial struggles with the premiers. Kelly does not consider the anti-Charter premiers and their coterie of supporters as framers. From the outset, their intent, he demonstrates, was to derail by every political and judicial means possible a charter they considered “revolutionary,” a veritable threat to parliamentary supremacy — in reality executive supremacy — and Canadian federalism. The framers radicalized the Charter in two steps. First, they assiduously orchestrated the televised CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE proceedings of the Special Joint Committee to coordinate support from the entire Canadian human rights community, including the radicalized and highly organized women’s and Aboriginal movements. Second, Trudeau effectively exploited the Supreme Court’s landmark 1981 Patriation decision which declared the Canada Bill legal and terminated the premier’s “historical” veto over the amendment and Canadianization of the British North America Act, 1867. His hand strengthened, Trudeau accepted the recalcitrant premiers’, namely Lougheed’s, 7/50 amending formula in exchange for the “revolutionizing” Charter, albeit one with a time-limited notwithstanding clause applying to sections 2 and 7 to 15. The deed was done! Having established the bone fides of the intended activist Charter — a flexible instrument that summons the Supreme Court to move well past its “frozen rights” philosophy, Kelly brilliantly analyzes all of the Supreme Court’s numerous Charter decisions — two-thirds of the total between 1982–2003 — pertaining to the controversial area of legal rights which had fuelled the consolidation of the human rights movement in the 1960s and 1970s. He demonstrates convincingly that the Supreme Court, in checking the discretionary conduct of the police by infusing the crime control model with important elements of due process, “has deepened constitutional supremacy because it has required those exercising power on behalf of the state to do so in a manner consistent with the Charter” (p. 108). Stirred but not shaken, this balanced approach to policing legal rights strengthened dramatically the democratic bond between Canadian citizens and their state. How was this necessary evolution in the interpretation and implementation of rights accomplished so smoothly? Kelly’s groundbreaking chapter, “Guardians of the Constitution” reveals the emergence of a highly orchestrated model of coordinated constitutionalism whereby all of Canada’s political actors, institutions and agencies — with Cabinet and the Department of Justice at the core — responded in a tight partnership to the imperatives of Canada’s POLITIQUES , VOL . XXXII , NO. 3 2006 Reviews/Comptes rendus intended “activist” Charter. Of 175 statutes reviewed by the Supreme Court between 1982–2003, only 64 were invalidated, the vast majority pre-dated the Charter and were manifestly discriminatory. The Supreme Court, as one of three central guardians of the constitution, had no option but to declare a range of statutes, partly or entirely, unconstitutional. It is largely these early decisions that the court-centred Charterphobes use as evidence of excessive and unwarranted judicial activism by a Supreme Court intent on imposing its policy preferences. Kelly’s in-depth analysis of all the Court’s Charter decisions virtually obliterates all the Charter critics’ arguments. The Supreme Court’s approach to post-1982 statutes, Kelly points out, is very nuanced and imaginative, especially so since 1993. First, the Supreme Court spelt out a cogent “least drastic means” test for section 1, the brilliantly crafted reasonable limits clause, forcing lower courts and all legislators to think twice before using section 1 to circumvent the Charter. Two, the Supreme Court has resorted to suspended decisions in dealing with unconstitutional legislation, thereby enjoining executives and legislators to reconsider and amend their laws to conform to the imperatives of the Charter. In short, coordinate constitutionalism in action spurred on by a court sensitive to its and the other actors’ guardianship responsibilities. Kelly tackles head on the Charter critics, led by Québécois nationalists and secessionists, allegation that Trudeau’s Charter was designed primarily as an instrument of centralization for imposing national standards on the provinces. Consequently, the Charter, they contend, is intrinsically and indubitably destructive of Canadian federalism. “Poppycock,” retorts Kelly. All the of the empirical evidence proves that Canada’s Supreme Court sees itself as the guardian of democracy, federalism, and the Charter. In its role as umpire of Canadian federalism, the Court’s interpretation of the Charter demonstrates a comprehensive respect for provincial autonomy, using the Constitution Act as a shield to the point of embracing a limited degree of provincial asymmetry. Once provincial cabinets and their Departments 345 of Justice instituted Charter-vetted practices, since 1990 the Supreme Court has invalidated very few provincial statutes involving rights matters. Governing with the Charter is initiated by provincial cabinets and the courts react, rather than vice versa as claimed by the Charter critics. In his highly original and revealing final chapter, Kelly analyzes why and how governing with the Charter effectively begins with the legislative activism, federal and provincial, operating in a rights culture environment. Ottawa took the lead in this development and it is slowly permeating provincial cabinets but not their legislatures. At the centre of this legislative activism since 1990 are the federal Cabinet, the Department of Justice, and its branches in every line department, all of which have embraced fully their constitutional guardianship roles in the defence and the promotion of Charter rights by participating in a novel and complex Charter-vetting process for all pertinent legislation. Kelly accepts the critics’ argument that there is a crucial democratic deficit but this is not the Supreme Court’s fault. The virtual dominance from the outset of the Charter-vetting process by the federal Cabinet and the Department of Justice has prevented Parliament from playing its constitutionally mandated guardianship role vis-à-vis the Charter. Kelly makes a very convincing case that the Charter review process should be initiated by Parliament, that is, by well-informed, institutionalized committees of the House of Commons and the Senate. Kelly maintains somewhat optimistically that this process will ensure that Canada’s rights culture permeates in a comprehensive manner all of Parliament. This coordinated constitutionalism will reduce dramatically the need for the Supreme Court to suspend or invalidate Charter-sensitive legislation. Given the nature of Canadian society, it is not likely that there will ever be unanimity on the need to embrace uncritically a comprehensive rights culture. Perhaps the best that can be expected is that most Canadians come to understand the strengths and weaknesses of their “activist” Charter as well as the respective roles of all of the political CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, VOL . XXXII, NO . 3 2006 346 Reviews/Comptes rendus actors in the executives, the bureaucracies, the legislators, and the courts, in the effective governance with the Charter under a parliamentary regime of constitutional supremacy. Kelly’s magnificent Governing with the Charter is, by far, the first and ideal place to begin that learning process. REFERENCE Behiels, M.D. 2003. “Pierre Elliott Trudeau’s Legacy: The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,” in The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: Reflections on the Charter after Twenty Years, ed. J.E. Magnet et al. Toronto: LexisNexis Butterworths. MICHAEL D. BEHIELS, Professor of Canadian History, University of Ottawa CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES , VOL . XXXII , NO. 3 2006 Reviews/Comptes rendus It Takes a Candidate: Why Women Don’t Run for Office by Jennifer L. Lawless and Richard L. Fox. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005. The question of why women continue to be significantly underrepresented in representative political institutions is one that has been the focus of much research in the United States and Canada. The two countries rank 68th and 44th respectively amongst the 188 ranked on the Inter-Parliamentary Union’s Women in National Parliaments 1 list and behind a mix of countries that includes Rwanda (1st), Denmark (6th), Iraq (27th) and Australia (30th). The absence of formal barriers restricting women’s political participation and positive changes in women’s employment, income, and educational achievements have proven insufficient for significantly increasing the number of women who choose to contest and win elections at various levels of government. Research focused on structural barriers — the single member plurality system, for example — and situational factors — the gender gap in income and pink-collar employment ghettos — has provided only an incomplete understanding of why women continue to be significantly underrepresented. But the research conducted by Jennifer Lawless and Richard Fox in the United States and reported on in the book, It Takes a Candidate: Why Women Don’t Run for Office, goes some distance toward uncovering the missing pieces of this puzzle by focusing the lens on the concept of political ambition and on why women make up a significantly smaller share of those nominated by political parties to contest elections. In their words, “this book is about political ambition: why men have it, and why women don’t” (p. 4). While political ambition plays a larger role in determining who gets nominated in the more candidatecentred electoral process in the US, it nevertheless provides insight into Canadian electoral outcomes. The strength of the book stems in part from the research strategy adopted by the authors. Much of existing research in this area consists of surveys of 347 women and men who have run for office or of those who have been elected; while these provide important insight into who decides to contest elections and the reasons behind their decisions, they tell us little about differences between the women and men who consider but ultimately decide against running for office. Lawless and Fox instead conduct a national survey of and subsequent interviews with a stratified sample of women and men selected from the four professions from which political candidates are normally drawn: lawyer, business leader, educator, and political activist.2 By doing so they effectively limit gender differences in objective qualifications and experience, as well as political interest among the respondents, factors that play a role in shaping political ambition and perceived electoral potential. Not surprisingly, the authors find that women’s greater responsibility for household tasks and childcare play a role in their decreased willingness to consider running for office. They also find that as children, male respondents were more likely to discuss politics and to be encouraged to run for office by their parents. The latter is found to continue into adulthood, with women receiving less encouragement from family and friends. Most interestingly perhaps, the authors identify the existence of a “gendered psyche” in political ambition that develops in part through traditional gender role socialization. Women reveal a tendency to overestimate the set of qualifications necessary for running for office and they combine this with a tendency to underestimate the qualifications that they themselves possess. The result is that women are significantly less willing to consider running for office and to actually throw their hats in the ring. In short, they possess less political ambition. This finding is doubly important because self-assessments of qualifications are found to play a larger role in shaping women’s standing for office calculus than men’s. Direct recruitment of candidates by political parties could help to offset the gendered impact of this CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE POLITIQUES, VOL . XXXII, NO . 3 2006 348 Reviews/Comptes rendus tendency, but their findings suggest that a “masculinized ethos” within political parties results in men being considered and recruited as potential nominees and candidates far more often than women, even when women possess similar or even stronger qualifications for the position. And again this result is doubly important because recruitment plays a larger role in shaping women’s decisions to run than men. As such, efforts undertaken by political parties to recruit women are crucial for increasing their levels of representation at both the nomination and candidate stages of elections. The implications for these findings are clear; in the absence of strong incentives for political parties to increase the number of women that they nominate to contest seats, or of an electoral system that simplifies the adoption of gender quotas and targets, women’s political underrepresentation is unlikely to be mitigated anytime soon. Traditional gender role socialization and CANADIAN PUBLIC POLICY – ANALYSE DE the actions of political parties continue to exert a powerful force in driving home the message that politics “is a man’s world,” a message strong enough to ensure that the best and brightest American (and one could easily argue, Canadian) women remain largely absent from representative political institutions. NOTES 1 This ranking refers to the situation as of 30 April 2006. See the Inter-Parliamentary Union, Women in National Parliaments, found at www.ipu.org/wmn-e/classif.htm. 2 The Citizen Political Ambition Survey consisted of a standard mail survey conducted between July 2001 and August 2002 with 3,614 women and men, and subsequent follow-up phone interviews in July and August of 2003 with 100 of the men and 100 of the women who completed the original mail survey. BRENDA O’NEILL, Department of Political Science, University of Calgary POLITIQUES , VOL . XXXII , NO. 3 2006