F.A. Hayek: the radical economist Jack Birner University of Trento

advertisement
F.A. Hayek: the radical economist
Jack Birner
University of Trento
Konrad Lorenz Institute for Cognition and Evolution
Abstract
If anything like a change in direction can be distinguished in the development of the work of
Friedrich August von Hayek, it does not lie in his supposed abandoning of the idea of equilibrium
(which is based on a mistaken interpretation of his work). It is rather the transition of a radically
systematic approach to problems and the elaboration of their solution that is characterized by a high
level of analytic sophistication to a more associative approach. Examples of the former are Hayek’s
theory of mind and his monetary, business cycle and capital theories; his theory of evolution and
social and political philosophy are examples of the latter.
Hayek’s economics constitutes a research programme. One of the factors that influenced its further
development was Sraffa’s criticism of Hayek’s Prices and Production. In reply to this, Hayek
developed his highly sophisticated capital theory and his ideas on neutral money and the
international monetary order. I intend to show that the development of Hayek’s economic research
programme can only be understood if one takes into account his radically systematic and analytical
approach.
Research programmes
The work of both Hayek and Popper have the characteristics of research programmes. I mean by
this that the development of their work is guided by a series of systematic successive attempts to
solve particular problems. That is particularly clear in the case of Hayek. Whenever Hayek starts
working on a problem, he always gives an extensive historical account of the problem and the
solutions that have been proposed for solving it (this, by the way, has turned Hayek into a
formidable historian of ideas). He sketches the outlines of the theory that according to him should
be capable of solving the problem (“necessary solution” in figure 1) – including the methodological
constraints it has to satisfy. He analyzes the strengths and weaknesses of previous theories. This
preliminary analysis allows Hayek to identify the gaps between the theory of the future and the
useful elements of theories of the past that remain to be filled. Filling these gaps constitutes
Hayek’s research agenda.
Hayek’s systematic procedure
Theories of the past
problem
Hayek’s
Research
agenda
Necessary solution,
subject to desired
methodological principles
Fig. 1 Hayek’s systematic procedure
Hayek’s business cycle theory provides an excellent illustration of this procedure. This will be
shown in the following paragraphs.
Hayek’s early economics: utility theory and imputation
In 1923-4 Hayek spent a year and a half in the United States. During his stay he studied the latest
statistical research on business cycles and wrote a draft for a PhD thesis (that was never
submitted).1 After his return to Austria he published a series of articles in which he developed his
theory of the business cycle. I have described elsewhere2 how he arrived at this theory, and how he
developed it further, so I will here give a summary. In “Bemerkungen zum Zurechnungsproblem”
of 1926, he first gives a historical analysis of the different versions of utility theory and their
solutions to the problem of the determination of the value of factors of production or production
goods. According to Hayek, the valuation of production goods and consumer goods both involve
the imputation problem, i.e., how to attribute value (and costs) to the goods that have gone into the
making of a particular commodity. Hayek says that solving this problem is crucial because it would
allow to unify the explanation of prices in terms of subjective values with the explanation of income
distribution with the help of subjective-value theory. This logically precedes the explanation of
exchange.
Hayek thinks Friedrich von Wieser was the first to see this clearly, even though he failed to solve
the problem. That is because he derives the values of production goods from the values of consumer
goods without taking into account that these can only be determined if we know the actually
employed combinations of production goods.
“If, like Wieser, we assume as our basis that value can be calculated numerically - this can
hardly be avoided if the problem is to be solved - then even a state of maximum utility
cannot be calculated without the distribution to the factors of production of the level of
utility realized by the products. It follows that the condition of maximum utility cannot be
calculated without prior solution of the problem of imputation” (McCloughry 1984: 52).
In the next paragraph, Hayek continues his discussion with what is in effect a thorough application
of the idea of opportunity costs:
“Any one-sided derivation of the value of producer goods from that of the product
necessarily comes to grief on the fact that the value of the product cannot be ascertained
without taking account of the resistance to the expansion of production to its physically
possible limit, a resistance which differs for each individual factor used in the production
of the value of the final goods. This restriction depends on the value which is to be
imputed to the factor in question in its alternative use, in so far as it can be employed
elsewhere, a proviso which is applicable in the majority of cases.” (McCloughry 1984:
52].
The value of products and of production goods cannot be obtained from the one independently from
the other, as “[n]either producer goods nor products exhibit independently both the sets of data
which are necessary for the determination of value. Rather, the one element, the utility level
attained, makes its appearance only in the products, while the second element, the limit to the
available supply, is determined “absolutely” only for producer goods” (McCloughry 1984: 52-3)
The recognition of this mutual dependence has transformed the problem into a form that allows of a
solution:
1
2
The draft contains the first contours of his research programme in economics. Cp. Birner 2000 or 1997.
In Birner 2000 and Birner 1997.
“The problem is not the derivation of the value of producer goods, assuming a given value
of the product. Rather, it is the influence which the relative scarcity of a producer good
exerts on the admissible level of expansion of each process of production, assuming given
alternatives of employment and given complementary goods. The problem of imputation
becomes identical with the question of how, on the assumption of given quantities of
producer goods and given scales of needs and wants, the producer goods available are to be
allocated among the different branches of production. Any answer to this question, and thus
any solution to the problem of imputation, has therefore to take into account the totality of
all the complementary goods utilized in an economic system and all the needs and wants
which their products serve to satisfy.” (McCloughry 1984: 53, my emphasis)
What Hayek proposes is a general economic equilibrium theory. Consistent with this is the fact that
he also takes over from Wieser the endogeneity of national income: the composition and size of
income depends on the specific combinations of production factors. But he does not stop here. He
extends or generalizes general-equilibrium theory into an intertemporal and dynamic general
equilibrium theory. He does so with the objective of explaining the dynamic disequilibrium growth
that constitutes the business cycle. The result is "Das intertemporale Gleichgewichtssystem der
Preise und die Bewegungen des ’Geldwertes’" (Hayek 1928).3
In Hayek’s hands substitution and complementarity in the structure of production4 together with
time become the elements for unifying the theories of value and imputation. Hayek achieves this by
a consistent application of the principle of opportunity costs (as will be shown in more detail in the
next paragraph). This in summary is the economic-theoretical background for the further
development of Hayek’s research programme in economics.
The structure and development of Hayek’s research programme in economics
The instrument I will use for reconstructing Hayek’s economic research programme is the following
scheme of Popper’s.5
P1 →T1 → EE →P2, etc.
Theories (Ti) are formulated as solutions to problems (Pi). The adequacy of the solutions is
examined and leads to the elimination of errors (EE). This almost invariably gives rise to new
problems.6 Problems are always problems in the light or against the background of a particular set
of accepted theories: the background knowledge. In terms of the scheme above: P1 has arisen out of
an attempt to eliminate the errors from a previous theory, and so on. So, in order to understand a
research programme, we must identify the problem it addresses originally. In addition – and this is
something on which Popper is not explicit but which is evident in all of Hayek’s work – research
programmes are characterized by the methodological constraints that a solution to the problem must
satisfy. That gives us the following elements:
Problem situation:
3
- background knowledge
- problem to be solved
- methodological principles.
This and the contemporaneous article by Erik Lindahl were the first intertemporal general equilibrium theories in
economics.
4
For the modelling of which he borrows from Böhm-Bawerk.
5
Cp., for instance, Popper 1976, c. 29.
6
In most of what follows I will simplify the scheme to a sequence of problems and theories and omit explicit mention
of error elimination, as this would get us too deeply involved in technical details.
These instruments allow us to define a research programme and distinguish one research
programme from another. If we apply this toolbox to Hayek’s economics, we obtain the following
reconstruction. The global problem (or original problem situation) that defines the outlines of his
programme is how to explain fluctuations in the level of production and employment, a dynamic
disequilibrium phenomenon, by means of general equilibrium theory. General equilibrium theory is
part of the background knowledge. At the time Hayek started working on this, however, this theory
was static. Therefore, either the business cycle has to be modelled in a way that makes it amenable
to analysis in terms of static general equilibrium theory, or that theory has to be made dynamic.
From this global problem setting follow a number of more specific problems of a technical
economic nature.
An integral part of Hayek’s research programme in economics (as in all other domains that he dealt
with) is a methodological analysis. Geldtheorie und Konjunkturtheorie devotes an entire chapter to
methodology, and the first chapter of Prices and Production is explicitly methodological when it
explains the reasons for the stagnation in the development of business cycle theory: economists
have adopted the wrong method. He holds Irving Fisher responsible for the revival of the
mechanistic form of the quantity theory of money. This has led to “the present isolation of the
theory of money from the main body of general economic theory” (PP: 4), because of the use of
“different methods for the explanation of values as they are supposed to exist irrespective of any
influence of money, and for the explanation of that influence of money on prices (...)” (ibid.).
Economists make the methodological mistake that they
“try to establish direct causal connections between the total quantity of money, the
general level of all prices and, perhaps, also the total amount of production. For none of
these magnitudes as such ever exerts an influence on the decision of individuals; yet it is
on the assumption of a knowledge of the decisions of individuals that we owe whatever
understanding of economic phenomena that we possess; that the modern ’subjective’
theory has advanced beyond the classical school in its consistent use is probably its main
advantage over their teaching.” (PP: 4)
Instead of this, Hayek proposes methodological subjectivism and individualism:
“from the very nature of economic theory, averages can never form a link in its reasoning;
but to prove this contention would go far beyond the subject of these lectures. I shall here
confine myself to an attempt to show in a special field the differences between explanations
which do and explanations which do not have recourse to such concepts.” (PP, p. 5)
So, not only does Hayek sketch a research programme in economics, he also proposes a
methodological research programme.7 It is elaborated in “Economics and Knowledge”, “The Facts
of the Social Sciences, and the publications that were collected in The Counterrevolution of Science.
Hayek’s methodology comprises subjectivism, the principle that social science explanations must
take account of what individuals perceive. He also adopts methodological individualism, which is a
logical consequence of subjectivism. In the case of Hayek’s business cycle theory it takes the form
of applying marginal value theory (the “pure logic of choice” of the individual, or the principle of
opportunity costs) to hypothetical disaggregated investment processes. Hayek does this very
systematically in the Pure Theory of Capital. This is consistent with a third methodological
7
The impression that Prices and Production is an exercise in the application of a particular method, and not just an
economic theory, is reinforced by the remark: “it is the method of approach more than the details of the results which is
of importance in what follows.” (p. 31)
principle of Hayek’s research programme, theoretical unification. Finally, he uses the method of
decreasing abstraction. Hayek typically starts with the construction of a simplified or idealized
model. This is then “complicated” or “factualized” in a number of successive steps.8 This allows
him to separate the main causal elements and explanatory factors from secondary ones. It also
makes the exposition of the complex arguments clearer – provided the procedure is understood.9
Now we have all the elements to reconstruct Hayek’s research programme in economics. In his
work on the imputation problem Hayek came to the conclusion that only a general equilibrium
framework would be appropriate. So he chooses that as his background knowledge. The only
available general equilibrium theory, however, was the static general equilibrium theory of Walras
and Pareto. This immediately creates a follow-up problem: in order for a static theory of
equilibrium conditions to explain an inherently dynamic disequilibrium phenomenon such as the
business cycle, two problems have to be solved. One is the incorporation of time, the other the
introduction of a factor or mechanism that causes the disturbances of equilibrium. These two basic
or global problems give rise to two sub-programmes.10 One deals with the systematic reduction of
business cycle theory to marginal value theory, in accordance with methodological individualism
(MI). It amounts to a systematic application of the opportunity-cost concept to investment, capital
and production. The other branch concentrates on the causes of the disturbances that are inherent to
our economic system. Hayek explains these, in accordance with the methodological principle of
subjectivism, from the misperception of real scarcities by individuals that is caused by the fact that,
due to the money multiplier, changes in money prices do not necessarily reflect changes in real
relative prices.
8
This procedure is described in great detail in Birner 2001.
This is an important proviso. Some examples of the confusion to which the failure to recognize this leads are given in
Birner 1995.
10
Marina Colonna distinguishes two problems. Besides the “contradiction” between general equilibrium theory and
disequilibrium growth, she draws the attention to Hayek's opposition to the primitive quantity theory: according to
Hayek, a change in the money supply affects relative prices and the distribution of income. Cp. Colonna 1990: XXV.
Notice also that according to Colonna 1990: XXXV, & n. 51, MTTC still assumes the endogeneity of monetary
disturbances, whereas PP attributes them to the intervention of monetary authorities. While this does not change the
mechanism, it probably reflects Hayek's reaction to the events of 1929.
9
T0.0: static general equilibrium theory
P1.1: how is time to be incorporated?
P2.1: how do disequilibria arise?
T1.1: generalized, diachronic (or intertemporal)
general equilibrium theory
T2.2': theory about perceptions
P1.2: in reality there are hardly
any diachronic prices and futures markets
P2.3': what gives rise to wrong
perceptions?
T1.2: theory of the production structure
T2.3': monetary theory
P1.3: how is the production structure adapted?
T0.3: trade cycle theory
P1.4: how to reduce trade cycle
theory to marginal value theory
P2.4: the coordination
process
P2.4' theory of
socialist economics
T1.4-1.5 :subsequently more individualistic
versions of trade cycle theory
T2.4: contribution to the
debate on central planning
P1.6: various problems and criticisms
P2.5: how do markets coordinate knowledge?
T1.6: capital theory
P1.7: imputation problem: capital theory is only
in part based on marginal value theory
T1.7: capital theory in accordance
with MI: Pure Theory of Capital
P1.7: how to describe dynamics?
T1.7: theory of markets and competition
T 1.7': capital/cycle theory in monetary terms (Vol. II of PTC)
Fig. 2 Hayek’s research programme in economics
Hayek introduces time by a stroke of genius:11 he makes the planning individual the basis of his
analysis in Hayek 1928. Since the concept of a plan logically implies time (timeless planning is a
contradiction in terms), this turns static general equilibrium theory into an intertemporal general
equilibrium theory that may describe a growing, stationary or shrinking economy – so deal with
dynamics – according to the (time) preferences of individuals to increase their income, keep it
constant, or plan for its reduction. Hayek can now give a very straightforward definition of the
equilibrium of the individual; it is the situation in which an individual’s expectations are realized.
And the realization of expectations (or the consistency of the information that reaches the individual
with that on which his plan is based) means that the individual has no incentive to adapt his
behaviour.12 The model Hayek has in mind in “Das intertemporale Gleichgewichtssystem” of
192813 is as follows.
11
With characteristic modesty Hayek attributes the introduction of the planning individual to Hans Mayer and Leo
Schönfeld.
12
Hayek models a simple feed-back or control system.
13
And which is clearly present in “Economics and Knowledge”. The schedule is my reconstruction of this article.
INDIVIDUAL
(price)
signals
ENVIRONMENT
consists of all
other individuals.
(price)
signals
Signal perception &
information processing.
These, together with his
preferences, serve as inputs
for the individual’s
PLAN,
on which operates the
PURE LOGIC OF
CHOICE.
This produces planned
BEHAVIOUR,
which, when executed,
generates
SIGNALS
Fig. 3 Scheme of the basis of Hayek’s intertemporal general equilibrium theory of 1928:
The planning individual
In a subsequent step, in “Economics and Knowledge” of 1937, Hayek defines the equilibrium of the
economic system as the mutual compatibility of all individual plans. This is a straightforward
application and extension of the concept of the equilibrium of the individual as he had defined it in
his intertemporal general equilibrium theory of 1928.14 It shows the power and fruitfulness of the
concept of the planning individual.15
It takes little effort to apply Popper’s scheme of the sequence of problems, error elimination,
theories and further problems to Hayek’s economics. That is because long before Popper formulated
it, the organization of Hayek’s work is so exemplary of the scheme that one might be tempted to
conjecture that Popper was inspired by Hayek’s economics. But that would be philosophy fiction.16
Hayek’s research programme
I have shown the origin and structure of Hayek’s economic research programme as an illustration of
the systematic character of the whole of his work. Before he dealt with economics at all, he had
already applied the same systematic procedure to his theory of mind in 1920. And later, whenever
he starts working in a new domain of intellectual endeavour, he continues to plan and develop his
work in the same manner.- though never again with the same degree of analytical rigour that
characterizes his theory of mind and his economics. This gives rise to a series of “partial research
14
Hence, far from abandoning equilibrium analysis, he takes it a step forward. In 1988 Bruce Caldwell has introduced a
red herring by failing to recognize this, which in turn is due to his failure to see that Hayek’s economics constitutes a
research programme.
15
In the context of Hayek 1928 it is clear that the interaction between individuals is supposed to take place on markets.
Desai 1994 and Birner (for instance 1999, which argues that “Economics and Knowledge” is a forerunner of a network
model) point out that the argument in Hayek 1937 involves more than the interaction on markets, and that Hayek 1945
is a step backward from this more complex picture precisely because Hayek refers only to the price system as the
mechanism that resolves the coordination problem.
16
Nothing indicates that Popper had such detailed knowledge not only of Hayek’s economic theory but also of the way
it was developed. Hayek also states his methodology explicitly, something that is missing from Popper’s scheme.
programmes”. These have engendered subsequent partial research programmes. Notice that I am not
saying that Hayek, right from the beginning of his scientific career, had clear ideas of where he
wanted to arrive at; 17 Hayek never planned the whole of his work right from his first contribution to
science in 1920. Nevertheless, hindsight allows us to observe that it constitutes a “grand research
programme”:18 As the list of similarities between Hayek and Popper indicates, Hayek is much more
than an economist; his work also covers, roughly in chronological order, the philosophy of mind
and the psychology of perception (already referred to), the history of economics, the history of ideas,
the philosophy of social science, political and social philosophy, and the philosophy of law. In a
very simplified picture this may be shown as a sequence of research programmes, each of which
evolved out of previous ones.
1920
1923
1941
1952
The Road to
Serfdom
business
cycle
theory
1960
1973-9
social
philosophy
capital
theory
legal
philosophy
methodology
articles
(Counter
Revolution of
Science)
“Beiträge zu
einer
Theorie der EntWicklung des
Bewusstseins”
central
economic
planning
The Sensory
Order
political
philosophy
Fig. 4: Hayek’s grand research programme
A full reconstruction of Hayek’s entire research programme cannot be given here.19 I will limit
myself to sketching the development of some of his main ideas.
The development of Hayek’s research programme: from the criticism of central economic
planning to the rejection of socialism as a form of social organization
When we go beyond Hayek’s economics, we can see his research programme in action in all its
fruitfulness. Thus, RS is a generalization from his criticism on central economic planning as a
method of organizing the economy to his criticism of central planning as a principle for the
Hayek’s “Two types of mind” (1975) may be read as a description of his way of proceeding. Hayek distinguishes
between the "puzzlers" or "muddlers", who "know many things" on the one hand, and the "masters of the subject" or
"the memory type", who "know one big thing", on the other. He reckons himself to belong to the first type. The
distinction is practically identical to Isaiah Berlin’s in "The Hedgehog and the Fox" of the same year. Hayek’s muddler
corresponds to Berlin’s fox.
18
As I have called it in the Introduction to Birner & Van Zijp 1994. In the sequel I will drop the adjective.
19
Some of the transformations and generalizations that drive the development of Hayek’s work as a whole are described
in Birner 2006.
17
organization of society as a whole. And just as Hayek makes this transition from his economic
criticism to the philosophical criticism of socialism, in RS he already “announces” (as we can say
with the benefit of hindsight) his future work on the legal framework of a competitive economy:
Constitution of Liberty and Law, Legislation and Liberty: “The systematic study of the forms of
legal institutions which will make the competitive system work has been sadly neglected …” (RS:
28). In later years, Hayek rolls up his sleeves, so to speak, and starts working out the features of the
legal framework of a liberal society.
Hayek’s radicalism
The example of Hayek’s taking Wieser’s theory of imputation to its logical consequences is
indicative of a feature of his thought that has been little noticed: its radicalism. Once Hayek has
defined an area of research, or, as I prefer to call it, one of his partial research programmes, he
carries it out rigorously, to its ultimate logical consequences.20 Other examples are his radical antisocialism, which goes so far as to reject all non-liberal political ideologies, including social
democracy, and his rejection of social justice as a concept deprived of meaning. 21 But the first
instance of Hayek’s radicalism is his theory of mind, in which he derives logical consequences from
Schlick’s epistemology that go beyond Schlick’s own. As I have argued above, all its main features
are contained in the ms. of 1920, and they were elaborated into SO, to which I will refer in what
follows.
Radical empiricism
Though Hayek adopted Schlick’s empiricism, he felt it failed to solve the problem posed by Kant,
viz. that we need a pre-existing mental framework that makes consciousness and knowledge about
the world possible:
“There is … a part of our knowledge which, although it is the result of experience, cannot be
controlled by experience, because it constitutes the ordering principle of that universe by
which we distinguish the different kinds of objects of which it consists and to which our
statements refer.” (The Sensory Order: 8.18)
But rather than criticizing empiricism from the outside, Hayek says that he has led it to its logical
conclusion:
“in so far as we have been led into opposition to some of the theses traditionally associated
with empiricism, we have been led to their rejection not from an opposite point of view, but
on the contrary, by a more consistent and radical [sic] application of its basic idea. Precisely
because all our knowledge, including the initial order of our different sensory experiences of
the world, is due to experience, it must contain elements which cannot be contradicted by
experience.” (The Sensory Order: 8.27)22
Keynes was probably the first to draw attention to this. In his reply to Hayek’s review of Treatise on Money he writes
about Prices and Production: "The book, as it stands, seems to me to be one of the most frightful muddles I have ever
read with scarcely a sound proposition in it. (...) It is an extraordinary example of how, starting with a mistake, a
remorseless logician can end up in Bedlam. Dr. Hayek has seen a vision, and though when he woke up he has made
nonsense of his story by giving the wrong names to the objects which occur in it, his Kubla Khan is not without
inspiration and must set the reader thinking with the germs of an idea in his head." (Keynes 1931: 394).
21
In correspondence Popper criticized Hayek for this. Cp. for example Popper’s letter of 28 April 1977 (Hayek
Archives, Hoover Institution, box 44/2): “I understand your feeling that “social justice” is a meaningless pseudo
concept. But I think this feeling ought to be resisted: the people who speak of “social justice” may want to support the
demand for, simply, an equalitarian society; and such a society may exist … even though it may be imposed upon us
only by loss of freedom.”
22
This idea already clearly stated in the ms.: “Gewiss ist es ein auf die Spitze Treiben des Empirismus wenn wir auch das
Verhältnis der Empfindungen untereinander durch die Erfahrung entstehen lassen; aber gerade dadurch werden viele seiner
20
This made Hayek adopt structuralism and naturalism.
Radical epistemological structuralism, naturalism and functionalism
Hayek’s theory of mind led him to a radical epistemological structuralism, naturalism and
functionalism. To see this, let us examine what Hayek says about scientific explanation in CRS,
which was directly influenced by his work in the philosophy of mind. According to Hayek to
explain means to reclassify our sense impressions until we are left with an abstract system of
relationships without any sensory qualities. We are left with “pure structure” without content, for
the description of which we need mathematics. The process of scientific explanation as Hayek
describes it is the same as the process by which the human mind forms classifications of the world.
(CRS: 20). Moreover, the functions of the mind could be realized in any physical substrate that has
the characteristics of a classifier system and is not necessarily restricted to the brain’s physical
multi-layered neural networks.23
He hints at how we can use the theories of physics to make predictions: “their significance is due to
the fact that we possess rules, a “key”, which enables us to translate them into statements about
perceptible phenomena.” (CRS: 21). Presumably, Hayek has in mind the correspondence rules that
were discussed in philosophy of science texts of the 1960s.24 What Hayek writes about explanation
is an elaboration of some of the ideas with which he concluded his ms. of 1920, and which found
their way into the last chapter of SO: when the mind has completed its work, we are left with a
system of definitions or tautologies. Since tautologies are necessarily true, we must accept them.
That leads Hayek to another radical conclusion (one that I have already mentioned).
Radical realism
Hayek seems to argue that he tautological nature of our “finalized” knowledge of the physical world
makes its acceptance compulsory:
“Its concern [i.e., of “Science”] is not what men think about the world and how they
consequently behave, but what they ought to think. The concepts which men actually
employ, the way in which they see nature, is to the scientist necessarily a provisional affair
and his task is to change that picture, to change the concepts in use so as to be able to make
more definite and more certain our statements about the new classes of events.” (CRS: 22;
already quoted on p. Error! Bookmark not defined.Error! Reference source not found.
above; emphasis added).
Apparently, “Science” will produce the only valid classification possible, which therefore ought to
be accepted. As I have argued above, this only applies to the explanation (or rather, classification)
of the physical order; the explanation of the social order: the domain of the “moral sciences” must
always remain incomplete to us, who with our minds and subjective ideas constitute this order: they
are both explananda and explanantia, the “data on which the explanation of human action guided by
those phenomena must be based.” (CRS: 24).
Radical economics
I intend by Hayek’s radical economics the rigourous way in which he elaborated the original ideas,
some of which are indicated in the outline for a PhD-thesis he sketched but never wrote when he
was in the United States in the early 1920s, partly as a reaction to criticism, the most important of
Härten gemildert, da danach die uns mittels dieser Empfindungen vermittelten Erfahrungen sich immer innerhalb dieser
Verhältnisse halten müssen und diese daher einen gewissen apriorischen Charakter erhalten.“ (p. 40).
23
For a clear exposition of these three aspects of Hayek’s theory of the mind, see Feser 2006.
24
Cp. for example Nagel 1961.
which was Sraffa’s in his reaction to the first part of Hayek’s review of Keynes’ Treatise on Money.
Here is the outline:
{Beginning of transcript.}
F.A. HAYEK: Outline of the thesis: [(for N.Y. University Ph.D., 1923)]
“Is the function of money consistent with an artificial stabilization of its purchasing power?”
[“Money’s one function is to serve as a medium of exchange’, J.F. Johnson, Money and bus. Rev. Ed. p.
14]{25}
INTRODUCTION:
1. The need for stabilization.
a. Money originated irrespective of stability in value.
b. Methods of exchange underwent a change while its medium remained unchanged in its essentials.
c. Evils of instability.
2. Meaning of stabilization.
a. Mere elimination of the monetary causes of the fluctuations in prices.
b. Stabilization of value.
c. Stabilization of purchasing power.
3. “Artificial Stabilization” (stabilization of purchasing power contrasted with mere elimination of the
monetary means {“means” has been crossed out and replaced by: “causes”} of prices {the “s” has been
crossed out, and the word has been completed so as to read “price fluctuations”}
4. Sources of possible doubts in its possibility. (Are not sometimes changes in the price level necessary to
reestablish the equilibrium between demand and supply?).
5. Plan of the investigation.
CHAPTER I.
Plans for stabilization and how they are supposed to work.
1. Direct regulations of the volume of circulation (Snyder, Foster and Catching etc.)
2. Indirect regulations of the volume of circulation:
a. Changing the weight of the metallic unit (Fisher, Williams).
b. Through discount policy. (Wicksell, Genoa Conference, Keynes)
CHAPTER II.
Possibility of maintaining the medium of exchange at par with an extraneous standard of value.
1. With actual redemption: the old exchange standard
Without actual redemption:
2. With a single commodity as the standard of value (B.M. Anderson’s illustration of a gold standard of
value, represented in circulation by paper, redeemable in silver at the gold value).
3. With a tabular standard.
25
The book referred to is Joseph French Johnson, Money and Currency in Relation to Industry, Prices, and the Rate of
Interest, Revised edition, no year (but probably 1914), Ginn and Company. Although the abbreviated title is not correct,
the quotation is. As is the case with other hand-written notes on type-written manuscripts by Hayek, this comment may
have been added later, perhaps even decades after the outline was written, when Hayek ordered his papers. The
reference here is interesting for several reasons. In Hayek's published work of the first half of the 1920s the book is not
mentioned. Despite the fact that Johnson does not refer to Carl Menger or any other Austrian economist, his monetary
theory has a distinctly “Austrian” flavour. Thus, he compares the way in which money evolved with language (“Money,
like speech, is doubtless a product of unconscious evolution.”, p. 2). He also does not believe in the neutrality of money.
Johnson explains that the disturbing effects of a change in the value of money is due to four circumstances: “(1) the use
of credit, (2) the fact that production involves a period of time, (3) the fact that prices do not change uniformly, and (4)
the psychology of confidence and depression.” (p. 163). As we shall see below, these are elements that recur
prominently in Hayek's theory of the business cycle. Regarding point (3), Johnson extends the analogy with language. If
additional money does not enter the economy in all sectors at the same time, it will have the same disturbing effects on
economic life as when every year part of the population of a country all of a sudden starts to change part of the English
vocabulary. “Just as language is a medium of exchange of ideas, so is money a medium of exchange of goods and
services.” (p. 172). Johnson's book also contains a detailed account of the monetary reform in the U.S. at the beginning
of this century, and much statistical material.
Appendix on the proposals to use an independent stable accounting unit as a remedy against an unstable
circulating medium.
CHAPTER III.
Effects of an artificial stabilization. Money and the distribution of income.
CHAPTER IV.
Effects of an artificial stabilization, continued: Relation to price movements of non-monetary origin.
CHAPTER V.
Effects of an artificial stabilization, continued: Stabilization and the business cycles.
CHAPTER VI.
International aspects of stabilization.
1. Stabilization attempted by one country only.
2. Several or all important countries accept a stabilization scheme but work it according to their individual
index numbers.
3. The same, but worked on the basis of one uniform international index number of prices.
{End of transcript}
The thesis was never submitted. However, it is a very important document for understanding the
development of Hayek’s economic thought. As we can observe with hindsight, it sketches the
research agenda that Hayek set himself. Here is what he says about it himself:
“The thesis on which I started work while I was registered as a Ph.D. student in New York
University (I believe I proposed to call it: “Is a stabilization of the value of money compatible with
its function?” 26 ), although neither it nor the German work into which I turned it during the
following years in Vienna were ever completed was in many ways the beginning of a continuous
development of which most of my publications during the next two years are rather by-products or
statements of partial results suggested by a particular occasion. One of the first conclusions at
which I remember I had arrived toward the end of 1923 was that stabilization of national price
levels and stabilization of foreign exchange were conflicting aims.27 But before I could anywhere
submit for publication the short article I had written on the subject I found that Keynes had just
stated the same contention in his Tract on Monetary Reform [1923]. Lest anybody should
think that this disappointment in my hope of having made an original discovery is
responsible for my later persistent opposition to Keynes I should add that Keynes was
then, and remained for a good deal longer, one of my heroes and that I greatly admired
this particular work of his.” (Hayek on Hayek, p. 97)
26
Hayek's recollection of the title is not accurate. This mistake is compounded by McCormick 1982, p. 40, who turns it
into: “Is the stabilization of the value of money compatible with the functions of money?” Both the original title and the
title as Hayek remembered it speak of the function of money. Added to the quotation from Johnson, this seems to justify
the conclusion that Hayek agreed that the only function of money is to be a medium of exchange, and that all other
functions (store of value and unit of account) derive from this.
27
This means that policies aimed at achieving both are doomed. Notice that many decades later Hayek still cites this
example when he discusses his “explanation of the principle”. Cp. “Degrees of Explanation”, in Hayek 1967: 17: “The
practical value of such knowledge [i.e., theories that tell us that when we observe given patterns of phenomena, certain
other patterns are to be expected but not some others] consists indeed largely in that it protects us from striving for
incompatible aims.” “If economics tells us that we cannot at the same time maintain fixed rates of foreign exchange and
at will control the internal price level of a country by changing the quantity of money, the character of such a
'prediction' is essentially the same as in the previous case [of the taxonomic scheme of zoology which excludes, for
instance, winged vertebrates with more than two legs].”).
Hayek does not give any details about what German work he turned the thesis into,28 so we can only
conjecture. The first two chapters look as if they were intended as a report on the state of affairs in
economics. Perhaps, the material Hayek collected for these chapters went into his „Das
Stabilisierungsproblem in Goldwährungsländern“ of 1924 and „Die Währungspolitik der
Vereinigten Staaten seit der Überwindung der Krise von 1920", which was published in 1925.
Chapter III may have been intended to contain, inter alia, a discussion of Ludwig von Mises’ theory
of money and the business cycle, in which distribution, or Cantillon effects, play a central part.
Chapters IV and V look like an announcement of Hayek’s own theory of the business cycle which
was published in his Geldtheorie und Konjunkturtheorie of 1929, and Prices and Production of
1931. Despite the fact that according to Hayek, Keynes’ Tract made publication of what was to
have gone into chapter VI superfluous, he kept international monetary matters on his agenda. In
1937 he wrote on the international monetary framework in his Monetary Nationalism and
International Stability. As the thesis outline makes clear, Hayek considered himself a monetary
theorist. But the crux of his theoretical position was that one could not be a good monetary theorist
without analyzing the influence money has on the decisions to consume, save, invest and produce.
On this, at least, he agreed with Keynes’ Treatise on Money.29
Hayek’s self-imposed systematicity and thoroughly (“gediegen”) analytical approach led him to
reply to Sraffa’s criticism in a series of articles and books on capital theory and monetary theory
(for example, Hayek 1934, 1935a, 1936, 1936a, 1937a, 1939, 1941). Few if any commentators have
understood this. An unfortunate consequence is that the importance of Hayek’s contributions in
these fields has been underestimated, neglected, or simply misinterpreted. To give just two
examples, if Hayek 1934 had been known by the participants at the Cambridges debates in capital
theory, the debate would never have taken place (cp. Birner 1999). In addition, the widely diffused
opinion that Sraffa had got the better of Hayek may reflect some of the reactions to Sraffa’s
criticism during the 1930s, but t does not stand up to a more detailed scrutiny of he development of
Hayek’s research programme in economics.
Bibliography
Berlin, I. 1978, "The Hedgehog and the Fox", in Berlin 1978a
Berlin, I 1978a, Russian Thinkers, Hogarth
Birner, J. 1990, “A roundabout solution to a fundamental problem in Menger’s methodology and
beyond”, History of Political Economy
Birner, J. 1995, “Comment: F.A. Hayek's Research Programme in Economics”, in Colonna et al.
2006
Birner, J. 1997, “Money, utility, intertemporal general equilibrium, and cyclical fluctuations: on the
origins of F.A. Hayek’s research programme in economics”, working paper 17/97, ICER, Turin,
Italy
Birner, J. 1999, “The Place of the Ricardo Effect in Hayek’s Economic Research Programme”,
Revue d’économie politique
Birner, J. 2000, “Nascita e struttura del programma di ricerca economico di F.A. Hayek”, in G.
Clerici & S. Rizzello (eds.), Organizzazione, informazione e conoscenza. Saggi su Hayek, volume I,
Turin, UTET 2000
Birner, J. 2001, The Cambridge Controversies in Capital Theory; A Study in the Logic of Theory
Development, Routledge
Thanks to the work of Hansjörg Klausinger in editing the last two volumes of Hayek’s Collected Works, the two
volumes on business cycle theory, we now know that Hayek refers to a largely unpublished ms. in German
(“Geldtheoretische Untersuchungen”. The part that has been published is Hayek 1928.
29
He was openly critical of Keynes' book. For a discussion of the ensuing controversy and its context, see Birner 1992
and 1993a, and for a fuller discussion Birner 1997a.
28
Birner, J. 2004, "F.A. Hayek’s The Sensory Order. An Evolutionary Perspective", unpublished
paper.
Birner, J. 2009, “From group selection to ecological niches. Popper’s rethinking of evolution
in the light of Hayek’s theory of culture”, in Parusnikova et al. 2009
Birner, J. & van Zijp, R. 1994, Hayek, Co-ordination and Evolution; His Legacy in Philosophy,
Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas, Routledge
Caldwell, B.J. 1988, “Hayek’s transformation”, History of Political Economy
Campbell, D.T. 1988, Methodology and Epistemology for Social Science. Selected Papers, ed. by
E.S. Overman, University of Chicago Press
Champion, R. 2000, “Let’s Get Metaphysical. With Criticism of lakatos and Kuhn”, in Champion
2000a
Champion, R. 2000a, Reason and Imagination. Philosophical writings on the works of Karl Popper
& William Bartley, privately published (see also http://zap.to/rafechampion )
Claassen, E.M. (ed.) 1967, Les fondements philosophiques des systèmes économiques: Textes de
Jacques Rueff et essais rédigés en son honneur, Payot
M. Colonna (ed) 1990, Friedrich A. Hayek; Prezzi e produzione; il dibatito sulla moneta, Edizioni
Scientifiche Italiane
Colonna, M., Hagemann, H. & Hamouda. O. (eds.), Capitalism Socialism and Knowledge, Edward
Elgar 1995
Desai, M. (1994) “Equilibrium, Expectations and Knowledge”, in Birner and Van Zijp (eds) (1994)
Ebenstein 2001, Friedrich Hayek. A Biography, University of Chicago Press
Feser, E., 2006, “Hayek the cognitive scientist and philosopher of mind”, in Feser 2006a
Feser, E (ed.), 2006a, The Cambridge Companion to Hayek Cambridge University Press
Hayek, F.A. 1920, "Beiträge zur Theorie der Entwicklung des Bewusstseins", Hayek Archives,
Hoover Institute, Box 92/1
Hayek, F.A. 1924, "Das Stabilisierungsproblem in Goldwährungsländern“, Zeitschrift für
Volkwsirtschaft .und .Sozialpolitik
Hayek, F.A. 1925, "Die Währungspolitik der Vereinigten Staaten seit der Ueberwindung der Krise
von 1920", I&II, Zeitschrift für Volksirtschaft .und .Sozialpolitik
Hayek, F.A. 1926, "Bemerkungen zum Zurechnungsproblem", Jahrbücher .für Nationalöonomie.
Und Statistik
Hayek, F.A. 1926a, "Friedrich Freiherr von Wieser", Jahrbücher .für Nationalöonomie. Und
Statistik
Hayek, F.A. 1927, "Zur Problemstellung der Zinstheorie", Arch.f.Soz.w.u.Soz.pol.
Hayek, F.A. 1928, "Das intertemporale Gleichgewichtssystem der Preise und die Bewegungen des
’Geldwertes’"Weltw.Arch.
Hayek, F.A. 1929, Geldtheorie und Konjunkturtheorie, Holder-Pichler-Tempsky
Hayek, F.A. 1931, Prices and Production, Routledge & Sons, as PP
Hayek, F.A. 1933, Monetary Theory and the Trade Cycle, Augustus M. Kelley, 1975, tr. of Hayek
1929, quoted as MTTC
Hayek, F.A. 1934, “On the Relationship between Investment and Output”, The Economic Journal
Hayek, F.A. 1935a, "The Maintenance of Capital", ch. III of PII
Hayek, F.A. 1936, “Utility analysis and interest”, EJ
Hayek, F.A. 1936a, “The Mythology of Capital”, Economic Journal
Hayek, F.A. 1937, “Economics and Knowledge”, ch. II of Hayek 1949
Hayek, F.A. 1937a, “Einleitung zu einer Kapitaltheorie”, Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie
Hayek, F.A. 1937b, Hayek, Friedrich A., Monetary Nationalism and International Stability,
Augustus M. Kelley 1971 (1st ed. 1937, Longmans Green)
Hayek, F.A. 1939, Profits, Interest and Investment and Other Essays on the Theory of Industrial
Fluctuations, Augustus M. Kelley 1975, quoted as PII
Hayek, F.A. 1941, The Pure Theory of Capital, Routledge & Kegan Paul, quoted as PTC
Hayek, F.A. 1943, “The Facts of the Social Sciences”, in Hayek 1949
Hayek, F.A. 1945a, “Individualism: True and False”, in: Hayek 1949, quoted as ITF
F.A. Hayek 1949, Individualism and Economic Order, Routledge and Kegan Paul
Hayek, F.A. 1952, The Sensory Order. An Inquiry into the foundations of Theoretical Psychology,
Chicago University Press, quoted as SO
Hayek, F.A. 1955, The Counterrevolution of Science, The Free Press, quoted as CRS
Hayek, F.A. 1964, “Kinds of Rationalism”, in Hayek 1967
Hayek, F.A. 1964a, “The Theory of Complex Phenomena”, in Hayek 1967
Hayek, F.A. 1963, “Rules, Perception and Intelligibility”, in Hayek 1967
Hayek, F.A. 1963a, “The Legal and Political Philosophy of David Hume”, in Hayek 1967
Hayek, F.A. 1967, Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, University of Chicago Press
Hayek, F.A. 1967a, “Notes on the Evolution of Systems of Rules of Conduct” in Hayek 1967
Hayek, F.A. 1968, “Economics as a Discovery Procedure”, in Hayek 1978
Hayek, F.A. 1978, The Three Sources of Human Values, L.T. Hobhouse Memorial Trust Lecture
44, The London School of Economics and Political Science
Kauder, E. 1965, A History of Marginal Utility Theory, Princeton UP
Keynes, J.M. 1931, “A pure Theory of Money. A Reply to Dr. Hayek”, Economic Journal
Koertge, N. 1975, "Popper's Metaphysical Research Program for the Human Sciences", Inquiry
Koertge, N. 1979, "The Methodological Status of Popper's Rationality Principle", Theory & Decision
Latsis, S. 1972, "Situational Determinism in Economics", British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
McCloughry, R. 1984 (ed), F.A. Hayek, Money, Capital and Fluctuations; Early Essays, Routledge
& Kegan Paul
Miller, D. (ed.) 1983, A Pocket Popper, Fontana Paperbacks
Nagel, E., 1961, The Structure of Science, Routledge & Kegan Paul
Parusnikova, S. & Cohen, R. S. (eds.), Rethinking Popper, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of
Science vol. 272, Springer 2009
Perroux, F. 1943, La Valeur, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris
Popper, K.R. 1952, « The Nature of Philosophical Problems and their Roots in Science », in Popper
1963a
Popper, K.R. 1957, The Poverty of Historicism, Routledge & Kegan Paul
Popper, .R. 1957a, “The Aim of Science”, in Popper 1972.
Popper, K.R. 1963, “Models, Instruments and Truth. The status of the rationality principle in the
social sciences”, in Popper 1994
Popper, K.R.1963a, Conjectures and Refutations, Routledge & Kegan Paul
Popper, K.R. 1967, “La rationalité et le statut du principe de rationalité”, in Claassen 1967, also
retranslated into English and published as "The Rationality Principle", in Miller 1983
Popper, K.R. 1972, Objective Knowledge. An Evolutionary Approach, Oxford University Press
Poper, K.R. 1984, Auf der Suche nach einer besseren Welt Vorträge und Aufsätze aus dreissig Jahren,
Piper
Popper,K.R. 1992, In Search of a Better World.Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years, Routledge
Popper, K.R. 1994, The Myth of the Framework. In defence ofscience and rationality, ed. by M.A.
Notturno, Routledge
Download