CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS Contents 1.

advertisement
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL
CALCULATIONS
SAM RASKIN
Contents
1. Introduction
2. Review of Zastava spaces
3. Limiting case of the Casselman-Shalika formula
4. Identification of the Chevalley complex
5. Hecke functors: Zastava calculation over a point
6. Around factorizable Satake
7. Hecke functors: Zastava with moving points
Appendix A. Proof of Lemma 6.18.1
Appendix B. Universal local acyclicity
References
1
14
22
27
31
38
52
64
67
70
1. Introduction
1.1. Semi-infinite flag variety. This paper begins a series concerning 𝐷-modules on the semiinfinite flag variety of Feigin-Frenkel.
Let 𝐺 be a split reductive group over π‘˜ a field of characteristic zero. Let 𝐡 be a Borel with
radical 𝑁 and reductive quotient 𝐡{𝑁 “ 𝑇 .
Let 𝑋 be a smooth curve. We let π‘₯ P 𝑋 be a fixed π‘˜-point. Let 𝑂π‘₯ “ π‘˜rr𝑑π‘₯ ss and 𝐾π‘₯ “ π‘˜pp𝑑π‘₯ qq be
π‘œ
the rings Taylor and Laurent series based at π‘₯. Let π’Ÿπ‘₯ and π’Ÿπ‘₯ denote the spectra of these rings.
8
Informally, the semi-infinite flag variety should be a quotient Flπ‘₯2 :“ 𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝑁 p𝐾π‘₯ q𝑇 p𝑂π‘₯ q, but
this quotient is by an infinite-dimensional group and therefore leaves the realm of usual algebraic
geometry.
8
Still, we will explain in future work [Ras2] how to make precise sense of 𝐷-modules on Flπ‘₯2 ,
but we ask the reader to take on faith for this introduction that such a category makes sense.1
This category will not play any explicit role in the present paper, and will be carefully discussed
in [Ras2]; however, it plays an important motivational role in this introduction.
1.2. Why semi-infinite flags? The desire for a theory of sheaves on the semi-infinite flag variety stretches back to the early days of geometric representation theory: see [FF], [FM], [FFKM],
[BFGM], and [ABB` ] for example. Among these works, there are diverse goals and perspectives,
8
showing the rich representation theoretic nature of Flπ‘₯2 .
Date: March 28, 2015.
1For the overly curious reader: one takes the category 𝐷 ! p𝐺p𝐾 qq from [Ber] (c.f. also [Ras4]) and imposes the
π‘₯
coinvariant condition with respect to the group indscheme 𝑁 p𝐾π‘₯ q𝑇 p𝑂π‘₯ q.
1
2
SAM RASKIN
‚ [FF] explains that the analogy between Wakimoto modules for an affine Kac-Moody algebra gΜ‚πœ…,π‘₯ and Verma modules for the finite-dimensional algebra g should be understood
8
through the Beilinson-Bernstein localization picture, with Flπ‘₯2 playing the role of the finitedimensional 𝐺{𝐡.
‚ [FM], [FFKM] and [ABB` ] relate the semi-infinite flag variety to representations of Lusztig’s
small quantum group, following Finkelberg, Feigin-Frenkel and Lusztig.
8
‚ As noted in [ABB` ], 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q “ 𝐷p𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝑁 p𝐾π‘₯ q𝑇 p𝑂π‘₯ qq plays the role of the universal
unramified principal series representation of 𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q in the categorical setting of local geometric Langlands (see [FG2] and [Ber] for some modern discussion of this framework and
its ambitions).
However, these references (except [FF], which is not rigorous on these points) uses ad hoc finitedimensional models for the semi-infinite flag variety.
Remark 1.2.1. One of our principal motivations in this work and its sequels [Ras2] and [Ras3] is to
8
study 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q from the perspective of the geometric Langlands program, and then to use local to
global methods to apply this to the study of geometric Eisenstein series in the global unramified
geometric Langlands program. But this present work is also closely2 connected to the above, earlier
work, as we hope to explore further in the future.
8
1.3. The present series of papers will introduce the whole category 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q and study some interesting parts of its representation theory: e.g., we will explain how to compute Exts between certain
objects in terms of the Langlands dual group.
8
Studying the whole of 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q was neglected by previous works (presumably) due to the technical
and highly infinite-dimensional nature of its construction.
8
1.4. The role of the present paper. Whatever the definition of 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q is, it is not obvious how
to compute directly with it. The primary problem is that we do not have such a good theory of
perverse sheaves in the infinite type setting: the usual theory [BBD] of middle extensions, so crucial
in connecting combinatorics (e.g., Langlands duality) and geometry, does not exist for embeddings
of infinite codimension.
8
Therefore, to study 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q, it is necessary to reduce our computations to finite-dimensional
8
ones. This paper performs those computations, and this is the reason why the category 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q
does not explicitly appear here.3 However, the author finds these computations to be interesting in
their own right, and hopes the reader will agree.
1.5. In the remainder of the introduction, we will discuss problems close to those to be considered
in [Ras2], and discuss the contents of the present paper and their connection to the above problems.
8
8
1.6. 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q is boring. One can show4 that 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q is equivalent to the category 𝐷pFlaff
𝐺,π‘₯ q of
𝐷-modules on the affine flag variety 𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝐼 (where 𝐼 is the Iwahori subgroup) in a 𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ qequivariant way.5
2But non-trivially, due to the ad hoc definitions in earlier works.
3We hope the reader will benefit from this separation, and not merely suffer through an introduction some much of
whose contents has little to do with the paper at hand.
4This result will appear in [Ras2].
5This is compatible with the analogy with 𝑝-adic representation theory: c.f. [Cas].
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
3
At first pass, this means that essentially6 every question in local geometric Langlands about
8
𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q has either been answered in the exhaustive works of Bezrukavnikov and collaborators
(especially [AB], [ABG], and [Bez]), or else is completely out of reach at the moment.
8
Thus, it would appear that there is nothing new to say about 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q.
8
1.7. 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q is not boring (or: factorization). However, there is a significant difference between
the affine and semi-infinite flag varieties: the latter factorizes in the sense of Beilinson-Drinfeld [BD].
We refer to the introduction to [Ras1] for an introduction to factorization. Modulo the non8
existence of Flπ‘₯2 , let us recall that this essentially means that for each finite set 𝐼, we have a “semi8
8
Ε›
infinite flag variety” Fl𝑋2 𝐼 over 𝑋 𝐼 whose fiber at a point pπ‘₯𝑖 q𝑖P𝐼 P 𝑋 𝐼 is the product π‘₯Ptπ‘₯𝑖 u𝑖P𝐼 Flπ‘₯2𝑖 .
Here tπ‘₯𝑖 u𝑖P𝐼 is the unordered set in which we have forgotten the multiplicities with which points
appear.
However, it is well-known that the Iwahori subgroup (unlike 𝐺p𝑂π‘₯ q) does not factorize.7
8
Remark 1.7.1. The methods of the Bezrukavnikov school do not readily adapt to studying Flπ‘₯2
factorizably: they heavily rely on the ind-finite type and ind-proper nature of Flaff
𝐺 , which are not
manifested in the factorization setting.
1.8. But why is it not boring (or: why factorization)? As discussed in the introduction to
8
[Ras1], there are several reasons to care about the factorization structure on Flπ‘₯2 .
‚ Most imminently (from the perspective of Remark 1.2.1), the theory of chiral homology
(c.f. [BD]) provides a way of constructing global invariants from factorizable local ones.
Therefore, identifying spectral and geometric factorization categories allows us to compare
globally defined invariants as well.
‚ Factorization structures also play a key, if sometimes subtle, role in the purely local theory.
Let us mention one manifestation of this: the localization theory [FG3] (at critical level)
for Flaff
gπ‘π‘Ÿπ‘–π‘‘ as a bare Lie algebra.
𝐺 has to do with the structure of the Kac-Moody algebra p
8
A factorizable localization theory for Flπ‘₯2 would connect to the vertex algebra structure on
its vacuum representation.
8
‚ In [FM], [FFKM], [ABB` ], and [BFS], sheaves on Flπ‘₯2 are defined using factorization struc8
tures. We anticipate the eventual comparison between our category 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q and the previous
8
ones to pass through the factorization structure of Flπ‘₯2 .
1.9. Main conjecture. Our main conjecture is about Langlands duality for certain factorization
categories: the geometric side concerns some 𝐷-modules on the semi-infinite flag variety, and the
spectral side concerns coherent sheaves on certain spaces of local systems.
See below for a more evocative description of the two sides.
6
This is not completely true: for the study of Kac-Moody algebras, the semi-infinite flag variety has an interesting
global sections functor. It differs from the global sections functor of the affine flag variety in as much as Wakimoto
modules differ from Verma modules.
7It is instructive to try and fail to define a factorization version of the Iwahori subgroup that lives over 𝑋 2 : a point
should be a pair of points π‘₯1 , π‘₯2 in 𝑋, 𝐺-bundle on 𝑋 with a trivialization away from π‘₯1 and π‘₯2 , and with a reduction
to the Borel 𝐡 at the points π‘₯1 and π‘₯2 . However, to formulate this scheme-theoretically, we need to ask for a reduction
to 𝐡 at the scheme-theoretic union of the points π‘₯1 and π‘₯2 . Therefore, over a point π‘₯ in the diagonal 𝑋 Ď 𝑋 2 , we
are asking for a reduction to 𝐡 on the first infinitesimal neighborhood of π‘₯, which defines a rather smaller subgroup
of 𝐺p𝑂π‘₯ q than the Iwahori group.
4
SAM RASKIN
1.10. Let 𝐡 ´ be a Borel opposite to 𝐡, and let 𝑁 ´ denote its unipotent radical.
Recall that for any category C acted on by 𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q in the sense of [Ber], we can form its Whittaker
subcategory, WhitpCq Ď C consisting of objects equivariant against a non-degenerate character of
𝑁 ´ p𝐾q.
Moreover, up to certain twists (which we ignore in this introduction: see S2.8 for their definitions),
this makes sense factorizably.
8
For each finite set 𝐼, there is therefore a category Whit𝑋2 𝐼 to be the of Whittaker equivariant
8
8
𝐷-modules on Fl𝑋2 𝐼 , and the assignment 𝐼 ÞÑ Whit𝑋2 𝐼 defines a factorization category in the sense
of [Ras1]. This forms the geometric side of our conjecture.
π‘œ
1.11.
For a point π‘₯ P 𝑋 and an affine algebraic group 𝛀 , let LocSys𝛀 pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q denote the prestack of
π‘œ
de Rham local systems with structure group 𝛀 on π’Ÿπ‘₯ .
Formally: we have the indscheme Conn𝛀 of Liep𝛀 q-valued 1-forms (i.e., connection forms) on the
punctured disc, which is equipped with the usual gauge action of 𝛀 p𝐾π‘₯ q. We form the quotient and
π‘œ
stackify for the étale topology on AffSch and denote this by LocSys𝛀 pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q.
π‘œ
Remark 1.11.1. LocSys𝛀 pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q is not an algebraic stack of any kind because we quotient by the loop
group 𝛀 p𝐾π‘₯ q, an indscheme of ind-infinite type. It might be considered as a kind of semi-infinite
Artin stack, the theory of which has unfortunately not been developed.
π‘œ
The assignment π‘₯ ÞÑ LocSys𝛀 pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q factorizes in an obvious way.
1.12. Recall that for a finite type (derived) scheme (or stack) 𝑍, [GR] has defined a DG category
IndCohp𝑍q of ind-coherent sheaves on 𝑍.8
We would like to take as the spectral side of our equivalence the factorization category:
π‘œ
`
π‘₯ ÞÑ IndCoh LocSys𝐡ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
ˆ
π‘œ
˘
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q .
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
Λ‡ to refer to the reductive group Langlands dual to 𝐺, and 𝐡
Λ‡ΔŽπΊ
Λ‡
Here and everywhere, we use e.g. 𝐺
to refer to the corresponding Borel subgroup, etc. (c.f. S1.40).
However, note that IndCoh has not been defined in this setting: the spaces of local systems on
the punctured disc are defined as the quotient of an indscheme of ind-infinite type by a group of
ind-infinite type.
We ignore this problem in what follows, describing a substitute in S1.15 below.
1.13.
We now formulate the following conjecture:
Conjecture 1. There is an equivalence of factorization categories:
´
π‘œ
`
˘¯
8 »
Whit 2 Ý
Ñ π‘₯ ÞÑ IndCoh LocSys𝐡ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
ˆ
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q .
(1.13.1)
π‘œ
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
Remark 1.13.1. Identifying 𝐷-modules on the affine flag variety and on the semi-infinite flag variety,
one can show that fiberwise, this conjecture recovers the main result of [AB]. However, as noted in
Remark 1.7.1, the methods of loc. cit. are not amenable to the factorizable setting.
8For the reader unfamiliar with the theory of loc. cit., we recall that this sheaf theoretic framework is very close
to the more familiar QCoh, but is the natural setting for Grothendieck’s functor 𝑓 ! of exceptional inverse image (as
opposed to the functor 𝑓 ˚ , which is adapted to QCoh).
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
5
1.14. What is contained in this paper? In [FM], Finkelberg and Mirkovic argue that their
Zastava spaces provide finite-dimensional models for the geometry of the semi-infinite flag variety.
We essentially use this model in the present paper: we compute some twisted cohomology groups
of Zastava spaces, and these computations will provide the main input for our later study [Ras2]
of semi-infinite flag varieties.
In S1.15-1.21, we describe a certain factorization algebra Υň and its role in Conjecture 1. In
S1.22-1.27, we recall some tactile aspects of the geometry of Zastava spaces. Finally, in S1.28-1.37,
we formulate the main results of this text: these realize Υň (and its modules) as twisted cohomology
groups on Zastava space.
Remark 1.14.1. Some of the descriptions below may go a bit quickly for a reader who is a nonexpert in this area. We hope that for such a reader, the material that follows helps to supplement
what it is written more slowly in the body of the text, and that it is not wholly a wash.
1.15. The factorization algebra Υň . To describe the main results of this paper, we need to
describe how we model the spectral side of Conjecture 1, i.e., the category of ind-coherent sheaves
on the appropriate space of local systems.
We will do this using the graded factorization algebra Υň , introduced in [BG2].
After preliminary remarks about what graded factorization algebras are in S1.16, we introduce
Υň in S1.17. Finally, in S1.20-1.21, we explain why factorization modules for Υň are related to the
spectral side of Conjecture 1.
1.16. Let ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  Ď Λ̌ :“ tcocharacters of 𝐺u denote the ZΔ›0 -span of the simple coroots (relative to
𝐡).
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Let DivΛ̌
denote the space of ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -valued divisors on 𝑋. I.e., its π‘˜-points are written:
eff
ÿ
Λ‡ 𝑖 ¨ π‘₯𝑖
πœ†
(1.16.1)
tπ‘₯𝑖 uΔŽπ‘‹ finite
Λ‡ 𝑖 P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  , and for 𝐺 of semi-simple rank 1, this space is the union of the symmetric powers of
for πœ†
𝑋 (for general 𝐺, connected components are products of symmetric powers of 𝑋).
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  , we let Divπœ†Λ‡ denote the connected component of DivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  of divisors of total degree
For πœ†
eff
eff
Λ‡ (i.e., in the above we have Ε™ πœ†
Λ‡ 𝑖 “ πœ†).
Λ‡
πœ†
A (ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  )-graded factorization algebra is the datum of 𝐷-modules:
Λ‡
Λ‡
Aπœ† P 𝐷pDivπœ†eff q,
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
πœ†
plus symmetric and associative isomorphisms:
Λ‡
Aπœ†`Λ‡πœ‡ |rDivπœ†Λ‡
eff
Λ‡
Λ‡
ˆ Divπœ‡
eff s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
» Aπœ† b Aπœ‡Λ‡ |rDivπœ†Λ‡
eff
Λ‡
ˆ Divπœ‡
eff s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
.
Here:
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
rDivπœ†eff ˆ Divπœ‡eff
s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 Ď Divπœ†eff ˆ Divπœ‡eff
denotes the open locus of pairs of (colored) divisors with disjoint supports, which we consider
Λ‡ πœ‡
mapping to Divπœ†`Λ‡
through the map of addition of divisors (which is étale on this locus).
eff
Remark 1.16.1. The theory of graded factorization algebras closely imitates the theory of factorπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
ization algebras from [BD], with the above DivΛ̌
replacing the Ran space from loc. cit.
eff
6
1.17.
SAM RASKIN
The ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -graded Lie algebra ň defines a Lie-˚ algebra:9
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ‡
nΜŒπ‘‹ :“ ‘𝛼ˇ a coroot of 𝐺 nΜŒπ›ΌΛ‡ b βˆ†π›ΌΛš,𝑑𝑅
pπ‘˜π‘‹ q P 𝐷pDivΛ̌
eff q.
In this notation, for a finite type scheme 𝑆, π‘˜π‘† denotes its (𝐷-module version of the) constant sheaf;
Λ‡
nΜŒπ›ΌΛ‡ denotes the corresponding graded component of ň; and βˆ†π›ΌΛ‡ : 𝑋 Ñ Div𝛼eff
denotes the diagonal
embedding.
As in [BD], we may form the chiral enveloping algebra of nΜŒπ‘‹ : we let Υň denote the corresponding
factorization algebra. For the reader unfamiliar with [BD], we remind that Υň is associated to nΜŒπ‘‹
as a sort of Chevalley complex; in particular, the ˚-fiber of Υň at a point (1.16.1) is:
Λ‡
b 𝐢‚ pňqπœ†π‘–
𝑖
where 𝐢‚ denotes the (homological) Chevalley complex of a Lie algebra (i.e., the complex computing
Lie algebra homology).
1.18. Next, we recall that in the general setup of S1.16, to a graded factorization algebra A and
a closed point π‘₯ P 𝑋, we can associate a DG category A–modfact
of its (Λ̌-graded) factorization
π‘₯
modules “at π‘₯ P 𝑋.”
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
denote the indscheme of Λ̌-valued divisors on 𝑋 which are ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -valued on
First, let Diveff
𝑋zπ‘₯. So π‘˜-points of this space are sums:
ÿ
πœ‡
Λ‡¨π‘₯`
Λ‡ 𝑖 ¨ π‘₯𝑖
πœ†
tπ‘₯𝑖 uΔŽπ‘‹zπ‘₯ finite
ˇ𝑖 P
where πœ‡
Λ‡ P Λ̌ and πœ†
(to see the indscheme structure, bound how small πœ‡
Λ‡ can be).
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
q equipped with an isomorThen a factorization module for A is a 𝐷-module 𝑀 P 𝐷pDiveff
phism:
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
add! p𝑀 q|rDivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ˆ DivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯ » A b 𝑀 |rDivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ˆ DivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
eff
eff
eff
eff
which is associative with respect to the factorization structure on A, where add is the map:
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌
Diveff
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
ˆ DivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Ñ DivΛ̌
eff
of addition of divisors.
Factorization modules form a DG category in the obvious way.
Remark 1.18.1. In what follows, we will need unital versions of the above, i.e., unital factorization
algebras and unital modules. This is a technical requirement, and for the sake of brevity we do not
spell it out here, referring to [BD] or [Ras1] for details. However, this is the reason that notations
fact
of the form A–modfact
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ appear below instead of Υň –mod𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ . However, we remark that whatever
these unital structures are, chiral envelopes always carry them, and in particular Υň does.
Remark 1.18.2. Note that the affine Grassmannian Gr𝑇,π‘₯ “ 𝑇 p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝑇 p𝑂π‘₯ q with structure group
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
𝑇 embeds into Diveff
as the locus of divisors supported at the point π‘₯. We remind that the
reduced scheme underlying Gr𝑇,π‘₯ is the discrete scheme Λ̌.
9Here the structure of Lie-˚ algebra is defined in [BD] (see also [FG1], [Ras1] for derived versions). For the reader’s
sake, we simply note that this datum encodes the natural structure on nΜŒπ‘‹ inherited from the Lie bracket on ň.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
1.19.
7
The following provides the connection between Υň and Conjecture 1.
Principle.
(1) There is a canonical equivalence:
π‘œ
`
^
Υň –modfact
Λ‡ pπ’Ÿ π‘₯ q
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ » IndCoh LocSys𝐡
ˆ
π‘œ
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
˘
(1.19.1)
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
π‘œ
where LocSys𝐡ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q^ is the formal completion at the trivial local system.
(2) Under this equivalence, the functor:10
Oblv
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Λ̌
Υň –modfact
ÝÝÑ π·pDiveff
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ Ý
!´restriction
q ÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÑ π·pGr𝑇,π‘₯ q » Repp𝑇ˇq » QCohpLocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ qq
corresponds to the functor of !-restriction along the map:
π‘œ
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q Ñ LocSys𝐡ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q^
ˆ
π‘œ
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q.
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
(3) The above two facts generalize to the factorization setting, where π‘₯ is replaced by several
points allowed to move and collide.
Remark 1.19.1. This is a principle and not a theorem because the right hand side of (1.19.1) is
not defined (we remind that this is because IndCoh is only defined in finite type situations, while
LocSys leaves this world). Therefore, the reader might take it simply as a definition.
For the reader familiar with derived deformation theory (as in [Lur2], [GR]) and [BD], we will
explain heuristically in S1.20-1.21 why we take this principle as given. However, the reader who is
not familiar with these subjects may safely skip this material, as it plays only a motivational role
for us.
Remark 1.19.2. We note that (heuristically) ind-coherent sheaves on (1.19.1) should be a full subπ‘œ
˘
`
ˆ
category of IndCoh LocSys𝐡ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q .11
π‘œ
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
In [Ras2], we will use the computations of the present paper to construct a functor
¯
´
π‘œ
˘
`
8 »
ˆ
Whit 2 Ý
Ñ π‘₯ ÞÑ IndCoh LocSys𝐡ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q^
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q :“ Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯
π‘œ
LocSys𝑇ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q
8
and identify a full subcategory of Whit 2 on which this functor is an equivalence.
1.20. As stated above, the reader may safely skip S1.20-1.21, which are included to justify the
principle of S1.19.
We briefly recall Lurie’s approach to deformation theory [Lur2].
Suppose that X is a “nice enough” stack and π‘₯ P X is a π‘˜-point, with the formal completion of
X at π‘₯ denoted by X^
π‘₯ . Then the fiber 𝑇X,π‘₯ r´1s of the shifted tangent complex of X at π‘₯ identifies
with the Lie algebra of the (derived) automorphism group (alias: inertia) Autπ‘₯ pXq :“ π‘₯ ˆX π‘₯ of X
at π‘₯, and there is an identification of the DG category IndCohpX^
π‘₯ q of ind-coherent sheaves on the
formal completion of X at π‘₯ with 𝑇X,π‘₯ r´1s-modules.
10Here and throughout the text, for an algebraic group 𝛀 , Repp𝛀 q denotes the derived (i.e., DG) category of its
representations, i.e., QCohpB𝐺q.
11This combines the facts that ind-coherent sheaves on a formal completion are a full subcategory of ind-coherent
sheaves of the whole space, and the fact that ind-coherent sheaves on the classifying stack of the formal group of a
unipotent group are a full subcategory of ind-coherent sheaves on the classifying stack of the group.
8
SAM RASKIN
π‘œ
1.21.
At the trivial local system, the fiber of the shifted tangent complex of LocSys𝑁ˇ pπ’Ÿπ‘₯ q is the
π‘œ
˚ pπ’Ÿ , ň b π‘˜q. The philosophy of [BD] indicates that modules for this Lie
(derived) Lie algebra 𝐻𝑑𝑅
π‘₯
algebra should be equivalent to factorization modules for the chiral envelope of the Lie-˚ algebra
ň b π‘˜π‘‹ on 𝑋.
The Λ̌-graded variant of this—that is, the version in the setting of S1.16 in which symmetric
powers of the curve replace the Ran space from [BD]—provides the principle of S1.19.
1.22. Zastava spaces. Next, we describe the most salient features of Zastava spaces. We remark
that this geometry is reviewed in detail in S2.
π‘œ
1.23.
π‘œ
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
There are two Zastava spaces, 𝒡 and 𝒡, each fibered over DivΛ̌
eff : the relationship is that
π‘œ
𝒡 embeds into 𝒡 as an open, and for this reason, we sometimes refer to 𝒡 as Zastava space and 𝒡
as open Zastava space.
For the purposes of this introduction, we content ourselves with a description of the fibers of the
maps:
π‘œ
𝒡

/𝒡
"
π‘œ
πœ‹
πœ‹
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
DivΛ̌
eff
.
To give this description, we will first recall the so-called central fibers of the Zastava spaces.
1.24.
Recall that e.g. Gr𝐺,π‘₯ denotes the affine Grassmannian 𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝐺p𝑂π‘₯ q of 𝐺 at π‘₯.
π‘œ
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  , define the central fiber Zπœ†Λ‡ as the intersection:
For π‘₯ P 𝑋 a geometric point and πœ†
π‘₯
´
¯
č
Λ‡
Λ‡ π‘₯ q𝐺p𝑂π‘₯ q {𝐺p𝑂π‘₯ q Ď 𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝐺p𝑂π‘₯ q “ Gr𝐺,π‘₯
Gr𝑁 ´ ,π‘₯ X Grπœ†π΅,π‘₯ “ 𝑁 ´ p𝐾π‘₯ q𝐺p𝑂π‘₯ q 𝑁 p𝐾π‘₯ qπœ†p𝑑
Λ‡
where 𝑑π‘₯ is any uniformizer at π‘₯. Here we recall that Gr𝑁 ´ ,π‘₯ and Grπœ†π΅,π‘₯ embed into Gr𝐺,π‘₯ as
ind-locally closed subschemes (of infinite dimension and codimension).12
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
A small miracle: the intersections Zπœ† are finite type, and equidimensional of dimension p𝜌, πœ†q.
π‘₯
π‘œ
Λ‡“𝛼
Example 1.24.1. For πœ†
Λ‡ a simple coroot, one has Z𝛼π‘₯Λ‡ » A1 zt0u.
1.25.
Λ‡
πœ†
Λ‡
πœ†
Let Gr𝐡,π‘₯ denote the closure of Gr𝐡,π‘₯ in Gr𝐺,π‘₯ .13 We remind that Gr𝐡,π‘₯ has an (infinite)
Λ‡
πœ‡
stratification by the ind-locally closed subschemes Grπœ†´Λ‡
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  .
𝐡,π‘₯ for πœ‡
Λ‡
We then define Zπœ†π‘₯ as the corresponding intersection:
Λ‡
πœ†
Gr𝑁 ´ ,π‘₯ XGr𝐡,π‘₯ Ď Gr𝐺,π‘₯ .
Λ‡
Again, this intersection is finite-dimensional, and equidimensional of dimension p𝜌, πœ†q.
Λ‡“𝛼
Example 1.25.1. For πœ†
Λ‡ a simple coroot, one has Z𝛼π‘₯Λ‡ » A1 .
12The requirement that πœ†
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  is included so that this intersection is non-empty.
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†
13As a moduli problem, Grπœ†
𝐡,π‘₯ can be defined analogously to Drinfeld’s compactification of Bun𝐡 .
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
1.26.
is:
9
π‘œ
Λ‡
Λ‡ :“ Ε™ πœ†
Λ‡ 𝑖 ), the corresponding fiber of 𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ along πœ‹π‘œ
Now, for a π‘˜-point (1.16.1) of Divπœ†eff (for πœ†
ΕΊ π‘œΛ‡
Zπœ†π‘₯𝑖𝑖
(1.26.1)
and similarly for 𝒡.
π‘œ
π‘œ
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡ and moreover, 𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ is actually smooth.
Again, 𝒡 πœ† and 𝒡 πœ† are equidimensional of dimension p2𝜌, πœ†q,
1.27. Finally, there is a canonical map can : 𝒡 Ñ Gπ‘Ž , which is constructed (fiberwise) as follows.
First, define the map 𝑁 ´ p𝐾π‘₯ q Ñ Gπ‘Ž by:
sum over coordinates
ΕΊ
𝑁 ´ p𝐾π‘₯ q Ñ p𝑁 ´ {r𝑁 ´ , 𝑁 ´ sqp𝐾π‘₯ q »
𝑓 ÞÑResp𝑓 ¨π‘‘𝑑π‘₯ q
𝐾π‘₯ ÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÑ πΎπ‘₯ ÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÑ Gπ‘Ž
simple roots
where Res denotes the residue map and 𝑑π‘₯ is a coordinate in 𝐾π‘₯ .
Remark 1.27.1. The twists we mentioned in S1.10 are included so that we do not have to choose
a coordinate 𝑑π‘₯ , but rather have a canonical residue map to Gπ‘Ž . But we continue to ignore these
twists, reminding simply that they are spelled out in S2.8.
It is clear that this map factors uniquely through the projection 𝑁 ´ p𝐾π‘₯ q Ñ Gr𝑁 ´ .
We now map (1.26.1) by embedding into the product of Gr𝑁 ´ ,π‘₯𝑖 and summing the corresponding
maps to Gπ‘Ž over the points π‘₯𝑖 .
π‘œ
In what follows, we let πœ“π’΅ P 𝐷p𝒡q (resp. πœ“ π‘œ P 𝐷p𝒡q) denote the !-pullback of the Artin-Shreier
𝒡
(i.e., exponential) 𝐷-module on Gπ‘Ž (normalized to be in the same cohomological degree as the
dualizing 𝐷-module of Gπ‘Ž ).
Remark 1.27.2. The above map 𝑁 ´ p𝐾π‘₯ q Ñ Gπ‘Ž is referred to as the Whittaker character, and we
refer to sheaves constructed out of it the Artin-Shreier sheaf (e.g., πœ“ π‘œ , πœ“π’΅ ) as Whittaker sheaves.
𝒡
1.28. Formulation of the main results of this paper. Here is a rough overview of the main
results of this paper, to be expanded upon below:
Roughly, the first main result of this paper, Theorem 4.6.1, identifies Υň with certain Whittaker
cohomology groups on Zastava space; see loc. cit. for more details. This theorem, following [BG2]
Λ‡ (via Υň ) which is different
and [FFKM], provides passage from the group 𝐺 to the dual group 𝐺
from geometric Satake.
The second main result, Theorem 7.8.1 (see also Theorem 5.14.1) compares Theorem 4.6.1 with
the geometric Satake equivalence.
1.29. We now give a more precise description of the above theorems.
Our first main result is the following.
!
π‘œ
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Theorem (c.f. Theorem 4.6.1). πœ‹ ˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ b IC π‘œ q P 𝐷pDivΛ̌
eff q is concentrated in cohomological
𝒡
𝒡
degree zero, and identifies canonically with Υň . Here IC indicates the intersection cohomology sheaf14
π‘œΛ‡
π‘œ
(by smoothness of the 𝒡 πœ† , this just effects cohomological shifts on the connected component of 𝒡).
Moreover, the factorization structure on Zastava spaces induces a factorization algebra structure
!
π‘œ
on πœ‹ ˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ b IC π‘œ q, and the above equivalence upgrades to an equivalence of factorization algebras.
𝒡
π‘œ
𝒡
π‘œ
Λ‡
14Since 𝒡 is a union of the varieties 𝒡 πœ†
, we define this IC sheaf as the direct sum of the IC sheaves of the connected
components.
10
SAM RASKIN
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
In words: the (DivΛ̌
eff -parametrized) cohomology of Zastava spaces twisted by the Whittaker
sheaf is Υň .
π‘œ
1.30. Polar Zastava space. To formulate Theorem 5.14.1, we introduce a certain indscheme 𝒡 8¨π‘₯
π‘œ
π‘œ
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Λ̌
with a map πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯ : 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ Ñ Diveff
π‘œ
π‘œ
π‘œ
, where the geometry is certainly analogous to πœ‹ : 𝒡 Ñ DivΛ̌
eff .
π‘œ
As with 𝒡, for this introduction we only describe the fibers of the map πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯ . Namely, at a point15
Ε™
Λ‡ 𝑖 ¨ π‘₯𝑖 of DivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯ , the fiber is:
πœ‡
Λ‡ ¨ π‘₯ ` tπ‘₯𝑖 uΔŽπ‘‹zπ‘₯ finite πœ†
eff
Λ‡
Grπœ‡π΅,π‘₯
ˆ
ΕΊ π‘œΛ‡
Zπœ†π‘₯𝑖𝑖 .
𝑖
We refer the reader to S5 for more details on the definition.
π‘œ
Λ‡ Ñ π·p𝒡 8¨π‘₯ q.
1.31. We will explain in S5 how geometric Satake produces a functor Repp𝐺q
Though this functor is not so complicated, giving its definition here would require further digressions, so we ask the reader to take this point on faith. Instead, for the purposes of an overview,
we refer to S1.33, where we explain what is going on when we restrict to divisors supported at the
point π‘₯, and certainly we refer to S5 where a detailed construction of this functor is given.
Example 1.31.1. The above functor sends the trivial representation to the ˚-extension of πœ“ π‘œ under
π‘œ
the natural embedding 𝒡 ãÑ
𝒡
π‘œ
𝒡 8¨π‘₯ .
We now obtain a functor:
π‘œ
π‘œ
πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯
˚,𝑑𝑅
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ‡ Ñ π·p𝒡 8¨π‘₯ q ÝÝÝÑ π·pDivΛ̌ ,8¨π‘₯ q.
Repp𝐺q
eff
For geometric reasons explained in S5, Theorem 4.6.1 allows us to upgrade this construction to
a functor:
fact
Λ‡
Chevgeom
ň,π‘₯ : Repp𝐺q Ñ Υň –mod𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
We now have the following compatibility between geometric Satake and Theorem 4.6.1.
Theorem (c.f. Theorem 5.14.1). The functor Chevgeom
is canonically identified with the functor
ň,π‘₯
Chevspec
,
which
by
definition
is
the
functor:
ň,π‘₯
Res
Res
Indπ‘β„Ž
Λ‡ ÝÝÑ Repp𝐡q
Λ‡ ÝÝÑ ň–modpRepp𝑇ˇqq ÝÝÝÑ Υň –modfact
Repp𝐺q
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
Here Indπ‘β„Ž is the chiral induction functor from Lie-* modules for ň b π‘˜π‘‹ to factorization modules
for Υň .
Remark 1.31.2. Here we remind the reader that chiral induction is introduced (abelian categorically) in [BD] S3.7.15. Like the chiral enveloping algebra operation used to define Υň , chiral induction
is again a kind of homological Chevalley complex.
Example 1.31.3. For the trivial representation, Example 1.31.1 reduces Theorem 5.14.1 to Theorem 4.6.1. Here, the claim is that Chevgeom
of the trivial representation is the 𝐷-module on
ň,π‘₯
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
𝐷pDivΛ̌
q obtained by pushforward from Υň along DivΛ̌
eff
eff
vacuum representation of Υň (at π‘₯).
15We remind that this means that πœ‡
Λ‡ 𝑖 P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  .
Λ‡ P Λ̌ and πœ†
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
ãÑ DivΛ̌
eff
, i.e., the so-called
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
1.32.
11
Our last main result is the following, which we leave vague here.
Theorem (c.f. Theorem 7.8.1). A generalization of Theorem 7.8.1 holds when we work factorizably
in the variable π‘₯, i.e., working at several points at once, allowing them to move and to collide.
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 “over 𝑋 𝐼 ” (i.e., with a
Somewhat more precisely, we define in S6 a DG category Repp𝐺q
𝑑𝑅
𝐼
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 .16
𝐷p𝑋 q-module category structure) encoding the symmetric monoidal structure on Repp𝐺q
Most of S6 is devoted to giving preliminary technical constructions that allow us to formulate
Theorem 7.8.1.
8
1.33. Interpretation in terms of Flπ‘₯2 . We now indicate briefly what e.g. Theorem 5.14.1 has to
8
do with Flπ‘₯2 . This section has nothing to do with the contents of the paper, and therefore can be
skipped; we include it only to make contact with our earlier motivation.
Fix a closed point π‘₯ P 𝑋, and consider the spherical Whittaker category Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
Ď 𝐷pGr𝐺,π‘₯ q,
π‘₯
which by definition is the Whittaker category (in the sense of S1.10) of 𝐷pGr𝐺,π‘₯ q. There is a
canonical object in this category (supported on Gr𝑁 ´ ,π‘₯ Ď Gr𝐺,π‘₯ ), and one can show (c.f. Theorem
6.36.1) that the resulting functor:
geometric Satake
Λ‡ ÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÑ Sph𝐺,π‘₯ Ñ Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
Repp𝐺q
π‘₯
is an equivalence, where Sph𝐺,π‘₯ :“ 𝐷pGr𝐺,π‘₯ q𝐺p𝑂qπ‘₯ is the spherical Hecke category, and the latter
functor is convolution with this preferred object of Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
π‘₯ .
8
8
Let 𝑖 2 ,! : 𝐷pFlπ‘₯2 q Ñ π·pGr𝑇,π‘₯ q denote the functor encoding !-restriction along:
8
8
𝑖 2 : Gr𝑇,π‘₯ “ 𝐡p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝑁 p𝐾π‘₯ q𝑇 p𝑂π‘₯ q ãÑ πΊp𝐾π‘₯ q{𝑁 p𝐾π‘₯ q𝑇 p𝑂π‘₯ q “ Flπ‘₯2 .
Consider the problem of computing the composite functor:
8
8 ,!
pullback
pushforward
𝑖2
Λ‡ » Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
Repp𝐺q
ÝÝÝÝÑ Whitp𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝐡p𝑂π‘₯ qq ÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÑ Whitπ‘₯2 ÝÝÑ π·pGr𝑇,π‘₯ q » Repp𝑇ˇq.
π‘₯ Ý
By base-change, this amounts to computing pullback-pushforward of Whittaker17 sheaves along the
correspondence:
𝐺p𝐾π‘₯ q{𝐡p𝑂π‘₯ q ˆ Gr𝑇,π‘₯
8
Gr𝐡,π‘₯
Flπ‘₯2
Gr𝐺,π‘₯
"
w
Gr𝑇,π‘₯ .
One can see this is exactly the picture obtained by restricting the problem of Theorem 5.14.1
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
to Gr𝑇,π‘₯ Ď Diveff
, and therefore we obtain an answer in terms of factorization Υň -modules.
Namely, this result says that the resulting functor:
Λ‡ Ñ Repp𝑇ˇq
Repp𝐺q
is computed as Lie algebra homology along ň.
16More precisely, the construction of Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 is a categorification of the construction of [BD] that associated a
factorization algebra with a usual commutative algebra.
17It is crucial here that our character be with respect to 𝑁 ´ , not 𝑁 .
12
SAM RASKIN
Remark 1.33.1. The point of upgrading Theorem 5.14.1 to Theorem 7.8.1 is to allow a picture of
this sort which is factorizable in terms of the point π‘₯, i.e., in which we replace the point π‘₯ P 𝑋 by
a variable point in 𝑋 𝐼 for some finite set 𝐼.
1.34. Methods. We now remark one what goes into the proofs of the above theorems.
1.35.
Our key computational tool is the following result.
Theorem (Limiting case of the Casselman-Shalika formula, c.f. Theorem 3.4.1). The pushforward
Λ‡
!
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
πœ†
πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅
pπœ“π’΅ b IC𝒡 q P 𝐷pDivΛ̌
eff q is the (one-dimensional) skyscraper sheaf at the zero divisor (concentrated in cohomological degree zero).
Λ‡
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  vanishes.
In particular, the restriction of this pushforward to each Divπœ†eff with 0 ‰ πœ†
We prove this using reasonably standard methods from the sheaf theory of Zastava spaces.
1.36. Our other major tool is the study of Υň given in [BG2], where Υň is connected to the
untwisted cohomologies of Zastava spaces (in a less derived framework than in Theorem 4.6.1).
1.37. Finally, we remark that the proofs of Theorems 3.4.1, 4.6.1, and 5.14.1 are elementary:
they use only standard perverse sheaf theory, and do not require the use of DG categories or
non-holonomic 𝐷-modules. (In particular, these theorems work in the β„“-adic setting, with the usual
Artin-Shreier sheaf replacing the exponential sheaf). The reader uncomfortable with higher category
theory should run into no difficulties here by replacing the words “DG category” by “triangulated
category” essentially everywhere (one exception: it is important that the definition of Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯
be understood higher categorically).
However, Theorem 7.8.1 is not elementary in this sense. This is the essential reason for the length
of S6: we are trying to construct an isomorphism of combinatorial nature in a higher categorical
setting, and this is essentially impossible except in particularly fortuitous circumstances. We show
in S6, S7 and Appendix B that the theory of ULA sheaves provides a usable method for this
particular problem.
1.38. Conventions. For the remainder of this introduction, we establish the conventions for the
remainder of the text.
1.39. We fix a field π‘˜ of characteristic zero throughout the paper. All schemes, etc, are understood
to be defined over π‘˜.
1.40. Lie theory. We fix the following notations from Lie theory.
Let 𝐺 be a split reductive group over π‘˜, let 𝐡 be a Borel subgroup of 𝐺 with unipotent radical
»
𝑁 and let 𝑇 be the Cartan 𝐡{𝑁 . Let 𝐡 ´ be a Borel opposite to 𝐡, i.e., 𝐡 ´ X 𝐡 Ý
Ñ π‘‡ . Let 𝑁 ´
denote the unipotent radical of 𝐡 ´ .
Λ‡ denote the corresponding Langlands dual group with corresponding Borel 𝐡,
Λ‡ who in turn
Let 𝐺
´
´
Λ‡ and torus 𝑇ˇ “ 𝐡{
Λ‡ 𝑁
Λ‡ , and similarly for 𝐡
Λ‡ and 𝑁
Λ‡ .
has unipotent radical 𝑁
´
´
´
´
Let g, b, n, t, b , n , ǧ, b̌, ň, ť, b̌ and ň denote the corresponding Lie algebras.
Let Λ denote the lattice of weights of 𝑇 and let Λ̌ denote the lattice of coweights. We let Λ and
Λ̌ denote the weights and coweights of 𝐺. We let Λ` (resp. Λ̌` ) denote the dominant weights (resp.
coweights), and let ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  denote the ZΔ›0 -span of the simple coroots.
Let ℐ𝐺 be the set of vertices in the Dynkin diagram of 𝐺. We recall that ℐ𝐺 is canonically
identified with the set of simple positive roots and coroots of 𝐺. For 𝑖 P ℐ𝐺 , we let 𝛼𝑖 P Λ (resp.
𝛼
Λ‡ 𝑖 P Λ̌) denote the corresponding root (resp. coroot).
Moreover, we fix a choice of Chevalley generators t𝑓𝑖 u𝑖PI𝐺 of n´ .
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
13
Finally, we use the notation 𝜌 P Λ for the half-sum of the positive roots of g, and similarly for
πœŒΛ‡ P Λ̌.
1.41.
For an algebraic group 𝛀 , let let B𝛀 denote the classifying stack Specpπ‘˜q{𝛀 for 𝛀 .
1.42. Let 𝑋 be a smooth projective curve.
We let Bun𝐺 denote the moduli stack of 𝐺-bundles on 𝑋. Recall that Bun𝐺 is a smooth Artin
stack locally of finite type (though not quasi-compact).
Similarly, we let Bun𝐡 , Bun𝑁 , and Bun𝑇 denote the corresponding moduli stacks of bundles on
𝑋. However, we note that we will abuse notation in dealing specifically with bundles of structure
group 𝑁 ´ : we will systematically incorporate a twist discussed in detail in S2.8.
1.43. Categorical remarks. The ultimate result in this paper, Theorem 7.8.1, is about computing
a certain factorization functor between factorization (DG) categories. This means that we need to
work in a higher categorical framework (c.f. [Lur1], [Lur3]) at this point.
We will impose some notations and conventions below regarding this framework. With that said,
the reader may read up to S5 essentially without ever worrying about higher categories.
1.44. We impose the convention that essentially everything is assumed derived. We will make this
more clear below, but first, we note the only exception: schemes can be understood as classical
schemes throughout the body of the paper, since we deal only with 𝐷-modules on them.
1.45. We find it convenient to assume higher category theory as the basic assumption in our
language. That is, we will understand “category” and “1-category” to mean “p8, 1q-category,”
“colimit” to (necessarily) mean “homotopy colimit,” “groupoid” to mean “8-groupoid” (aliases:
homotopy type, space, etc.), and so on. We use the phrase “set” interchangeably with “discrete
groupoid,” i.e., a groupoid whose higher homotopy groups at any basepoint vanish.
When we need to refer to the more traditional notion of category, we use the term p1, 1q-category.
As an example: we let Gpd denote the category (i.e., 8-category) of groupoids (i.e., 8-groupoids).
Remark 1.45.1. Unlike [Lur1] and [Lur3], our use of higher category theory is model independent.
1.46. DG categories. By DG category, we mean an (accessible) stable (8-)category enriched over
π‘˜-vector spaces.
We denote the category of DG categories under π‘˜-linear exact functors by DGCat and the category
of cocomplete18 DG categories under continuous19 π‘˜-linear functors by DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ .
We consider DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ as equipped with the symmetric monoidal structure b from [Lur3] S6.3.
For C, D P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ and for F P C and G P D, we let F b G denote the induced object of C b D,
since this notation is compatible with geometric settings.
For C a DG category equipped with a 𝑑-structure, we let CΔ›0 denote the subcategory of coconnective objects, and Cď0 the subcategory of connective objects (i.e., the notation is the standard
notation for the convention of cohomological grading). We let Cβ™‘ denote the heart of the 𝑑-structure.
We let Vect denote the DG category of π‘˜-vector spaces: this DG category has a 𝑑-structure with
heart Vectβ™‘ the abelian category of π‘˜-vector spaces.
We use the material of the short note [Gai3] freely, taking for granted the reader’s comfort with
the ideas of loc. cit.
18We actually mean presentable, which differs from cocomplete by a set-theoretic condition that will always be satisfied
for us throughout this text.
19There is some disagreement in the literature of the meaning of this word. By continuous functor, we mean a functor
commuting with filtered colimits. Similarly, by a cocomplete category, we mean one admitting all colimits.
14
SAM RASKIN
1.47. For a scheme 𝑆 locally of finite type, we let 𝐷p𝑆q denote its DG category of 𝐷-modules. For
a map 𝑓 : 𝑆 Ñ π‘‡ , we let 𝑓 ! : 𝐷p𝑇 q Ñ π·p𝑆q and π‘“Λš,𝑑𝑅 : 𝐷p𝑆q Ñ π·p𝑇 q denote the corresponding
functors.
We always equip 𝐷p𝑆q with the perverse 𝑑-structure,20 i.e., the one for which IC𝑆 lies in the heart
of the 𝑑-structure. In particular, if 𝑆 is smooth of dimension 𝑑, then the dualizing sheaf πœ”π‘† lies in
degree ´π‘‘ and the constant sheaf π‘˜π‘† lies in degree 𝑑. We sometimes refer to objects in the heart of
this 𝑑-structure as perverse sheaves (especially if the object is holonomic), hoping this will not cause
any confusion (since we do not assume π‘˜ “ C, we are in no position to apply the Riemann-Hilbert
correspondence).
1.48.
Finally, we use the notation Oblv throughout for various forgetful functors.
1.49. Acknowledgements. We warmly thank Dennis Gaitsgory for suggesting this project to us,
and for his continuous support throughout its development. I have tried to acknowledge his specific
ideas throughout the paper, but in truth, his influence on me and on this project runs more deeply
than that.
We further thank Dima Arinkin, Sasha Beilinson, David Ben-Zvi, Dario Beraldo, Roman Bezrukavnikov,
Sasha Braverman, Vladimir Drinfeld, Sergey Lysenko, Ivan Mirkovic, Nick Rozenblyum, and Simon
Schieder for their interest in this work and their influence upon it.
Within our gratitude, we especially single out our thanks to Dario Beraldo for conversations that
significantly shaped S6.
We thank MSRI for hosting us while this paper was in preparation.
This material is based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation under Award
No. 1402003.
2. Review of Zastava spaces
2.1. In this section, we review the geometry of Zastava spaces, introduced in [FM] and [BFGM].
Note that this section plays a purely expository role; our only hope is that by emphasizing
the role of local Zastava stacks, some of the basic geometry becomes more transparent than other
treatments.
2.2. Remarks on 𝐺. For simplicity, we assume throughout this section that 𝐺 has a simplyconnected derived group.
However, [ABB` ] S4.1 (c.f. also [Sch] S7) explains how to remove this hypothesis, and the basic
geometry of Zastava spaces and Drinfeld compactifications remains exactly the same. The reader
may therefore either assume 𝐺 has simply-connected derived group for the rest of this text, or may
refer to [Sch] for how to remove this hypothesis (we note that this applies just as well for citations
to [BG1], [BG2], and [BFGM]).
2.3. The basic affine space. Recall that the map:
𝐺{𝑁 Ñ πΊ{𝑁 :“ Specp𝐻 0 pΓp𝐺{𝑁, O𝐺{𝑁 qqq “ SpecpFunp𝐺q𝑁 q
is an open embedding. We call 𝐺{𝑁 the basic affine space 𝐺{𝑁 the affine closure of the basic affine
space.
The following result is direct from the Peter-Weyl theorem.
20Alias: the right (as opposed to left) 𝑑-structure. C.f. [BD] and [GR].
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
15
Lemma 2.3.1. For 𝑆 an affine test scheme,21 a map πœ™ : 𝑆 Ñ πΊ{𝑁 with πœ™´1 p𝐺{𝑁 q dense in 𝑆 is
equivalent to a “Drinfeld structure” on the trivial 𝐺-bundle 𝐺 ˆ 𝑆 Ñ π‘†, i.e., a sequence of maps
for πœ† P Λ` .
𝜎 πœ† : β„“πœ† b O𝑆 Ñ π‘‰ πœ† b O𝑆
π‘˜
π‘˜
are monomorphisms of quasi-coherent sheaves and satisfy the Plücker relations.
Remark 2.3.2. By dense, we mean scheme-theoretically, not topologically (e.g., for Noetherian 𝑆,
the difference here is only apparent in the presence of associated points).
Example 2.3.3. For 𝐺 “ SL2 , 𝐺{𝑁 identifies equivariantly with A2 . The corresponding map SL2 Ñ
A2 here is given by:
ˆ
Λ™
π‘Ž 𝑏
ÞÑ pπ‘Ž, 𝑐q P A2 .
𝑐 𝑑
2.4.
Let 𝑇 be the closure of 𝑇 “ 𝐡{𝑁 Ď 𝐺{𝑁 in 𝐺{𝑁 .
Lemma 2.4.1.
(1) 𝑇 is the toric variety Specpπ‘˜rΛ` sq (here π‘˜rΛ` s is the monoid algebra defined
by the monoid Λ` ). Here the map 𝑇 “ Specpπ‘˜rΛsq Ñ π‘‡ corresponds to the embedding
Λ` Ñ Λ and the map Funp𝐺q𝑁 Ñ π‘˜rΛ` s realizes the latter as 𝑁 -coinvariants of the former.
(2) The action of 𝑇 on 𝐺{𝑁 extends to an action of the monoid 𝑇 on 𝐺{𝑁 (where the coalgebra
structure on Funp𝑇 q “ π‘˜rΛ` s is the canonical one, that is, defined by the diagonal map for
the monoid Λ` ).
Here (1) follows again from the Peter-Weyl theorem and (2) follows similarly, noting that 𝑉 πœ† b
Ď Funp𝐺q𝑁 “ Funp𝐺{𝑁 q has Λ-grading (relative to the right action of 𝑇 on 𝐺{𝑁 ) equal to
πœ† P Λ` .
β„“πœ†,_
2.5. Note that (after the choice of opposite Borel) 𝑇 is canonically a retract of 𝐺{𝑁 , i.e., the
embedding 𝑇 ãÑ πΊ{𝑁 admits a canonical splitting:
𝐺{𝑁 Ñ π‘‡ .
(2.5.1)
`
𝑁
Indeed, the retract corresponds to the map π‘˜rΛ s Ñ Funp𝐺q sending πœ† to the canonical element
in:
β„“πœ† b β„“πœ†,_ Ď 𝑉 πœ† b 𝑉 πœ†,_ Ď Funp𝐺q
(note that the embedding β„“πœ†,_ ãÑ π‘‰ πœ†,_ uses the opposite Borel).
By construction, this map factors as 𝐺{𝑁 Ñ π‘ ´ zp𝐺{𝑁 q Ñ π‘‡ .
Let 𝑇 act on 𝐺{𝑁 through the action induced by the adjoint action of 𝑇 on 𝐺. Choosing a
regular dominant coweight πœ†0 P Λ̌` we obtain a Gπ‘š -action on 𝐺{𝑁 that contracts22 onto 𝑇 . The
induced map 𝐺{𝑁 Ñ π‘‡ coincides with the one constructed above.
Warning 2.5.1. The induced map 𝐺{𝑁 Ñ π‘‡ does not factor through 𝑇 . The inverse image in 𝐺{𝑁
of 𝑇 Ď 𝑇 is the open Bruhat cell 𝐡 ´ 𝑁 {𝑁 .
21It is important here that 𝑆 is a classical scheme, i.e., not DG.
22We recall that a contracting G -action on an algebraic stack 𝒴 is an action of the multiplicative monoid A1 on 𝒴.
π‘š
For schemes, this is a property of the underlying Gπ‘š action, but for stacks it is not. Therefore, by the phrase “that
contracts,” we rather mean that it canonically admits the structure of contracting Gπ‘š -action. See [DG] for further
discussion of these points.
16
SAM RASKIN
2.6.
Define the stack B𝐡 as 𝐺z𝐺{𝑁 {𝑇 . Note that B𝐡 has canonical maps to B𝐺 and B𝑇 .
π‘œ
2.7. Local Zastava stacks. Let 𝜁 denote the stack 𝐡 ´ z𝐺{𝐡 “ B𝐡 ´ ˆB𝐺 B𝐡 and and let 𝜁 denote
the stack 𝐡 ´ zp𝐺{𝑁 q{𝑇 “ B𝐡 ´ ˆB𝐺 B𝐡. We have the sequence of open embeddings:
π‘œ
B𝑇 ãÑ πœ ãÑ πœ
where B𝑇 embeds as the open Bruhat cell.
The map B𝑇 ãÑ πœ factors as:
B𝑇 “ 𝑇 zp𝑇 {𝑇 q ãÑ π‘‡ zp𝑇 {𝑇 q “ B𝑇 ˆ 𝑇 {𝑇 ãÑ πœ.
(2.7.1)
𝐡´
ˆ 𝑇 -equivariant, where
One immediately verifies that the retraction 𝐺{𝑁 Ñ π‘‡ of (2.5.1) is
acts on the left on 𝐺{𝑁 and 𝑇 acts on the right, and the action on 𝑇 is similar but is induced
by the 𝑇 ˆ 𝑇 -action and the homomorphism 𝐡 ´ ˆ 𝑇 Ñ π‘‡ ˆ 𝑇 . Therefore, we obtain a canonical
map:
𝐡´
𝜁 “ 𝐡 ´ z𝐺{𝑁 {𝑇 Ñ π΅ ´ z𝑇 {𝑇 Ñ π‘‡ z𝑇 {𝑇.
Moreover, up to the choice of πœ†0 from loc. cit. this retraction realizes B𝑇 ˆ 𝑇 {𝑇 as a “deformation
retract” of 𝜁.
We will identify 𝑇 z𝑇 {𝑇 with B𝑇 ˆ 𝑇 {𝑇 in what follows by writing the former as 𝑇 zp𝑇 {𝑇 q and
noting that 𝑇 acts trivially here on 𝑇 {𝑇 .
In particular, we obtain a canonical map:
𝜁 Ñ π‘‡ {𝑇.
(2.7.2)
π‘Ÿ
By Lemma 2.4.1 (2) we have an action of the monoid stack 𝑇 {𝑇 on 𝜁. The morphism 𝜁 Ñ
Ý
𝑝2
B𝑇 ˆ 𝑇 {𝑇 ÝÑ π‘‡ {𝑇 is 𝑇 {𝑇 -equivariant.
Lemma 2.7.1. A map πœ™ : 𝑆 Ñ π‘‡ {𝑇 with πœ™´1 pSpecpπ‘˜qq dense (where Specpπ‘˜q is realized as the
open point 𝑇 {𝑇 ) is canonically equivalent to a ΛΜŒπ‘›π‘’π‘” :“ ´ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -valued Cartier divisor on 𝑆.
First, we recall the following standard result.
Lemma 2.7.2. A map 𝑆 Ñ Gπ‘š zA1 with inverse image of the open point dense is equivalent to the
data of an effective Cartier divisor on 𝑆.
Proof. Tautologically, a map 𝑆 Ñ Gπ‘š zA1 is equivalent to a line bundle L on 𝑆 with a section
𝑠 P Γp𝑆, Lq.
𝑠
We need to check that the morphism O𝑆 Ñ
Ý L is a monomorphism of quasi-coherent sheaves
under the density hypothesis. This is a local statement, so we can trivialize L. Now 𝑠 is a function
𝑓 whose locus of non-vanishing is dense, and it is easy to see that this is equivalent to 𝑓 being a
non-zero divisor.
Proof of Lemma 2.7.1. Let 𝐺1 Ď 𝐺 denote the derived subgroup r𝐺, 𝐺s of 𝐺 and let 𝑇 1 “ 𝑇 X 𝐺1
1
and 𝑁 1 “ 𝑁 X 𝐺1 . Then with 𝑇 defined as the closure of 𝑇 1 in the affine closure of 𝐺1 {𝑁 1 , the
induced map:
1
𝑇 {𝑇 1 Ñ π‘‡ {𝑇
is an isomorphism, reducing to the case 𝐺 “ 𝐺1 .
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
17
Because the derived group (assumed to be equal to 𝐺 now) is assumed
we
Ε› simply-connected,
Ε›
`
have have canonical fundamental weights tπœ—π‘– u𝑖Pℐ𝐺 , πœ—π‘– P Λ . The map 𝑖Pℐ𝐺 πœ—π‘– : 𝑇 Ñ π‘–Pℐ𝐺 Gπ‘š
Ε›
extends to a map 𝑇 Ñ π‘–Pℐ𝐺 A1 inducing an isomorphism:
»
𝑇 {𝑇 Ý
Ñ pA1 {Gπ‘š qℐ𝐺 .
Because we use the right action of 𝑇 on 𝑇 , the functions on 𝑇 are graded negatively, and therefore
we obtain the desired result.
2.8. Twists. Fix an irreducible smooth projective curve 𝑋. We digress for a minute to normalize
certain twists.
Let Ω𝑋 denote the sheaf of differentials on 𝑋. For an integer 𝑛, we will sometimes use the
notation Ω𝑛𝑋 for Ωb𝑛
𝑋 , there being no risk for confusion with 𝑛-forms because 𝑋 is a curve.
1
2
a square root of Ω𝑋 . This choice extends the definition of Ω𝑛𝑋 to 𝑛 P 12 Z. We obtain
We fix Ω𝑋
the 𝑇 -bundle:
´1
π’«π‘‡π‘π‘Žπ‘› :“ πœŒΛ‡pΩ´1
𝜌pΩ𝑋 2 q.
𝑋 q :“ 2Λ‡
(2.8.1)
We use the following notation:
Bun𝑁 ´ :“ Bun𝐡 ´ ˆ tπ’«π‘‡π‘π‘Žπ‘› u
Bun𝑇
:“ BunGπ‘š Λ™Gπ‘Ž
BunG´
π‘Ž
´1
ˆ tΩ𝑋 2 u.
BunGπ‘š
Here Gπ‘š Λ™ Gπ‘Ž is the “negative” Borel of PGL2 .
1
´1
2
and therefore there is a canonical map:
Note that BunG´
classifies extensions of Ω𝑋 2 by Ω𝑋
π‘Ž
canG´
: BunG´
Ñ π» 1 p𝑋, Ω𝑋 q “ Gπ‘Ž .
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
The choice of Chevalley generators t𝑓𝑖 u𝑖Pℐ𝐺 of n´ defines a map:
𝐡 ´ {r𝑁 ´ , 𝑁 ´ s Ñ
ΕΊ
pGπ‘š Λ™ Gπ‘Ž q.
𝑖Pℐ𝐺
By definition of π’«π‘‡π‘π‘Žπ‘› , this induces a map:
ΕΊ
r𝑖 : Bun𝑁 ´ Ñ
𝑖Pℐ𝐺
ΕΊ
BunG´
.
π‘Ž
𝑖Pℐ𝐺
We form the sequence:
Ε›
Bun𝑁 ´ Ñ
ΕΊ
𝑖Pℐ𝐺
canG´
π‘Ž
BunG´
ÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÑ
π‘Ž
𝑖Pℐ𝐺
ΕΊ
Gπ‘Ž Ñ Gπ‘Ž
𝑖Pℐ𝐺
and denote the composition by:
can : Bun𝑁 ´ Ñ Gπ‘Ž .
(2.8.2)
18
SAM RASKIN
2.9. For a pointed stack p𝒴, 𝑦 P 𝒴pπ‘˜qq and a test scheme 𝑆, we say that 𝑋 ˆ 𝑆 Ñ π’΄ is nondegenerate if there exists π‘ˆ Ď 𝑋 ˆ 𝑆 universally schematically dense relative to 𝑆 in the sense
of [GAB` ] Exp. XVIII, and such that the induced map π‘ˆ Ñ π’΄ admits a factorization as π‘ˆ Ñ
𝑦
Specpπ‘˜q Ý
Ñ π’΄ (so this is a property for a map, not a structure). We let Mapsπ‘›π‘œπ‘›´π‘‘𝑒𝑔𝑒𝑛. p𝑋, 𝒴q denote
the open substack of Mapsp𝑋, 𝒴q consisting of non-degenerate maps 𝑋 Ñ π’΄.
π‘œ
We consider 𝜁, 𝜁, and 𝑇 {𝑇 as openly pointed stacks in the obvious ways.
2.10. Zastava spaces. Observe that there is a canonical map:
𝜁 Ñ B𝑇
(2.10.1)
given as the composition:
𝜁 “ B𝐡 ´ ˆ B𝐡 Ñ B𝐡 ´ Ñ B𝑇.
B𝐺
Let 𝒡 be the stack of π’«π‘‡π‘π‘Žπ‘› -twisted non-degenerate maps 𝑋 Ñ πœ, i.e., the fiber product:
Mapsπ‘›π‘œπ‘›´π‘‘𝑒𝑔𝑒𝑛. p𝑋, 𝜁q ˆ tπ’«π‘‡π‘π‘Žπ‘› u
Bun𝑇
where the map Mapsπ‘›π‘œπ‘›´π‘‘𝑒𝑔𝑒𝑛. p𝑋, 𝜁q Ñ Bun𝑇 is given by (2.10.1).
π‘œ
π‘œ
π‘œ
Let 𝒡 Ď 𝒡 be the open substack of π’«π‘‡π‘π‘Žπ‘› -twisted non-degenerate maps 𝑋 Ñ πœ. Note that 𝒡 and
π‘œ
π‘œ
𝒡 lie in Sch Ď PreStk. We call 𝒡 the Zastava space and 𝒡 the open Zastava space. We let πš₯ : 𝒡 Ñ π’΅
denote the corresponding open embedding.
We have a Cartesian square where all maps are open embeddings:
𝒡
π‘œ
/𝒡
/ Bun ´ ˆ Bun𝐡
𝑁
Bun𝑁 ´ ˆ Bun𝐡
Bun𝐺
Bun𝐺
The horizontal arrows realize the source as the subscheme of the target where the two reductions
are generically transverse.
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
“ Mapsπ‘›π‘œπ‘›´π‘‘𝑒𝑔𝑒𝑛. p𝑋, 𝑇 {𝑇 q denote the scheme of ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -divisors on 𝑋 (we include
2.11. Let DivΛ̌
eff
the subscript “eff” for emphasis that we are not taking Λ̌-valued divisors).
We have the canonical map:
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
deg : πœ‹0 pDivΛ̌
.
eff q Ñ Λ̌
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  let Divπœ†Λ‡ denote the corresponding connected component of DivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  .
For πœ†
eff
eff
Ε™
Λ‡
Λ‡“
Remark 2.11.1. Writing πœ†
Λ‡ 𝑖 as a sum of simple coroots, we see that Divπœ†eff is a product
𝑖Pℐ𝐺 𝑛𝑖 𝛼
Ε›
𝑛𝑖
𝑖Pℐ𝐺 Sym 𝑋 of the corresponding symmetric powers of the curve.
Recall that we have the canonical map π‘Ÿ : 𝜁 Ñ B𝑇 ˆ 𝑇 {𝑇 . For any non-degenerate map 𝑋 ˆ 𝑆 Ñ
𝜁, Warning 2.5.1 implies that the induced map to 𝑇 {𝑇 (given by composing π‘Ÿ with the second
projection) is non-degenerate as well.
Therefore we obtain the map:
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
πœ‹ : 𝒡 Ñ DivΛ̌
eff
19
.
π‘œ
π‘œ
We let πœ‹ denote the restriction of πœ‹ to 𝒡. It is well-known that the morphism πœ‹ is affine.
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
π‘œ
Λ‡
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
Let 𝒡 πœ† (resp. 𝒡 πœ† ) denote the fiber of 𝒡 (resp. 𝒡) over Divπœ†eff . We let πœ‹ πœ† (resp. πœ‹ πœ† ) denote the
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
restriction of πœ‹ to 𝒡 πœ† (resp. 𝒡 πœ† ). We let πš₯πœ† : 𝒡 πœ† Ñ π’΅ πœ† denote the restriction of the open embedding
πš₯.
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ‡
Ñ π’΅, whose restriction to each Divπœ†eff we
Note that πœ‹ admits a canonical section s : DivΛ̌
eff
Λ‡
denote by sπœ† . Note that up to a choice of regular dominant coweight, the situation is given by
contraction.
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
Each 𝒡 πœ† is of finite type (and therefore the same holds for 𝒡 πœ† ). It is known (c.f. [BFGM] Corollary
π‘œΛ‡
3.8) that 𝒡 πœ† is a smooth variety.
π‘œ
Λ‡ “ 0, we have 𝒡 0 “ 𝒡 0 “ Div0 “ Specpπ‘˜q.
For πœ†
eff
We have a canonical (up to choice of Chevalley generators) map 𝒡 Ñ Gπ‘Ž defined as the compocan
sition 𝒡 Ñ Bun𝑁 ´ ÝÝÑ Gπ‘Ž . For 𝛼
Λ‡ 𝑖 a positive simple coroot the induced map:
ˇ𝑖
ˆGπ‘Ž “ 𝑋 ˆ Gπ‘Ž
𝒡 𝛼ˇ 𝑖 Ñ Div𝛼eff
(2.11.1)
π‘œ
is an isomorphism that identifies 𝒡 𝛼ˇ 𝑖 with 𝑋 ˆ Gπ‘š .
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡ “ p𝜌, πœ†q`dim
Λ‡
The dimension of 𝒡 πœ† and 𝒡 πœ† is p2𝜌, πœ†q
Divπœ†eff (this follows e.g. from the factorization
property discussed in S2.12 below and then by the realization discussed in S2.13 of the central fiber
as an intersection of semi-infinite orbits in the Grassmannian, that are known by [BFGM] S6 to be
Λ‡
equidimensional with dimension p𝜌, πœ†q).
Example 2.11.2. Let us explain in more detail the case of 𝐺 “ SL2 . In this case, tensoring with the
1
2
bundle Ω𝑋
identifies 𝒡 with the moduli of commutative diagrams:
L
πœ™
!
/E
1
0
/ Ω2
𝑋
πœ™_
1
/ Ω´ 2
𝑋
/0
L_
π‘œ
in which the composition L Ñ L_ is zero and the morphism πœ™ is non-zero. The open subscheme 𝒡
is the locus where the induced map CokerpL Ñ Eq Ñ L_ is an isomorphism. The associated divisor
´1
of such a datum is defined by the injection L ãÑ β„¦π‘‹ 2 .
π‘œ
π‘œ
Over a point π‘₯ P 𝑋, we have an identification of the fiber 𝒡 1π‘₯ of 𝒡 1 over π‘₯ P 𝑋 (considering
1 P Z “ Λ̌SL2 as the unique positive simple coroot) with Gπ‘š . Up to the twist by our square root
1
2
Ω𝑋
, the point 1 P Gπ‘š corresponds to a canonical extension of O𝑋 by Ω𝑋 associated to the point
π‘₯, that can be constructed explicitly using the Atiyah sequence of the line bundle O𝑋 pπ‘₯q.
Recall that for a vector bundle E, the Atiyah sequence (c.f. [Ati]) is a canonical short exact
sequence:
20
SAM RASKIN
0 Ñ EndpEq Ñ AtpEq Ñ π‘‡π‘‹ Ñ 0
whose splittings correspond to connections on E. For a line bundle L, we obtain a canonical extension
AtpLq b Ω1𝑋 of O𝑋 by Ω1𝑋 . Taking L “ O𝑋 pπ‘₯q, we obtain the extension underlying the canonical
π‘œ
point of 𝒡 1π‘₯ .
Note that we have a canonical map L “ O𝑋 pπ‘₯q Ñ AtpO𝑋 pπ‘₯qq b Ω1𝑋 that may be thought of
as a splitting of the Atiyah sequence with a pole of order 1, and this splitting corresponds to the
π‘œ
obvious connection on O𝑋 pπ‘₯q with a pole of order 1. This defines the corresponding point of 𝒡 1
completely.
2.12. Factorization. Now we recall the crucial factorization property of 𝒡.
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
ˆ Diveff
Ñ DivΛ̌
denote the addition map for the commutative monoid
Let add : Diveff
eff
Λ‡
Λ‡ and πœ‡
structure defined by addition of divisors. For πœ†
Λ‡ fixed, we let addπœ†,Λ‡πœ‡ denote the induced map
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ‡
Ñ Divπœ†`Λ‡
Divπœ†eff ˆ Divπœ‡eff
eff .
Define:
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌
rDiveff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌
ˆ DivΛ̌
eff s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 Ď Diveff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
ˆ DivΛ̌
eff
as the moduli of pairs of disjoint ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -divisors. Note that the restriction of add to this locus is étale.
Then we have canonical “factorization” isomorphisms:
𝒡
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
ˆ
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
DivΛ̌
eff
rDivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
»
Λ̌
Ñ p𝒡 ˆ 𝒡q
ˆ Diveff
s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 Ý
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
DivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
ˆ
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
ˆ DivΛ̌
eff
rDivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
ˆ DivΛ̌
eff s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
that are associative in the natural sense.
The morphisms πœ‹ and s are compatible with the factorization structure.
Λ‡
Λ‡
2.13. The central fiber. By definition, the central fiber Zπœ† of the Zastava space 𝒡 πœ† is the fiber
product:
Λ‡
Λ‡
Zπœ† :“ 𝒡 πœ† ˆ 𝑋
Λ‡
Divπœ†
eff
Λ‡
where 𝑋 Ñ Divπœ†eff is the closed “diagonal” embedding, i.e., it is the closed subscheme where the
π‘œΛ‡
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
divisor is concentrated at a single point. We let Zπœ† denote the open in Zπœ† corresponding to 𝒡 πœ† ãÑ π’΅ πœ† .
Λ‡
Similarly, we let Z Ď 𝒡 be the closed corresponding to the union of the Zπœ† .
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
π‘œΛ‡
We let 𝛽 πœ† (resp. 7πœ† ) denote the closed embedding Zπœ† ãÑ π’΅ πœ† (resp. Zπœ† ãÑ π’΅ πœ† ).
π‘π‘Žπ‘› , 𝒫 π‘π‘Žπ‘› and 𝒫 π‘π‘Žπ‘› be the torsors induced by the
2.14. Twisted affine Grassmannian. Let 𝒫𝐺
𝐡
𝐡´
π‘π‘Žπ‘›
𝑇 -torsor 𝒫𝑇 under the embeddings of 𝑇 into each of these groups.
π‘π‘Žπ‘› -twisted Beilinson-Drinfeld affine Grassmannian” classifying a
We let Gr𝐺,𝑋 denote the “𝒫𝐺
π‘π‘Žπ‘› |
point π‘₯ P 𝑋, a 𝐺-bundle 𝒫𝐺 on 𝑋, and an isomorphism 𝒫𝐺
𝑋zπ‘₯ » 𝒫𝐺 |𝑋zπ‘₯ . More precisely, the
𝑆-points are:
#
+
π‘₯ : 𝑆 Ñ π‘‹, 𝒫𝐺 a 𝐺-bundle on 𝑋 ˆ 𝑆,
.
𝑆 ÞÑ
π‘π‘Žπ‘› |
𝛼 an isomorphism 𝒫𝐺 |𝑋ˆπ‘†zΓπ‘₯ » 𝒫𝐺
𝑋ˆπ‘†zΓπ‘₯
Similarly for Gr𝐡,𝑋 , etc. We define Gr𝑁 ´ ,𝑋 :“ Gr𝐡 ´ ,𝑋 ˆGr𝑇,𝑋 𝑋, where the map 𝑋 Ñ Gr𝑇,𝑋
being the tautological section.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
21
Let Gr𝐡,𝑋 denote the “union of closures of semi-infinite orbits,” i.e., the indscheme:
#
Gr𝐡,𝑋 : 𝑆 ÞÑ
π‘₯ : 𝑆 Ñ π‘‹, πœ™ : 𝑋 ˆ 𝑆 Ñ πΊzp𝐺{𝑁 q{𝑇 ,
𝛼 a factorization of πœ™|p𝑋ˆπ‘†qzΓπ‘₯ through the
canonical map Specpπ‘˜q Ñ πΊzp𝐺{𝑁 q{𝑇 .
+
.
Here Γπ‘₯ denotes the graph of the map π‘₯.
2.15.
In the above notation, we have a canonical isomorphism:
»
ZÝ
Ñ Gr𝑁 ´ ,𝑋
ˆ Gr𝐡,𝑋 .
Gr𝐺,𝑋
Indeed, this is immediate from the definitions.
š
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†
πœ†
Note that Gr𝐡,𝑋 has a canonical map to Gr𝑇,𝑋 “ πœ†P
Λ‡ Λ̌ Gr𝑇,𝑋 . Letting Gr𝐡,𝑋 be the fiber over
the corresponding connected component of Gr𝑇,𝑋 , we obtain:
Λ‡ »
Zπœ† Ý
Ñ Gr𝑁 ´ ,𝑋
Λ‡
πœ†
ˆ Gr𝐡,𝑋 .
Gr𝐺,𝑋
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
2.16. By S2.7, we have an action of DivΛ̌
on 𝒡 so that the morphism πœ‹ is DivΛ̌
eff
eff -equivariant.
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌
We let act𝒡 denote the action map Diveff ˆπ’΅ Ñ π’΅. We abuse notation in denoting the induced
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
map DivΛ̌
eff
π‘œ
π‘œ
ˆπ’΅ Ñ π’΅ by act π‘œ (that does not define an action on 𝒡, i.e., this map does not factor
𝒡
π‘œ
through 𝒡).
Λ‡ P Λ̌ acting on 𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ defines the map:
For πœ†
Λ‡
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
actπœ†π’΅ : DivΛ̌
eff
Λ‡
ˆπ’΅ πœ† Ñ π’΅.
Λ‡
Λ‡,πœ†
For πœ‚Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  we use the notation actπœ‚π’΅
for the induced map:
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡,πœ†
ˆπ’΅ πœ† Ñ π’΅ πœ†`Λ‡πœ‚ .
: Divπœ‚eff
actπœ‚π’΅
Λ‡
Λ‡
𝒡
𝒡
πœ‚
Similarly, we have the maps actπœ†π‘œ and actπœ†,Λ‡
π‘œ .
The following lemma is well-known (see e.g. [BFGM]).
Λ‡πœ‚
Λ‡πœ‚
πœ†,Λ‡
Λ‡ πœ‚Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  , the actπœ†,Λ‡
Lemma 2.16.1. For every πœ†,
𝒡 is finite morphism and the map act π‘œ is a locally
Λ‡ the set of locally closed subschemes of 𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ :
closed embedding. For fixed πœ†
𝒡
π‘œ
Λ‡
tactπœ‚Λ‡π‘œ,Λ‡πœ‡ pDivπœ‚eff
ˆπ’΅ πœ‡Λ‡ qu πœ‡Λ‡`Λ‡πœ‚“πœ†Λ‡
𝒡
πœ‡,Λ‡
Λ‡ πœ‚ PΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
forms a stratification.
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  we now review the description from
2.17. Intersection cohomology of Zastava. For πœ†
[BFGM] of the fibers of the intersection cohomology 𝐷-module IC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ along the strata described
above, i.e., the 𝐷-modules:
π‘œ
Λ‡
Λ‡
actπœ‚Λ‡π‘œ,Λ‡πœ‡,! pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ q P 𝐷pDivπœ‚eff
ˆπ’΅ πœ‡Λ‡ q, πœ‚Λ‡, πœ‡
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  , πœ‡
Λ‡ ` πœ‚Λ‡ “ πœ†.
𝒡
22
SAM RASKIN
Theorem 2.17.1.
(1) With notation as above, the regular holonomic 𝐷-module:
π‘œ
Λ‡
actπœ‚Λ‡π‘œ,Λ‡πœ‡,! pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ q P 𝐷pDivπœ‚eff
ˆπ’΅ πœ‡Λ‡ q
(2.17.1)
𝒡
π‘œ
is concentrated in constructible cohomological degree ´ dim 𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ .
π‘œ
(2) For π‘₯ P 𝑋 a point, the further ˚-restriction of (2.17.1) to Zπœ‡π‘₯Λ‡ is a lisse sheaf in constructible
π‘œ
degree ´ dim 𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ isomorphic to:
π‘œ
π‘ˆ pňqpΛ‡
πœ‚ q b π‘˜ π‘œ πœ‡Λ‡ rdim 𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ s
Zπ‘₯
where π‘ˆ pňqpΛ‡
πœ‚ q indicates the πœ‚Λ‡-weight space.
π‘œ
(3) The !-restriction of (2.17.1) to 𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ is a sum of sheaves:
π‘œ
‘
partitions πœ‚Λ‡“
Ε™π‘Ÿ
𝑗“1
𝛼
ˇ𝑗
π‘˜ π‘œ πœ‡Λ‡ r´π‘Ÿ ` dim 𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ s
(2.17.2)
Zπ‘₯
𝛼
Λ‡ 𝑗 a positive coroot
π‘œ
Remark 2.17.2. Recall from the above that, 𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ is equidimensional with dim 𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ “ 2p𝜌, πœ‡
Λ‡q.
Remark 2.17.3. For clarity, in (2.17.2) we sum over all partitions of πœ‚Λ‡ as a sum of positive coroots
(where two partitions are the same if the multiplicity of each coroot is the same). We emphasize
that the 𝛼
Λ‡ 𝑗 are not assumed to be simple coroots, so the total number of summands is given by
the Kostant partition function.
Remark 2.17.4. This theorem is a combination of Theorem 4.5 and Lemma 4.3 of [BFGM] using
the inductive procedure of loc. cit.
1
2
, we obtain an iden2.18. Locality. For 𝑋 a smooth (possibly affine) curve with choice of Ω𝑋
tical geometric picture. One can either realize this by restriction from a compactification, or by
reinterpreting e.g. the map 𝒡 Ñ Gπ‘Ž through residues instead of through global cohomology.
3. Limiting case of the Casselman-Shalika formula
3.1. The goal for this section is to prove Theorem 3.4.1, on the vanishing of the IC-Whittaker
cohomology groups of Zastava spaces. This vanishing will play a central role in the remainder of
the paper.
Remark 3.1.1. The method of proof is essentially by a reduction to the geometric Casselman-Shalika
formula of [FGV].
Remark 3.1.2. We are grateful to Dennis Gaitsgory for suggesting this result to us.
3.2. Artin-Schreier sheaves. We define the !-Artin-Schreier 𝐷-module πœ“ P 𝐷pGπ‘Ž q to be the
exponential local system normalized cohomologically so that πœ“r´1s P 𝐷pGπ‘Ž qβ™‘ . Note that πœ“ is
multiplicative with respect to !-pullback.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
23
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  , let πœ“ πœ†Λ‡ P 𝐷p𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ q denote the !-pullback of the Artin-Schreier 𝐷-module πœ“ along
3.3. For πœ†
𝒡
the composition:
Λ‡
can
𝒡 πœ† Ñ Bun𝑁 ´ ÝÝÑ Gπ‘Ž .
!
Λ‡
Note that πœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ b IC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ P 𝐷p𝒡 πœ† qβ™‘ .
We then also define:
Λ‡
πœ“ π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ “ πš₯πœ†,! pπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q.
𝒡
3.4.
The main result of this section is the following:
Λ‡ ‰ 0, then:
Theorem 3.4.1. If πœ†
!
Λ‡
πœ†
πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅
pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ bπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q “ 0.
The proof will be given in S3.6 below.
This theorem is étale local on 𝑋, and therefore we may assume that we have 𝑋 “ A1 . In
1
2
particular, we have a fixed trivialization of Ω𝑋
.
3.5. Central fibers via affine Schubert varieties. In the proof of Theorem 3.4.1 we will use
Proposition 3.5.1 below. We note that it is well-known, though we do not know a published reference.
Throughout S3.5, we work only with reduced schemes and indschemes, so all symbols refer to
the reduced indscheme underlying the corresponding indscheme. Note that this restriction does not
affect 𝐷-modules on the corresponding spaces.
Let 𝑇 p𝐾q𝑋 denote the group indscheme over 𝑋 of meromorphic jets into 𝑇 (so the fiber of
𝑇 p𝐾q𝑋 at π‘₯ P 𝑋 is the loop group 𝑇 p𝐾π‘₯ q). Because we have chosen an identification 𝑋 » A1 , we
have a canonical homomorphism:
Gr𝑇,𝑋 » A1 ˆ Λ̌ Ñ π‘‡ p𝐾q𝑋 » A1 ˆ 𝑇 p𝐾q
Λ‡ ÞÑ pπ‘₯, πœ†p𝑑qq
Λ‡
pπ‘₯, πœ†q
where 𝑑 is the uniformizer of A1 (of course, the formula Gr𝑇,𝑋 » A1 ˆ Λ̌ is only valid at the
reduced level). This induces an action of the 𝑋-group indscheme Gr𝑇,𝑋 on Gr𝐡,𝑋 , Gr𝐺,𝑋 and
Gr𝑁 ´ ,𝑋 “ Gr0𝐡 ´ ,𝑋 .
Using this action, we obtain a canonical isomorphism:
Λ‡
Zπœ† “ Gr0𝐡 ´ ,𝑋
Λ‡
πœ†
Λ‡
Ñ Grπœ‚π΅
ˆ Gr𝐡,𝑋 Ý
´ ,𝑋
Λ‡ πœ‚
πœ†`Λ‡
»
Gr𝐺,𝑋
ˆ Gr𝐡,𝑋
Gr𝐺,𝑋
of 𝑋-schemes for every πœ‚Λ‡ P Λ̌.
Proposition 3.5.1. For πœ‚Λ‡ deep enough23 in the dominant chamber we have:
Λ‡
Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,𝑋
Λ‡ πœ‚
πœ†`Λ‡
Λ‡
ˆ Gr𝐡,𝑋 “ Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,𝑋
Gr𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡
πœ‚
ˆ Grπœ†`Λ‡
𝐺,𝑋 .
Gr𝐺,𝑋
This equality also identifies:
Λ‡
Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,𝑋
Λ‡
πœ‚
πœ‚Λ‡
ˆ Grπœ†`Λ‡
𝐡,𝑋 “ Gr𝐡 ´ ,𝑋
Gr𝐺,𝑋
23This should be understood in a way depending on πœ†.
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ‚
ˆ Grπœ†`Λ‡
𝐺,𝑋 .
Gr𝐺,𝑋
24
SAM RASKIN
Proof. It suffices to verify the result fiberwise and therefore we fix π‘₯ “ 0 P 𝑋 “ A1 (this is really
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
just a notational convenience here). We let Zπœ†π‘₯ (resp. Zπœ†π‘₯ ) denote the fiber of Zπœ† (resp. Zπœ† ) at π‘₯. Let
𝑑 P 𝐾π‘₯ be a coordinate at π‘₯.
π‘œ
Λ‡ and because each Zπœ‡π‘₯Λ‡ is finite type, for πœ‚Λ‡ deep
Because there are only finitely many 0 ď πœ‡
Λ‡Δπœ†
enough in the dominant chamber we have:
π‘œ
Zπœ‡π‘₯Λ‡ “ Gr𝑁 ´ ,π‘₯ X Ad´Λ‡πœ‚p𝑑q p𝑁 p𝑂π‘₯ qq ¨ πœ‡
Λ‡p𝑑q
(Λ‡
πœ‡p𝑑q being regarded as a point in Gr𝐺,π‘₯ here and the intersection symbol is short-hand for fiber
Λ‡ Choosing πœ‚Λ‡ possibly larger, we can also assume that πœ‚Λ‡ ` πœ‡
product over Gr𝐺,π‘₯ ) for all 0 ď πœ‡
Λ‡ ď πœ†.
Λ‡
Λ‡
is dominant for all 0 ď πœ‡
Λ‡ ď πœ†. Then we claim that such a choice πœ‚Λ‡ suffices for the purposes of the
proposition.
Λ‡ we have:
Observe that for each 0 ď πœ‡
Λ‡Δπœ†
ˆ
Λ™
π‘œ
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
πœ‚Λ‡
πœ‚Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
πœ‡
Λ‡
πœ‡ ` πœ‚Λ‡qp𝑑q Ď Grπœ‚π΅
Gr𝐡 ´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐡,π‘₯ “ πœ‚Λ‡p𝑑q ¨ Zπ‘₯ Ď Gr𝐡 ´ ,π‘₯ X 𝑁 p𝑂π‘₯ q ¨ pΛ‡
´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐺,π‘₯ .
Λ‡ πœ‚
πœ†`Λ‡
Recall (c.f. [MV]) that Gr𝐡,π‘₯ is a union of strata:
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
Λ‡
Λ‡Δπœ†
Gr𝐡,π‘₯ , πœ‡
while for πœ‡
Λ‡:
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐡,π‘₯ “ H
πœ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
Λ‡
unless πœ‡
Λ‡ Δ› 0. Therefore, Grπœ‚π΅
Λ‡ ď πœ†.
´ ,π‘₯ intersects Gr𝐡,π‘₯ only in the strata Gr𝐡,π‘₯ for 0 ď πœ‡
The above analysis therefore shows that:
Λ‡ πœ‚
πœ†`Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ‚Λ‡
πœ†`Λ‡
πœ‚
Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ XGr𝐡,π‘₯ Ď Gr𝐡 ´ ,π‘₯ XGr𝐺,π‘₯ .
Λ‡ ` πœ‚Λ‡qp𝑑q is open in Grπœ†Λ‡ . Therefore, we have:
Now observe that 𝐡p𝑂π‘₯ q ¨ pπœ†
Λ‡ πœ‚
πœ†`Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ‚
Grπœ†`Λ‡
𝐺,π‘₯ Ď Gr𝐡
giving the opposite inclusion above.
π‘œΛ‡
It remains to show that the equality identifies Zπœ†π‘₯ in the desired way. We have already shown
that:
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†`Λ‡
πœ‚
πœ‚Λ‡
πœ†`Λ‡
πœ‚
Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐡,π‘₯ Ď Gr𝐡 ´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐺,π‘₯ .
so it remains to prove the opposite inclusion. Suppose that 𝑦 is a geometric point of the right hand
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
side. Then, by the Iwasawa decomposition, 𝑦 P Grπœ‡π΅,π‘₯
for some (unique) πœ‡
Λ‡ P Λ̌ and we wish to show
Λ‡
that πœ‡
Λ‡ “ πœ†.
Because:
Λ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
πœ‚
𝑦 P Grπœ‡π΅,π‘₯
XGrπœ†`Λ‡
𝐺,π‘₯ ‰ H
Λ‡ We also have:
we have πœ‡
Λ‡ ď πœ†.
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
Λ‡
𝑦 P Grπœ‡π΅,π‘₯
X Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ ‰ H
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
25
which implies πœ‡
Λ‡ Δ› 0. Therefore, by construction of πœ‚ we have:
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
πœ‚Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
𝑦 P Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐡,π‘₯ Ď Gr𝐡 ´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐺,π‘₯ Ď Gr𝐺,π‘₯
Λ‡ πœ‚
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
Λ‡ (because πœ‡
Λ‡ ` πœ‚Λ‡ are assumed dominant) and therefore
but Grπœ‡πΊ,π‘₯
X Grπœ†`Λ‡
Λ‡‰πœ†
Λ‡ ` πœ‚Λ‡ and πœ†
𝐺,π‘₯ “ H if πœ‡
Λ‡ as desired.
we must have πœ‡
Λ‡“πœ†
We continue to use the notation introduced in the proof of Proposition 3.5.1.
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
Recall that 𝛽 πœ† (resp. 7πœ† ) denotes the closed embedding Zπœ† ãÑ π’΅ πœ† (resp. Zπœ† ãÑ π’΅ πœ† ). For π‘₯ P 𝑋,
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
π‘œΛ‡
let 𝛽π‘₯πœ† (resp. 7πœ†π‘₯ ) denote the closed embedding Zπœ†π‘₯ ãÑ π’΅ πœ† (resp. Zπœ†π‘₯ ãÑ π’΅ πœ† ).
Corollary 3.5.2. For every π‘₯ P 𝑋, the cohomology:
´
¯
!
Λ‡
Λ‡
˚
𝐻𝑑𝑅
Zπœ†π‘₯ , 𝛽π‘₯πœ†,! pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ bπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q
(3.5.1)
Λ‡ it is concentrated in strictly
is concentrated in non-negative cohomological degrees, for for 0 ‰ πœ†,
positive cohomological degrees.
Remark 3.5.3. It follows a posteriori from Theorem 3.4.1 that the whole cohomology vanishes for
Λ‡
0 ‰ πœ†.
Proof. First, we claim that when either:
‚ 𝑖 Δƒ 0, or:
Λ‡‰0
‚ 𝑖 “ 0 and πœ†
we have:
´π‘œ
¯
!
Λ‡ Λ‡
𝑖
π‘œ
π‘œ
𝐻𝑑𝑅
Zπœ†π‘₯ , 7πœ†,!
pIC
bπœ“
q
“0
π‘₯
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†
πœ†
𝒡
π‘œΛ‡
(3.5.2)
𝒡
!
Λ‡
Indeed, from the smoothness of 𝒡 πœ† , we see that IC π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ b7πœ†,!
q is a rank one local system
π‘₯ pπœ“ π‘œ πœ†
𝒡
𝒡ˇ
concentrated in perverse cohomological degree:
π‘œΛ‡
π‘œΛ‡
π‘œΛ‡
dimp𝒡 πœ† q ´ dimpZπœ†π‘₯ q “ dimpZπœ†π‘₯ q.
This gives the desired vanishing in negative degrees.
Moreover, from Proposition 3.5.1 and the Casselman-Shalika formula ([FGV] Theorem 1), we
Λ‡ ‰ 0, the restriction of our rank one local system to every irreducible component
deduce that, for πœ†
π‘œΛ‡
of Zπœ†π‘₯ is moreover non-constant. This gives (3.5.2).
Λ‡ the !-restriction of
To complete the argument, note that by Theorem 2.17.1 (3), for 0 ď πœ‡
Λ‡ ď πœ†,
π‘œ
Λ‡
IC πœ†Λ‡ to Zπœ‡π‘₯Λ‡ lies in perverse cohomological degrees Δ› p𝜌, πœ‡
Λ‡q, with strict inequality for πœ‡
Λ‡ ‰ πœ†.
𝒡
!
π‘œ
Λ‡
Λ‡ 𝛽π‘₯πœ†,!
By lisseness of πœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ , we deduce that for 0 ď πœ‡
Λ‡ Δƒ πœ†,
pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ bπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q has !-restriction to Zπœ‡π‘₯Λ‡ in
Λ‡
perverse cohomological degrees strictly greater than p𝜌, πœ‡
Λ‡q “ dimp𝒡 πœ† q. Therefore, the non-positive
cohomologies of these restrictions vanish.
We find that the cohomology is the open stratum can contribute to the non-positive cohomology,
but this vanishes by (3.5.2).
26
SAM RASKIN
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  then we have the vanishing Euler characteristic:
Corollary 3.5.4. If 0 ‰ πœ†
ˆ
´
¯Λ™
!
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†
πœ†,!
˚
“ 0.
πœ’ 𝐻𝑑𝑅 Zπ‘₯ , 𝛽π‘₯ pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ bπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q
Proof. The key point is to establish the following equality:
Λ‡
r𝛽π‘₯πœ†,! pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ qs “ rπœ„! pIC
Λ‡
Λ‡ πœ‚
Grπœ†`Λ‡
𝐺,π‘₯
𝑏
qs P 𝐾0 pπ·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™
pZπœ†π‘₯ qq
(3.5.3)
Λ‡
in the Grothendieck group of complexes of (coherent and) holonomic 𝐷-modules on Zπœ†π‘₯ . Here the
map πœ„ is defined as:
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†`Λ‡
πœ‚
πœ†`Λ‡
πœ‚
Zπ‘₯ Ý
Ñ Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ XGr𝐺,π‘₯ Ñ Gr𝐺,π‘₯ .
»
Λ‡ the !-restrictions of these classes coincide in the
It suffices to show that for each 0 ď πœ‡
Λ‡ ď πœ†,
Grothendieck group of:
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐺,π‘₯ .
Indeed, these locally closed subvarieties form a stratification.
Λ‡ πœ‡
πœ†`Λ‡
First, note that the !-restriction of IC πœ†`Λ‡
Λ‡ πœ‚ to Gr𝐺,π‘₯ has constant cohomologies (by 𝐺p𝑂qGr𝐺,π‘₯
equivariance). Moreover, by [Lus] the corresponding class in the Grothendieck group is the dimension of the weight component:
`
˘
Λ‡
dim 𝑉 ´π‘€0 pπœ†`Λ‡πœ‚q p´Λ‡
πœ‡ ´ πœ‚Λ‡q ¨ rIC
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡
Grπœ†`
𝐺,π‘₯
s.
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
Further !-restricting to Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐺,π‘₯ , we obtain that the right hand side of our equation is given
by:
Λ‡
dim 𝑉 ´π‘€0 pπœ†`Λ‡πœ‚q p´Λ‡
πœ‡ ´ πœ‚Λ‡q ¨ rICGrπœ‚Λ‡
𝐡 ´ ,π‘₯
Λ‡ πœ‚ s.
X Grπœ‡`Λ‡
𝐺,π‘₯
Λ‡
By having π‘ˆ pňq act on a lowest weight vector of 𝑉 πœ†`Λ‡πœ‚ , we observe that for πœ‚Λ‡ large enough, we have:
Λ‡
Λ‡´πœ‡
𝑉 ´π‘€0 pπœ†`Λ‡πœ‚q p´Λ‡
πœ‡ ´ πœ‚Λ‡q » π‘ˆ pňqpπœ†
Λ‡q.
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚
The similar identification for the left hand side follows from the choice of πœ‚Λ‡ (so that Grπœ‚π΅
´ ,π‘₯ X Gr𝐺,π‘₯
π‘œ
identifies with Zπœ‡π‘₯Λ‡ ) and Theorem 2.17.1 (3).
Appealing to (3.5.3), we see that in order to deduce the corollary, it suffices to prove that:
ˆ
´
Λ‡
˚
πœ’ 𝐻𝑑𝑅
Zπœ†π‘₯ , πœ„! pIC
!
Λ‡
πœ‚
Grπœ†`Λ‡
𝐺,π‘₯
qb
Λ‡
𝛽π‘₯πœ†,! pπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q
¯Λ™
“ 0.
Even better: by the geometric Casselman-Shalika formula [FGV], this cohomology itself vanishes.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
3.6.
27
Now we give the proof of Theorem 3.4.1.
Λ‡ so we assume the result holds for all
Proof of Theorem 3.4.1. We proceed by induction on p𝜌, πœ†q,
!
Λ‡ By factorization and induction, we see that F :“ πœ‹ πœ†Λ‡ pIC πœ†Λ‡ bπœ“ πœ†Λ‡ q is concentrated on
0Δƒπœ‡
Λ‡ Δƒ πœ†.
˚,𝑑𝑅
𝒡
𝒡
Λ‡
the main diagonal 𝑋 Ď Divπœ†eff .
Λ‡
Λ‡
!
The (˚ “!-)restriction of F to 𝑋 is the ˚-pushforward along Zπœ† Ñ π‘‹ of 𝛽 πœ†,! pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ bπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q. MoreΛ‡
over, since Zπœ† Ñ π‘‹ is a Zariski-locally trivial fibration, the cohomologies of F on 𝑋 are lisse and
the fiber at π‘₯ P 𝑋 is:
´
¯
!
Λ‡
Λ‡
˚
Zπœ†π‘₯ , 𝛽π‘₯πœ†,! pIC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ bπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q .
𝐻𝑑𝑅
!
Λ‡
Because πœ‹ πœ† is affine and IC𝒡 πœ†Λ‡ bπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ is a perverse sheaf, F lies in perverse degrees ď 0. Moreover,
by Corollary 3.5.2, its !-fibers are concentrated in strictly positive degrees. Since F is lisse along 𝑋,
this implies that F is actually perverse. Now Corollary 3.5.4 provides the vanishing of the Euler
characteristics of the fibers of F, giving the result.
4. Identification of the Chevalley complex
4.1. The goal for this section is to identify the Chevalley complex in the cohomology of Zastava
space with coefficients in the Whittaker sheaf: this is the content of Theorem 4.6.1.
The argument combines Theorem 3.4.1 with results from [BG2].
Remark 4.1.1. Theorem 4.6.1 is one of the central results of this text: as explained in the introduction, it provides a connection between Whittaker sheaves on the semi-infinite flag variety and the
factorization algebra Υň , and therefore relates to Conjecture 1.
4.2. We will use the language of graded factorization algebras.
The definition should encode the following: a ZΔ›0 -graded factorization algebra is a system A𝑛 P
𝐷pSym𝑛 𝑋q such that we have, for every pair π‘š, 𝑛 we have isomorphisms:
´
¯
´
¯
»
Aπ‘š b A𝑛 |rSymπ‘š 𝑋ˆSym𝑛 𝑋s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 Ý
Ñ Aπ‘š`𝑛 |rSymπ‘š 𝑋ˆSym𝑛 𝑋s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
satisfying (higher) associativity and commutativity. Note that the addition map Symπ‘š 𝑋ˆSym𝑛 𝑋 Ñ
Symπ‘š`𝑛 𝑋 is étale when restricted to the disjoint locus, and therefore the restriction notation above
is unambiguous.
š
Formally, the scheme Sym 𝑋 “ 𝑛 Sym𝑛 𝑋 is naturally a commutative algebra under correspondences, where the multiplication is induced by the maps:
rSym𝑛 𝑋 ˆ Symπ‘š 𝑋s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
t
Sym𝑛 𝑋 ˆ Symπ‘š 𝑋
)
Symπ‘š`𝑛 𝑋.
Therefore, as in [Ras1] S6, we can apply the formalism of loc. cit. S5 to obtain the desired theory.
Remark 4.2.1. We will only be working with graded factorization algebras in the heart of the 𝑑structure, and therefore the language may be worked out “by hand” as in [BD], i.e., without needing
to appeal to [Ras1].
28
SAM RASKIN
Similarly, we have the notion of ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -graded factorization algebra: it is a collection of 𝐷-modules
Λ‡
on the schemes Divπœ†eff with similar identifications as above.
4.3. Recall that [BG2] has introduced a certain ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -graded commutative factorization algebra,
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
i.e., a commutative factorization 𝐷-module on DivΛ̌
eff . This algebra incarnates the homological
Chevalley complex of ň. In loc. cit., this algebra is denoted by ΥpnΜŒπ‘‹ q: we use the notation Υň
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
instead. We denote the component of Υň on Divπœ†eff by Υπœ†ň . Recall from loc. cit. that each Υπœ†ň lies in
Λ‡
𝐷pDivπœ†eff qβ™‘ .24
Remark 4.3.1. To remind the reader of the relation between Υň and the homological
ř𝑛 Λ‡ Chevalley
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
complex 𝐢‚ pňq of ň, we recall that the ˚-fiber of Υň at a Λ̌ -colored divisor 𝑖“1 πœ†π‘– ¨ π‘₯𝑖 (here
Λ‡ 𝑖 P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  and the π‘₯𝑖 P 𝑋 are distinct closed points) is canonically identified with:
πœ†
𝑛
Λ‡
b 𝐢‚ pňqπœ†π‘–
𝑖“1
where 𝐢‚
Λ‡
pňqπœ†π‘–
Λ‡ 𝑖 -graded piece of the complex.
denotes the πœ†
Remark 4.3.2. The ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -graded vector space:
ň “
nΜŒπ›ΌΛ‡
‘
𝛼
Λ‡ a positive coroot
gives rise to the 𝐷-module:
Λ‡
pnΜŒπ›ΌΛ‡ b π‘˜π‘‹ q P 𝐷pDivΛ̌
‘
βˆ†π›ΌΛš,𝑑𝑅
eff q
𝛼
Λ‡ a positive coroot
Λ‡
Divπœ†eff is the diagonal embedding. The Lie algebra
nΜŒπ‘‹ :“
Λ‡ P Λ̌, βˆ†πœ†Λ‡ : 𝑋 Ñ
where for πœ†
structure on ň gives
a Lie-˚ structure on nΜŒπ‘‹ .
Then Υň is tautologically given as the factorization algebra associated to the chiral enveloping
algebra of this Lie-˚ algebra.
Remark 4.3.3. We emphasize the miracle mentioned above and crucially exploited in [BG2] (and
below): although 𝐢‚ pňq is a cocommutative (DG) coalgebra that is very much non-classical, its
𝐷-module avatar does lie in the heart of the 𝑑-structure. Of course, this is no contradiction, since
the ˚-fibers of a perverse sheaf need only live in degrees ď 0.
4.4.
Observe that πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ q naturally factorizes on 𝒡. Therefore, s˚,𝑑𝑅 πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ q is naturally a
𝒡
𝒡
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
𝐷pDivΛ̌
eff q.
factorization 𝐷-module in
The following key identification is essentially proved in [BG2], but we include a proof with
detailed references to loc. cit. for completeness.
Theorem 4.4.1. There is a canonical identification:
»
𝐻 0 ps˚,𝑑𝑅 πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ qq Ý
Ñ Υň
𝒡
of ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -graded factorization algebras.
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  fixed, IC π‘œ
Remark 4.4.2. To orient the reader on cohomological shifts, we note that for πœ†
Λ‡
πœ†
𝒡
is concentrated in degree 0 and therefore the above 𝐻 0 is the maximal cohomology group of the
complex s˚,𝑑𝑅 πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ q.
𝒡
24We explicitly note that in this section we exclusively use the usual (perverse) 𝑑-structure.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
29
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,simple
Proof of Theorem 4.4.1. Let 𝑗 : DivΛ̌
ãÑ DivΛ̌
effΕ™ denote the open consisting of simple
eff
divisors, i.e., its geometric points are divisors of the form 𝑛𝑖“1 𝛼
Λ‡ 𝑖 ¨ π‘₯𝑖 for 𝛼
Λ‡ 𝑖 a positive simple coroot
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†,simple
πœ†
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ‡ P Λ̌ , we let 𝑗 : Div
Ñ Divπœ†eff denote the
and the points tπ‘₯𝑖 u pairwise distinct. For each πœ†
eff
Λ‡
corresponding open embedding. Note that 𝑗 and each embedding 𝑗 πœ† is affine.
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,simple
Observe that DivΛ̌
has a factorization structure induced by that of Diveff . The restriceff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,simple
tion of Υň to DivΛ̌
identifies canonically with the exterior product over 𝑖 P ℐ𝐺 of the
eff
corresponding “sign” (rank 1) local systems under the identification:
Λ‡
Divπœ†,simple
»
eff
ΕΊ
Sym𝑛𝑖 ,simple 𝑋
𝑖Pℐ𝐺
Λ‡“
where πœ†
Λ‡ 𝑖 and on the right the subscript simple means “simple effective divisor” in the
𝑖Pℐ𝐺 𝑛𝑖 𝛼
same sense as above. Moreover, these identifications are compatible with the factorization structure
in the natural sense.
π‘œ
π‘œΛ‡
π‘œ
π‘œΛ‡
Let 𝒡 simple and 𝒡 πœ†,simple denote the corresponding opens in 𝒡 and 𝒡 πœ† obtained by fiber product.
Λ‡
Λ‡
Let ssimple and sπœ†,simple denote the corresponding restrictions of s and sπœ† .
Ε™
π‘œΛ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
p𝜌,πœ†q
Λ‡
-scheme by (2.11.1), and these identifications
ˆGπ‘š as a Divπœ†,simple
Then 𝒡 πœ†,simple Ý
Ñ Divπœ†,simple
eff
eff
are compatible with factorization.
Therefore, we deduce an isomorphism:
»
»
𝐻 0 pssimple,˚,𝑑𝑅 πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ simple qq Ý
Ñ π‘— ! pΥň q
𝒡
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,simple
of factorization 𝐷-modules on DivΛ̌
eff
the Koszul rule of signs).
Therefore, we obtain a diagram:
(note that the sign local system appears on the left by
𝑗! 𝐻 0 pssimple,˚,𝑑𝑅 πš₯˚ pIC π‘œ simple qq
»
𝒡
/ 𝑗! 𝑗 ! pΥň q
(4.4.1)
𝐻 0 ps˚,𝑑𝑅 πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ qq
Υň
𝒡
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Note that the top horizontal arrow is a map of factorization algebras on DivΛ̌
eff .
By (the Verdier duals to) [BG2] Lemma 4.8 and Proposition 4.9, the vertical maps in (4.4.1)
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
β™‘
are epimorphisms in the abelian category 𝐷pDivΛ̌
eff q . Moreover, by the analysis in loc. cit. S4.10,
there is a (necessarily unique) isomorphism:
»
𝐻 0 ps˚,𝑑𝑅 πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ qq Ý
Ñ Υň
𝒡
completing the square (4.4.1). By uniqueness, this isomorphism is necessarily an isomorphism of
factorizable 𝐷-modules.
π‘œ
4.5. Observe that the 𝐷-module πœ“ π‘œ canonically factorizes on 𝒡. Therefore, πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ q factorizes
𝒡
𝒡
in 𝐷p𝒡q.
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  we have a map:
By Theorem 4.4.1, we have for each πœ†
30
SAM RASKIN
´
¯
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
πš₯πœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ q Ñ sπœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝐻 0 sπœ†,˚,𝑑𝑅 πš₯πœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ q “ s˚,𝑑𝑅 pΥπœ†ň q.
(4.5.1)
𝒡
𝒡
Λ‡
These maps are compatible with factorization as we vary πœ†.
Λ‡
Lemma 4.5.1. The map (4.5.1) is an epimorphism in the abelian category 𝐷p𝒡 πœ† qβ™‘ .
Λ‡
Proof. Let F P 𝐷p𝒡 πœ† qď0 . Then the canonical map:
Λ‡
Λ‡
F Ñ sπœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 sπœ†,˚,𝑑𝑅 pFq
(4.5.2)
Λ‡
has kernel given by restricting to and then !-extending from the complement to the image of sπœ† .
Since this is an open embedding, the kernel of (4.5.2) is concentrated in cohomological degrees ď 0.
Taking the long exact sequence on cohomology, we see that the map:
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡
F Ñ π» 0 psπœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 sπœ†,˚,𝑑𝑅 pFqq “ sπœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝐻 0 psπœ†,˚,𝑑𝑅 pFqq P 𝐷p𝒡 πœ† qβ™‘
is an epimorphism.
Λ‡
Applying this to F “ πš₯πœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ q gives the claim.
𝒡
!
Λ‡
»
4.6. Applying πœ“π’΅ b ´ to (4.5.1) and using the canonical identifications sπœ†,!,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“π’΅ πœ†Λ‡ q Ý
Ñ πœ”Divπœ†Λ‡ , we
eff
obtain maps:
Λ‡
!
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ‚ πœ† : πš₯πœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ b IC π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ q Ñ s˚,𝑑𝑅 pΥπœ†ň q.
𝒡
𝒡
Λ‡ the maps πœ‚ πœ†Λ‡ are as well.
Because everything above is compatible with factorization as we vary πœ†,
!
We let πœ‚ : πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ b IC π‘œ q Ñ s˚,𝑑𝑅 pΥň q denote the induced map of factorizable 𝐷-modules on 𝒡.
𝒡
𝒡
Theorem 4.6.1. The map:
!
π‘œ
!
πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅 pπœ‚q
πœ‹ ˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ b IC π‘œ q “ πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅 πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ b IC π‘œ q ÝÝÝÝÝÑ πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅 s˚,𝑑𝑅 pΥň q “ Υň
𝒡
𝒡
𝒡
𝒡
(4.6.1)
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
is an equivalence of factorizable 𝐷-modules on DivΛ̌
eff .
π‘œ
!
Remark 4.6.2. In particular, the theorem asserts that πœ‹ ˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ b IC π‘œ q is concentrated in cohomo𝒡
𝒡
logical degree 0.
Λ‡ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  that πœ‹ πœ†Λ‡ pπœ‚ πœ†Λ‡ q is an equivalence.
Proof of Theorem 4.6.1. It suffices to show for fixed πœ†
˚,𝑑𝑅
Recall from [BG2] Corollary 4.5 that we have an equality:
ÿ
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡,Λ‡
πœ‡
𝑏
rπš₯πœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 pIC π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ qs “
ractπœ‚π’΅,˚,𝑑𝑅
pΥπœ‚nΜŒΛ‡ b IC𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ qs P 𝐾0 pπ·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™
p𝒡 πœ† qq.
(4.6.2)
𝒡
πœ‡
Λ‡,Λ‡
πœ‚ PΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚ “πœ†
in the Grothendieck group of (coherent and) holonomic 𝐷-modules. Therefore, because πœ“π’΅ is lisse,
we obtain a similar equality:
!
Λ‡
rπš₯πœ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ b IC π‘œ πœ†Λ‡ qs “
𝒡
𝒡
ÿ
πœ‡
Λ‡,Λ‡
πœ‚ PΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡`Λ‡
πœ‚ “πœ†
´
¯
!
Λ‡,Λ‡
πœ‡
ractπœ‚π’΅,˚,𝑑𝑅
Υπœ‚nΜŒΛ‡ b pπœ“ π‘œ πœ‡Λ‡ b IC𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ q s
𝒡
(4.6.3)
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
31
by the projection formula.
Λ‡ we have:
For every decomposition πœ‡
Λ‡ ` πœ‚Λ‡ “ πœ†,
¯
¯
´
´
!
!
Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡,Λ‡
πœ‡
Λ‡,Λ‡
πœ‡
πœ†
pπœ“ π‘œ πœ‡Λ‡ b IC𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ q .
Υπœ‚nΜŒΛ‡ b πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅
πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅
actπœ‚π’΅,˚,𝑑𝑅
Υπœ‚nΜŒΛ‡ b pπœ“ π‘œ πœ‡Λ‡ b IC𝒡 πœ‡Λ‡ q “ addπœ‚Λš,𝑑𝑅
𝒡
𝒡
By Theorem 3.4.1, this term vanishes for πœ‡
Λ‡ ‰ 0.
Therefore, we see that the left hand side of (4.6.1) is concentrated in degree 0, and that it agrees
in the Grothendieck group with the right hand side.
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†
Moreover, by affineness of πœ‹ πœ† , the functor πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅
is right exact. Therefore, by Lemma 4.5.1, the
Λ‡
Λ‡
πœ†
pπœ‚ πœ† q is an epimorphism in the heart of the 𝑑-structure; since the source and target agree
map πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅
in the Grothendieck group, we obtain that our map is an isomorphism.
5. Hecke functors: Zastava calculation over a point
5.1. Next, we compare Theorem 4.6.1 with the geometric Satake equivalence.
Λ‡ there are two ways to associate a
More precisely, given a representation 𝑉 of the dual group 𝐺,
factorization Υň -module: one is through its Chevalley complex 𝐢‚ pň, 𝑉 q, and the other is through
a geometric procedure explained below, relying on geometric Satake and Theorem 4.6.1. In what
follows, we refer to these two operations as the spectral and geometric Chevalley functors respectively.
The main result of this section, Theorem 5.14.1, identifies the two functors.
Notation 5.1.1. We fix a π‘˜-point π‘₯ P 𝑋 in what follows.
5.2. Polar Drinfeld structures. Suppose 𝑋 is proper for the moment.
8¨π‘₯
Recall the ind-algebraic stack Bun𝑁 ´ from [FGV]: it parametrizes 𝒫𝐺 a 𝐺-bundle on 𝑋 and
non-zero maps:25
bpˇ
𝜌,πœ†q
Ñ π‘‰π’«πœ†πΊ p8 ¨ π‘₯q
Ω𝑋
defined for each dominant weight πœ† and satisfying the Plucker relations.
8¨π‘₯
Example 5.2.1. Let 𝐺 “ 𝑆𝐿2 . Then Bun𝑁 ´ classifies the datum of an 𝑆𝐿2 -bundle E and a non-zero
1
2
map Ω𝑋
Ñ Ep8 ¨ π‘₯q.26
8¨π‘₯
Example 5.2.2. For 𝐺 “ Gπ‘š , Bun𝑁 ´ is the affine Grassmannian for 𝑇 at π‘₯.
8¨π‘₯
8¨π‘₯
5.3. Hecke action. The key feature of Bun𝑁 ´ is that Hecke functors at π‘₯ act on 𝐷pBun𝑁 ´ q.
More precisely, the action of the Hecke groupoid on Bun𝐺 lifts in the obvious way to an action on
8¨π‘₯
Bun𝑁 ´ .
π‘₯ denote the Hecke stack at π‘₯,
For definiteness, we introduce the following notation. Let H𝐺
parametrizing pairs of 𝐺-bundles on 𝑋 identified away from π‘₯. Let β„Ž1 and β„Ž2 denote the two
π‘₯ Ñ Bun .
projections H𝐺
𝐺
π‘₯
Define the Drinfeld-Hecke stack H𝐺,Drin
as the fiber product:
8¨π‘₯
π‘₯
H𝐺
ˆ Bun𝑁 ´
Bun𝐺
1
25Here if pˇ
2
𝜌, πœ†q is half integral, we appeal to our choice of Ω𝑋
.
26Here we are slightly abusing notation in letting E denote the rank two vector bundle underlying our 𝑆𝐿 -bundle.
2
32
SAM RASKIN
π‘₯ Ñ Bun in order to form this fiber product. We abuse notation in
where we use the map β„Ž1 : H𝐺
𝐺
8¨π‘₯
π‘₯
using the same notation for the two projections H𝐺,Drin
Ñ Bun𝑁 ´ .
π‘₯
Example 5.3.1. Let 𝐺 “ 𝑆𝐿2 . Then H𝐺,Drin
parametrizes a pair of 𝑆𝐿2 -bundles E1 and E2 identified
1
2
Ñ E1 p8 ¨ π‘₯q. The two projections β„Ž1 and β„Ž2 correspond to
away from π‘₯ and a non-zero map Ω𝑋
8¨π‘₯
the maps to Bun𝑁 ´ sending a datum as above to:
`
1
2
E1 , Ω 𝑋
Ñ E1 p8 ¨ π‘₯q
˘
1
˘
`
»
2
Ñ E1 p8 ¨ π‘₯q Ý
Ñ E2 p8 ¨ π‘₯q
E 2 , Ω𝑋
respectively.
π‘₯ from objects of Sph
𝐺p𝑂qπ‘₯ .
We have the usual procedure for producing objects of H𝐺
𝐺,π‘₯ :“ 𝐷pGr𝐺,π‘₯ q
π‘₯ from 𝐷pBun q to itThese give Hecke functors acting on 𝐷pBun𝐺 q using the correspondence H𝐺
𝐺
self and the kernel induced by this object of Sph𝐺,π‘₯ . We normalize our Hecke functors so that we
8¨π‘₯
!-pullback along β„Ž1 and ˚-pushforward along β„Ž2 . The same discussion applies for 𝐷pBun𝑁 ´ q.
We use Λ™ to denote the action by convolution of Sph𝐺,π‘₯ on these categories.
π‘œ
5.4. Polar Zastava space. We let 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ denote the indscheme defined by the ind-open embedding:
8¨π‘₯
𝒡 8¨π‘₯ Ď Bun𝐡 ˆ Bun𝑁 ´
Bun𝐺
given by the usual generic transversality condition.
π‘œ
π‘œ
π‘œ
8¨π‘₯
Note that 𝒡 Ď 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ is the fiber of 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ along Bun𝑁 ´ Ď Bun𝑁 ´ .
π‘œ
Remark 5.4.1. As in the case of usual Zastava, note that 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ is of local nature with respect to 𝑋:
i.e., the definition makes sense for any smooth curve, and is étale local on the curve. Therefore, we
typically remove our requirement that 𝑋 is proper in what follows.
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
be the indscheme parametrizing Λ̌-valued divisors on 𝑋 that are ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -valued
5.5. Let Diveff
away from π‘₯.
As for usual Zastava space, we have the map:
π‘œ
π‘œ
πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
𝒡 8¨π‘₯ ÝÝÝÑ DivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Remark 5.5.1. There is a canonical map deg : DivΛ̌
eff
π‘˜-scheme) of taking the total degree of a divisor.
.
Ñ Λ̌ (considering the target as a discrete
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
5.6. Factorization patterns. Note that DivΛ̌
is a unital factorization module space for
eff
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
Diveff . This means that e.g. we have a correspondence:
β„‹
w
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
Diveff
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
ˆ DivΛ̌
eff
$
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
DivΛ̌
eff
.
For this action, the left leg of the correspondence is the open embedding encoding disjointness of
pairs of divisors, while the right leg is given by addition. (For the sake of clarity, let us note that
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
33
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
the only reasonable notion of the support of a divisor in DivΛ̌
requires that π‘₯ always lie in
eff
the support).
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Therefore, as in S4.2, we can talk about unital factorization modules in DivΛ̌
for a unital
eff
fact
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘ 
graded factorization algebra A P 𝐷pDiveff q. We denote this category by A–mod𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Remark 5.6.1. The factorization action of DivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
on DivΛ̌
eff
is commutative in the sense of
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
[Ras1] S7. Indeed, it comes from the obvious action of the monoid DivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
on DivΛ̌
eff
.
Remark 5.6.2. We emphasize that there is no Ran space appearing here: all the geometry occurs
on finite-dimensional spaces of divisors.
π‘œ
5.7.
There is a similar picture to the above for Zastava. More precisely, 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ is a unital factorπ‘œ
ization module space for 𝒡 in a way compatible with the structure maps to and from the spaces of
divisors.
π‘œ
π‘œ
8¨π‘₯ q.
Therefore, for a unital factorization algebra B on 𝒡, we can form the category B–modfact
𝑒𝑛 p𝒡
π‘œ
π‘œ
π‘œ
fact
8¨π‘₯ q, πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯ pβ„³q is tautologically an object of πœ‹
Moreover, for β„³ P B–modfact
˚,𝑑𝑅 pBq–mod𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
𝑒𝑛 p𝒡
˚,𝑑𝑅
We denote the corresponding functor by:
π‘œ
π‘œ
π‘œ
fact
8¨π‘₯
πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯
q Ñ πœ‹ ˚,𝑑𝑅 pBq–modfact
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
˚,𝑑𝑅 : B–mod𝑒𝑛 p𝒡
5.8. Construction of the geometric Chevalley functor. We now define a functor:
fact
Λ‡
Chevgeom
ň,π‘₯ : Repp𝐺q Ñ Υň –mod𝑒𝑛,π‘₯
using the factorization pattern for Zastava space.
Λ‡ denotes the DG category of representations of
Remark 5.8.1. Following our conventions, Repp𝐺q
Λ‡
𝐺.
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Remark 5.8.2. We will give a global interpretation of the induced functor to 𝐷pDivΛ̌
eff
S5.12; this phrasing may be easier to understand at first pass.
q in
π‘œ
5.9. First, observe that there is a natural “compactification” 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ of 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ : for 𝑋 proper, it is the
appropriate ind-open locus in:
8¨π‘₯
𝒡 8¨π‘₯ Ď Bun𝐡
8¨π‘₯
8¨π‘₯
8¨π‘₯
ˆ Bun𝑁 ´ .
Bun𝐺
Here Bun𝐡 is defined analogously to Bun𝑁 ´ ; we remark that it has a structure map to Bun𝑇
8¨π‘₯
with fibers the variants of Bun𝑁 ´ for other bundles. Again, 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ is of local nature on the curve 𝑋.
The advantage of 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ is that there is a Hecke action here, so Sph𝐺,π‘₯ acts on 𝐷p𝒡 8¨π‘₯ q. Note
8¨π‘₯
that !-pullback from Bun𝑁 ´ commutes with Hecke functors.
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
There is again a canonical map to DivΛ̌
, and the factorization pattern of S5.7 carries over
eff
in this setting as well, that is, 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ is a unital factorization module space for 𝒡. Moreover, this
factorization schema is compatible with the Hecke action.
34
SAM RASKIN
8¨π‘₯
5.10. Define Y Ď 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ as the preimage of Bun𝑁 ´ Ď Bun𝑁 ´ in 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ : again, Y is of local nature
on 𝑋.
π‘œ
Remark 5.10.1. The notation 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ would be just as appropriate for Y as for the space we have
π‘œ
π‘œ
denoted in this way: both are polar versions of 𝒡, but for 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ we allow poles for the 𝑁 ´ -bundle,
while for Y we allow poles for the 𝐡-bundle.
There is a canonical map Y Ñ Gπ‘Ž which e.g. for 𝑋 proper comes from the canonical map
Bun𝑁 ´ Ñ Gπ‘Ž . We can !-pullback the exponential 𝐷-module πœ“ on Gπ‘Ž (normalized as always to be
in perverse degree -1): we denote the resulting 𝐷-module by πœ“Y P 𝐷pYq.
We then cohomologically renormalize: define πœ“YIC by:
πœ“YIC :“ πœ“Y r´p2𝜌, degqs.
Here we recall that we have a degree map Y Ď 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ Ñ Λ̌, so pairing with 2𝜌, we obtain an integer
valued function on Y: we are shifting accordingly.
Remark 5.10.2. The reason for this shift is the normalization of Theorem 4.6.1: this shift is implicit
!
there in the notation b IC π‘œ . This is also the reason for our notation πœ“YIC .
𝒡
π‘œ
π‘œ
5.11. Recall that πš₯ denotes the embedding 𝒡 ãÑ π’΅. We let πš₯8¨π‘₯ denote the map 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ ãÑ π’΅ 8¨π‘₯ .
Let:
»
Λ‡ β™‘ Ñ
Satβ™‘
Sphβ™‘
π‘₯ : Repp𝐺q Ý
𝐺,π‘₯
denote the geometric Satake equivalence. Then let:
Λ‡ Ñ Sph𝐺,π‘₯
Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
: Repp𝐺q
π‘₯
denote the induced monoidal functor.
We then define Chevgeom
as the following composition:
ň,π‘₯
´Λ™πœ“ IC
Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
Λ‡ ÝÝÝπ‘₯ÝÝÑ Sph𝐺,π‘₯ ÝÝÝÝYÑ
Repp𝐺q
!
πš₯˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ b
𝒡
8¨π‘₯,!
8¨π‘₯ πš₯
IC π‘œ q–modfact
q ÝÝÝÑ
𝑒𝑛 p𝒡
𝒡
(5.11.1)
π‘œ
!
pπœ“ π‘œ b
𝒡
π‘œ
πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯
˚,𝑑𝑅
8¨π‘₯
IC π‘œ q–modfact
q ÝÝÝÑ
𝑒𝑛 p𝒡
𝒡
Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
Here in the last step, we have appealed to the identification:
!
π‘œ
πœ‹ ˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ“ π‘œ b IC π‘œ qq “ Υň
𝒡
𝒡
of Theorem 4.6.1. We also abuse notation in not distinguishing between πœ“YIC and its ˚-pushforward
to 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ .
5.12. Global interpretation. As promised in Remark 5.8.2, we will now give a description of the
functor Chevgeom
in the case 𝑋 is proper.
ň,π‘₯
Since 𝑋 is proper, we can speak about Bun𝑁 ´ and its relatives. Let Wβ„Žπ‘–π‘‘ P 𝐷pBun𝑁 ´ q denote
the canonical Whittaker sheaf, i.e., the !-pullback of the exponential sheaf on Gπ‘Ž (normalized as
always to be in perverse degree ´1). We then have the functor:
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Λ‡ Ñ π·pDivΛ̌
Repp𝐺q
eff
q
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
35
8¨π‘₯
given by applying geometric Satake, convolving with the p˚ “!q-pushforward of Wβ„Žπ‘–π‘‘ to 𝐷pBun𝑁 ´ q,
π‘œ
π‘œ
and then !-pulling back to 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ and ˚-pushing forward along πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯ .
8¨π‘₯
Since !-pullback from Bun𝑁 ´ to 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ commutes with Hecke functors, up to the cohomological
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
shifts by degrees, this functor computes the object of 𝐷pDivΛ̌
q underlying the factorization
eff
geom
Υň -module coming from Chevň,π‘₯ .
5.13. Spectral Chevalley functor. We need some remarks on factorization modules for Υň :
Recall from Remark 4.3.2 that Υň is defined as the chiral enveloping algebra of the graded Lie-˚
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
algebra nΜŒπ‘‹ P 𝐷pDivΛ̌
:
eff q. By Remark 5.6.1, we may speak of Lie-˚ modules for nΜŒπ‘‹ on Diveff
the definition follows [Ras1] S7.19. Let nΜŒπ‘‹ –modπ‘₯ denote the DG category of Lie-˚ modules for
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
nΜŒπ‘‹ supported on Gr𝑇,π‘₯ Ď Diveff
(this embedding is as divisors supported at π‘₯). We have a
tautological equivalence:
nΜŒπ‘‹ –modπ‘₯ » ň–modpRepp𝑇ˇqq
(5.13.1)
coming from identifying Repp𝑇ˇq with the DG category of Λ̌-graded vector spaces. Note that the
right hand side of this equation is just the category of Λ̌-graded ň-representations.
Moreover, by [Ras1] S7.19, we have an induction functor Indπ‘β„Ž : nΜŒπ‘‹ –modπ‘₯ Ñ Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
spec
fact
Λ‡
We then define Chevň,π‘₯ : Repp𝐺q Ñ Υň –mod𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ as the composition:
(5.13.1)
Oblv
Oblv
Ind
Λ‡ Ý
Λ‡ Ý
Repp𝐺q
ÝÝÑ Repp𝐡q
ÝÝÑ ň–modpRepp𝑇ˇqq » nΜŒπ‘‹ –modπ‘₯ ÝÝÝÑ Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
π‘β„Ž
(5.13.2)
5.14. Formulation of the main result. We can now give the main result of this section.
geom
Theorem 5.14.1. There exists a canonical isomorphism between the functors Chevspec
ň,π‘₯ and Chevň,π‘₯ .
The proof will be given in S5.16 below after some preliminary remarks.
Remark 5.14.2. As stated, the result is a bit flimsy: we only claim that there is an identification
of functors. The purpose of S7 is essentially to strengthen this identification so that it preserves
Λ‡
structure encoding something about the symmetric monoidal structure of Repp𝐺q.
5.15. Equalizing the Hecke action. Suppose temporarily that 𝑋 is a smooth proper curve. One
8¨π‘₯
then has the following relationship between Hecke functors acting on Bun𝐡 and Hecke functors
8¨π‘₯
acting on Bun𝑁 ´ .
8¨π‘₯
8¨π‘₯
Let 𝛼 (resp. 𝛽) denote the projection 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ Ñ Bun𝑁 ´ (resp. 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ Ñ Bun𝐡 ). Recall that 𝛼!
and 𝛽 ! commute with the actions of Sph𝐺,π‘₯ .
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Let πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯ denote the canonical map 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ Ñ DivΛ̌
eff
8¨π‘₯
𝐷pBun𝑁 ´ q,
Lemma 5.15.1. For F P
fication:
GP
8¨π‘₯
𝐷pBun𝐡 q,
.
and S P Sph𝐺,π‘₯ , there is a canonical identi-
´
¯
´
¯
!
!
8¨π‘₯
8¨π‘₯
πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅
𝛼! pS Λ™ Fq b 𝛽 ! pGq q » πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅
𝛼! pFq b 𝛽 ! pS Λ™ Gq .
More precisely, we have a canonical functor:
8¨π‘₯
𝐷pBun𝑁 ´ q
computed using the above.
b
Sph𝐺,π‘₯
8¨π‘₯
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Λ̌
𝐷pBun𝐡 q Ñ π·pDiveff
q
36
SAM RASKIN
Proof. By base-change, each of these functors is constructed by pullback-pushforward along some
8¨π‘₯
8¨π‘₯
correspondence between Bun𝑁 ´ ˆ 𝐺p𝑂π‘₯ qz Gr𝐺,π‘₯ ˆBun𝐡 and Div8¨π‘₯
eff .
In both cases, one finds that this correspondence is just the Hecke groupoid (at π‘₯) for Zastava,
8¨π‘₯
8¨π‘₯
mapping via β„Ž1 to Bun𝑁 ´ and via β„Ž2 to Bun𝐡 .
5.16.
We now give the proof of Theorem 5.14.1.
Λ‡ is semi-simple, we reduce to showing this for 𝑉 “ 𝑉 πœ†Λ‡ an
Proof of Theorem 5.14.1. As Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ P Λ̌` .
irreducible highest weight representation with highest weight πœ†
Our technique follows that of Theorem 4.4.1.
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Λ̌
Step 1. Let 𝑗 : π‘ˆ ãÑ Diveff
be the locally closed subscheme parametrizing divisors of the form:
Λ‡ ¨π‘₯`
𝑀0 pπœ†q
ÿ
𝛼
Λ‡ 𝑖 ¨ π‘₯𝑖
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,simple
where π‘₯𝑖 P 𝑋 are pairwise disjoint and distinct from π‘₯ (this is the analogue of the open DivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
DivΛ̌
which
appeared
in
the
proof
of
Theorem
4.4.1).
eff
We have an easy commutative diagram:
Λ‡
πœ†
𝑗! 𝑗 ! Chevgeom
ň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q
Λ‡
πœ†
Chevgeom
ň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q
»
Ď
Λ‡
/ 𝑗! 𝑗 ! Chevspec p𝑉 πœ†Λ‡ q “ 𝑑𝑀0 pπœ†q pΥň q
ň,π‘₯
˚,𝑑𝑅
(5.16.1)
Λ‡
πœ†
Chevspec
ň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q.
One easily sees that the right vertical map is an epimorphism (this is [BG2] Lemma 9.2).
It suffices to show that the left vertical map in (5.16.1) is an epimorphism, and that there exists
a (necessarily unique) isomorphism in the bottom row of the diagram (5.16.1).
This statement is local on 𝑋, and therefore we can (and do) assume that 𝑋 is proper in what
follows.
Step 2. Next, we show that
Λ‡ we have:
By Lemma 5.15.1, for every representation 𝑉 of 𝐺
!
!
𝛼! pSatπ‘₯ p𝑉 q Λ™ Wβ„Žπ‘–π‘‘q b 𝛽 ! pICBun𝐡 q » 𝛼! pWβ„Žπ‘–π‘‘q b 𝛽 ! pSatπ‘₯ p𝑉 q Λ™ ICBun𝐡 q.
(5.16.2)
8¨π‘₯
Of course, here ICBun𝐡 indicates the ˚-extension of this 𝐷-module to Bun𝐡 .
8¨π‘₯
Then by definition, Chevgeom
ň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q is obtained by applying πœ‹Λš,𝑑𝑅 to the left hand side of (5.16.2).
Comparing this to the right hand side, we then obtain the result from Theorem 3.4.1 and from S9
of [BG2].
As in the proof of Theorem 3.3.2 from [BG1], the Mirkovic-Vilonen [MV] realization of weight
8¨π‘₯
Λ‡
spaces of 𝑉 πœ† as semi-infinite integrals, and the fact that ICBun𝐡 P 𝐷pBun𝐡 q is equivariant for the
Hecke action for 𝐡 (not 𝐺!), imply the claim (c.f. the discussion of [BG2] preceding the statement
of Theorem 8.8).
Step 3. We will use (a slight variant of) the following construction.27
27As Dennis Gaitsgory pointed out to us, one can argue somewhat more directly, by combining Lemma 5.15.1 with
Theorem 8.11 from [BG2] (and the limiting case of the Casselman-Shalika formula, Theorem 3.4.1).
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
37
Suppose that π‘Œ is a variety and F P 𝐷pπ‘Œ ˆ A1 qGπ‘š is Gπ‘š -equivariant for the action of Gπ‘š by
homotheties on the second factor, and that F is concentrated in negative (perverse) cohomological
degrees.
For 𝑐 P π‘˜, let 𝑖𝑐 denote the embedding π‘Œ ˆ t𝑐u ãÑ π‘Œ ˆ A1 .
Then, for each π‘˜ P Z, the theory of vanishing cycles furnishes specialization maps:
𝐻 π‘˜ p𝑖!1 pFqq Ñ π» π‘˜ p𝑖!0 pFqq P 𝐷pπ‘Œ qβ™‘
(5.16.3)
that are functorial in F, and which is an epimorphism for π‘˜ “ 0. Indeed, these maps arise from the
boundary map in the triangle:28
var
`1
𝑖!0 pFq Ñ Φ𝑒𝑛 pFq ÝÝÑ Ψ𝑒𝑛 pFq ÝÝÑ
when we use Gπ‘š -equivariance to identify Ψ𝑒𝑛 pFq with F1 r1s. The 𝑑-exactness of Φ𝑒𝑛 and the
assumption that F is in degrees Δƒ 0 shows that (5.16.3) is an epimorphism for π‘˜ “ 0:
. . . Ñ π» ´1 pΨ𝑒𝑛 pFqq “ 𝐻 0 p𝑖!1 pFqq Ñ π» 0 p𝑖!0 pF0 qq Ñ π» 0 pΦ𝑒𝑛 pFqq “ 0
Step 4. We now apply the previous discussion to see that:
spec
Chevgeom
ň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q » Chevň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Λ‡ β™‘ finite-dimensional.
q for 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
as objects of 𝐷pDiveff
Forget for the moment that we chose Chevalley generators t𝑓𝑖 u and let π‘Š denote the vector
π‘œ
space pn´ {rn´ , n´ sq˚ . Note that 𝑇 acts on π‘Š through its adjoint action on n´ . Let π‘Š Ď π‘Š denote
the open subscheme corresponding to non-degenerate characters.
Then we have a canonical map:
Y ˆ π‘Š Ñ Gπ‘Ž
by imitating the construction of the map can : 𝒡 Ñ Gπ‘Ž of (2.8.2). Note that this map is 𝑇 equivariant for the diagonal action on the source and the trivial action on the target.29
Let W P 𝐷p𝒡 8¨π‘₯ ˆ π‘Š q𝑇 denote the result of !-pulling back of the exponential 𝐷-module on Gπ‘Ž
to Y ˆ π‘Š and then ˚-extending. We then define:
´
¯
r :“ pπœ‹π‘œ 8¨π‘₯ ˆ idπ‘Š q˚,𝑑𝑅 pπš₯8¨π‘₯ ˆ idπ‘Š q! Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’ p𝑉 q Λ™ Wr´p2𝜌, degqs P 𝐷pDivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯ ˆπ‘Š q𝑇 .
W
π‘₯
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
Here the 𝑇 -equivariance now refers to the 𝑇 -action coming from the trivial action on Diveff
.
The notation for the cohomological shift is as in S5.10.
π‘œ
r are constant along the open stratum DivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯ ˆπ‘Š .
By 𝑇 -equivariance, the cohomologies of our W
eff
r is concentrated in cohomological degrees ď ´ rankp𝐺q “ ´ dimpπ‘Š q: as
Moreover, note that W
in Step 2, Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
p𝑉 q Λ™ Wr´p2𝜌, degqs has a filtration by translates of W, which then gives the
π‘₯
π‘œ
claim by ind-affineness of πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯ .
Therefore, !-restricting to the line through our given non-degenerate character, Step 3 gives us
the specialization map:
28Our nearby and vanishing cycles functors are normalized to preserve perversity.
29We use the canonical 𝑇 -action on 𝒡, coming from the action of 𝑇 on Bun ´ induced by its adjoint action on 𝑁 ´ .
𝑁
38
SAM RASKIN
` π‘œ 8¨π‘₯ 8¨π‘₯,!
˘
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯ β™‘
q .
𝐻 0 πœ‹ ˚,𝑑𝑅
πš₯
pSatπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
p𝑉 q Λ™ πœ”Y r´p2𝜌, degqsqq Ñ π» 0 pChevgeom
π‘₯
ň,π‘₯ p𝑉 qq P 𝐷pDiveff
By Step 3, this specialization map is an epimorphism.
However, the Zastava space version of Theorem 8.8 from [BG2] (which is implicit in loc. cit.
and easy to deduce from there) implies that the left hand term coincides with Chevspec
ň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q, and
therefore this map is an isomorphism by the computation in the Grothendieck group.
Moreover, one immediately sees that this picture is compatible with the diagram (5.16.1), and
therefore we actually do obtain an isomorphism of factorization modules, as desired.
6. Around factorizable Satake
6.1. Our goal in S7 is to prove a generalization of Theorem 5.14.1 in which we treat several
points tπ‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯𝑛 u Ď 𝑋, allowing these points to move and collide (in the sense of the Ran space
formalism). This section plays a supplementary and technical role for this purpose.
6.2. Generalizing the geometric side of Theorem 5.14.1 is an old idea: one should use the BeilinsonDrinfeld affine Grassmannian Gr𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 and the corresponding factorizable version of the Satake
category.
Therefore, we need a geometric Satake theorem over powers of the curve. This has been treated
in [Gai1], but the treatment of loc. cit. is inconvenient for us, relying too much on specific aspects
of perverse sheaves that do not generalize to non-holonomic 𝐷-modules.
6.3. The goal for this section is to give a treatment of factorizable geometric Satake for 𝐷-modules.
However, most of the work here actually goes into treating formal properties of the spectral side
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 which provide factorizable versions of
of this equivalence. Here we have DG categories Repp𝐺q
Λ‡
the category Repp𝐺q appearing in the Satake theory.
These categories arise from a general construction, taking C a symmetric monoidal object of
DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ (so we assume the tensor product commutes with colimits in each variable), and producing C𝑋 𝐼 P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q. As we will see, this construction is especially well-behaved
Λ‡
for C rigid monoidal (as for C “ Repp𝐺q).
6.4. Structure of this section. We treat the construction and general properties of the categories
C𝑋 𝐼 in S6.5-6.18, especially treating the case where C is rigid. We specialize to the case where C is
representations of an affine algebraic group in S6.19.
We then discuss the (naive) factorizable Satake theorem from S6.28 until the end of this section.
6.5. Let C P ComAlgpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q be a symmetric monoidal DG category. We denote the monoidal
operation in C by b.
6.6. Factorization. Recall from [Ras1] S7 that we have an operation attaching to each finite set
𝐼 a 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-module category C𝑋 𝐼 .30
We will give an essentially self-contained treatment of this construction below, but first give
examples to give the reader a feeling for the construction.
Example 6.6.1. For 𝐼 “ ˚, we have C𝑋 “ C b 𝐷p𝑋q.
30In [Ras1], we use the notation Γp𝑋 𝐼 , Loc 𝐼 pCqq in place of C 𝐼 .
𝑑𝑅
𝑋
𝑋
𝑑𝑅
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
39
Example 6.6.2. Let 𝐼 “ t1, 2u. Let 𝑗 denote the open embedding π‘ˆ “ 𝑋 ˆ 𝑋z𝑋 ãÑ π‘‹ ˆ 𝑋.
Then we have a fiber square:
/ C b 𝐷p𝑋 2 q
C𝑋 2
`
idC b𝑗 !
˘
C b C b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ q
/ C b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ q.
p´b´qbid𝐷p𝑋 2 q
We emphasize that p´ b ´q indicates the tensor product morphism C b C Ñ C.
Example 6.6.3. If 𝛀 is an affine algebraic group and we take C “ Repp𝛀 q, then the above says that
2 with the structure of a 𝛀 ˆπ›€ -representation
Repp𝛀 q𝑋 2 parametrizes a representation of 𝛀 over 𝑋𝑑𝑅
on the complement to the diagonal, compatible under the diagonal embedding 𝛀 ãÑ π›€ ˆ 𝛀 .
6.7. For the general construction of C𝑋 𝐼 , we need the following combinatorics.
First, for any surjection 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽 of finite sets, let π‘ˆ p𝑝q denote the open subscheme of points
pπ‘₯𝑖 q𝑖P𝐼 with π‘₯𝑖 ‰ π‘₯𝑖1 whenever 𝑝p𝑖q ‰ 𝑝p𝑖1 q.
id
𝐼
of
Example 6.7.1. For 𝑝 : 𝐼 Ñ Λš, we have π‘ˆ p𝑝q “ 𝑋 𝐼 . For 𝑝 : 𝐼 Ý
Ñ πΌ, π‘ˆ p𝑝q is the locus 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
𝐼
pairwise disjoint points in 𝑋 .
𝑝
π‘ž
We let S𝐼 denote the p1, 1q-category indexing data 𝐼 𝐽 𝐾, where we allow morphisms of
diagrams that are contravariant in 𝐽 and covariant in 𝐾, and surjective termwise.
6.8.
𝑝
π‘ž
For every Σ “ p𝐼 𝐽 𝐾q in S𝐼 , define CΣ P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q as:
CΣ “ 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq b Cb𝐾 .
For Σ1 Ñ Σ2 P S𝐼 , we have a canonical map CΣ1 Ñ CΣ2 P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q constructed
as follows. If the morphism Σ1 Ñ Σ2 is induced by the diagram:
𝐼
𝐼
𝑝1
𝑝2
/ / 𝐽1
OO
π‘ž1
/ / 𝐽2
π‘ž2
/ / 𝐾1
𝛼
/ / 𝐾2
then our functor is given as the tensor product of:
Cb𝐾1 Ñ Cb𝐾2
b Fπ‘˜ ÞÑ b p
π‘˜P𝐾1
b
Fπ‘˜2 q
π‘˜1 P𝐾2 π‘˜2 P𝛼´1 pπ‘˜1 q
and the 𝐷-module restriction along the map π‘ˆ p𝑝2 q Ñ π‘ˆ p𝑝1 q.
It is easy to upgrade this description to the homotopical level to define a functor:
S𝐼 Ñ π·p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q.
We define C𝑋 𝐼 as the limit of this functor.
Example 6.8.1. It is immediate to see that this description recovers our earlier formulae for 𝐼 “ ˚
and 𝐼 “ t1, 2u.
40
SAM RASKIN
Remark 6.8.2. This construction unwinds to say the following: we have an object F P C b 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
such that for every 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽, its restriction to C b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq has been lifted to an object of
Cb𝐽 b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq.
Example 6.8.3. For C “ Repp𝛀 q with 𝛀 an affine algebraic group, this construction is a derived
version of the construction of [Gai1] S2.5.
Remark 6.8.4. Obviously each C𝑋 𝐼 is a commutative algebra in 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q. Indeed,
each CΣ “ 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq b Cb𝐾 , is and the structure functors are symmetric monoidal. We have an
obvious symmetric monoidal functor:
Loc “ Loc𝑋 𝐼 : Cb𝐼 Ñ C𝑋 𝐼
for each 𝐼, with these functors being compatible under diagonal maps.
6.9. Factorization. It follows from [Ras1] S7 that the assignment 𝐼 ÞÑ C𝑋 𝐼 defines a commutative
unital chiral category on 𝑋𝑑𝑅 . For the sake of completeness, the salient pieces of structure here are
twofold:
(1) For every pair of finite sets 𝐼1 and 𝐼2 , we have a symmetric monoidal map:
C𝑋 𝐼1 b C𝑋 𝐼2 Ñ C𝑋 𝐼1 š 𝐼2
š
of 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼1 𝐼2 q-module categories that is an equivalence after tensoring with 𝐷pr𝑋 𝐼1 ˆ 𝑋 𝐼2 s𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 q.
(2) For every 𝐼1 𝐼2 , an identification:
C 𝑋 𝐼1
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼1 q
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼2 q » C𝑋 𝐼2 .
These should satisfy the obvious compatibilities, which we do not spell out here because in the
homotopical setting they are a bit difficult to say: we refer to [Ras1] S7 for a precise formulation.
We will construct these maps in S6.10 and 6.11.
š
6.10. First, suppose 𝐼 “ 𝐼1 𝐼2 .
𝑝
π‘ž
Define a functor S𝐼 Ñ S𝐼1 as follows. We send 𝐼 𝐽 𝐾 to 𝐼1 Imagep𝑝|𝐼1 q Imagepπ‘ž ˝𝑝|𝐼1 q.
It is easy to see that this actually defines a functor. We have a similar functor S𝐼 Ñ S𝐼2 , so we
obtain S𝐼 Ñ S𝐼1 ˆ S𝐼2 .
𝑝
π‘ž
𝑝1
π‘ž1
Given 𝐼 𝐽 𝐾 as above, let e.g. 𝐼1 𝐽1 𝐾1 denote the corresponding object of S𝐼1 .
We have a canonical map:
π‘ˆ p𝑝q ãÑ π‘ˆ p𝑝1 q ˆ π‘ˆ pπ‘ž1 q Ď 𝑋 𝐼1 ˆ 𝑋 𝐼2 “ 𝑋 𝐼 .
We also š
have a canonical map Cb𝐾1 b Cb𝐾2 Ñ Cb𝐾 induced by tensor product and the obvious
map 𝐾1 𝐾2 Ñ πΎ. Together, we obtain maps:
p𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝1 qq b Cb𝐾1 q b p𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝2 qq b Cb𝐾2 q Ñ π·pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq b C𝐾
that in passage to the limit define
C 𝑋 𝐼1 b C 𝑋 𝐼2 Ñ C 𝑋 𝐼 .
That this map is an equivalence over the disjoint locus follows from a cofinality argument.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
6.11.
41
Next, suppose for 𝑓 : 𝐼1 𝐼2 is given. We obtain S𝐼2 Ñ S𝐼1 by restriction.
𝑝
π‘ž
Moreover, for any given 𝐼2 𝐽 𝐾 P S𝐼2 , we have the functorial identifications:
𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq b Cb𝐾 » p𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝 ˝ 𝑓 qq
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼1 q
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼2 qq b Cb𝐾 q
that give a map:
C 𝑋 𝐼1
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼1 q
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼2 q Ñ C𝑋 𝐼2 .
An easy cofinality argument shows that this map is an equivalence.
6.12. A variant. We now discuss a variant of the preceding material a categorical level down.
6.13. First, if 𝐴 is a commutative algebra in Vect, then there is an assignment 𝐼 ÞÑ π΄π‘‹ 𝐼 P
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q defining a commutative factorization algebra. Indeed, it is given by the same procedure as
before—we have:
𝐴𝑋 𝐼 :“
𝑝
lim
π‘ž
𝑗𝑝,˚,𝑑𝑅 p𝐴b𝐾 b πœ”π‘ˆ p𝑝q q P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q.
(6.13.1)
p𝐼 𝐽 𝐾qPS𝐼
The structure maps are as before.
6.14. More generally, when C is as before and 𝐴 P C is a commutative algebra, we can attach a
(commutative) factorization algebra 𝐼 ÞÑ π΄π‘‹ 𝐼 P C𝑋 𝐼 .
We will need this construction in this generality below. However, the above formula does not
make sense, since there is no way to make sense of 𝑗𝑝,˚,𝑑𝑅 pπœ”π‘ˆ p𝑝q q b 𝐴b𝐾 as an object of C𝑋 𝐼 . So we
need the following additional remarks:
We do have 𝐴𝑋 𝐼 defined as an object of 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q b C by the above formula. Moreover, as in S6.10,
for every 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽 we have canonical “multiplication” maps:
b 𝐴𝑋 𝐼𝑗 Ñ π΄π‘‹ 𝐼 P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q b C
𝑗P𝐽
where 𝐼𝑗 is the fiber of 𝐼 at 𝑗 P 𝐽, and where our exterior product should be understood as a mix of
the tensor product for C and the exterior product of 𝐷-modules. This map is an equivalence over
π‘ˆ p𝑝q.
This says that for every 𝑝 as above, the restriction of 𝐴𝑋 𝐼 to π‘ˆ p𝑝q has a canonical structure as
an object of 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq b Cb𝐽 , lifting its structure of an object of 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq b C. Moreover, this is
compatible with further restrictions in the natural sense. This is exactly the data needed to upgrade
𝐴𝑋 𝐼 to an object of C𝑋 𝐼 (which we denote by the same name).
6.15. ULA objects. For the remainder of the section, assume that C is compactly generated and
rigid : recall that rigidity means that this means that the unit 1C is compact and every 𝑉 P C
compact admits a dual.
Under this rigidity assumption, we discuss ULA aspects of the categories C𝑋 𝐼 : we refer the reader
to Appendix B for the terminology here, which we assume for the remainder of this section.
42
SAM RASKIN
6.16. Recall that QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C𝑋 𝐼 q denotes the object of QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q obtained from
C𝑋 𝐼 P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q by induction along the (symmetric monoidal) forgetful functor
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q Ñ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q.
Proposition 6.16.1. For F P Cb𝐼 compact, Loc𝑋 𝐼 pFq P C𝑋 𝐼 is ULA.
We will deduce this from the following lemma.
Let 1C𝑋 𝑛 “ Loc𝑋 𝐼 p1C q denote the unit for the (𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-linear) symmetric monoidal structure on
C𝑋 𝑛 .
Lemma 6.16.2. 1C𝑋 𝑛 is ULA.
Proof. By 1-affineness (see [Gai4]) of 𝑋𝑑𝑅 and 𝑋, the induction functor:
𝐷p𝑋q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q Ñ QCohp𝑋q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q
commutes with limits.
It follows that QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C𝑋 𝐼 q is computed by a similar limit as defines C𝑋 𝐼 , but with QCohpπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq
replacing 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq everywhere.
Since this limit is finite and since each of the terms corresponding to Oblvp1C𝑋 𝑛 q P QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C𝑋 𝐼 q
is compact, we obtain the claim.
Proof of Proposition 6.16.1. Since the functor Cb𝐼 Ñ C𝑋 𝐼 is symmetric monoidal and since each
compact object in Cb𝐼 admits a dual by assumption, we immediately obtain the result from Lemma
6.16.2.
Remark 6.16.3. Proposition 6.16.1 fails for more general C: the tensor product C b C Ñ C typically
fails to preserve compact objects, which implies that Loc𝑋 2 does not preserve compacts.
6.17. We now deduce the following result about the categories C𝑋 𝐼 (for the terminology, see
Definition B.6.1).
Theorem 6.17.1. C𝑋 𝐼 is ULA over 𝑋 𝐼 .
We will use the following lemma, which is implicit but not quite stated in [Gai4].
Lemma 6.17.2. Let 𝑆 be a (possibly DG) scheme (almost) of finite type, and let 𝑖 : 𝑇 ãÑ π‘† be a
closed subscheme with complement 𝑗 : π‘ˆ ãÑ π‘†. For D P QCohp𝑆q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q, the composite
functor:
Kerp𝑗 ˚ : D Ñ Dπ‘ˆ q ãÑ D Ñ D
b
QCohp𝑆q
QCohp𝑆𝑇^ q
(6.17.1)
is an equivalence, where 𝑆𝑇^ is the formal completion of 𝑆 along 𝑇 .
Proof. By [Gai4] Proposition 4.1.5, the restriction functor:
QCohp𝑆𝑇^ q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q Ñ QCohp𝑆q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q
is fully-faithful with essential image being those module categories on which objects of QCohpπ‘ˆ q Ď
QCohp𝑆q act by zero. But the endofunctor Kerp𝑗 ˚ q of QCohp𝑆q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q is a localization
functor for the same subcategory, giving the claim.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
43
Proof of Theorem 6.17.1. Suppose G P QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C𝑋 𝐼 q is some object with:
HomQCohp𝑋 𝐼 ,C
𝑋𝐼
q pP
b Oblv Loc𝑋 𝐼 pFq, Gq “ 0
for all P P QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q perfect and all F P Cb𝐼 compact. Then by Proposition 6.16.1, it suffices to
show that G “ 0.
Fix 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽. We will show by decreasing induction on |𝐽| that the restriction of G to π‘ˆ p𝑝q is
zero.
𝐽
We have the closed embedding 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
ãÑ π‘ˆ p𝑝q with complement being the union:
ď
𝐽
π‘ˆ p𝑝qzp𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
q“
π‘ˆ pπ‘žq.
π‘ž1
π‘ž
𝐼 𝐽 1 𝐽,π‘ž 1 π‘ž“𝑝
‰
In particular, the inductive hypothesis implies that the restriction of G to this complement is zero.
𝐽
in π‘ˆ p𝑝q and let 𝑖𝑝 : X ãÑ π‘ˆ p𝑝q denote the embedding.
Let X denote the formal completion of 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
By Lemma 6.17.2, it suffices to show that:
π‘–Λšπ‘ pGq “ 0 P QCohpX, C𝑋 𝐼 q :“ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C𝑋 𝐼 q
b
QCohpXq.
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q
𝐼 factors through 𝑋 𝐽
The map X Ñ π‘‹π‘‘π‘…
𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗,𝑑𝑅 (embedded via 𝑝), so by factorization we have:
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C𝑋 𝐼 q
b
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q
QCohpXq “ C𝑋 𝐼
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
QCohpXq » Cb𝐽 b QCohpXq.
𝑝
This identification is compatible with the functors Loc in the following way. Let b : Cb𝐼 Ñ Cb𝐽
denote the map induced by the tensor structure on C. We then have a commutative diagram:
Cb𝐼
Loc𝑋 𝐼
/C 𝐼
𝑋
/ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C 𝐼 q
𝑋
𝑝
π‘–Λš
𝑝
b
Cb𝐽
id bOX
/ Cb𝐽 b QCohpXq.
by construction.
Since QCohpXq is compactly generated by objects of the form π‘–Λšπ‘ pPq with P P QCohpπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq perfect
𝐽 ), we reduce to the following:
(and with set-theoretic support in 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
Each F P Cb𝐽 compact then defines a continuous functor 𝐹F : Cb𝐽 b QCohpXq Ñ QCohpXq, and
our claim amounts to showing that an object in Cb𝐽 b QCohpXq is zero if and only if each functor
𝐹F annihilates it, but this is obvious e.g. from the theory of dualizable categories.
6.18. Dualizability. Next, we record the following technical result.
Lemma 6.18.1. For every D P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q, the canonical map:
C𝑋 𝐼
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
´
D“
𝑝
lim
π‘ž
p𝐼 𝐽 𝐾qPS𝐼
is an equivalence.
Cb𝐾 b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq
¯
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
DÑ
𝑝
lim
π‘ž
p𝐼 𝐽 𝐾qPS𝐼
´
Cb𝐾 b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
¯
D
44
SAM RASKIN
This proof is digressive, so we postpone the proof to Appendix A, assuming it for the remainder
of this section.
We obtain the following consequence.31
Corollary 6.18.2. C𝑋 𝐼 is dualizable and self-dual as a 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-module category.
Remark 6.18.3. In fact, one can avoid the full strength of Lemma 6.18.1 for our purposes: we include
it because it gives an aesthetically nicer treatment, and because it appears to be an important
technical result that should be included for the sake of completeness.
With that said, we apply it below only for D “ Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 , and here it is easier: it follows from the
dualizability of Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 as a 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-module category, which is much more straightforward.
6.19.
Let 𝛀 be an affine algebraic group. We now specialize the above to the case C “ Repp𝛀 q.
6.20. Induction. Our main tool in treating Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 is the good behavior of the induction functor
𝐼
Av𝑀
𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ : 𝐷p𝑋 q Ñ Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 introduced below.
6.21. The symmetric monoidal forgetful functor Oblv : Repp𝛀 q Ñ Vect induces a conservative
functor Oblv𝑋 𝐼 : Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 Ñ π·p𝑋 𝐼 q compatible with 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-linear symmetric monoidal structures.
We abuse notation in also letting Oblv𝑋 𝐼 denote the QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q-linear functor:
Oblv𝑋 𝐼 : QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 q Ñ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q
promising the reader to always take caution to make clear which functor we mean in the sequel.
6.22. Applying the discussion of S6.14, we obtain O𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 P Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 factorizable corresponding to
the regular representation O𝛀 P Repp𝛀 q of 𝛀 (so we are not distinguishing between the sheaf O𝛀
and its global sections in this notation).32
Proposition 6.22.1.
(1) The functor Oblv𝑋 𝐼 : Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 Ñ π·p𝑋 𝐼 q admits a 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-linear
𝑀
33
right adjoint Av𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ : 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q Ñ Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 compatible with factorization.34
(2) The functor Av𝑀
𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ maps πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 to the factorization algebra O𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 introduced above.
Proof. By Proposition B.7.1 and Theorem 6.17.1, it suffices to show that Oblv𝑋 𝐼 maps the ULA
generators Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q of Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 to ULA objects of 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q, which is obvious.
For the second part, note that the counit map O𝛀 Ñ π‘˜ P ComAlgpVectq induces a map Oblv𝑋 𝐼 O𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ
πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q factorizably, and therefore induces factorizable maps:
O𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Av𝑀
𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ pπœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q.
By factorization, it is enough to show that this map is an equivalence for 𝐼 “ ˚, where it is clear.
31We remark that this result is strictly weaker than the above, and more direct to prove.
𝐼
32The 𝐷-module Oblv 𝐼 pO
𝑋
𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 q P 𝐷p𝑋 q (or its shift cohomologically up by |𝐼|, depending on one’s conventions)
appears in [BD] as factorization algebra associated with the the constant 𝐷𝑋 -scheme 𝛀 ˆ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ π‘‹ 𝐼 .
33The superscript 𝑀 stands for “weak,” and is included for compatibility with [FG2] S20.
34More generally, the proof below shows that the analogous statement holds more generally for any symmetric
monoidal functor 𝐹 : C Ñ D P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ with C rigid, where this is generalizing the forgetful functor Oblv :
Repp𝛀 q Ñ Vect.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
45
6.23. Coalgebras. We now realize the categories Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 in more explicit terms.
Lemma 6.23.1. The functor Oblv𝑋 𝐼 is comonadic, i.e., satisfies the conditions of the comonadic
Barr-Beck theorem.
In fact, we will prove the following strengthening:
Lemma 6.23.2. For any D P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q, the forgetful functor:
Oblv𝑋 𝐼 b idD : Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
DÑD
is comonadic.
Proof. Using Lemma 6.18.1, we deduce that Oblv𝑋 𝐼 b idD arises by passage to the limit over S𝐼
from the compatible system of functors:
Repp𝛀 qb𝐾 b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
D Ñ π·pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
D.
Therefore, it suffices to show that each of these functors is conservative and commutes with Oblvsplit totalizations.
But by [Gai4] Theorem 2.2.2 and Lemma 5.5.4, the functor Repp𝛀 𝑛 q b E Ñ E is comonadic for
any E P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ . This obviously gives the claim.
6.24. 𝑑-structures. It turns out that the categories Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 admit particularly favorable 𝑑structures.
Proposition 6.24.1. There is a unique 𝑑-structure on Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 (resp. QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 q) such
that Oblv𝑋 𝐼 is 𝑑-exact. This 𝑑-structure is left and right complete.
Proof. We first treat the quasi-coherent case.
𝑝
π‘ž
For every p𝐼 𝐽 𝐾q P S𝐼 , the category:
Repp𝛀 qb𝐽 b QCohpπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq “ QCohpB𝛀 𝐽 ˆ π‘ˆ p𝑝qq
admits a canonical 𝑑-structure, since it is quasi-coherent sheaves on an algebraic stack. This 𝑑structure is left and right exact, and the forgetful functor to QCohpπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq is obviously 𝑑-exact.
Moreover, the structure functors corresponding to maps in S𝐼 are 𝑑-exact, and therefore we obtain
a 𝑑-structure with the desired properties on the limit, which is QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 q.
We now deduce the 𝐷-module version. We have the adjoint functors:35
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 q o
Ind
Oblv
/ Repp𝛀 q 𝐼 .
𝑋
Since the monad Oblv Ind is 𝑑-exact on QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 q and since Oblv is conservative, it
follows that Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 admits a unique 𝑑-structure such that the functor36 Oblvrdimp𝑋 𝐼 qs “
Oblvr|𝐼|s : Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 Ñ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 q is 𝑑-exact. Since this functor is continuous and commutes with limits (being a right adjoint), this 𝑑-structure on Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 is left and right complete.
35Apologies are due to the reader for using the different functors Oblv and Oblv 𝐼 in almost the same breath.
𝑋
36We use a cohomological shift here since for 𝑆 smooth, Oblv : 𝐷p𝑆q Ñ QCohp𝑆q only 𝑑-exact up to shift by the
dimension, since Oblvpπœ”π‘† q “ O𝑆 . This is because we are working with the so-called left forgetful functor, not the
right one.
46
SAM RASKIN
It remains to see that Oblv𝑋 𝐼 : Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 Ñ π·p𝑋 𝐼 q is 𝑑-exact. This is immediate: we see that
Oblvr|𝐼|s
the 𝑑-structure we have constructed is the unique one for which the composition Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ÝÝÝÝÝÑ
Oblv
Oblv
𝐼
𝐼
QCohpRepp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 q ÝÝÝÝ𝑋ÝÑ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q is 𝑑-exact, and this composition coincides with Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ÝÝÝÝ𝑋ÝÑ
Oblvr|𝐼|s
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q ÝÝÝÝÝÑ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q. We obtain the claim, since the standard 𝑑-structure on 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q is the
unique one for which Oblv𝑋 𝐼 r|𝐼|s : 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q Ñ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q is 𝑑-exact.
𝐼
Proposition 6.24.2. The functor Av𝑀
𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ : 𝐷p𝑋 q Ñ Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 is 𝑑-exact for the 𝑑-structure
of Proposition 6.24.1, and similarly for the corresponding quasi-coherent functor QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q Ñ
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 q.
We will use the following result of [BD]. We include a proof for completeness.
Lemma 6.24.3. Let 𝐴 P Vectβ™‘ be a classical (unital) commutative algebra and let 𝐼 ÞÑ π΄π‘‹ 𝐼 P
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q be the corresponding factorization algebra. Then 𝐴𝑋 𝐼 r´|𝐼|s P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 qβ™‘ .
Proof. We can assume |𝐼| Δ… 1, since otherwise the result is clear.
Choose 𝑖, 𝑗 P 𝐼 distinct. Let 𝐼 𝐼 be the set obtained by contracting 𝑖 and 𝑗 onto a single
element (so |𝐼| “ |𝐼| ´ 1).
The map 𝐼 𝐼 defines a diagonal closed embedding βˆ† : 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ π‘‹ 𝐼 . Let 𝑗 : π‘ˆ ãÑ π‘‹ 𝐼 denote the
complement, which here is affine.
Since βˆ†! p𝐴𝑋 𝐼 q “ 𝐴𝑋 𝐼 , the result follows inductively if we show that the map π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝑗 ! p𝐴𝑋 𝐼 q Ñ
βˆ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 βˆ†! p𝐴𝑋 𝐼 qr1s is surjective after taking cohomology in degree ´|𝐼|.
š
Writing 𝐼 “ t𝑖u 𝐼 using the evident splitting, we obtain the following commutative diagram
from unitality of 𝐴 and from the commutative factorization structure:
πœ”π‘‹ b 𝐴 𝑋 𝐼
/ π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝑗 ! pπœ”π‘‹ b 𝐴 𝐼 q
𝑋
𝐴𝑋 b 𝐴𝑋 𝐼
π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝑗 ! p𝐴𝑋 b 𝐴𝑋 𝐼 q
/ π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝑗 ! p𝐴 𝐼 q
𝑋
𝐴𝑋 𝐼
/ βˆ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 p𝐴 𝐼 qr1s
𝑋
»
/ βˆ†Λš,𝑑𝑅 βˆ†! p𝐴 𝐼 qr1s
𝑋
The top line is obviously (by induction) a short exact sequence in the |𝐼|-shifted heart of the
𝑑-structure. Since the right vertical map is an isomorphism, this implies the claim.
Proof of Proposition 6.24.2. E.g., in the quasi-coherent setting: it suffices to show that Av𝑀
𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ ˝ Oblv𝑋 𝐼
𝐼
is 𝑑-exact. This composition is given by tensoring with O𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 P 𝐷p𝑋 q by construction, which we
have just seen is in the heart of the 𝑑-structure (since Oblv : 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q Ñ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q is 𝑑-exact only
after a shift by |𝐼|).
It follows that this functor is right 𝑑-exact, since it is given by tensoring with something in the
heart. But it is also left 𝑑-exact, since it is right adjoint to the 𝑑-exact functor Oblv𝑋 𝐼 .
Corollary 6.24.4. Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 is the derived category of the heart of this 𝑑-structure.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
47
Proof. At the level of bounded below derived categories, this is a formal consequence of the corresponding fact for 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q and the fact that Oblv𝑋 𝐼 and Av𝑀
𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ are 𝑑-exact.
To treat unbounded derived categories, it suffices to show that the derived category of Repp𝛀 qβ™‘
𝑋𝐼
is left complete, but this is clear: the category has finite homological dimension.
6.25. Constructibility. We now show how to recover Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 from a holonomic version.
This material is not necessary for our purposes, but we include it for completeness. The reader
may safely skip straight to S6.28.
6.26. Let π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q Ď 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q denote the ind-completion of the subcategory of 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q formed by
compact objects (i.e., coherent 𝐷-modules) that are holonomic in the usual sense. We emphasize
that we allow infinite direct sums of holonomic objects to be counted as such.
Definition 6.26.1. Define the holonomic subcategory Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ of Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 to consist of those
objects that map into π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q under the forgetful functor.
Remark 6.26.2. We have:
Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ »
limπ‘ž
𝑝
Repp𝛀 qb𝐾 b π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq Ď
p𝐼 𝐽 𝐾q
limπ‘ž
𝑝
Repp𝛀 qb𝐾 b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq “: Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 .
(6.26.1)
p𝐼 𝐽 𝐾q
Indeed, the key point is that Repp𝛀 qb𝐾 b π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq Ñ Repp𝛀 qb𝐾 b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq is actually fullyfaithful, and this follows from the general fact that tensoring a fully-faithful functor (here π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq ãÑ
𝐷pπ‘ˆ p𝑝qq with a dualizable category (here Repp𝛀 qb𝐾 ) gives a fully-faithful functor.
Since e.g. for each 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽, π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐽 q is dualizable as a π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q-module category (for
the same reason as for the non-holonomic categories), we deduce that Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ satisfies the
same factorization patterns at Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 , but with holonomic 𝐷-module categories being used
everywhere. Indeed, the arguments we gave were basically formal cofinality arguments, and therefore
apply verbatim.
6.27.
We have the following technical result.
Proposition 6.27.1. The functor:
Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™
b
π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™
p𝑋 𝐼 q
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q Ñ Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼
is an equivalence.
Remark 6.27.2. In light of (6.26.1), this amounts to commuting a limit with a tensor product.
However, we are not sure how to use this perspective to give a direct argument, since 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q is
(almost surely) not dualizable as a π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q-module category.
Proof of Proposition 6.27.1. The idea is to appeal to use Proposition B.8.1.
Step 1. Let 𝑉 P Repp𝛀 qb𝐼 be given. We claim that Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q lies in Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ and that induced
object of Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™
b 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q is ULA in this category (considered as a 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-module
π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q
category in the obvious way) if 𝑉 is compact.
Indeed, that Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q is holonomic follows since Oblv𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q is lisse. The ULA condition then
follows from Proposition B.5.1 and Remark B.5.2.
48
SAM RASKIN
Step 2. Next, we claim that Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ is generated as a π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q-module category by the
objects Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q, 𝑉 P Repp𝛀 qb𝐼 , i.e., the minimal π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q-module subcategory of Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™
containing the Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q is the whole category.
Indeed, this follows as in the proof of Theorem 6.17.1.
Step 3. We now claim that Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™
We have to show that Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼
b
b
π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q
π·β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ p𝑋 𝐼 q
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q is ULA as a 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-module category.
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q is generated as a QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q-module category
by objects coming from Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q. But this is clear from Step 2.
Step 4. Finally, we apply Proposition B.8.1 to obtain the result:
Our functor sends a set of ULA generators to ULA objects. And moreover, by Remark 6.26.2,
𝐽 q for each 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽, giving the result.
this functor is an equivalence after tensoring with 𝐷p𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
Remark 6.27.3. Taking (6.26.1) as a definition of C𝑋 𝐼 ,β„Žπ‘œπ‘™ for general rigid C, the above argument
shows that the analogue of Proposition 6.27.1 is true in this generality.
Λ‡
6.28. The naive Satake functor. We now specialize the above to 𝛀 “ 𝐺.
6.29. Digression: more on twists. We will work with Grassmannians and loop groups twisted
by π’«π‘‡π‘π‘Žπ‘› as in S2.14.
To define Gr𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 for 𝛀 P t𝑇, 𝐡, 𝑁 ´ , 𝐺u, one exactly follows S2.14.
Similarly, we have a group scheme (resp. group indscheme) 𝛀 p𝑂q𝑋 𝐼 (resp. 𝛀 p𝐾q𝑋 𝐼 ) over 𝑋 𝐼 for
𝛀 as above, where 𝛀 p𝐾q𝑋 𝐼 acts on Gr𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 . Trivializing π’«π‘‡π‘π‘Žπ‘› locally on 𝑋 𝐼 , the picture becomes the
usual picture for factorizable versions of the arc and loop groups: c.f. [BD] and [KV] for example.
6.30. Let Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 denote the spherical Hecke category 𝐷pGr𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 q𝐺p𝑂q𝑋 𝐼 . The assignment 𝐼 ÞÑ
Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 defines a factorization monoidal category.
Our goal for the remainder of this section is to construct and study certain monoidal functors:
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼
: Repp𝐺q
Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
𝑋𝐼
compatible with factorization.
Remark 6.30.1. We follow Gaitsgory in calling this functor naive because it is an equivalence only
on the hearts of the 𝑑-structures (indeed, it is not an equivalence on Exts between unit objects,
since equivariant cohomology appears in the right hand side but not the left).
6.31.
The following results provide toy models for constructing the functors Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
𝑋𝐼 .
Lemma 6.31.1. For D P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ , the map:
t𝐹 : Repp𝛀 q Ñ D P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ u Ñ O𝛀 –comodpDq
𝐹 ÞÑ πΉ pO𝛀 q
is an equivalence.
Oblv
Proof. Since Repp𝛀 q is self-dual and since Repp𝛀 q b D ÝÝÝÑ Vect b D “ D is comonadic (c.f. the
proof of Lemma 6.23.1), we obtain the claim.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
49
Lemma 6.31.2. For D P AlgpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q a monoidal (in the cocomplete sense) DG category, the
map:
t𝐹 : Repp𝛀 q Ñ D continuous and lax monoidalu Ñ AlgpO𝛀 –comodpDqq
𝐹 ÞÑ πΉ pO𝛀 q
is an equivalence. Here O𝛀 –comodpDq is equipped with the obvious monoidal structure, induced from
that of D.
Remark 6.31.3. Here is a heuristic for Lemma 6.31.2:
Given 𝐴 P O𝛀 –comodpDq, the corresponding functor Repp𝛀 q Ñ D is given by the formula
𝑉 ÞÑ p𝑉 b 𝐴q𝛀 (where the invariants here are of course derived). If 𝐴 is moreover equipped with a
𝛀 -equivariant algebra structure, we obtain the canonical maps:
p𝑉 b 𝐴q𝛀 b pπ‘Š b 𝐴q𝛀 Ñ p𝑉 b 𝐴 b π‘Š b 𝐴q𝛀 “ p𝑉 b π‘Š b 𝐴 b 𝐴q𝛀 Ñ p𝑉 b π‘Š b 𝐴q𝛀
as desired, where the last map comes from the multiplication on 𝐴.
Proof of Lemma 6.31.2. This follows e.g. from the identification of the monoidal structure of Repp𝛀 qb
D with the Day convolution structure on the functor category HomDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ pRepp𝛀 q, Dq, identifying
the two via self-duality of Repp𝛀 q.
6.32.
We will use the following more sophisticated version of the above lemmas.
Lemma 6.32.1. For D P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q, the functor:
t𝐹 : Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 Ñ D P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ qu Ñ Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼
b
𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q
D
Lem. 6.23.2
“
O𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 –comodpDq
𝐹 ÞÑ πΉ pO𝛀,𝑋 𝐼 q
is an equivalence. Giving a lax monoidal structure in the left hand side amounts to giving an algebra
structure on the right hand side.
Proof. By Lemma 6.18.1, 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-linear functors Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 Ñ D are equivalent to objects of
Repp𝛀 q𝑋 𝐼 b𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q D.
The result then follows from Lemma 6.23.2 and Lemma 6.31.2.
as a lax monoidal
6.33. Construction of the functor. By Lemma 6.32.1, to construct Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
𝑋𝐼
Λ‡
functor, we need to specify an object of Repp𝐺q𝑋 𝐼 with an algebra structure.
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 b𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 are defined in a factorizable way in Appendix
Such objects β„‹π‘β„ŽπΌ P Repp𝐺q
𝑋
B of [Gai1] (they go by the name chiral Hecke algebra and were probably first constructed by
π‘β„Ž is concentrated in cohomological degree ´|𝐼|.
Beilinson).37 For each 𝐼, ℋ𝑋
𝐼
π‘β„Ž comes from the regular representation of 𝐺
Λ‡ under geometric Satake.
Example 6.33.1. For 𝐼 “ ˚, ℋ𝑋
Remark 6.33.2. We emphasize that the general construction (and the data required to define the
output) is purely abelian categorical, and comes from the usual construction of the geometric Satake
equivalence.
Lemma 6.33.3. The lax monoidal functors Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
are actually monoidal.
𝑋𝐼
37In the notation of [Gai1], we have β„‹π‘β„Ž “ R𝑑 r𝑑s “ 𝑓 R𝑑 r𝑑s.
𝑋
𝑋
𝑋𝑑
50
SAM RASKIN
Proof. We need to check that some maps between some objects of Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 are isomorphisms. It
suffices to do this after restriction to strata on 𝑋 𝐼 , and by factorization, we reduce to the case 𝐼 “ ˚
where it follows from usual geometric Satake and the construction of the chiral Hecke algebra.
6.34.
We have the following important fact:
Proposition 6.34.1. Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
is 𝑑-exact.
𝑋𝐼
We begin with the following.
π‘β„Ž is 𝑑-exact.
Lemma 6.34.2. The functor Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 defined by convolution with ℋ𝑋
𝐼
Proof. Recall that for each 𝐼 and 𝐽, there is the exterior convolution functor:
Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 b Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐽 Ñ Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 š 𝐽
š
which is a morphism of 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 𝐽 q-module categories.38 The relation to usual convolution is that
for 𝐽 “ 𝐼, convolution is obtained by applying exterior convolution and then !-restricting to the
diagonal.
The usual semi-smallness argument shows that exterior convolution is 𝑑-exact. Therefore, since
π‘β„Ž lies in degree ´|𝐼|, we deduce from the above that convolution with β„‹π‘β„Ž has cohomological
ℋ𝑋
𝐼
𝑋𝐼
amplitude r´|𝐼|, 0s: in particular, it is right 𝑑-exact.
It remains to see that this convolution functor is left 𝑑-exact. For a given partition 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽,
𝐽
Ñ π‘‹ 𝐼 denote the embedding of the corresponding stratum of 𝑋 𝐼 . The !-restriction
let 𝑖𝑝 : 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
π‘β„Ž to 𝑋 𝐽
of ℋ𝑋
𝐼
𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 is concentrated in cohomological degree ´|𝐽|, and is the object corresponding to
the regular representation under geometric Satake. It follows that the functor of convolution with
π‘β„Ž q is left 𝑑-exact from the exactness of convolution in the Satake category for a point.
𝑖𝑝,˚,𝑑𝑅 𝑖!𝑝 pℋ𝑋
𝐼
We now obtain the claim by dévissage.
Proof of Proposition 6.34.1. First, we claim that our functor is left 𝑑-exact.
We can write Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
as a composition of tensoring F with the delta 𝐷-module on the unit of
𝑋𝐼
π‘β„Ž , and then taking invariants with respect to the “diagonal” actions
Gr𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 , convolving with ℋ𝑋
𝐼
Λ‡ 𝐽 . The first step is obviously 𝑑-exact, and the second step is 𝑑-exact by Lemma 6.34.2; the
for the 𝐺
third step is obviously left 𝑑-exact.
It remains to show that it is right 𝑑-exact.
Λ‡ 𝐼 qβ™‘ “ Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ b𝐼,β™‘ . We claim that convolution with Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
First, let 𝑉 P Repp𝐺
𝑋 𝐼 pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq is
𝑑-exact (as an endofunctor of Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 ).
It suffices to show this for 𝑉 finite-dimensional, and then duality of 𝑉 and monoidality of Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
𝑋𝐼
reduces us to showing exactness in either direction: we show that this convolution functor is left
𝑑-exact. This then follows by the same stratification argument as in the proof of Lemma 6.34.2.
In particular, convolving with the unit, we see that Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
𝑋 𝐼 pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq is concentrated in cohoπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
mological degree ´|𝐼|, and more generally, Sat𝑋 𝐼 ˝ Loc𝑋 𝐼 is 𝑑-exact up to this same cohomological
shift.
Λ‡ ď0𝐼 is
For simplicity, we localize on 𝑋 to assume 𝑋 is affine. Then by Theorem 6.17.1, Repp𝐺q
𝑋
generated under colimits by objects of the form Ind OblvpLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq for 𝑉 P Repp𝛀 𝐼 qď|𝐼| : indeed,
this follows from the observation that Ind Oblv is 𝑑-exact, which is true since after applying Oblv
38We emphasize that 𝐼 and 𝐽 play an asymmetric role in the definition, i.e., the definition depends on an ordered
pair of finite sets, not just a pair of finite sets.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
51
again, it is given by tensoring with the ind-vector bundle of differential operators on 𝑋 𝐼 . The same
reasoning shows that Ind Oblv is 𝑑-exact on Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 , giving the result.
6.35. The naive Satake theorem. We will not need the following result, but include a proof for
completeness. Since we are not going to use it, we permit ourselves to provide substandard detail.
Theorem 6.35.1. The functor Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
induces an equivalence between the hearts of the 𝑑-structures:
𝑋𝐼
»
Λ‡ ♑𝐼 Ý
Satβ™‘
: Repp𝐺q
Ñ Sphβ™‘
.
𝑋𝐼
𝑋
𝐺,𝑋 𝐼
We will give an argument in S6.37.
Remark 6.35.2. In the setting of perverse sheaves, Theorem 6.35.1 is proved in [Gai1] Appendix
B. We provide a different argument from loc. cit. that more easily deals with the problem of nonholonomic 𝐷-modules.
6.36. Spherical Whittaker sheaves. Our argument for Satake will appeal to the following. Let
Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
denote the category of Whittaker 𝐷-modules on Gr𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 , i.e., 𝐷-modules equivariant against
𝑋𝐼
𝑁 ´ p𝐾q𝑋 𝐼 equipped with its standard character (we use the πœŒΛ‡pπœ”π‘‹ q-twist here).
given by convolution with the unit object
We have a canonical functor Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
𝑋𝐼
π‘ π‘β„Ž
unitWhitπ‘ π‘β„Ž P Whit𝑋 𝐼 , i.e., the canonical object cleanly extended from Gr𝑁 ´ ,𝑋 𝐼 (i.e., the ˚ and
𝑋𝐼
!-extensions coincide here).
Theorem 6.36.1 (Frenkel-Gaitsgory-Vilonen, Gaitsgory, Beraldo). The composite functor:
Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
𝐼
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 ÝÝÝ𝑋ÝÝÑ Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
Repp𝐺q
𝑋𝐼
is an equivalence.
Proof. We will appeal to Proposition B.8.1.
It is easy to see that the unit object of Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
is ULA: this follows from the usual cleanness
𝑋𝐼
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 and monoidality
argument. We then formally deduce from dualizability of ULA objects in Repp𝐺q
π‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
of Sat𝑋 𝐼 that the above functor sends ULA objects to ULA objects.
Then since these sheaves of categories are locally constant along strata (by factorizability), we
obtain the claim by noting that this functor is an equivalence over a point, as follows from [FGV]
and the comparison of local and global39 definitions of spherical Whittaker categories, as has been
done e.g. in the unpublished work [Gai2].
We also use the following fact about Whittaker categories.
Lemma 6.36.2. The object Av𝐺p𝑂q𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ punitWhitπ‘ π‘β„Ž q P Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 lies in cohomological degrees Δ› ´|𝐼|.
𝑋𝐼
The adjunction map:
unitSph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Av𝐺p𝑂q𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ punitWhitπ‘ π‘β„Ž q
𝑋𝐼
is an equivalence on cohomology in degree ´|𝐼|. (Here unitSph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 is the delta 𝐷-module on 𝑋 𝐼
˚-pushed forward to Gr𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 using the tautological section).
39I.e., using Drinfeld’s compactifications as in [FGV].
52
SAM RASKIN
Proof. The corresponding fact over a point is obvious: the fact that Sph𝐺,π‘₯ Ñ Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
is 𝑑-exact
π‘₯
on hearts of 𝑑-structures implies that its right adjoint left 𝑑-exact, so applying the above averaging
to the unit, one obtains an object in degrees Δ› 0. The adjunction map is an equivalence on 0th
cohomology because Sph𝐺,π‘₯ Ñ Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž
is an equivalence on hearts of 𝑑-structures.
π‘₯
We then deduce that from factorization that for each 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽, the !-restriction of:
CokerpunitSph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Av𝐺p𝑂q𝑋 𝐼 ,˚ punitWhitπ‘ π‘β„Ž qq
𝑋𝐼
𝐽
to the corresponding stratum 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
defined by 𝑝 is concentrated in cohomological degrees Δ… ´|𝐽|,
which immediately gives the claim.
6.37.
We now deduce factorizable Satake.
Proof of Theorem 6.35.1. We have an adjunction Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 o
/ Whitπ‘ π‘β„Ž where the left adjoint is
𝑋𝐼
convolution with the unit and the right adjoint is ˚-averaging with respect to 𝐺p𝑂q𝑋 𝐼 .
From Theorem 6.36.1, we obtain the adjunction:
Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 o
Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
𝐼
/ Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ 𝑋𝐼 .
𝑋
Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’
𝑋𝐼
Since
is 𝑑-exact, we obtain a corresponding adjunction between the hearts of the 𝑑-structure.
Lemma 6.36.2 implies that the left adjoint is fully-faithful at the abelian categorical level, and the
right adjoint Satπ‘›π‘Žπ‘–π‘£π‘’,β™‘
is conservative by Theorem 6.36.1, so we obtain the claim.
𝑋𝐼
7. Hecke functors: Zastava with moving points
7.1. As in S5, the main result of this section, Theorem 7.8.1, will compare geometrically and
spectrally defined Chevalley functors. However, in this section, we work over powers of the curve:
we are giving a compatibility now between Theorem 4.6.1 and the factorizable Satake theorem of
S6.
7.2. Structure of this section. In S7.3-7.8, we give “moving points” analogues of the constructions of S5 and formulate our main theorem.
The remainder of the section is dedicated to deducing this theorem from Theorem 7.8.1.
There are two main difficulties in proving the main theorem: working over powers of the curve
presents difficulties, and the fact that we are giving a combinatorial (i.e., involving Langlands
duality) comparison functors in the derived setting.
The former we treat by exploiting ULA objects: c.f. Appendix B and S6. These at once exhibit
good functoriality properties and provide a method for passing from information the disjoint locus
𝐼
𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
to the whole of 𝑋 𝐼 .
We treat the homotopical difficulties by exploiting a useful 𝑑-structure on factorization Υň modules, c.f. Proposition 7.10.1.
7.3.
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
Define the indscheme Diveff,𝑋
over 𝑋 𝐼 as parametrizing an 𝐼-tuple π‘₯ “ pπ‘₯𝑖 q of points of
𝐼
𝑋 and a Λ̌-valued divisor on 𝑋 that is ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  -valued on 𝑋ztπ‘₯𝑖 u.
Warning 7.3.1. The notation 8 ¨ π‘₯ in the superscript belies that π‘₯ is a dynamic variable: it is used
to denote our 𝐼-tuple of points in 𝑋. We maintain this convention in what follows, keeping the
subscript 𝑋 𝐼 to indicate that we work over powers of the curve now.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
53
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
Remark 7.3.2. We again have a degree map DivΛ̌
Ñ Λ̌.
eff,𝑋 𝐼
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
Let Υň –modfact
.
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 denote the DG category of unital factorization modules for Υň on Diveff,𝑋 𝐼
fact
Λ‡
The two functors we will compare will go from Repp𝐺q𝑋 𝐼 to Υň –mod
𝐼.
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
7.4. Geometric Chevalley functor. To construct the geometric Chevalley functor, we imitate
much of the geometry that appeared in S5.2-5.14.
8¨π‘₯
7.5. For starters, define Bun𝑁 ´ ,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ π‘‹ 𝐼 as parametrizing π‘₯ “ pπ‘₯𝑖 q𝑖P𝐼 P 𝑋 𝐼 , a 𝐺-bundle 𝒫𝐺 on
𝑋, and non-zero maps:
bpˇ
𝜌,πœ†q
Ω𝑋
Ñ π‘‰π’«πœ†πΊ p8 ¨ π‘₯q
defined for each dominant weight πœ† and satisfying the Plucker relations, in the notation of S5.2.
Here the notation of twisting by O𝑋 p8 ¨ π‘₯q makes sense in 𝑆-points: for π‘₯ “ pπ‘₯𝑖 q𝑖P𝐼 : 𝑆 Ñ π‘‹ 𝐼 , we
take the sum of the Cartier divisors on 𝑋 ˆ 𝑆 associated with the graphs of the maps π‘₯𝑖 to define
O𝑋ˆπ‘† pπ‘₯q.
π‘œ
7.6.
We can imitate the other constructions in the same fashion, giving the indscheme 𝒡 8¨π‘₯
(resp.
𝑋𝐼
π‘œ
π‘œ
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
8¨π‘₯ : 𝒡 8¨π‘₯ Ñ DivΛ̌ ,8¨π‘₯ ).
𝒡 8¨π‘₯ ) over 𝑋 𝐼 and the map πœ‹ 8¨π‘₯
: 𝒡 8¨π‘₯
Ñ DivΛ̌
(resp. πœ‹π‘‹
𝐼
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
eff,𝑋 𝐼
eff,𝑋 𝐼
8¨π‘₯
Let 𝒴𝑋 𝐼 be the inverse image of 𝑋 𝐼 ˆ Bun𝑁 ´ Ď Bun𝑁 ´ ,𝑋 𝐼 . We have a distinguished object
πœ“π’΄π‘‹ 𝐼 P 𝐷p𝒴𝑋 𝐼 q, obtained by !-pullback from πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 b Wβ„Žπ‘–π‘‘ P 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 ˆ Bun𝑁 ´ q.
8¨π‘₯ q.
We also have a 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-linear action of Sph𝐺,𝑋 𝐼 on 𝐷p𝒡𝑋
𝐼
We obtain a 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-linear functor:
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Υň –modfact 𝐼
Chevgeom
: Repp𝐺q
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
ň,𝑋 𝐼
imitating our earlier functor Chevgeom
ň,π‘₯ . Indeed, we use the naive Satake functor, convolution with
π‘œ
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
(the ˚-pushforward of) πœ“Y𝑋 𝐼 , !-restriction to 𝒡 8¨π‘₯
, and then ˚-pushforward to DivΛ̌
, exactly
𝑋𝐼
eff,𝑋 𝐼
as in S5.
7.7. Spectral Chevalley functor. To construct Chevspec
, we will use the following.
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Lemma 7.7.1. The category nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 of Lie-˚ modules on 𝑋 𝐼 for nΜŒπ‘‹ P Repp𝑇ˇq𝑋 is canonically
identified with the category ň–modpRepp𝑇ˇqq𝑋 𝐼 , i.e., the 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-module category associated with the
symmetric monoidal DG category ň–modpRepp𝑇ˇqq by the procedure of S6.6.
Proof. Let à Ď 𝑋 ˆ 𝑋 𝐼 be the union of the graphs of the projections 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ π‘‹. Let 𝛼 (resp. 𝛽)
denote the projection from Γ to 𝑋 (resp. 𝑋 𝐼 ).
Since 𝛽 is proper, one finds that:
π›½Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝛼! : 𝐷p𝑋q Ñ π·p𝑋 𝐼 q
!
is colax symmetric monoidal, and in particular maps Lie coalgebras for p𝐷p𝑋q, bq to Lie coalgebras
!
for p𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q, bq.
Moreover, if 𝐿 P 𝐷p𝑋q is a Lie-˚ algebra and compact as a 𝐷-module, then its Verdier dual
!
D𝑉 π‘’π‘Ÿπ‘‘π‘–π‘’π‘Ÿ p𝐿q is a Lie coalgebra in p𝐷p𝑋q, bq, and 𝐿-modules on 𝑋 𝐼 are equivalent to π›½Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝛼! pD𝑉 π‘’π‘Ÿπ‘‘π‘–π‘’π‘Ÿ p𝐿qqcomodules. We have an obvious translation of this for the “graded” case, where e.g. 𝐷pGr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 q
54
SAM RASKIN
replaces 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q. (See [Roz] Proposition 4.5.2 for a non-derived version of this; essentially the same
argument works in general).
One then easily finds that for 𝑉 P Vect, one has:
π›½Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝛼! p𝑉 b πœ”π‘‹ q
lim
p𝐼𝐽𝐾qPS𝐼
𝑗𝑝,˚,𝑑𝑅 p𝑉 ‘𝐾 b πœ”π‘ˆ p𝑝q q
where the notation is as in S6. We remark that this limit is a “logarithm” of the one appearing in
1
(6.13.1): we use the addition maps 𝑉 ‘𝐾 Ñ π‘‰ ‘𝐾 for 𝐾 𝐾 1 to give the structure maps in the
limit, i.e., the canonical structure of commutative algebra on 𝑉 in pVect, ‘q.
Moreover, this identification is compatible with Lie cobrackets, so that the Lie coalgebra pň_ qbπœ”π‘‹
maps to the Lie coalgebra:
π›½Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝛼! pň_ b πœ”π‘‹ q
lim
p𝐼𝐽𝐾qPS𝐼
𝑗𝑝,˚,𝑑𝑅 ppň_ q‘𝐾 b πœ”π‘ˆ p𝑝q q.
This immediately gives the claim.
Remark 7.7.2. We identify nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 and ň–modpRepp𝑇ˇqq𝑋 𝐼 in what follows. We emphasize that
although the Λ̌-grading does not appear explicitly in the notation, it is implicit in the fact that nΜŒπ‘‹
is always considered as Λ̌-graded.
We obtain the restriction functor:
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 .
Repp𝐡q
Using the chiral induction functor Indπ‘β„Ž : nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 and the restriction functor
Λ‡
Λ‡
from 𝐺 to 𝐡, we obtain:
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Υň –modfact 𝐼
Chevspec
: Repp𝐺q
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
ň,𝑋 𝐼
as desired.
7.8. Formulation of the main theorem. Observe that formation of each of the functors Chevspec
ň,𝑋 𝐼
and Chevgeom
are
compatible
with
factorization
as
we
vary
the
finite
set
𝐼
(here
we
use
the
external
ň,𝑋 𝐼
fusion construction of [Ras1] S6.12 and S8.14 on Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 ).
Theorem 7.8.1. The factorization functors 𝐼 ÞÑ Chevspec
and 𝐼 ÞÑ Chevgeom
are canonically
ň,𝑋 𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
isomorphic as factorization functors.
The proof of Theorem 7.8.1 will occupy the remainder of this section.
Remark 7.8.2. Here is the idea of the argument: since both functors factorize, we know the result
over strata of 𝑋 𝐼 by Theorem 5.14.1. We glue these isomorphisms over all of 𝑋 𝐼 by analyzing ULA
objects.
Remark 7.8.3. This theorem is somewhat loose as stated, as it does not specify how they are
isomorphic. This is because the construction of the isomorphism is somewhat difficult, due in part
to the difficulty of constructing anything at all in the higher categorical setting.
However, we remark that for 𝐺 simply-connected, we will see that such an isomorphism of
factorization functors is uniquely characterized as such. Similarly, for 𝐺 a torus, it is easy to write
down such an isomorphism by hand (just as it is easy to write down the (naive) geometric Satake
by hand in this case). This should be taken to indicate the existence of a canonical isomorphism in
general. We refer to Remark 7.9.2 and S7.21 for further discussion of this point.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
7.9.
55
First, we observe the following.
Lemma 7.9.1. Chevspec
and Chevgeom
are canonically isomorphic for 𝐼 “ ˚.
ň,𝑋 𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Proof. We are comparing two 𝐷p𝑋q-linear functors:
Λ‡ 𝑋 “ Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ b 𝐷p𝑋q Ñ Υň –modfact
Repp𝐺q
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
or equivalently, two continuous functors:
Λ‡ Ñ Υň –modfact .
Repp𝐺q
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
By lisseness along 𝑋, we obtain the result from Theorem 5.14.1 (alternatively: the methods of
Theorem 5.14.1 work when the point π‘₯ is allowed to vary, giving the result).
Remark 7.9.2. In what follows, we will see that the isomorphism of Theorem 7.8.1 is uniquely pinned
down by a choice of isomorphism over 𝑋, i.e., an isomorphism as in Lemma 7.9.1. Indeed, this will
follow from Proposition 7.17.2. Note that we have constructed such an isomorphism explicitly in
the proof of Theorem 5.14.1, and therefore this completely pins down Theorem 7.8.1.
7.10. Digression: a 𝑑-structure on factorization modules. We now digress to discussion the
following result.
Proposition 7.10.1.
(1) There is a (necessarily unique) 𝑑-structure on Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 such that
the forgetful functor:
8¨π‘₯
Oblvϒň : Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ π·pDiveff,𝑋 𝐼 q
(7.10.1)
is 𝑑-exact.
(2) With respect to this 𝑑-structure, the chiral induction functor:
Indπ‘β„Ž : nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼
is 𝑑-exact with respect to the 𝑑-structure on the left hand side coming from Proposition 7.7.1.
(3) This 𝑑-structure is left and right complete.
Proof. Note that we have a commutative diagram:
/ nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod 𝐼
𝑋
Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼
Oblvϒň
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
𝐷pDiveff,𝑋 𝐼
q
𝑖!
(7.10.2)
/ 𝐷pGr
𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 q
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
where we use 𝑖 to denote the map Gr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 Ñ DivΛ̌
.
eff,𝑋 𝐼
ď0 as the subcategory generated under colimits by ň –modď0 by Indπ‘β„Ž .
Define pΥň –modfact
𝑋
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 q
𝑋𝐼
fact
Δ…0
This defines a 𝑑-structure in the usual way. Note that an object lies in pΥň –mod𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 q if and only
if its image under Oblvπ‘β„Ž lies in nΜŒπ‘‹ –modΔ…0
𝑋𝐼 .
The main observation is that the composition Oblvϒň ˝ Indπ‘β„Ž is 𝑑-exact:
The PBW theorem for factorization modules [Ras1] S7.19 says that for 𝑀 P nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 , Indπ‘β„Ž p𝑀 q
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
has a filtration as an object of 𝐷pDiveff,𝑋
q with subquotients given by the ˚-pushforward of:
𝐼
56
SAM RASKIN
`
˘
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  𝑛
ň
r1s
b
.
.
.
b
ň
r1s
b
𝑀
P
𝐷
pDiv
q
ˆ
Gr
𝐼
𝑋
𝑋
𝑇,𝑋
eff
looooooooooomooooooooooon
𝑛 times
ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
Diveff,𝑋
.
𝐼
along the addition map to
Formation of this exterior product is obviously 𝑑-exact, and
the ˚-pushforward operation is as well by finiteness, giving our claim.
Then from the commutative diagram (7.10.2), we see that Oblvπ‘β„Ž ˝ Indπ‘β„Ž is left 𝑑-exact. This
immediately implies the 𝑑-exactness of Indπ‘β„Ž .
It remains to show that Oblvϒň is 𝑑-exact. By the above computation of Oblvϒň Indπ‘β„Ž , it is right
𝑑-exact.
Δ…0
!
Suppose 𝑀 P Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 with 𝑖 Oblvϒň p𝑀 q P 𝐷pGr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 q . By factorization and since Υň P
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
β™‘
𝐷pDivΛ̌
eff q , we deduce that Oblvϒň p𝑀 q is in degree Δ… 0. By the commutative diagram (7.10.2),
Δ…0
this hypothesis is equivalent to assuming that 𝑀 P pΥň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 q , so we deduce our left 𝑑exactness.
Finally, that this 𝑑-structure is left and right complete follows immediately from (1).
spec
fact
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Υň –mod
Corollary 7.10.2. The functor Chev 𝐼 : Repp𝐺q
𝐼 is 𝑑-exact.
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
ň,𝑋
7.11. ULA objects. Next, we discuss the behavior of ULA objects under the Chevalley functors.
In the discussion that follows, we use the term “ULA” as an abbreviation for “ULA over 𝑋 𝐼 .”
7.12.
We begin with a technical remark on the spectral side.
Proposition 7.12.1.
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 to ULA objects
(1) The functor Chevspec
maps ULA objects in Repp𝐺q
ň,𝑋 𝐼
in Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 .
Λ‡ b𝐼 , the object Oblvϒ Chevspec𝐼 p𝑉 q P 𝐷pDivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
(2) For every 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
q underlying
ň
ň,𝑋
eff,𝑋 𝐼
spec
Chevň,𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q is ind-ULA.
Λ‡ P Λ̌, the restriction of this 𝐷-module to
More precisely, if 𝑉 is compact, then for every πœ†
40
Λ‡
the locus of divisors of total degree πœ† is ULA.
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 preserves ULA objects by the same argument as in
Proof. The functor Repp𝐡q
Proposition 6.16.1, and then the first part follows from 𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q-linearity of the adjoint functors
nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 o
Indπ‘β„Ž/
Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 .
Λ‡ 𝑋𝐼
For the second part, we claim more generally that Oblvϒň Indπ‘β„Ž maps ULA objects in Repp𝐡q
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
to objects in 𝐷pDiveff,𝑋
q whose restriction to each degree is ULA.
𝐼
Λ‡ 𝐼 , since
To this end, we immediately reduce to the case of one-dimensional representations of 𝐡
b𝐼
Λ‡
every compact object of Repp𝐡q
admits a finite filtration with such objects as the subquotients.
Λ‡ the corresponding object is the vacuum repreIn the case of the trivial representation of 𝐡,
sentation, which in this setting is obtained by ˚-pushforward from πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 b Υň along the obvious
map:
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
𝑋 𝐼 ˆ DivΛ̌
eff
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
.
Ñ Diveff,𝑋
𝐼
Since this map is a closed embedding, we obtain the claim since πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 b Υň obviously has the
corresponding property.
40Note that this claim is wrong if we do not restrict to components, since ULA objects are compact.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
57
The general case of a 1-dimensional representation differs from this situation by a translation on
π‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
DivΛ̌
, giving the claim here as well.
eff,𝑋 𝐼
7.13.
Next, we make the following observation on the geometric side.
Λ‡ b𝐼 , Oblvϒ Chevgeom𝐼 pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq P 𝐷pDivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ,8¨π‘₯
q
Proposition 7.13.1.
(1) For every 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
ň
ň,𝑋
eff,𝑋 𝐼
is ind-ULA.
Λ‡ P Λ̌, the restriction of Oblvϒ Chevgeom𝐼 pLoc 𝐼 p𝑉 qq
More precisely, for 𝑉 compact and πœ†
𝑋
ň
ň,𝑋
Λ‡
to the locus of divisors of total degree πœ† is ULA.
Λ‡ b𝐼,β™‘ , Chevgeom𝐼 pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq P Υň –modfact 𝐼 lies in cohomological degree
(2) For 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
ň,𝑋
´|𝐼|.
Λ‡ b𝐼,β™‘ compact, then that
Proof. As in Proposition 7.12.1 suffices to show that for 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
Chevgeom
pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq admits a filtration by Λ̌𝐼 with πœ‡
Λ‡-subquotient Indπ‘β„Ž pβ„“πœ‡Λ‡ q b 𝑉 pΛ‡
πœ‡q, where 𝑉 pΛ‡
πœ‡q is
ň,𝑋 𝐼
πœ‡
Λ‡
b𝐼,β™‘
Λ‡
the πœ‡
Λ‡-weight space of 𝑉 and β„“ P Repp𝐡q
is the corresponding one dimensional representation.
Λ‡ b𝐼
This follows exactly as in Step 2 of the proof of Theorem 5.14.1: the weight space of 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
appears as a semi-infinite integral aΜ€ la Mirkovic-Vilonen by the appropriate moving points version
of Lemma 5.15.1.
7.14.
We now deduce the following key result, comparing Chevgeom
and Chevspec
on ULA objects.
ň,𝑋 𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Proposition 7.14.1. The two functors:
Λ‡ b𝐼 Ñ Υň –modfact 𝐼
Chevgeom
˝ Loc𝑋 𝐼 : Repp𝐺q
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Λ‡ b𝐼 Ñ Υň –modfact 𝐼
Chevspec
˝ Loc𝑋 𝐼 : Repp𝐺q
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
ň,𝑋 𝐼
are isomorphic.
More precisely, there exists a unique such isomorphism extending the isomorphism between these
𝐼
coming from Lemma 7.9.1 and factorization.
functors over 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
Proof. It suffices to produce an isomorphism between the restrictions of Chevgeom
and Chevspec
to
ň,𝑋 𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
b𝐼,β™‘
Λ‡
the category of compact objects in the heart of Repp𝐺q
.
Λ‡ b𝐼,β™‘ is compact. By [Rei] IV.2.8,41 ULAness of Chevgeom𝐼 pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq and
Suppose 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
ň,𝑋
perversity (up to shift) imply that as a 𝐷-module, Chevgeom
pLoc
p𝑉
qq
is
concentrated in one
𝐼
𝐼
𝑋
ň,𝑋
degree, and as such, it is middle extended from this disjoint locus. The same conclusion holds for
Chevspec
pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq for the same reason.
ň,𝑋 𝐼
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
𝐼
Since the isomorphism above over DivΛ̌
ˆπ‘‹ 𝐼 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
is compatible with factorization modeff,𝑋 𝐼
ule structures, we deduce that the factorization module structures on Chevgeom
pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq and
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Chevspec
pLoc
p𝑉
qq
are
compatible
with
the
middle
extension
construction,
and
we obtain that
𝑋𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
these two are isomorphic as factorization modules for Υň .
Corollary 7.14.2. The functor Chevgeom
is 𝑑-exact.
ň,𝑋 𝐼
41Note that loc. cit. only formulates its claim for complements to smooth Cartier divisors, since this reference only
defines the ULA condition in this case. However, the claim from loc. cit. is still true in this generality, as one sees by
combining Beilinson’s theory [Bei] and Corollary B.5.3.
58
SAM RASKIN
Proof. For simplicity, we localize to assume that 𝑋 is affine.
First, we claim that Chevgeom
is right 𝑑-exact.
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Λ‡ ď0𝐼 is generated under colimits by objects
Indeed, as in the proof of Proposition 6.34.1, Repp𝐺q
𝑋
!
Λ‡ 𝐼 qď|𝐼| “ Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ b𝐼,ď|𝐼| .
of the form Ind OblvpLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq “ 𝐷𝑋 𝐼 b Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q for 𝑉 P Repp𝐺
!
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
The functor 𝐷𝑋 𝐼 b ´ is 𝑑-exact on 𝐷pDiveff,𝑋
q (since after applying forgetful functors, it is
𝐼
given by tensoring with the ind-vector bundle that is the pullback of differential operators on 𝑋 𝐼 ),
and since:
!
!
Chevgeom
p𝐷𝑋 𝐼 b Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq “ 𝐷𝑋 𝐼 b Chevgeom
pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq
ň,𝑋 𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Prop. 7.14.1
“
!
𝐷𝑋 𝐼 b Chevspec
pLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq
ň,𝑋 𝐼
we obtain the result from Corollary 7.10.2.
For left 𝑑-exactness: let 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽 be given, and let 𝑖𝑝 denote the corresponding locally closed em𝐽
bedding 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
Ñ π‘‹ 𝐼 . Note that the functors 𝑖!𝑝 Chevgeom
are left 𝑑-exact by factorization. Therefore,
ň,𝑋 𝐼
is filtered by the functors 𝑖𝑝,˚,𝑑𝑅 𝑖!𝑝 Chevgeom
, we obtain the claim.
since Chevgeom
ň,𝑋 𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Warning 7.14.3. It is not clear at this point that the isomorphisms of Proposition 7.14.1 are
compatible with restrictions to diagonals. Here we note that, as in the proof of loc. cit., this question
reduces to the abelian category, and here it becomes a concrete, yes-or-no question. The problem
𝐼
is that the isomorphism of Proposition 7.14.1 was based on middle extending from 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
Ď 𝑋𝐼 ,
𝐽
𝐼
do not speak to one another. We will deal with this problem in
and 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
and for 𝑋 𝐽 ãÑ π‘‹ 𝐼 , 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
S7.21.
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 . Next, we construct a functor:
7.15. Factoring through Repp𝐡q
1
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Repp𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋𝐼
Chevgeom
: Repp𝐺q
ň,𝑋 𝐼
so that the composition:
1
Chevgeom
𝐼
π‘β„Ž
ň,𝑋
Ind
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 ÝÝÝÝÝ
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 Ý
Repp𝐺q
ÝÑ Repp𝐡q
ÝÝÑ Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼
identifies with Chevgeom
.
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Lemma 7.15.1. The 𝑑-exact functor:
Indπ‘β„Ž
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 ÝÝÝÑ Υň –modfact 𝐼
Repp𝐡q
𝑒𝑛,𝑋
is fully-faithful on the hearts of the 𝑑-structures.
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 is obviously fully-faithful (even at the derived level),
Proof. The functor Repp𝐡q
as is clear by writing both categories as limits and using the fully-faithfulness of the functors
Λ‡ b𝐽 Ñ ň–modpRepp𝑇ˇqb𝐽 .
Repp𝐡q
So it remains to show that Indπ‘β„Ž : nΜŒπ‘‹ –mod𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Υň –modfact
𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 is fully-faithful at the abelian
categorical level.
This follows from the chiral PBW theorem, as in the proof of Proposition 7.10.1:
Indeed, let Oblvπ‘β„Ž denote the right adjoint to Indπ‘β„Ž . Then for 𝑀 P nΜŒπ‘‹ –modβ™‘
, Oblvπ‘β„Ž Indπ‘β„Ž p𝑀 q
𝑋𝐼
is filtered as a 𝐷-module with associated graded terms:
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
´
¯
𝑖! add𝑛,˚,𝑑𝑅 ň
r1s
b
.
.
.
b
ň
r1s
b
𝑖
p𝑀
q
P 𝐷pGr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 q
𝑋
𝑋
˚,𝑑𝑅
looooooooooomooooooooooon
59
(7.15.1)
𝑛 times
where add𝑛 is the addition map:
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
Λ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
Λ̌
pDiveff
q𝑛 ˆ DivΛ̌
Ñ Diveff,𝑋
𝐼
eff,𝑋 𝐼
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
,8¨π‘₯
and 𝑖 is the embedding Gr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 ãÑ DivΛ̌
. It suffices to show that 𝐻 0 of this term vanishes for
eff,𝑋 𝐼
𝑛 ‰ 0.
Observe that we have a fiber square:
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
/ pDivΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  q𝑛 ˆ DivΛ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
eff
eff,𝑋 𝐼
eff
Greff
𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 ˆπΌ . . . ˆπΌ Gr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 ˆπΌ Gr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼
𝑋
𝑋
𝑋
loooooooooooooomoooooooooooooon
𝑛 times
add𝑛
π‘π‘œπ‘ 
/ DivΛ̌ ,8¨π‘₯
eff,𝑋 𝐼
𝑖
Gr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼
𝐼
where Greff
𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 is the locus of points in 𝑋 ˆ Diveff of pairs ppπ‘₯𝑖 q𝑖P𝐼 , 𝐷q so that 𝐷 is zero when
Δ
restricted to 𝑋ztπ‘₯𝑖 u (so the reduced fiber of Greff
Ñ π‘‹ 𝐼 is the discrete
𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 over a point π‘₯ P 𝑋 Ý
scheme ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  ).
Λ‡ given, we have a
Let à Ď 𝑋 ˆ 𝑋 𝐼 be the incidence divisor, as in the proof of Lemma 7.7.1. For πœ†
Λ‡
𝐼
𝑛
Λ‡
canonical map 𝛽 πœ† : Γ Ñ Greff
𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 over 𝑋 , sending pπ‘₯, pπ‘₯𝑖 q𝑖“1 q P Γ to the divisor πœ†¨π‘₯. More generally,
Λ‡ π‘Ÿ q𝑛 with πœ†
Λ‡ π‘Ÿ P ΛΜŒπ‘π‘œπ‘  , we obtain a map:
for every datum pπœ†
π‘Ÿ“1
Λ‡
𝑛
eff
𝛽 pπœ†π‘Ÿ qπ‘Ÿ“1 : Γ ˆ . . . ˆ Γ Ñ Greff
𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 ˆ . . . ˆ Gr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 .
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
eff
By base-change, the !-restriction of nΜŒπ‘‹ r1sb. . .bnΜŒπ‘‹ r1sbπ‘–Λš,𝑑𝑅 p𝑀 q to Greff
𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 ˆ . . . ˆ Gr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼 ˆ Gr𝑇,𝑋 𝐼
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
is the direct sum of terms:
¯
´
!
!
!
!
!
p𝛼
Λ‡ π‘Ÿ q𝑛
π‘Ÿ“1
π›½Λš,𝑑𝑅
𝑝!1 πœ‘! pnΜŒπ›ΌΛ‡ 1 b π‘˜π‘‹ r1sq b . . . b 𝑝!𝑛 πœ‘! pnΜŒπ›ΌΛ‡ 𝑛 b π‘˜π‘‹ r1sq b 𝑝!𝑛`1 p𝑀 q .
where the 𝑝𝑖 are the projections and πœ™ is the map Γ Ñ π‘‹, and where the sum runs over all 𝑛-tuples
pˇ
π›Όπ‘Ÿ qπ‘›π‘Ÿ“1 of positive coroots. Since π‘˜π‘‹ r1s “ πœ”π‘‹ r´1s, these terms are concentrated in cohomological
degree Δ› 𝑛, which gives the claim.
fact
Λ‡ β™‘
Proposition 7.15.2. The functor Chevgeom
|
Λ‡ β™‘ factors through Repp𝐡q𝑋 𝐼 Ď Υň –mod𝑒𝑛,𝑋 𝐼 .
ň,𝑋 𝐼 Repp𝐺q
𝑋𝐼
Proof. Since
!
Λ‡ ď0𝐼
Repp𝐺q
𝑋
is generated under colimits by objects of the form Ind OblvpLoc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 qq “
Λ‡ 𝐼 qď|𝐼| “ Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ b𝐼,ď|𝐼| , Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ β™‘ 𝐼 is generated under (for emphasis:
𝐷𝑋 𝐼 b Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q for 𝑉 P Repp𝐺
𝑋
possibly non-filtered) colimits by the top cohomologies of such objects, i.e., by objects of the form
!
Λ‡ b𝐼 concentrated in degree |𝐼|.
𝐷𝑋 𝐼 b Loc𝑋 𝐼 p𝑉 q for 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ β™‘ 𝐼 , giving the claim.
But we have seen that such objects map into Repp𝐡q
𝑋
60
SAM RASKIN
We now obtain the desired functor Chevgeom
from Corollary 6.24.4, i.e., from the fact that
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 is the derived category of its heart. These functors factorize as one varies 𝐼.
Repp𝐺q
1
7.16. Kernels. By Lemma 6.32.1, the functor Chevgeom
is defined by a kernel:
ň,𝑋 𝐼
1
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋𝐼 .
Kgeom
P Repp𝐺
𝑋𝐼
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 underlying Kgeom
Recall that the object of Repp𝐡q
is Chevgeom
pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 q. Moreover, we recall that
𝑋𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
1
!
1
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 , F b K𝑋 𝐼 P Repp𝐺
Λ‡ ˆπΊ
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋𝐼 ,
one recovers the functor Chevgeom
by noting that for F P Repp𝐺q
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Λ‡ 𝐽 on each π‘ˆ p𝑝q (𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽), where 𝐺
Λ‡ 𝐽 acts diagonally
and then we take invariants with respect to 𝐺
Λ‡ ãÑ πΊ
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐺).
Λ‡
through the embedding 𝐺
spec
Λ‡
Λ‡
Λ‡ Ñ Repp𝐡q,
Λ‡
Let K𝑋 𝐼 P Repp𝐺 ˆ 𝐡q𝑋 𝐼 denote the kernel defining the tautological functor Repp𝐺q
spec
i.e., for each 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽, K𝑋 𝐼 |π‘ˆ p𝑝q is given by the regular representation O𝐺ˇ 𝐽 considered as a
ˇ𝐽 , 𝐡
Λ‡ 𝐽 q-bimodule by restriction from its p𝐺
ˇ𝐽 , 𝐺
Λ‡ 𝐽 q-bimodule structure (i.e., forgetting Kspec
p𝐺
down
𝑋𝐼
Λ‡
to Repp𝐺q𝑋 𝐼 , we recover O𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 from S6).
7.17.
We have the following preliminary observations about these kernels.
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋2 .
Lemma 7.17.1. Kgeom
and Kspec
are concentrated in cohomological degree ´|𝐼| in Repp𝐺
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
Proof. For Kspec
, this follows from Lemma 6.24.3.
𝑋𝐼
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 by evaluating 1 Chevgeom𝐼 on O Λ‡ 𝐼 .
By construction, we recover Kgeom
as an object of Repp𝐡q
𝐺,𝑋
𝑋𝐼
ň,𝑋
Since this object is concentrated in degree ´|𝐼| by Lemma 6.24.3, we obtain the claim from 𝑑exactness of Chevgeom
.
ň,𝑋 𝐼
Proposition 7.17.2. The group42 of automorphisms of Kspec
restricting to the identity automor𝑋𝐼
𝐼
phism on 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 is trivial.
Proof. Note that the underlying object of Gpd underlying this group is a set by Lemma 7.17.1.
Λ‡
Then automorphisms of Kspec
inject into automorphisms of O𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 P Repp𝐺q𝑋 𝐼 , so it suffices to
𝑋𝐼
verify the claim here.
By adjunction, we have: 43
HomRepp𝐺q
Λ‡
𝑋𝐼
pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 , πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q.
Λ‡ 𝐼 , O𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 q “ Hom𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q pO𝐺,𝑋
Therefore, it suffices to show that:
Hom𝐷p𝑋 𝐼 q pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 , πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q Ñ Hom𝐷p𝑋 𝐼
𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 q
p𝑗 ! pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 q, πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q
𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
(7.17.1)
𝐼
is an injection, where 𝑗 denotes the open embedding 𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
ãÑ π‘‹ 𝐼 .
!
!
Note that 𝑗 pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ qq is obviously ind-lisse, so 𝑗! is defined on it. Let 𝑖 denote
Λ‡ 𝐼 q » 𝑗 pLoc𝑋 𝐼 pO𝐺
the closed embedding of the union of all diagonal divisors into 𝑋 𝐼 , so 𝑗 is the complementary open
embedding. We then have the long exact sequence:
42Here by group, we mean a group object of Gpd.
43We emphasize here that Hom means the the groupoid of maps, not the whole chain complex of maps. In particular,
these Homs are actually sets, not more general groupoids.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
61
!
0 Ñ Hompπ‘–Λš,𝑑𝑅 π‘–Λš,𝑑𝑅 pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 q, πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q Ñ HompO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 , πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q Ñ Homp𝑗! 𝑗 pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 q, πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q “
Homp𝑗 ! pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 q, πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q Ñ . . . .
𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗
We can compute the first term as:
˚,𝑑𝑅
!
Hompπ‘–Λš,𝑑𝑅 π‘–Λš,𝑑𝑅 pO𝐺,𝑋
pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 q, πœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q “ Homp𝑖
Λ‡ 𝐼 q, 𝑖 pπœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 qq
which we then see vanishes, since π‘–Λš,𝑑𝑅 pO𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 q is obviously concentrated in cohomological degrees
!
ď ´|𝐼| (since O𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝐼 is in degree ´|𝐼|), while 𝑖 pπœ”π‘‹ 𝐼 q is the dualizing sheaf of a variety of dimension
|𝐼| ´ 1, and therefore is concentrated in cohomological degrees Δ› ´|𝐼| ` 1.
Remark 7.17.3. Note that by factorization and by the |𝐼| “ 1 case, we have an isomorphism
over the disjoint locus. We deduce from Proposition 7.17.2 that there is
between Kgeom
and Kspec
𝑋𝐼
𝑋𝐼
at most one isomorphism extending this given isomorphism, or equivalently, there is at most one
1
and the functor of restriction of representations that extends the
isomorphism between Chevgeom
ň,𝑋 𝐼
known isomorphism over the disjoint locus.
7.18. Commutative structure. The following discussion will play an important role in the sequel.
By factorization:
Λ‡
Λ‡
:“ 1 Chevgeom
pO𝐺,𝑋
𝐼 ÞÑ Kgeom
Λ‡ 𝐼 q P Repp𝐺 ˆ 𝐡q𝑋 𝐼
ň,𝑋 𝐼
𝑋𝐼
is a factorization algebra in a commutative factorization category.
Lemma 7.18.1. 𝐼 ÞÑ Kgeom
is a commutative factorization algebra.
𝑋𝐼
Remark 7.18.2. Since each term Kgeom
is concentrated in cohomological degree ´|𝐼|, this factor𝑋𝐼
ization algebra is classical, i.e., of the kind considered in [BD]. In particular, its commutativity is
a property, not a structure.
Proof of Lemma 7.18.1. Let Ξ denote the functor:
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋 b Repp𝐺
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋 Ñ Repp𝐺
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋2 .
Π: Repp𝐺
By [BD] S3.4, we only need to show that there is a map:
Λ‡ ˆ Repp𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋2
ΞpKgeom
b Kgeom
q Ñ Kgeom
P Repp𝐺
𝑋
𝑋
𝑋2
(7.18.1)
extending the factorization isomorphism on 𝑋 2 z𝑋.
Let 𝑖 denote diagonal embedding 𝑋 ãÑ π‘‹ 2 and let 𝑗 denote the complementary open embedding
2
𝑋𝑑𝑖𝑠𝑗 ãÑ π‘‹ 2 .
Since 𝑖! pKgeom
q “ Kgeom
is in cohomological degree ´1, we have a short exact sequence:
𝑋
𝑋2
0 Ñ Kgeom
Ñ π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝑗 ! pKgeom
q Ñ π‘–Λš,𝑑𝑅 pKgeom
qr1s Ñ 0
𝑋
𝑋2
𝑋2
in the shifted heart of the 𝑑-structure.
Therefore, the obstruction to a map (7.18.1) is the existence of a non-zero map:
Kgeom
b Kgeom
Ñ π‘–Λš,𝑑𝑅 pKgeom
qr1s.
𝑋
𝑋
𝑋
62
SAM RASKIN
b K𝑋 is similarly
We know (from the 𝐼 “ ˚ case of S7.9) that Kgeom
“ Loc𝑋 pO𝐺ˇ q, so Kgeom
𝑋
𝑋
geom
geom
˚,𝑑𝑅
localized. It follows that 𝑖
pK𝑋 b K𝑋 q is concentrated in cohomological degree ´3, while
Kgeom
r1s
is
concentrated
in
cohomological
degeree ´2, giving the claim.
𝑋
Λ‡ˆ
7.19. Lemma 7.18.1 endows Kgeom
with the structure of commutative algebra object of Repp𝐺
𝑋
geom
Λ‡
𝐡q𝑋 . Moreover, since K𝑋
is isomorphic to O𝐺,𝑋
Λ‡ , this object lies in the full subcategory:
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐺q
Λ‡ 𝑋 Ď Repp𝐺
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋.
Repp𝐺
can be recovered from
Moreover, the Beilinson-Drinfeld theory [BD] S3.4 then implies that Kgeom
𝑋𝐼
geom
K𝑋 equipped with its commutative algebra structure. For example, this observation already buys
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐺q
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ď Repp𝐺
Λ‡ ˆ 𝐡q
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 , and that 𝐼 ÞÑ K𝑋 𝐼 has a factorization
us that for every 𝐼, K𝑋 𝐼 P Repp𝐺
commutative algebra structure.
1
Using Lemma 6.32.1, it follows that the factorization functorctor Chevgeom
is induced from a
ň
»
Λ‡
Λ‡
symmetric monoidal functor equivalence 𝐹 : Repp𝐺q Ý
Ñ Repp𝐺q by composing 𝐹 with the restriction
Λ‡ and applying the functoriality of the construction C ÞÑ p𝐼 ÞÑ C𝑋 𝐼 q from S6.
functor to Repp𝐡q
7.20. We claim that 𝐹 is equivalent as a symmetric monoidal functor to the identity functor.
Indeed, this follows from the next lemma.
Λ‡ Ñ Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ be a symmetric monoidal equivalence such that for
Lemma 7.20.1. Let 𝐹r : Repp𝐺q
Λ‡
Λ‡
`
πœ†
πœ†
Λ‡ P Λ̌ , 𝐹rp𝑉 q is equivalent to 𝑉 in Repp𝐺q.
Λ‡ Then 𝐹r is equivalent (non-canonically) to the
every πœ†
identity functor as a symmetric monoidal functor.
Λ‡ Ñ πΊ.
Λ‡
Proof. By the Tannakian formalism, 𝐹r is given by restriction along an equivalence πœ™ : 𝐺
We need to show that πœ™ is an inner automorphism. We now obtain the result, since the outer
automorphism group of a reductive group is the automorphism group of its based root datum
and since our assumption implies that the corresponding isomorphism is the identity on Λ̌` and
therefore on all of Λ̌.
7.21. Trivializing the central gerbe. The above shows that there exists an isomorphism of the
factorization functors Chevgeom
and Chevspec
.
ň
ň
However, the above technique is not strong enough yet to produce a particular isomorphism.
Indeed, the isomorphism of Lemma 7.20.1 is non-canonical: the problem is that the identity functor
Λ‡ admits generally admits automorphisms as a symmetric monoidal functor: this automorof Repp𝐺q
Λ‡
phism group is the canonical the set of π‘˜-points of the center 𝑍p𝐺q.
Unwinding the above constructions, we see that the data of a factorizable isomorphism Chevgeom
ň
Λ‡
and Chevspec
form
a
trivial
𝑍p
𝐺q-gerbe.
ň
In order to trivialize this gerbe, it suffices (by Proposition 7.17.2, c.f. Remark 7.17.3) to show
the following.
Proposition 7.21.1. There exists a (necessarily unique) isomorphism of factorization functors
Chevgeom
» Chevspec
whose restriction to 𝑋 is the one given by Lemma 7.9.1.
ň
ň
Λ‡ “ ˚, this assertion is not obvious: c.f. Warning 7.14.3. Essentially,
Remark 7.21.2. Even when 𝑍p𝐺q
Λ‡ admits many automorphisms that are not tensor
the difficulty is that the identity functor of Repp𝐺q
automorphisms.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
7.22.
63
We will deduce the above proposition using the following setup.
Λ‡ Ñ Repp𝐺q
Λ‡
Lemma 7.22.1. Suppose that we are given a symmetric monoidal functor 𝐹 : Repp𝐺q
such that 𝐹 is (abstractly) isomorphic to the identity as a tensor functor, and such that we are
given a fixed isomorphism:
Λ‡
Λ‡
𝛼 : Res𝐺
˝𝐹 » Res𝐺
𝑇ˇ
𝑇ˇ
Λ‡ Ñ Repp𝑇ˇq (Res indicates the restriction functor here).
of symmetric monoidal functors Repp𝐺q
Then there exists an isomorphism of symmetric monoidal functors between 𝐹 and the identity
Λ‡ inducing 𝛼 if and only if, for every 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ β™‘ irreducible, there exists an
functor on Repp𝐺q
»
Λ‡ inducing the map:
isomorphism 𝛽𝑉 : 𝐹 p𝑉 q Ý
Ñ π‘‰ P Repp𝐺q
Λ‡
Λ‡
𝛼p𝑉 q : Res𝐺
𝐹 p𝑉 q » Res𝐺
p𝑉 q P Repp𝑇ˇq
𝑇ˇ
𝑇ˇ
Λ‡
upon application of Res𝐺
.
𝑇ˇ
Moreover, an symmetric monoidal isomorphism between 𝐹 and the identity compatible with 𝛼 is
unique if it exists. At the level of objects, it is given by the maps 𝛽𝑉 .
Remark 7.22.2. In words: an isomorphism 𝛼 as above may not be compatible with any tensor
Λ‡ is adjoint, so that a
isomorphism between 𝐹 and the identity. Indeed, consider the case where 𝐺
tensor isomorphism between 𝐹 and the identity is unique if it exists, while there are many choices
for 𝛼 as above. However, if this isomorphism exists, it is unique. Moreover, there is an object-wise
criterion to test whether or not such an isomorphism exists.
Proof. Choose some isomorphism 𝛽 between 𝐹 and the identity functor (of symmetric monoidal
Λ‡
. By Tannakian theory,
functors). From 𝛼, we obtain a symmetric monoidal automorphism of Res𝐺
𝑇ˇ
Λ‡
this is given by the action of some 𝑑 P 𝑇 pπ‘˜q.
Λ‡ is the center
Since the symmetric monoidal automorphism group of the identity functor of Repp𝐺q
Λ‡ (Moreover, we immediately deduce
of this group, it suffices to show that 𝑑 lies in the center of 𝐺.
the uniqueness from this observation).
Λ‡
To this end, it suffices to show that 𝑑 acts by a scalar on every irreducible representation on 𝐺.
But by Schur’s lemma, this is follows from our hypothesis.
7.23.
We now indicate how to apply Lemma 7.22.1 in our setup.
7.24.
First, we give factorizable identifications of the composite functors:
1
Chevgeom
𝐼
ň,𝑋
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 ÝÝÝÝÝ
Λ‡ 𝑋 𝐼 Ñ Repp𝑇ˇq𝑋 𝐼
Repp𝐺q
ÝÑ Repp𝐡q
Λ‡
with the functors induced from Res𝐺
.
𝑇ˇ
Indeed, we have done this implicitly already in the proof of Proposition 7.13.1: one rewrites the
functors Chevgeom
using (the appropriate generalization of) Lemma 5.15.1, and then uses the (facň,𝑋 𝐼
44
torizable of the) Mirkovic-Vilonen identification of restriction as cohomology along semi-infinite
orbits.
44This generalization is straightforward given the Mirkovic-Vilonen theory and the methods of this section and S6.
64
SAM RASKIN
Λ‡ β™‘ is irreducible.
7.25. Now suppose that 𝑉 P Repp𝐺q
Then for π‘₯ P 𝑋, Theorem 5.14.1 produces a certain isomorphism between Chevgeom
ň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q and
spec
fact,β™‘
β™‘
Λ‡
Chevň,π‘₯ p𝑉 q in Repp𝐡q Ď Υň –mod𝑒𝑛,π‘₯ .
To check that the conditions of Lemma 7.22.1 are satisfied, it suffices to show that this isomorphism induces the isomorphism of of S7.24 when we map to Repp𝑇ˇq.
Indeed, the isomorphism of Theorem 5.14.1 was constructed using a related isomorphism from
[BG2] Theorem 8.8. The isomorphism of [BG2] has the property above, as is noted in loc. cit.
Since the construction in Theorem 5.14.1 for reducing to the setting of [BG2] is compatible further
restriction to Repp𝑇ˇq, we obtain the claim.
Appendix A. Proof of Lemma 6.18.1
A.1. Suppose that we have a diagram 𝑖 ÞÑ C𝑖 P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ of categories with each C𝑖 dualizable
with dual C_
𝑖 in the sense of [Gai3].
In this case, we can form the dual diagram 𝑖 ÞÑ C_
𝑖 .
We can ask: when is C :“ lim𝑖PIπ‘œπ‘ C𝑖 dualizable with dual colim𝑖PI C_
𝑖 ? More precisely, there is a
canonical Vect valued pairing between the limit and colimit here, and we can ask when it realizes
the two categories as mutually dual.
As in [Gai3], we recall that this occurs if and only if colim𝑖PI C_
𝑖 is dualizable, which occurs if
and only if, for every D P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ , the canonical map:
`
˘
`
˘
lim
C
b
D
Ñ
lim
C
b
D
𝑖
𝑖
π‘œπ‘
π‘œπ‘
𝑖PI
𝑖PI
is an equivalence.
This section gives a criterion, Lemma A.2.1, in which this occurs, and which we will use to deduce
Lemma 6.18.1 in SA.3
A.2. A dualizability condition. Suppose we have a diagram:
C2
C1
𝐹
πœ“
/ C3
of dualizable categories. Let C denote the fiber product of this diagram.
The main result of this section is the following.
Lemma A.2.1. Suppose that πœ“ and 𝐹 have right adjoints πœ™ and 𝐺 respectively. Suppose in addition
that 𝐺 is fully-faithful.
Then if each C𝑖 is dualizable, C is dualizable as well. Moreover, for each D P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ , the
canonical map:
C b D Ñ C1 b D ˆ C 2 b D
C3 bD
is an equivalence.
The proof of this lemma is given in SA.7.
(A.2.1)
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
65
A.3. Proof of Lemma 6.18.1. We now explain how to deduce Lemma 6.18.1.
Proof that Lemma A.2.1 implies Lemma 6.18.1. Fix 𝐼 a finite set. We proceed by induction on |𝐼|,
the case |𝐼| “ 1 being obvious.
Recall that we have C P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ rigid and symmetric monoidal, and 𝑋 a smooth curve.
𝐼 and 𝑋 𝐼 (c.f. [Gai4]), we easily reduce to checking the corresponding
By 1-affineness of 𝑋𝑑𝑅
fact in the quasi-coherent setting. Note that by rigidity of QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q, dualizability questions in
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q are equivalent to dualizability questions in DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ .
Let π‘ˆ Ď 𝑋 𝐼 be the complement of the diagonally embedded 𝑋 ãÑ π‘‹ 𝐼 . We can then express C𝑋 𝐼
as a fiber product:
/ QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C 𝐼 q
𝑋
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 , C𝑋 𝐼 q
b
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q
QCohpπ‘ˆ q
/ QCohpπ‘ˆ q b C.
QCohp𝑋 𝐼 q b C
The two structure functors involved in defining this pullback admit continuous right adjoints,
and the right adjoint to the bottom functor is fully-faithful. Moreover, the bottom two terms are
obviously dualizable. Therefore, by Lemma A.2.1, it suffices to see that formation of the limit
involved in defining the top right term commutes with tensor products over QCohpπ‘ˆ q.
Note that π‘ˆ is covered by the open subsets π‘ˆ p𝑝q for 𝑝 : 𝐼 𝐽 with |𝐽| Δ… 1. By Zariski descent
for sheaves of categories, it suffices to check the commutation of tensor products and limits after
restriction to each π‘ˆ p𝑝q. But this follows from factorization and induction, using the same cofinality
result as in S6.10.
A.4.
The remainder of this section is devoted to the proof of Lemma A.2.1.
A.5. Gluing. Define the glued category Glue to consist of the triples pF, G, πœ‚q where F P C1 , G P C2 ,
and πœ‚ is a morphism πœ‚ : πœ“pGq Ñ πΉ pFq P C3 .
Note that the limit C :“ C1 ˆC3 C2 is a full subcategory of Glue.
Lemma A.5.1. The functor C ãÑ Glue admits a continuous right adjoint.
Proof. We construct this right adjoint explicitly:
r P C1 as the fiber product:
For pF, G, πœ‚q as above, define F
r
F
/ πΊπœ“pGq
F
𝐺pπœ‚q
/ 𝐺𝐹 pFq.
r Ñ πΉ πΊπœ“pGq » πœ“pGq is an isomorphism, and therefore
Since 𝐺 is fully-faithful, the map πœ€ : 𝐹 pFq
r G, πœ€q defines an object of C. It is easy to see that the resulting functor is the desired right adjoint.
pF,
66
SAM RASKIN
A.6. Let D P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ be given.
Define GlueD as with Glue, but instead use the diagram:
C2 b D
C1 b D
𝐹 bidD
πœ“bidD
/ C3 b D
Lemma A.6.1. The canonical functor:
Glue b D Ñ GlueD
is an equivalence.
Proof. First, we give a description of functors Glue Ñ E P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ for a test object E:
We claim that such a functor is equivalent to the datum of a pair πœ‰0 : C1 Ñ E and πœ‰1 : C2 Ñ E
of continuous functors, plus a natural transformation:
πœ‰0 Ñ πœ‰1 πœ™πΉ
of functors C1 Ñ E.
Indeed, given a functor Ξ : Glue Ñ E as above, we obtain such a datum as follows: for F P C1 ,
we let πœ‰0 pFq :“ ΞpFr´1s, 0, 0q, for G P C2 we let πœ‰1 pGq :“ Ξp0, G, 0q (here we write objects of Glue as
triples as above). The natural transformation comes from the boundary morphism in the obvious
exact triangle:
`1
pF, 0, 0q Ñ pF, 𝐹 pFq, id𝐹 pFq q Ñ p0, 𝐹 pFq, 0q ÝÝÑP Glue.
It is straightforward to see that this construction is an equivalence.
This universal property then makes the above property clear.
A.7.
We now deduce the lemma.
Proof of Lemma A.2.1. We need to see that for every D P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ , the map (A.2.1) is an equivalence.
First, observe that each of these categories is a full subcategory of GlueD . Indeed, for the left
hand side of (A.2.1), this follows from Lemma A.5.1, and for the right hand side, this follows from
Lemma A.6.1. Moreover, this is compatible with the above functor by construction.
Let 𝐿 denote the right adjoint to 𝑖 : C ãÑ Glue, and let 𝐿D denote the right adjoint to the
embedding:
𝑖D : C1 b D ˆ C2 b D ãÑ GlueD .
C3 bD
We need to show that:
p𝑖 ˝ 𝐿q b idD “ 𝑖D ˝ 𝐿D
as endofunctors of GlueD , since the image of the left hand side is the left hand side of (A.2.1), and
the image of the right hand side is the right hand side of (A.2.1).
But writing GlueD as Glue b D, this becomes clear.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
67
Appendix B. Universal local acyclicity
B.1. Notation. Let 𝑆 be a scheme of finite type and let C be a 𝐷p𝑆q-module category in DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ .
Let QCohp𝑆, Cq denote the category C b𝐷p𝑆q QCohp𝑆q.
Remark B.1.1. Everything in this section works with 𝑆 a general DG scheme almost of finite type.
The reader comfortable with derived algbraic geometry may therefore happily understand “scheme”
in the derived sense everywhere here.
B.2.
The adjoint functors:45
QCohp𝑆q o
/ 𝐷p𝑆q
Ind
Oblv
induce adjoint functors:
QCohp𝑆, Cq o
Ind
Oblv
/ C.
Lemma B.2.1. The functor Oblv : C Ñ QCohp𝑆, Cq is conservative.
Proof. This is shown in [GR] in the case C “ 𝐷p𝑆q.
In the general case, it suffices to show that Ind : QCohp𝑆, Cq Ñ C generates the target under
colimits. It suffices to show that the functor:
QCohp𝑆q b C Ñ π·p𝑆q b C Ñ π·p𝑆q b C
𝐷p𝑆q
generates, as it factors through Ind. But the first term generates by the [GR] result, and the second
term obviously generates.
B.3. Universal local acyclicity. We have the following notion.
Definition B.3.1. F P C is universally locally acyclic (ULA) over 𝑆 if OblvpFq P QCohp𝑆, Cq is
compact.
Notation B.3.2. We let Cπ‘ˆ 𝐿𝐴 Ď C denote the full (non-cocomplete) subcategory of ULA objects.
B.4.
We have the following basic consequences of the definition.
!
Proposition B.4.1. For every F P Cπ‘ˆ 𝐿𝐴 and for every compact G P 𝐷p𝑆q, G b F is compact in C.
Proof. Since Ind : QCohp𝑆q Ñ π·p𝑆q generates the target, objects of the form IndpPq P 𝐷p𝑆q for
P P QCohp𝑆q perfect generate the compact objects in the target under finite colimits and direct
summands.
!
Therefore, it suffices to see that IndpPq b F is compact for every perfect P P QCohp𝑆q.
To this end, it suffices to show:
»
!
IndpP b OblvpFqq Ý
Ñ IndpPq b F
(B.4.1)
since the left hand side is obviously compact by the ULA condition on F. We have an obvious map
from the left hand side to the right hand side. To show it is an isomorphism, we localize to assume
45Throughout this section, we use only the “left” forgetful and induction functors from [GR].
68
SAM RASKIN
𝑆 is affine, and then by continuity this allows us to check the claim when P “ O𝑆 . Then the claim
follows because Ind and Oblv are 𝐷p𝑆q-linear functors.
Corollary B.4.2. Any F P Cπ‘ˆ 𝐿𝐴 is compact in C.
Example B.4.3. Suppose that 𝑆 is smooth and C “ 𝐷p𝑆q. Then F is ULA if and only if F is compact
with lisse cohomologies. Indeed, if F is ULA, the cohomologies of OblvpFq P QCohp𝑆q are coherent
sheaves and therefore the cohomologies of F are lisse.
Proposition B.4.4. Suppose that 𝐹 : C Ñ D is a morphism in 𝐷p𝑆q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q with a
𝐷p𝑆q-linear right adjoint 𝐺. Then 𝐹 maps ULA objects to ULA objects.
Proof. We have the commutative diagram:
𝐹
C
/D
Oblv
QCohp𝑆, Cq
Oblv
/ QCohp𝑆, Dq
and the functor QCohp𝑆, Cq Ñ QCohp𝑆, Dq preserves compacts by assumption on 𝐹 .
B.5. Reformulations. For F P C, let HomC pF, ´q : C Ñ π·p𝑆q denote the (possibly non-continuous)
functor right adjoint to 𝐷p𝑆q Ñ C given by tensoring with F.
Proposition B.5.1. For F P C, the following conditions are equivalent.
(1) F is ULA.
(2) HomC pF, ´q : C Ñ π·p𝑆q is continuous and 𝐷p𝑆q-linear.
(3) For every M P 𝐷p𝑆q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q and every 𝑀 P M compact, the induced object:
F b 𝑀 PC b M
𝐷p𝑆q
𝐷p𝑆q
is compact.
Proof. First, we show (1) implies (2).
Proposition B.4.1, the functor 𝐷p𝑆q Ñ C of tensoring with F sends compacts to compacts, so its
right adjoint is continuous. We need to show that HomC pF, ´q is 𝐷p𝑆q-linear.
Observe first that Oblv HomC pF, ´q computes46 HomQCohp𝑆,Cq pOblvpFq, Oblvp´qq : C Ñ QCohp𝑆q.
!
Indeed, both are right adjoints to p´ b Fq ˝ Ind “ Ind ˝p´ b OblvpFqq, where we have identified
these functors by (B.4.1).
Then observe that:
HomQCohp𝑆,Cq pOblvpFq, ´q : QCohp𝑆, Cq Ñ QCohp𝑆q
is a morphism of QCohp𝑆q-module categories: this follows from rigidity of QCohp𝑆q. This now easily
gives the claim since Oblv is conservative.
Next, we show that (2) implies (3).
Let M and 𝑀 P M be as given. The composite functor:
46The notation indicates internal Hom for QCohp𝑆, Cq considered as a QCohp𝑆q-module category.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
69
!
p´bFqbidM
´b𝑀
Vect ÝÝÝÑ M “ 𝐷p𝑆q b M ÝÝÝÝÝÝÝÑ C b M
𝐷p𝑆q
𝐷p𝑆q
obviously sends π‘˜ P Vect to F b M. But this composite functor also obviously admits a continuous
𝐷p𝑆q
right adjoint: the first functor does because 𝑀 is compact, and the second functor does because
𝐷p𝑆q Ñ C admits a 𝐷p𝑆q-linear right adjoint by assumption.
It remains to show that (3) implies (1), but this is tautological: take M “ QCohp𝑆q.
Remark B.5.2. Note that conditions (2) and (3) make sense for any algebra A P DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ replacing
𝐷p𝑆q and any F P C a right A-module category in DGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ . That (2) implies (3) holds in this
generality follows by the same argument.
Here is a sample application of this perspective.
!
Corollary B.5.3. For G P 𝐷pπ‘ˆ q holonomic and F P Cπ‘ˆ 𝐿𝐴 , 𝑗! pG b 𝑗 ! pFqq P C is defined, and the
natural map:
!
!
𝑗! pG b 𝑗 ! pFqq Ñ π‘—! pGq b F
is an isomorphism. In particular, 𝑗! pFq is defined.
Proof. We begin by showing that there is an isomorphism:
𝑗 ! pHomC pF, ´qq » HomCπ‘ˆ p𝑗 ! pFq, 𝑗 ! p´qq
as functors C Ñ π·pπ‘ˆ q. Indeed, we have:
!
!
π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 𝑗 ! pHomC pF, ´qq “ π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 pπœ”π‘ˆ q b HomC pF, ´q “ HomC pF, π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 pπœ”π‘ˆ q b p´qq “
and the right hand side obviously identifies with π‘—Λš,𝑑𝑅 HomCπ‘ˆ p𝑗 ! pFq, 𝑗 ! p´qq.
r P C, we see:
Now for any F
!
r “ Hom𝐷pπ‘ˆ q pG, 𝑗 ! Hom pF, Fqq
r “
r “ Hom𝐷p𝑆q p𝑗! pGq, Hom pF, Fqq
HomC p𝑗! pGq b F, Fq
C
C
!
r
r
Hom𝐷pπ‘ˆ q pG, HomC p𝑗 ! pFq, 𝑗 ! pFqqq
“ HomCπ‘ˆ pG b 𝑗 ! pFq, 𝑗 ! pFqq
as desired.
B.6.
We now discuss a ULA condition for 𝐷p𝑆q-module categories themselves.
Definition B.6.1. C as above is ULA over 𝑆 if QCohp𝑆, Cq is compactly generated by objects of the
form P b OblvpFq with F P Cπ‘ˆ 𝐿𝐴 and P P QCohp𝑆q perfect.
Example B.6.2. 𝐷p𝑆q is ULA. Indeed, πœ”π‘† is ULA with Oblvpπœ”π‘† q “ O𝑆 .
Lemma B.6.3. If C is ULA, then C is compactly generated.
Proof. Immediate from conservativity of Oblv.
70
B.7.
SAM RASKIN
In this setting, we have the following converse to Proposition B.4.4.
Proposition B.7.1. For C ULA, a 𝐷p𝑆q-linear functor 𝐹 : C Ñ D admits a 𝐷p𝑆q-linear right
adjoint if and only if 𝐹 preserves ULA objects.
Proof. We have already seen one direction in Proposition B.4.4. For the converse, suppose 𝐹 preserves ULA objects.
Since C is compactly generated and 𝐹 preserves compact objects, 𝐹 admits a continuous right
adjoint 𝐺.
We will check linearity using Proposition B.5.1:
Suppose that F P 𝐷p𝑆q. We want to show that the natural transformation:
!
!
F b 𝐺p´q Ñ πΊpF b ´q
of functors D Ñ C is an equivalence.
It is easy to see that it is enough to show that for any G P Cπ‘ˆ 𝐿𝐴 , the natural transformation of
functors D Ñ π·p𝑆q induced by applying HomC pG, ´q is an equivalence.
But this follows from the simple identity HomD p𝐹 pGq, ´q “ HomC pG, 𝐺p´qq. Indeed, we see:
!
!
!
HomC pG, F b 𝐺p´qq “ F b HomC pG, 𝐺p´qq “ F b HomD p𝐹 pGq, p´qq “
`
˘
!
!
HomD p𝐹 pGq, F b p´qq “ HomD G, 𝐺pF b p´qq
as desired.
B.8.
Suppose that 𝑖 : 𝑇 ãÑ π‘† is closed with complement 𝑗 : π‘ˆ ãÑ π‘†.
Proposition B.8.1. Suppose C is ULA as a 𝐷p𝑆q-module category. Then 𝐹 : C Ñ D a morphism
in 𝐷p𝑆q–modpDGCatπ‘π‘œπ‘›π‘‘ q is an equivalence if and only if if preserves ULA objects and the functors:
πΉπ‘ˆ : Cπ‘ˆ :“ C b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ q Ñ Dπ‘ˆ :“ D b 𝐷pπ‘ˆ q
𝐷p𝑆q
𝐷p𝑆q
𝐹𝑇 : C𝑇 :“ C b 𝐷p𝑇 q Ñ D𝑇 :“ D b 𝐷p𝑇 q
𝐷p𝑆q
𝐷p𝑆q
are equivalences.
Remark B.8.2. Note that a result of this form is not true without ULA hypotheses: the restriction
functor 𝐷p𝑆q Ñ π·pπ‘ˆ q ‘ 𝐷p𝑇 q is 𝐷p𝑆q-linear and an equivalence over 𝑇 and over π‘ˆ , but not an
equivalence.
Proof of Proposition B.8.1. By Proposition B.7.1, the functor 𝐹 admits a 𝐷p𝑆q-linear right adjoint
𝐺. We need to check that the unit and counit of this adjunction are equivalences.
By the usual Cousin dévissage, we reduce to checking that the unit and counit are equivalences
for objects pushed forward from π‘ˆ and 𝑇 . But by 𝐷p𝑆q-linearity of our functors, this follows from
our assumption.
References
[AB]
Sergey Arkhipov and Roman Bezrukavnikov. Perverse sheaves on affine flags and Langlands dual group.
Israel J. Math., 170:135–183, 2009. With an appendix by Bezrukavrikov and Ivan Mirković.
[ABB` ] Sergey Arkhipov, Sasha Braverman, Roman Bezrukavnikov, Dennis Gaitsgory, and Ivan Mirković. Modules
over the small quantum group and semi-infinite flag manifold. Transform. Groups, 10(3-4):279–362, 2005.
CHIRAL PRINCIPAL SERIES CATEGORIES I: FINITE DIMENSIONAL CALCULATIONS
[ABG]
71
Sergey Arkhipov, Roman Bezrukavnikov, and Victor Ginzburg. Quantum groups, the loop Grassmannian,
and the Springer resolution. J. Amer. Math. Soc., 17(3):595–678, 2004.
[Ati]
Michael Atiyah. Complex analytic connections in fibre bundles. Transactions of the American Mathematical
Society, 85(1):181–207, 1957.
[BBD] Sasha Beilinson, Joseph Bernstein, and Pierre Deligne. Faisceaux pervers. Astérisque, 100, 1983.
[BD]
Sasha Beilinson and Vladimir Drinfeld. Chiral algebras, volume 51 of American Mathematical Society Colloquium Publications. American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2004.
[Bei]
Sasha Beilinson. How to glue perverse sheaves. In 𝐾-theory, arithmetic and geometry (Moscow, 1984–1986),
volume 1289 of Lecture Notes in Math., pages 42–51. Springer, Berlin, 1987.
[Ber]
Dario Beraldo. Loop group actions on categories and Whittaker invariants.
[Bez]
Roman Bezrukavnikov. On two geometric realizations of an affine hecke algebra. 2012. Available at: http:
//arxiv.org/pdf/1209.0403v3.pdf.
[BFGM] Sasha Braverman, Michael Finkelberg, Dennis Gaitsgory, and Ivan Mirković. Intersection cohomology of
Drinfeld’s compactifications. Selecta Math. (N.S.), 8(3):381–418, 2002.
[BFS]
Roman Bezrukavnikov, Michael Finkelberg, and Vadim Schechtman. Factorizable sheaves and quantum
groups, volume 1691 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1998.
[BG1]
Sasha Braverman and Dennis Gaitsgory. Geometric Eisenstein series. Invent. Math., 150(2):287–384, 2002.
[BG2]
Sasha Braverman and Dennis Gaitsgory. Deformations of local systems and Eisenstein series. Geom. Funct.
Anal., 17(6):1788–1850, 2008.
[Cas]
W. Casselman. The unramified principal series of 𝑝-adic groups. I. The spherical function. Compositio Math.,
40(3):387–406, 1980.
[DG]
Vladimir Drinfeld and Dennis Gaitsgory. On a theorem of Braden. arXiv preprint arXiv:1308.3786, 2013.
[FF]
Boris Feigin and Edward Frenkel. Affine Kac-Moody algebras and semi-infinite flag manifolds. Communications in mathematical physics, 128(1):161–189, 1990.
[FFKM] Boris Feigin, Michael Finkelberg, Alexander Kuznetsov, and Ivan Mirković. Semi-infinite flags. II. Local
and global intersection cohomology of quasimaps’ spaces. In Differential topology, infinite-dimensional Lie
algebras, and applications, volume 194 of Amer. Math. Soc. Transl. Ser. 2, pages 113–148. Amer. Math.
Soc., Providence, RI, 1999.
[FG1]
John Francis and Dennis Gaitsgory. Chiral Koszul duality. Selecta Math. (N.S.), 18(1):27–87, 2012.
[FG2]
Edward Frenkel and Dennis Gaitsgory. Local geometric Langlands correspondence and affine Kac-Moody
algebras. In Algebraic geometry and number theory, pages 69–260. Springer, 2006.
[FG3]
Edward Frenkel and Dennis Gaitsgory. 𝐷-modules on the affine flag variety and representations of affine
Kac-Moody algebras. Represent. Theory, 13:470–608, 2009.
[FGV] Edward Frenkel, Dennis Gaitsgory, and Kari Vilonen. Whittaker patterns in the geometry of moduli spaces
of bundles on curves. The Annals of Mathematics, 153(3):699–748, 2001.
[FM]
Michael Finkelberg and Ivan Mirković. Semi-infinite flags. I. Case of global curve P1 . 194:81–112, 1999.
`
[GAB ] A. Grothendieck, M. Artin, J. E. Bertin, M. Demazure, P. Gabriel, M. Raynaud, and J.-P. Serre. SGA III:
Schémas en groupes., volume 1963/64 of Séminaire de Géométrie Algébrique de l’Institut des Hautes Études
Scientifiques. Institut des Hautes Études Scientifiques, Paris, 1966.
[Gai1]
D. Gaitsgory. On de Jong’s conjecture. Israel J. Math., 157:155–191, 2007.
[Gai2]
Dennis Gaitsgory. Les jours et les travaux. Unpublished, 2010.
[Gai3]
Dennis Gaitsgory. Generalities on DG categories. Available at: http://math.harvard.edu/~gaitsgde/GL/
textDG.pdf, 2012.
[Gai4]
Dennis Gaitsgory. Sheaves of categories and the notion of 1-affineness. 2013.
[GR]
Dennis Gaitsgory and Nick Rozenblyum. Studies in derived algebraic geometry. 2015.
[KV]
Mikhail Kapranov and Eric Vasserot. Vertex algebras and the formal loop space. Publ. Math. Inst. Hautes
Études Sci., (100):209–269, 2004.
[Lur1]
Jacob Lurie. Higher topos theory, volume 170 of Annals of Mathematics Studies. Princeton University Press,
Princeton, NJ, 2009.
[Lur2]
Jacob Lurie. DAG X: Formal moduli problems. Available at: http://math.harvard.edu/~lurie/papers/
DAG-X.pdf, 2011.
[Lur3]
Jacob Lurie. Higher algebra. Available at: http://math.harvard.edu/~lurie/papers/HigherAlgebra.pdf,
2012.
72
SAM RASKIN
[Lus]
[MV]
[Ras1]
[Ras2]
[Ras3]
[Ras4]
[Rei]
[Roz]
[Sch]
George Lusztig. Singularities, character formulas, and a π‘ž-analog of weight multiplicities. In Analysis and
topology on singular spaces, II, III (Luminy, 1981), volume 101 of Astérisque, pages 208–229. Soc. Math.
France, Paris, 1983.
I. Mirković and K. Vilonen. Geometric Langlands duality and representations of algebraic groups over
commutative rings. Ann. of Math. (2), 166(1):95–143, 2007.
Sam Raskin. Chiral categories. 2015.
Sam Raskin. Chiral principal series categories II: the Whittaker category. 2015.
Sam Raskin. Chiral principal series categories III: the spherical category. 2015.
Sam Raskin. 𝐷-modules on infinite dimensional varieties. 2015.
Ryan Cohen Reich. Twisted geometric Satake equivalence via gerbes on the factorizable Grassmannian.
Represent. Theory, 16:345–449, 2012.
Nick Rozenblyum. Modules over a chiral algebra. Available at: http://arxiv.org/abs/1010.1998, 2010.
Simon Schieder. The Harder-Narasimhan stratification of the moduli stack of G-bundles via Drinfeld’s
compactifications. arXiv preprint arXiv:1212.6814, 2012.
Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 77 Massachusetts Avenue, Cambridge, MA 02139.
E-mail address: sraskin@mit.edu
Download